Essay Six:
Trotsky And Hegel -- How To Misconstrue The 'Law Of Identity', And How That Law
Is No Enemy Of Change
Ideally, this Essay should be read in
conjunction with Essays Four and
Five.
Technical Preliminaries
If you are using Internet Explorer 10 (or later), you might find some of the
links I have used won't work properly unless you switch to 'Compatibility View'
(in the Tools Menu); for IE11 select 'Compatibility View Settings' and add this
site (anti-dialectics.co.uk). Microsoft's browser,
Edge, automatically
renders these links compatible; Windows 10 does likewise.
However, if you are using Windows 10, IE11 and Edge unfortunately appear to colour these links
somewhat erratically. They are meant to be mid-blue, but those two browsers
render them intermittently light blue, dark blue, yellow, purple and red!
Chrome reproduces these
links correctly.
Unfortunately, several browsers also
underline these links erratically. Many are underscored boldly in black, others
in light blue! They are all meant to be underlined in the same colour as the
link itself.
In addition, the editor I have used to
publish this material on the Internet -- Microsoft's FrontPage -- has for
some reason inserted several formatting glitches into the final version of this
Essay, glitches which are only visible in Internet Explorer, so far as I can tell, and even then only in relation to
two of my Essays, this one and Essay Four! I have no idea
why and all my attempts to correct these problems have so far failed.
If you are viewing this using Mozilla
Firefox, you might find that some of the codes that Microsoft have put into
FrontPage make several of the font colours in the second half of this
Essay change somewhat erratically.
Finally, if you are also viewing this
with Mozilla Firefox, you might not be able to read all the symbols I have
used
-- Mozilla often replaces them with an "º'.
There are no problems with Chrome, Edge, or Internet Explorer, as far as I can
determine.
Preface
As is the case with all my
work, nothing here should be read as an attack
either on Historical Materialism [HM] -- a theory I fully accept --, or,
indeed,
on revolutionary socialism. I remain as committed to the self-emancipation of the
working class and the dictatorship of the proletariat as I was when I first became a revolutionary
thirty-five years ago.
The
difference between
Dialectical Materialism [DM] and HM, as I see it, is explained
here.
It is worth pointing
that phrases like "ruling-class theory", "ruling-class view of reality",
"ruling-class ideology" (etc.) used at this site (in connection with
Traditional Philosophy and DM), aren't meant to
suggest that all or even most members of various ruling-classes
actually invented these ways of thinking or of
seeing the world (although some of them did -- for example,
Heraclitus,
Plato,
Cicero,
and
Marcus Aurelius).
They are intended to
highlight theories (or "ruling ideas") that are conducive to, or which rationalise the
interests of the various ruling-classes history has inflicted on humanity, whoever invents them.
Up until
recently this dogmatic approach to knowledge had almost invariably been promoted by thinkers who
either relied on ruling-class patronage, or who, in one capacity or another, helped run
the system
for the elite.**
However, that will become the
central topic of Parts Two and Three of Essay Twelve (when they are published); until then, the reader is
directed
here,
here, and
here for
more
details.
[**Exactly
how this applies to DM will, of course, be explained in the other Essays
published at this site (especially
here,
here,
and here).
In addition to the three links in the previous paragraph, I have summarised the
argument (but this time for the benefit of absolute beginners!)
here.]
It is also worth adding out that a good 50% of my case
against DM has been relegated to the
End Notes. This has been done
in order to allow the main body of the Essay to flow a little more
smoothly. This means that if readers want to appreciate fully my case against DM, they will need to
consult this material. In many cases, I have qualified or amplified what I have
to say in
these Notes, and I have also added extra supporting evidence. I have also raised
numerous objections (some obvious, many not -- and some
that will have occurred to the reader) to my own ideas, which I have then proceeded to
answer.
[I explain why I have adopted this tactic in
Essay One.]
If readers skip this material, then my answers to any
objections they might have to my arguments will be missed, as will the extra
detail and evidence.
[Since I have been
debating this theory with comrades for over 30 years, I have heard all the
objections there are! Many of the more recent debates are listed
here.]
Several readers have
complained about the number of links I have added to these Essays because they
say it makes them very difficult to read. Of course, DM-supporters can hardly
lodge that complaint since they believe everything is interconnected, and
that must surely apply even to Essays that
attempt to debunk that very idea. However, to those
who find such links do make these Essays difficult to read I say this: ignore them -- unless you want to access
further supporting evidence and argument for a particular point, or a certain
topic fires your interest.
Others wonder why I have linked to familiar
subjects and issues that are part of common knowledge (such as the names of
recent Presidents of the
USA, UK Prime Ministers, the names of rivers and mountains, the titles of
popular films, or certain words
that are in common usage). I have done so for the following reason: my Essays
are read all over the world and by people from all 'walks of life', so I can't
assume that topics which are part of common knowledge in 'the west' are equally
well-known across the planet -- or, indeed, by those who haven't had the benefit
of the sort of education that is generally available in the 'advanced economies',
or any at
all. Many of my readers also struggle with English, so any help I can give them
I will continue to provide.
Finally on this specific topic, several of the aforementioned links
connect to
web-pages that regularly change their
URLs, or which vanish from the
Internet altogether. While I try to update them when it becomes apparent
that they have changed or have disappeared I can't possibly keep on top of
this all the time. I would greatly appreciate it, therefore, if readers
informed me
of any dead links they happen to notice.
In general, links to 'Haloscan'
no longer seem to work, so readers needn't tell me about them! Links to
RevForum, RevLeft, Socialist Unity and The North Star also appear to have died.
~~~~~~oOo~~~~~~
As of November 2024, this Essay is
just over 72,000 words long; a summary of
some of its
main ideas can be accessed
here.
The
material presented below does not represent my final view of any of the
issues raised; it is merely 'work in progress'.
[Latest Update: 15/11/24.]
Quick Links
Anyone using these links must remember that
they will be skipping past supporting argument and evidence set out in earlier
sections.
If your Firewall/Browser has a pop-up blocker, you will need to press
the "Ctrl" key at the same time or these and the other links here won't work!
I have adjusted the
font size used at this site to ensure that even those with impaired
vision can read what I have to say. However, if the text is still either too
big or too small for you, please adjust your browser settings!
(1)
Introduction
(2)
Trotsky On Identity
(3)
Ironically, "Identical" Is Not Identical With "Equal"
(a)
A Mistake Most Dialecticians
Make
(b)
Ordinary Language
Thwarts Dialectics
(c)
"Equal"
And "Identical" Not Identical
(d)
Mathematical Equality Vs Mathematical Identity
(e)
Trotsky Changes The Subject
(4)
Trotsky's Argument Dissected
(a)
Precisely What Is Trotsky
Denying?
(b)
Trotsky Has This Base Covered --
Or Has He?
(5)
Bags Of Sugar Actually Refute
Trotsky
(a)
Trotsky's Answer
(b)
Mere Guesswork On Trotsky's Part?
(c)
Trotsky's Instructions -- Followed Exactly And To The Letter?
(d)
Yet Another Misidentification
(e)
'Norms Of Tolerance' Refute
Trotsky, Too
(f)
Wrong Anyway
(g)
Identical A Priori Tactics
(h)
Super-Science From Mere Words
(i)
Physicists Discover Identical Particles!
(j)
Changeless Sub-Atomic
Particles
(k)
An Everyday
Example Of Absolute Identity
(6)
Trotsky Uses
Identity To Criticise Identity
(a)
Same Moment
(b)
A Turn To The Concrete
(c) Incomprehensible? Or Just Trivial?
(7)
Did Trotsky
Understand Identity?
(a)
How Can Anyone Learn What Identity
Is If
There Is None?
(b)
The Sting In The Tail
(c)
'Approximate' And
'Abstract' Identity
(d)
Plato, Hegel, Trotsky And
The Concept Of 'Abstract Identity'
(e)
Dialectical Dilemma
(f)
Identity Schmidentity
(g)
Trotsky's Exact Words
Dialectically Implode
(h)
Trotsky's Attack Unequal
To The Task
(i)
Materially-Induced
Dialectical Misery
(8)
The Knock-Out
Blow
(9)
Traditional Logic Versus Modern Formal Logic
(a)
Traditional Logic
Defective?
(b)
Dialectical Logic
Superior To Formal Logic?
(c)
Formal Logic: A Fragmented And Static View Of Reality?
(10)
Notes
(11)
References
Summary Of My Main Objections To
Dialectical Materialism
Abbreviations Used At This
Site
Return To The Main Index Page
Contact Me
Introduction
Few other areas of FL cause dialecticians more
problems than the LOI. For many it is the
bête noir of "formal thinking".
However, this Essay aims to show that not only have dialecticians misconstrued
this so-called 'Law', the vast majority have in fact attacked the wrong target!
[FL = Formal Logic;
LOI = Law of Identity; DM = Dialectical Materialism/Materialist, depending on
the context.]
Hegel's Logic is the immediate source of
these errors for it is there that we find Hegel applying his quirky 'reasoning
powers' to something that is not, as it turns out, inimical to change. Identity
is no more a threat to change than difference is to stability.
Nevertheless, the main thrust of my criticisms of Hegel's 'analysis' of this
'law' will appear in Essay Twelve. The objections I have raised here
against the highly repetitious and misguided criticisms that Marxist
Dialecticians level against the LOI also indirectly apply to
his work.
Since these Essays have been written from within
the Trotskyist tradition, and because Trotsky's comments on this 'law' are far
more influential on active revolutionaries than Hegel's (few of whom have
read or studied his work), it makes
sense to begin with his widely quoted remarks.
Trotsky On Identity
In his debate with
Burnham, Trotsky rehearsed
several
arguments aimed at exposing what he took to be serious limitations of
the LOI, criticisms he had lifted directly or indirectly from Hegel that have
resurfaced almost verbatim in the writings of Dialectical Trotskyists
ever since.1
The motivation for Trotsky's analysis was his belief that FL deals only with
'static and lifeless concepts', rendering it incapable of grasping the dynamism
found in concrete reality. Remarkably, Trotsky nowhere attempted to substantiate
these sweeping allegations; in fact there is no evidence that he consulted
a single logic text that had been written in the previous 100 years.2
Clearly, he didn't think that this failure to check his facts disqualified him
from passing
informed opinion on the
subject. By the same token, therefore, we may suppose him an expert in
High Energy Physics
--
and perhaps even brain surgery!
This
rather damning criticism applies equally well to the
vast majority of Trotsky's epigones –- to say nothing of DM-theorists in general
-- few of whom show any sign of ever having consulted a single logic text
(ancient or modern), saving, of course, those two badly misnamed
books written by Hegel: the
Shorter Logic and the
Science of Logic
(i.e., Hegel (1975, 1999)).
[AFL = Aristotelian Formal
Logic; MFL = Modern Formal Logic.]
Most of the criticisms DM-theorists
level against FL in general have been examined in Essay Four,
where they were shown to be based on
a serious misunderstanding even of AFL, let alone MFL. This is hardly surprising
given the allegations advanced in the previous paragraph.
Be this as it may, in
this Essay I plan to focus on Trotsky's criticisms of the LOI, which
DM-theorists -- at least those in the Trotskyist wing of Marxism -- generally
regard as definitive. John Rees, for example, outlined one key issue as follows:
"[In
FL] things are defined statically, according to certain fixed properties -–
colour, weight, size, and so on. This is denoted by the expression 'A is equal
to A'." [Rees (1998), p.272.]
Trotsky's own argument,
however, was this:
"The
Aristotelian logic of the simple syllogism starts from the proposition that 'A'
is equal to 'A'. This postulate is accepted as an axiom for a multitude of
practical human actions and elementary generalisations. But in reality 'A' is
not equal to 'A'. This is easy to prove if we observe these two letters under a
lens -– they are quite different from each other. But, one can object, the
question is not the size or the form of the letters, since they are only symbols
for equal quantities, for instance, a pound of sugar. The objection is beside
the point; in reality a pound of sugar is never equal to a pound of sugar -– a
more delicate scale always discloses a difference. Again one can object: but a
pound of sugar is equal to itself. Neither is true (sic) -– all bodies change
uninterruptedly in size, weight, colour etc. They are never equal to themselves.
A sophist will respond that a pound of sugar is equal to itself at 'any given
moment'…. How should we really conceive the word 'moment'? If it is an
infinitesimal interval of time, then a pound of sugar is subjected during the
course of that 'moment' to inevitable changes. Or is the 'moment' a purely
mathematical abstraction, that is, a zero of time? But everything exists in
time; and existence itself is an uninterrupted process of transformation; time
is consequently a fundamental element of existence. Thus the axiom 'A' is equal
to 'A' signifies that a thing is equal to itself if it does not change, that is
if it does not exist." [Trotsky
(1971), pp.63-64.]2a
One puzzling fact about this passage --
which it shares with the many references made to this 'law' in other DM-writings -- is that it
ignores classical versions of the LOI, none of which Trotsky, Rees or other
dialecticians ever bother to reference, let alone quote.3
[Except
when I am directly quoting DM-sources, where I use capital letters in that way
in this Essay I will highlight them in bold to distinguish them from the
ordinary use of capital letters.]
So, there appear to be at least a dozen substantive
points Trotsky was making, here:
T1: AFL begins with "A is equal
to A".
T2: This "postulate" applies quite well in most
practical situations. But, in reality "A is not equal to A".
T3: Close inspection under a lens, for example, will show that any
chosen letter
"A" is not exactly the same as any other letter "A".
T4: A similar observation applies if these
letters stand for material objects, like a pound bag of sugar.
T5: Any two weighings of seemingly equal bags of
sugar will always reveal minor differences.
T6: It is no
use arguing that all bodies are equal
to themselves since they all undergo constant change; so they are
never equal to themselves.
T7: The sophistical response -- that objects are
momentarily equal to themselves -- is based on an abstract conception of time.
T8: If a moment
in time is an interval, then any object
will undergo inevitable change in that interval.
T9: If
it isn't an interval, it must be
a mathematical abstraction, a "zero of time".
T10: Everything exists in time and existence is
an "uninterrupted process of transformation"; time is a "fundamental element of
existence".
T11: "A
is equal to A" implies that objects are equal to themselves if they don't change.
T12:
Objects that don't change, don't exist.
Trotsky nowhere backs any
of these up with evidence (or, none that isn't itself
based on
further
thought experiments), but that seemingly fatal defect
rarely seems to bother dialecticians. In earlier Essays, we saw why DM-theorists airily
brush aside the need to substantiate their theses with anything that remotely
resembles proof: if the universe is governed at every level by DL, a simple 'thought
experiment' is all the 'evidence' a dialectician really needs.
[DL = Dialectical Logic.]
Naturally, only consistent
materialists will object
at this point.
As George
Novack argued:
"A consistent materialism cannot proceed from
principles which are validated by appeal to abstract reason, intuition,
self-evidence or some other subjective or purely theoretical source. Idealisms
may do this. But the materialist philosophy has to be based upon evidence taken
from objective material sources and verified by demonstration in practice...."
[Novack (1965), p.17. Bold emphases added.]
Lest
anyone object to the above, it is worth pointing out that what little 'evidence'
Trotsky and/or his epigones have offered in support of their hyper-bold claims
-- about every single object in the entire universe, for all of time -- will be
examined below.
However, Trotsky's quasi-Hegelian observations
were based on a serious 'misunderstanding'
even of AFL -- a defect seriously
compromised by
an ironically appropriate mis-identification of the LOI, further
compounded by the invocation of an abstract metaphysical doctrine of his own.
[Of
course, there are many other serious weaknesses in Trotsky's argument, but they
are merely consequences of the above.]
Ironically,
"Identical" Is Not Identical With
"Equal"
A Mistake That
Applies Equally To Most Dialecticians
Trotsky's initial
characterisation of the LOI is itself rather strange. His paraphrase of it went as
follows:
S1: A is equal
to A.4
But, as an accurate depiction of identity,
S1 isn't even close -- not least because it omits mention of the word
"identity"! Contrast S1 with the following far less inaccurate -- but
simplified -- version of the same 'law':
S2: A is identical
to A.
But, why have generations of dialecticians
studiously avoided formulations of the LOI like S2 in favour of those that appear
to be about something entirely different? [No irony intended.] Why did Trotsky prefer S1 to S2?
Clearly, his
use of "equal" in S1 meant he was actually attacking the principle of
equality -- not the LOI. Naturally, this means that Trotsky's criticisms
of the LOI were misconceived from the start!
However, when confronted with the above
claims,
DM-apologists tend to respond, "So what? What's the difference between the two?" As will
be appreciated, that reply is itself problematic -- not the least because
it reveals that these individuals have an equally insecure grasp of the issues
involved. [Irony intended.]
Well:
(i) If there is no difference between the
two, then they are identical, which means that we would now have at least one genuine
example of the LOI on which all could agree, namely this -- that equality is
identical with identity!
(ii) If they are different
after all, Trotsky clearly attacked the
wrong target.
Now, when challenged with this dilemma, dialecticians
either ignore it, or they appeal to the "It's just abstract"
defence, accompanied, or not, with the by-now-clichéd accusation of "pedantry".
As we will soon see, this retreat is itself a step back too far, since
there is a clear difference between abstract equality and
abstract identity, too, which dialecticians have also failed to notice. So,
abstract or concrete, the two notions aren't the same. [Anyway,
'Abstract', or 'Absolute', Identity will be dealt with
later.]
Furthermore, as we discovered in Essay Three Parts
One and
Two,
dialecticians have an insecure grasp of the nature of abstraction, and are
largely content to be told what to think on this score by notorious Idealists -- like Aristotle,
Spinoza and Hegel.
As we will also find out, our grasp of words that
seek to depict or
criticise the nature of 'abstractions' depends on the employment of very real, material
correlates in this world. For example, the above objections have
themselves to be committed to paper, typed on to a computer screen, or propagated through the air as sound waves.
In which case, it
becomes pertinent to ask whether sentences containing the word "identical" make
exactly the same point as those containing the word "equal". If they
do, then Trotsky's criticisms of this 'law' can't apply to any material
embodiment of his ideas --, since, if they did, we would once again have an
employment of this 'law' in
the
material world which undermines all he had to say about it -- for here we would
have some very real, material sentences that would be identical in content -- if
"equal" were the same as "identical".
On the other hand, of course, if they
don't make exactly the same
point, then, once more, Trotsky attacked the wrong target.
Finally, the fact that dialecticians -- who are
supposed to be using 'cutting edge' science, philosophy,
and 'logic' --
failed to notice this serious error,
and continue to ignore it no matter how many times it is brought to their
attention, seriously undermines their credibility. Indeed, these major interpretive
blunders fatally compromise the claim that DM is a science to begin
with, let alone
a philosophical theory that merits serious attention.
Ordinary Language Once Again Thwarts Dialectical
Casuistry
Our comprehension of words for identity,
sameness, equality and difference clearly revolves around the use of certain
expressions in ordinary life, whatever technical modifications we might
subsequently want to introduce, and for whatever reason we might do that. But,
the ordinary use of terms like "equal", "identical", "same" and "different" is
itself highly complex, even though that isn't the
impression one gets from reading Trotsky's comments (or, indeed, those of his epigones).
Nor is it the impression one forms when reading Hegel, either.
[More on this later. The importance of
ordinary language was highlighted in Essays
Four and Twelve
Part One (as well as the rest of Essay
Twelve, summary here).
It was also stressed by
Marx himself.]
It could be objected that these two
principles (i.e., equality and identity) are approximately identical, to
such an extent that any difference between them can be ignored. However, as we
will see, that isn't even remotely
correct; these two concepts are radically different. But, even if it were
the case that they are approximately identical, that would still be of no help. Unless
we possessed a clear idea of what would count as absolute identity between these two, we
would be in no position to declare they have only approximated to that ideal. An
approximation only makes sense if we know with what it is that it
approximates; but, for us to know that, we would have to know what it
would be for the LOI to apply
absolutely in this case so that we could say why this is merely an approximation.
[There is more on this below.]
Whatever one thinks of the limitations (or
otherwise) of the vernacular, unless we begin with an accurate and representative
view of the use of such terms in ordinary language we stand in real danger of
making fundamental mistakes in more complex or technical areas. As we will see,
that is exactly what undermines the
criticisms DM-theorists make of the LOI.
It would be a mistake,
therefore, to
think "equal", "identical", "same" (and related terms) all mean the same (no
pun intended). But,
because of his cavalier attitude to the vernacular, Trotsky either ignored, or
was oblivious to, the conceptual space ordinary language
opens up for its users in this regard, a flexibility that allows them to make complex and intricate
allusions to identity, equality, similarity, difference, and much more besides,
with relative ease.
Consider
just a few examples: not only can two
or more things be equal and not identical, they can be identical
without being equal. For instance, two or more forces can be equal and opposite
(or equal and not opposite), yet still fail to be identical. [If they were
identical they couldn't be opposite.]
Again, two
individual
sportsmen/women could be identically the same player. For example, in cricket,
they could be "opening bat", "first slip", or "wicket keeper", at different
times in the same game or at the same time in different games, while
being unequal in many other respects.
Not only that, but identically the same man
or woman could occupy, say, two different official, semi-official or
work-related posts at the same time, but have unequal powers in each (e.g., NN
could be a Unison rep at
the same time as being the Treasurer of her local branch of Stop the War Coalition (STWC)). In that case we could say that "The
Unison rep is identical to the STWC Treasurer", and, since NN is both of
these at once,
slow or even change wouldn't affect this identity statement (unless, of course, she resigns
from one or both, or dies).5
Furthermore, two or more things can be the same even if they aren't at all alike: for example, two copies of identically
the same book (e.g., Das Kapital) in radically different
languages (say, English and Chinese) are easily recognisable as the same book even
if they are totally dissimilar. Minor differences between the two are
irrelevant here. Only a fool would try claim that a copy of Das Kapital wasn't in fact a copy
of that book because of a differently coloured cover, for example. So, while these books may not be identically the same physical
object, they are identically the same work by Marx. Indeed, countless different
readers can now access the same works of Marx's right across the planet at the
Marxist Internet Archive.
Despite the fact that they might access his work using different browsers,
screen resolutions or text magnification, few would claim that these facts prevent
readers accessing identically the same work.
This indicates that
our
application of identity criteria
in different areas of
discourse change depending on the
substantival terms and the circumstances involved.5a
In addition, this shows that in the vernacular
there is no such thing as
the meaning of any of our terms for identity, sameness or difference --, which
further implies that Hegel and other dialecticians focussed their attention on an
entirely spurious target.
To continue, two
totally different things can be equal. For example, two non-identical athletes who
cross the winning line together would both be equal joint-winners of the Gold
medal, say. Two women at the front of two different queues in the same or
different Post Office(s) would both be equally first in line. Two idiots who
shout "Fire!" at the same time in a cinema are equally to blame for the ensuing
panic. A bus or a train could be equally acceptable to a weary traveller as a
means of transport. Two delivery men who carry a packing case up three flights
of stairs will be equally responsible for delivering it. Two punters could equally share a lottery prize because
they completed the same winning ticket together, and both chose identically the
same numbers. Two comrades could sell equal numbers of different revolutionary papers on
separate paper sales weeks apart. Instances like these are easy to multiply. No
doubt two or more readers could imagine equally apposite (but non-identical) examples of their own to make
identically the same point.5b
[The following material used to be in Note 5b.]
-----------------------------------------
It could be argued that
these examples of identity aren't in fact examples of strict identity since all the
items listed will change in small ways, as will their relation to countless other
local, or even remote, objects. In that case, absolutely nothing in nature will be
identical to itself from moment to moment.
This objection has been partially defused in
Note 5, and will be completely laid to rest below (here, here,
and here), as well as the closing part
of this Essay.
However, it is worth pointing out that the examples given above were listed in
order to show that abstract, and what we might call,
for want of a better phrase, material identity, aren't the same as abstract, and
what we might also call, material
equality, and that ordinary language (but not the obscure jargon
philosophers have concocted) is our best guide to what we mean by
identity, sameness, equality and difference.
[The primacy of ordinary language is
taken for granted at this site; in Essay Twelve this stance will be defended in depth
(summary here); but see
also
here.]
Now, the other
objection
(i.e., that an alteration to a body's relational
properties changes that body) itself depends on
the truth of several other DM-theses -- for example, DM-Holism and the doctrine of
"internal relations". Since these are taken apart in Essays Three
Part Three and Eleven Parts One
and Two, no more will be said
about that topic in this Essay. [However, on this, see
here.]
Nevertheless, a few
points need to be
made
about the doctrine of universal change.
Naturally, it would be perverse to deny that
many things change; not only is this a given in our use of ordinary language and
our common understanding (a highly truncated list of ordinary words we have for
change has been posted
here), it is a familiar feature of everyday life
and highly
confirmed by science.
However, even if the evidence we now have were to be
multiplied by several million orders of magnitude (i.e., by a factor of, say, 102000000
--
or more), that would still fail to be enough to justify the sort of
mad dog
Heracliteanism
we find in DM-texts:
"[A]ll bodies change uninterruptedly in size,
weight, colour etc. They are never equal to themselves.... [E]verything
exists in time; and existence itself is an uninterrupted process of
transformation…. For concepts there also exists 'tolerance' which
is established not by formal logic…, but by the dialectical logic issuing from
the axiom that everything is always changing….... Dialectical thinking analyses all things and
phenomena in their continuous change….
Dialectics…teaches us to combine syllogisms in
such a way as to bring our understanding closer to the eternally changing
reality." [Trotsky
(1971), pp.64-66. Italic emphases added.
Paragraphs merged.]
"Dialectics…prevails throughout nature….
[T]he motion through opposites which asserts itself everywhere in nature,
and which by the continual conflict of the opposites…determines the life of
nature." [Engels (1954),
p.211. Italic emphases added.]
"[Among the elements of dialectics are the
following:]…internally contradictory tendencies…in this [totality]…and
unity of opposites…. [E]ach thing…is connected with every other…[this
involves] not only the unity of opposites, but the transitions of
every determination, quality, feature, side, property into
every other…. In brief, dialectics can be defined as the
doctrine of the unity of opposites. This embodies the essence of dialectics….
"The splitting of the whole and the cognition of
its contradictory parts…is the essence (one of the 'essentials', one of
the principal, if not the principal, characteristic features) of dialectics…. The identity of opposites…is the recognition…of
the contradictory, mutually exclusive, opposite tendencies in all
phenomena and processes of nature…. Development is the 'struggle' of opposites.… The unity…of opposites is conditional,
temporary, transitory, relative. The struggle of mutually exclusive opposites is
absolute, just as development and motion are absolute." [Lenin (1961),
pp.221-22,
357-58. Emphases in the original;
some paragraphs merged.]
"According to Hegel, dialectics is the
principle of all life…. [M]an has two qualities: first being alive, and
secondly of also being mortal. But on closer examination it turns out that
life itself bears in itself the germ of death, and that in general
any phenomenon is contradictory, in the sense that it develops out of
itself the elements which, sooner or later, will put an end to its existence and
will transform it into its opposite. Everything flows,
everything changes; and there is no force capable of holding back this
constant flux, or arresting its eternal movement. There is no force
capable of resisting the dialectics of phenomena….
"At a particular moment a moving body is at a
particular spot, but at the same time it is outside it as well because, if it
were only in that spot, it would, at least for that moment, become motionless.
Every motion is a dialectical process, a living contradiction, and
as there is not a single phenomenon of nature in explaining which we do
not have in the long run to appeal to motion, we have to agree with Hegel, who
said that dialectics is the soul of any scientific cognition. And this
applies not only to cognition of nature….
"And so every phenomenon, by the
action of those same forces which condition its existence, sooner or later, but
inevitably, is transformed into its own opposite…. When you apply the dialectical method to the
study of phenomena, you need to remember that forms change eternally
in consequence of the 'higher development of their content'…. In the words of Engels, Hegel's merit consists
in the fact that he was the first to regard all phenomena from the point
of view of their development, from the point of view of their origin and
destruction…." [Plekhanov
(1956), pp.74-77,
88,
163. Bold emphases alone added.
Some paragraphs merged.]
"'All is flux, nothing is
stationary,' said the ancient thinker from Ephesus. The combinations we call
objects are in a state of constant and more or less rapid change…. [M]otion does not only make objects…, it is
constantly changing them. It is for this reason that the logic of
motion (the 'logic of contradiction') never relinquishes its rights
over the objects created by motion….
"With Hegel, thinking progresses in consequence
of the uncovering and resolution of the contradictions inclosed (sic) in
concepts. According to our doctrine…the contradictions embodied in
concepts are merely reflections, translations into the language of thought,
of those contradictions that are embodied in phenomena owing to the
contradictory nature of their common basis, i.e., motion…. [T]he overwhelming majority of phenomena
that come within the compass of the natural and the social sciences are among
'objects' of this kind…[:ones in which there is a coincidence of opposites].
Diametrically opposite phenomena are united in the simplest globule of
protoplasm, and the life of the most undeveloped society…." [Plekhanov (1908),
pp.93-96. Bold emphases alone added. Some paragraphs merged.]
"There are two possible ways of regarding
everything in nature and in society; in the eyes of some everything is
constantly at rest, immutable…. To others, however, it appears that there is
nothing unchanging in nature or in society…. This second point of
view is called the dynamic point of view…; the former point of view is
called static. Which is the correct position?... Even a hasty glance
at nature will at once convince us that there is nothing immutable
about it….
"Evidently…there is nothing immutable
and rigid in the universe…. Matter in motion: such is the stuff of
this world…. This dynamic point of view is also called the dialectic
(sic) point of view…. The world being in constant
motion, we must consider phenomena in their mutual relations, and not as
isolated cases. All portions of the universe are actually related to each
other and exert an influence on each other…. All things in the universe are
connected with an indissoluble bond; nothing exists as an isolated object,
independent of its surroundings….
"In
the first place, therefore, the dialectic (sic) method of interpretation
demands that all phenomena be considered in their indissoluble relations; in
the second place, that they be considered in their state of motion….
Since everything in the world is in a state
of change, and indissolubly connected with everything else, we
must draw the necessary conclusions for the social sciences….
"The basis of all things is therefore the
law of change, the law of constant motion. Two philosophers
particularly (the ancient Heraclitus and the modern Hegel…) formulated this law
of change, but they did not stop there. They also set up the question of the
manner in which the process operates. The answer they discovered was that
changes are produced by constant internal contradictions, internal struggle.
Thus, Heraclitus declared: 'Conflict is the mother of all happenings,' while
Hegel said: 'Contradiction is the power that moves things.'
"...As we already know that all things
change, all things are 'in flux', it is certain that such an absolute state
of rest cannot possibly exist. We must therefore reject a
condition in which there is no 'contradiction between opposing and colliding
forces' no disturbance of equilibrium, but only an absolute immutability….
"In other words, the world consists of
forces, acting many ways, opposing each other. These forces are balanced for
a moment in exceptional cases only. We then have a state of 'rest', i.e., their
actual 'conflict' is concealed. But if we change only one of these forces,
immediately the 'internal contradictions' will be revealed, equilibrium will
be disturbed, and if a new equilibrium is again established, it will be on a new
basis, i.e., with a new combination of forces, etc. It follows that the 'conflict,'
the 'contradiction,' i.e., the antagonism of forces acting in various
directions, determines the motion of the system…." [Bukharin (1925),
pp.63-67,
72-74. Bold emphases added.
Some paragraphs merged.]
[Several
more quotations from the dialectical classics and other DM-texts that echo
the same sentiments can be found
here. (No irony intended.)]
Unfortunately, the evidence supporting these
hyper-bold claims is
conspicuous by its absence, as we discovered in Essay
Two. Despite this, the authority of
assorted Idealists and Mystics
(like Heraclitus and Hegel) seems to be sufficient for DM-theorists.
However, the uncontroversial admission (above) that change is a widespread phenomenon,
throughout nature and society, doesn't amount to
any sort of concession to DM, since 'dialectical change' is supposed to be caused
by, or is the result of,
'internal contradictions'. Now, that doctrine has been demolished in Essay Eight
Parts One and
Two. In
Essay Eleven Part One, Heraclitean change
has also been destructively criticised.
So, non-dialecticians can agree with dialecticians on the reality of change; where they differ is over
the cause of change: 'internal contradictions', and perhaps also the
dogmatic claim that everything in reality constantly changes in every respect,
always.
It is worth underlining here that the denial of universal change
doesn't imply that everything is changeless; just that some things might be
(and probably are) changeless, and some things maybe aren't. [On this see
Note 11 and
Note 12.] Plainly, this is an empirical
question which can't be settled by appealing
to the
'authority' of a handful Idealist Philosophers and
Hermetic Mystics -- nor,
indeed, on
the basis of a
set of highly repetitive and dogmatic assertions.
Nevertheless, let us suppose
for the moment that some object,
B, possesses the following properties, qualities or relations:
B1,
B2,
B3,...,
Bn.
According to several of the above
dialectical worthies, all of these properties, qualities and relations must change
all the time (into what they change we are kept in the dark don't
-- other than that we are informed they
change into their 'opposites' -- i.e.,
into
not (B1,
B2,
B3,...,
Bn),
or perhaps (B1*,
B2*,
B3*,...,
Bn*),
where each term with an attached asterisk is the 'opposite' of the 'same' term
without one).
[However, even that possibility is closed off in
Essays Part Three and Eleven
Part One. Henceforth, to save
on needless repetition, I will simply call these properties, qualities or
relations, "properties".]
Nevertheless, while B changes it is
still
identical with itself. In order to see this, let us suppose that when each
property, Bi,
changes, it becomes, say, Bi*,
in the first instance, and then
Bi**
in the next, and so on. But, at any moment, B's identity will be given by
its set of properties (if we must view identity
traditionally). So, in the first case, for example, B will have changed into
{B1*,
B2*,
B3*,...,
Bn*}.
Hence, even though B has changed, it retains its changed identity.
In which case, as
long as B exists it is identical to itself (albeit, its changed self).
Consequently, viewed this way, identity is no enemy of change.
[Dialecticians often appeal to the existence
of UOs to defuse this sort of objection; that topic has been examined in Essays
Seven
and Eight Parts One and
Two.]
[UO = Unity of Opposites/Unities of
Opposites, depending on the context.]
Of course, the above scenario (which is
called Maximal Heracliteanism (or MAH) in Essay Eleven Part One -- link
below) might not be the interpretation of change that most dialecticians would
want to adopt (even though the DM-classicists quoted above seem to be sold on
it). If so, they should pause for thought before finally deciding. That is
because, if just one of the properties possessed by B -- say, Bk --
remains the same, even for a few
nanoseconds,
then the LOI must apply to it, and the dialectical game is up, for here we would have something that remained the
same, and is identical with itself, even if only momentarily.
By way of contrast, the maximalist option (i.e.,
MAH -- again, this is explained at the following link) has even worse consequences for DM; these
have been
set out in detail in Essay Eleven
Part One.
Either way, Heraclitus is no friend of
dialectics --
or, if he is, he is also its worst enemy.
A nice unity of opposites
there, one
feels!
---------------------------------------------------------
Of
course, only those
with the same
opinion about this as Marx, who take their philosophical cue from ordinary language, will be impressed
with the examples given earlier. On the other
hand, since ordinary language is the means of communication invented, preserved and
maintained by ordinary workers (as they interface with one another and the
material world), only those who prefer for non-materialist language --
for instance, those with an inexplicable fondness for the obscure terminology
concocted by Philosophers, or even worse, the jargon cooked up by Hegel -- over the
materially-grounded
vernacular will have reason to cavil. Annoyingly, those in that category be
doing so for identically the same ideologically-compromised reasons.
[On
that see, Essay Twelve (summary
here).]
Such is the
cunning of ordinary discourse.
[The
following material used to be in Note 6.]
-----------------------------------------------------
The use of ordinary
words for identity and
difference is
reassuringly varied
and can sometimes be bewilderingly complex. Consider the following (greatly shortened) list of examples:
E1: The same letter can appear in the
same word in different places, and in a different word in the same place (e.g.,
"t" can appear first and fourth in both "trite" and "trot").
A different letter
can appear in the same word, in the same or in a different place (e.g., if
"chien" and "dog" are counted as the same word in different languages, "c"
appears in the first place in the French word, and "d" in the same (i.e.,
the first)
place in the English word, and different letter, "d" and "g", appear in the
same English word). Moreover, the
same word, in the same or different place in the same or different sentence, can mean the same or
different things. For instance, consider Chomsky's example: "Pretty little girls' school"; the
word "pretty" can be taken in several ways, depending on how the whole phrase is
read, as can each of these sub-phrases: "Pretty little", "little girls'" and "Pretty little
girls'", to name but three), and different words, in the same or different places
can mean the same or different things (as in, "The striker hit the scab" and
"The scab was hit by the striker" (where the same words mean the same in
different places in two different sentences with the same sense, but the two
sentences with the same words mean two different things); and "The
striker hit the ball", where the same word could mean different things (i.e.,
"striker"
could mean a player on a Football (soccer) field or someone engaged in a strike).
Furthermore, the same word can mean different things at one and the same time to
two different people (e.g., if one of them reads it as a code word, on one
occasion), and different things to the same person at different times (if, say, their facility with the language concerned
improves).
Naturally, permutations like this can be knitted together endlessly to form
complex identity/equality sentences that we can all understand, given the right
level of concentration. For example, the same word could mean different things
to the same person at different times, but the same thing in different places,
while it could mean the same thing at the same time or at different times in the
same place or in different places to the same or different people (etc., etc.).
E2: The same numeral can appear in the
same place in the same number in different places at the same or different times
(e.g., the figure "9" in a mathematics book, or on a bank statement), or in the
same place in different numbers (as in 191 and 1911). Not only that, identically
the same numeral can appear in the same number in different places, where it
will have a different mode of signification (e.g., in 2500, 2450 and 2445; here
the same numeral, "5", means something different in each case, or in 191 and
1911, where the "9" appears in the same place (i.e., second from the left) but
means something different in each case, or where it appears in different places
(in the tens column and in the hundreds column) but could mean the same (i.e.,
if the "9" in 191 stood for 90 ten cent coins, and the "9" in 1911 stood for 900
one cent coins)). And the very same number can change in other ways even while
it stays the same -- for example, the numeral, "5", will stay the same but will
signify something different as other numerals are added in. So, in 50, the 5
stands for five tens. If another zero is added
(to yield 500), the very same 5 will now mean five hundreds, and so on. [The
reader is to imagine all this being typed in one go, say, into a calculator) so
that the very same figure "5" on the screen changes while it remains the same
as zeros are added.] Furthermore, the same numeral can
appear in the same sign in the same place and mean something different,
depending on how it is read (e.g., the numeral "1" in "10" could mean "one"
written in the tens column, or it could mean "one" written in the unitary power
of two column in
binary code, with the first "one" signifying "ten" and the
second indicating "two"). Or the
very same "2" on a clock face could signify 2am or 2pm. Or think of
the way that "1" can mean something different if it occurs in the same place in
01/02; in the first sense it could mean the 1st of February (if read by a UK
citizen), in the second,
the 2nd of January (if read by a US citizen). So, in the last few cases,
the very same thing could be identical in certain respects while being different or
unequal in others. Examples are easy to multiply. The same points (or different
ones) can be made about the same (or different) musical notes, dance steps,
gestures, works of art, signs, signals, symbols and noises.
E3: The same day of the week
occurs in the same place in different weeks, and for 24 hours on the same day in
the same week. And it can occur in the same place in different weeks belonging
to the same
or different months. The reader, no doubt, can supply his/her own complex
permutations as the temporal vocabulary employed is changed -- as in: same/different
second, minute, hour, fortnight, year, decade, century, millennium, geological
age,
eon…
E4: The same book can appear in
different libraries in the same place, or in different libraries in different
places, and a different book can appear in the same or different libraries in
the same or different places. The same copy of The New York Times can be
read by different people in the same place at the same time, or in different
places at the same time, or in the same place at different times -- and it can be
read by the same person in different places at the same or different times, and
so on. The same can happen with TV programmes, films, photographs, music scores, works of art,
e-mails, computer games, texts, printed adverts, and plays.
E5: The same worker could join the same
strike at different times, or different strikes at the same time (if he/she has
two jobs and both are in dispute). And different workers could join the same or
different strikes at the same or different times in the same or different
places. And the same strike could spread to different places, involving
different workers at the same or different times. The same or different cheques could be made
valueless if the same Bank goes bust, and the same person could be made an
orphan at the same time if both their parents are killed in the
same or different accidents at the same or different times.
E6: The same element in the
periodic table can appear in different parts of the universe at the same or
different times, and in the same or different compounds at the same or different
times. The same geodesic can be traversed by different particles, at the same or
different times. The same inertial frame can contain the same or different
objects at the same or different times, and different inertial frames can
contain the same or different objects at the same or different times. The same
(or different) considerations apply to packing cases, bags, holes, tins of beans, garages, flats, sheds,
houses, cars, taxis, trains, aeroplanes, ships, buses, submarines, rockets...
And the same or different DM-fan could take exception
to the same or different example(s) above.
Try expressing
any of that in Hegel-speak!
But it's a doddle in the vernacular.
We needn't concentrate, either, on examples
that some might still consider "abstract"; two (physical) ink marks on a page (two
letter "A"s, again) which aren't even identical in shape or size (i.e., "a" and "A")
could be identically positioned between other non-identical letters. So, in
"pat" and "PAT", each letter "A" is sandwiched
identically between two other
non-identical letters (i.e., both are in the middle). Large or small physical differences
between these
letters, and any other incidental changes they might undergo (which don't
affect their
relative position) -- such as a change of colour on your screen, or on the page
-- won't alter the fact that they are identically placed
between two other letters. Indeed, the spacing of these letters could be
grossly unequal, but that wouldn't affect the fact that these letters are placed identically in
the middle.
[To be sure, the gap between the
letters might be different, but that wouldn't alter the fact that both are
identically placed in the middle. And by "middle" is meant "having one letter
either side", not "located at or near the geometric centre".]
Now, the position of ink marks on a page
(or even those electronically produced as pixels on your screen) isn't abstract,
it is eminently material --, so much so that one or both can be
obliterated by the non-dialectical use either of some
Tipp-ex or
the delete key.
And
deletion isn't the removal of an abstraction.
[Alternatively, just try deleting an
abstraction!]
As
noted elsewhere, ordinary and
technical or even semi-technical languages have seemingly limitless capacities for allowing
their users to express complex and
subtle differences in meaning way beyond that permitted by the obscure and
lifeless language Hegel inflicted on his readers. This shouldn't surprise
anyone; ordinary,
technical and semi-technical languages have been created over countless centuries
by working people and/or scientists in their interaction
with the world and with one another. These systems of communication reflect our
species' complex inter-relationship that each individual, class or group
has with others, and with changing reality --
and which contain our best guide to identity, sameness and
difference, and much else besides.
In contrast, Hegel's opaque, jargon-bound language reflects
alienated, ruling-class
forms-of-thought and material interests -- cobbled-together as part of a dubious, class-compromised
intellectual tradition that stretches back well over 2500 years --, and which (in
Hegel's case) was invented by
an individual who, in his theoretical activity, was far more concerned with his relation to the
world of ideas than he was with his interaction with ordinary human
beings, objects and
processes in the material and social world. Small wonder then that his ideas
can't cope with
changing reality.
------------------------------------
Clearly, Trotsky and Hegel created serious
problems for themselves when they erected an insecure 'logical' edifice on such an
insubstantial
linguistic
base. This predicament was further compounded by their choice of an extremely
narrow range of examples when compared with the countless available to them (and to ordinary speakers
-- on that see above),
which permit talk of equality, sameness, identity and difference with ease.
Equally annoyingly: Traditional Philosophers have in general done exactly the same
(irony intended).6
"Equal" And "Identical" Not Identical
As
will no doubt be apparent to any competent user of language, "equal" and
"identical" aren't synonymous. Several examples given above illustrate this
fact; the distinction can also be seen if "equal" is substituted for "identical"
in either of the following sentences:
S3: NN and NM are identical twins.
S4: The money that the victim
of the racial assault received was equal to that stolen in the assault.
The use of "equal" in S3 would make it
meaningless (viz., "NN and NM are equal twins"), and the presence of "identical"
in S4 would change its sense entirely:
S4a:
The money that the victim of
the racial assault received was identical to that stolen in the assault.
Clearly, the implication of S4a is that the very same notes and coins were
returned, whereas S4 itself would be true if the money the victim received was
merely
the same value as the money taken (perhaps presented to her in cheque form).
Mathematical Equality
Vs Mathematical Identity
Moreover, we needn't restrict our attention
to ordinary sentences (even though
Trotsky himself did); the above distinction is found in
mathematics. Consider the following:
S5: x2
- x - 42 = 0
⇒
x = 7, or x = -6.
S6: cos3θ + sinθ
º
4sinθcos2θ.
[In S6, "º"
is the sign for identity or equivalence.]
Nobody confuses "=" with "º"
in mathematics. Moreover, in S5, just because x = 7 or x = -6, that doesn't
mean x is identical
with
either -- otherwise it could never stand for another number (as it does in, say,
x2
+ x - 56 = 0
⇒
x = -7, or x = 8)
--
and, of course, if it couldn't stand for a different number, it wouldn't be called
a variable.
Worse still: two or more identicals can be equal to, but different from, the same
identical. For instance, while 0 = 0, it is also true that 0 + 0 = 0, and 0 x 0
= 0 -- even though it is also true that neither 0 + 0 nor 0 x 0 are identical to 0,
nor to one another. Even worse, some things can change even while
they remain the same. For example, it is relatively easy to transform 1/√n into √n/n
-- as follows: 1/√n x
√n/√n
º
√n/n. But, 1/√n doesn't even look like √n/n,
although the two
are identical: 1/√n
º
√n/n. So, here we have change with no change!
In which case,
equality and identity don't prevent change, nor do they even imply that things can't change
-- at least,
not in
mathematics.7
In MFL (i.e., outside of mathematics), the
distinction between these two is even more pronounced. The "=" sign is
used as a relational expression (which is legitimately flanked only by Proper
Names and other singular terms, such as
Definite Descriptions), whereas "º" is a
truth-functional operator (and can be flanked only by propositions or
clauses).
Of
course, these distinctions aren't the same as those we find in ordinary language
(no irony intended), nor yet those in Traditional Philosophy -- more on that below.
["Truth-functional"
is technical term that expresses a logical link between propositions, the
alteration of which changes the conditions under which they are true or false.
For those not too familiar with MFL, I
have posted a simplified explanation of these and other terms,
here.]
[MFL = Modern Formal
Logic.]
It could be objected once again that these examples are all
abstract; in which case, the reader is re-directed to my
earlier response to this
objection.
So, the question
returns: why did Trotsky make a claim about equality when he was trying to discuss identity?
The fact that he ignored all of the classical formulations of the LOI (such as
Leibniz's) only compounds the problem.8
Perhaps this was an oversight? But, this glaring omission -- coupled with
Trotsky's
subsequent and rather odd digression over bags of
sugar and eye-glasses, as well as his failure to consider the wider use of words
for identity in the language of everyday life
-- tends to suggest that he didn't really understand the very thing he was criticizing: identity.8a
It
therefore looks like Trotsky tried to undermine the LOI by appealing to a
principle (equality) that wasn't identical with it
(irony intended).
Trotsky Changes The Subject
One answer to this
'puzzle' might lie in the fact the change of subject recorded in S1 allowed
Trotsky to go on to raise what turn out to be largely irrelevant claims
points about things like bags of sugar. Because the latter involve objects that can be measured (as opposed to
their being counted), the interpretation of the "A"s in S1 as
quantities of sugar heavily biased Trotsky's criticism -- it allowed him to
focus his attention on one particular aspect of equality that isn't
necessarily connected with identity.
S1: A is equal
to A.
For example, one and the same bag of sugar
could be 'self-identical' and equal to itself in weight even while it was
unequal in weight to a second seemingly identical bag. [How this is
possible will become clear as the argument unfolds.] And, two different
bags of sugar could be equal in weight (even if only momentarily), as far as our
most sensitive instruments are able to detect. Not only that, two separate bags could
both have their weights changing in exactly the way Trotsky described (no
irony intended); the first bag could have its weight falling, the second rising. At some point, therefore, their two weights could
momentarily be identical. How could these possibilities be ruled out?
Furthermore,
in two separate piles, bag B in pile one, and bag C in pile two, could
be the heaviest in their respective heaps. In that case, each bag would be
equally the heaviest in their respective groupings while still being non-identical
in weight with one another. No doubt the reader can imagine other cases Trotsky failed to
consider.
Clearly, Trotsky's analysis blurred these clear distinctions
-– those,
incidentally, that are easily drawn in ordinary language (indeed, as
they have been here), and which are readily understood, even by working-class children.
More importantly, Trotsky clearly failed to
notice that even though objects might vary in weight, they could still be
identical in number. Indeed, as is patently obvious, any object is
identical to itself in number (and each is identical in number with any other
single object, too). Moreover, close inspection over an extended period of time will
fail to reveal any relevant difference with respect to their number, even
if other aspects of the said object(s) changed markedly (such as their weight). Trotsky overlooked this
obvious counter-example to his claim that things can't remain
the same while they change: in at least this sense most do.
Of course, it could be objected here that not only
do some things divide as they change, others merge together; in such cases,
their number wouldn't be identical from moment to moment. That is undeniable.
However, descriptions of divisions and mergers depend on the said objects being
identifiable first, which process clearly depends on the
application of the LOI. If we can't count objects before or after they divide
or merge, we are
surely in no position to judge that they have changed in this respect. Since
counting depends on identification under a given general term (so that we can
say we have, for instance, 2 bags of sugar -- or one amoeba, then two),
that aspect of this objection
itself depends on an application of the LOI as a rule of language.8b
Anyway, the above
comments still apply to objects that don't divide or merge. Plainly,
there are uses of numerical identity that aren't susceptible to this objection
(concerning objects that divide or merge). For example, if we consider, say, the
number of volumes of
Das Kapital, it is clear that there are just as many volumes today
as there were 100 years ago (viz., three -- that is, if we don't count
Theories of Surplus Value; six if we do). Even though the number of copies
of Das Kapital has increased markedly over the years, and most
copies will have changed markedly in the meantime, the number of volumes of Das
Kapital remains steadfastly fixed on three (or six). Hence, the following statements are true:
L1: The number of volumes of Das
Kapital in the year 1900 is identical to the number of volumes of Das
Kapital in 2019 (namely, three (or six)).
L2: The number of volumes of Das
Kapital on any one day in 2021 is identical to the number of volumes of
Das Kapital on the same day in 2021 (namely, three (or six)).
L3: A is identical to A.
In L1, we have identity over time and in L2
identity at any moment in time.
But, even though the "A"s in L3 stand
for "The number of volumes of Das Kapital on any one day in 2021"
(when interpreted as they are in L2), it is clear that it isn't possible to map
the same "A"s consistently onto anything analogous in L1. That is because the
first "A" would have to stand for "The number of volumes of Das
Kapital in the year 1900", the second for "the number of volumes of Das
Kapital in 2019", which phrases are clearly not typographically
identical, even though they are both part of sentences that express a simple rule we
have for identity.
This
demonstrates that Trotsky's narrow interpretation of the variable letter "A"s
(in L3 or S1) fails to capture the much wider use of words we have for identity in ordinary language --
some of which were considered above, and several more will be examined below. Even so,
both L1 and L2 surely count as further counter-examples to Trotsky's
ill-considered charges
against the LOI.
It is also worth recalling that the volumes
of Das Kapital are just as material as bags of sugar.
Again, it could be objected that number
is an abstract property of objects, making the above points irrelevant.
But, according to Lenin, anything that enjoys objective existence external to the
mind is material:
"[T]he sole
'property' of matter with
whose recognition philosophical; materialism is bound up is the property of
being an objective reality, of existing outside our mind." [Lenin
(1972), p.311.]
Well, the three volumes
of Das Kapital
surely exist just as objectively "outside the mind" as do pound bags of sugar.
Moreover, if Trotsky is allowed to refer to the measurable
properties of bags of sugar -- such as their weight, which will also be recorded
by the use of several numbers --, critics of the above
can't consistently object to a similar
appeal to their countable properties.
[Anyway, 'Abstract Identity' will be
examined below.]
In addition, consider the following perfectly
normal examples of the use of words associated with identity:
L4:
The number of months of the year is identical to the number of
Apostles.
L5: The number of elements lighter
than
Helium
is identical to the number of authors of
The Proletarian Revolution and the Renegade
Kautsky.
L6:
The
Morning Star is identical to the Evening Star.
L7:
The population of the United Kingdom at noon on any day in January 2021, is identical to
a whole number somewhere between 50 and 80 million.
L8: The point of all these
counterexamples is identical in each case: to refute Trotsky's criticisms of the
LOI.
L9:
The stance of the majority Trotskyists is identical to that of Marx on
the following issue:
The emancipation of the working class is
an act of the workers themselves.
L10: The editor of
International Socialism
in 2009 is identical to the author of
A People's History Of The World.
L11: Mount
Godwin-Austen
is
identical to K2.9
Once
again, sentences like these can be multiplied indefinitely. As a highly
competent user of language, Trotsky can't have been unaware of this. So why did
he feign ignorance? Was his analysis of this 'concept' biased by an extremely
narrow focus on a specific
philosophical use of words for identity -- derived from that notorious Idealist, Hegel -– and one that didn't match their application in ordinary language?
As we
will see, these rapidly-forming suspicions aren't easy to dismiss.
Trotsky's Argument
Precisely What
Is Trotsky Denying?
However, returning to Trotsky's
actual argument:
"In
reality 'A' is not equal to 'A'. This is easy to prove if we observe these two
letters under a lens -– they are quite different to each other…." [Trotsky
(1971), p.63.]
But, not even a lens-wielding Trotsky would
consider making the same point (no irony intended) in relation to the following legitimate
example of the use of the "=" sign:
S7: 2(x + 1) = 2x + 2.
[S1: A is equal to
A.
S1a: A is equal to
itself.]
[I am concerned here with Trotsky's use of "=", not with a more
proper use of "º".]
But, if not, why not? In S7,
the two sides of the equation don't even look similar (with or without the aid of a
magnifying glass!), quite unlike the two "A"s in S1. Despite that, few would question the fact that the left-hand side of S7 is still equal to the right-,
for all x. In which case, this use of "=" isn't susceptible to Trotsky's 'microscope argument'. That suggests this
particular point about the "A"s in S1 was equally misguided (irony not
intended, again).
It could be objected that S7 is an 'abstract'
example, which exempts it from such criticism. But, Trotsky's point about the
two "A"s in S1 is no less 'abstract'. Initially for Trotsky, the "A"s in S1 were
merely letters. And yet, if the symbols in S7 were to be interpreted in the same
light, his lens-inspired criticism would make no sense. Who in their left mind
would use a magnifying glass to check whether 2(x + 1) is exactly equal to 2x +
2 in
form? And who would ever employ S7-type sentences in mathematics if the
use of an equal
sign was only legitimate when the
symbols on either side of it had to be identical in shape, or
microscopically indistinguishable under a lens? When employing such sentences we surely advert to
the rule they express, not the physical form of the letters they happen to
assume.
Hence, despite the fact that the symbols appearing in S7 look totally different
to the naked eye, no one would question their role in expressing a simple
algebraic rule.
In that case, why did Trotsky use such a crass
argument against the expression of a logico-linguistic rule in S1? If mathematicians
were to scrutinise each other's work in the same crude way, they
would surely dispense with what we now call "proof", and resort to inspecting
alleged 'proofs' with magnifying
glasses. Mathematical advancement would then depend, not on proof, but on
proof-reading!
Trotsky Has This
Base Covered
-- Or Has He?
Some might
object and claim that Trotsky had anticipated
this point when he said:
"[Concerning]
the proposition to 'A' is equal to 'A'[:] This postulate is accepted as an axiom
for a multitude of practical human actions and elementary generalisations. But
in reality 'A' is not equal to 'A'. This is easy to prove if we observe these
two letters under a lens -– they are quite different from each other." [Trotsky
(1971), p.63.]
Hence, it could be argued that even though mathematicians deal with "abstract
concepts", the symbols they use to express them are constrained by limitations imposed on anyone operating in this world. In that case,
since no two symbols could be absolutely identical, Trotsky's point
remains valid -- or so this argument might go.
However, in the vast majority of cases in
mathematics symbols like "=" and "º"
occur between symbols that don't even look remotely the same. Several
examples were given above. Anyone who doubts this should consult a handful of mathematics
texts (of any level of difficulty equal to or above Intermediate Standard). There they will find few examples of schematic sentences like S1, but countless like S5 or S6.
S5: x2
- x - 42 = 0 ⇒
x = 7, or x = -6.
S6: cos3θ + sinθ
º
4sinθcos2θ.
Trotsky's analysis
thus fails completely to account for this use of symbols. In fact, not only are
mathematicians not really interested in "approximate equality", the notion of "abstract identity"
-- if any sense can be made of it -- is itself parasitic on
ordinary identity, or on a surreptitious material application of the LOI (as a
rule, not as a truth), as we shall soon
discover.
Bags Of
Sugar In Fact Refute
Trotsky
Trotsky's Answer
[In what
follows, I am assuming the sugar in question isn't loose, but is held in
container or a bag of some sort while it is being weighed -- clearly that would
reduce any effect the environment had on the sugar itself, etc. This minor
adjustment does not, I think, affect the points Trotsky wanted to make. If
anyone thinks differently, please contact
me and explain why you disagree.]
Again, some readers might still think that Trotsky
had anticipated these relatively minor quibbles, since he went on to consider a
possible response that
the two "A"s in S1 might really be "symbols for equal quantities, for
instance, a pound of sugar".
S1: A is equal to
A.
S1a: A is equal to
itself.
In response, he pointed out that in
the real world a pound of sugar is never equal to a pound of sugar, since any
apparent equality will vanish upon closer examination:
"But, one can object, the
question is not the size or the form of the letters, since they are only symbols
for equal quantities, for instance, a pound of sugar. The objection is beside
the point; in reality a pound of sugar is never equal to a pound of sugar -– a
more delicate scale always discloses a difference. Again one can object: but a
pound of sugar is equal to itself. Neither is true (sic) -– all bodies change
uninterruptedly in size, weight, colour etc. They are never equal to themselves.
A sophist will respond that a pound of sugar is equal to itself at 'any given
moment'…. How should we really conceive the word 'moment'? If it is an
infinitesimal interval of time, then a pound of sugar is subjected during the
course of that 'moment' to inevitable changes." [Trotsky
(1971), p.64.]
Mere
Guesswork?
The problem
with this is that Trotsky was clearly guessing here. He had no way of knowing
for sure that greater accuracy in weighing would always reveal detectable differences.
Indeed, there are several possibilities that
he failed to consider. For example, the weighing scales themselves could alter
slightly, which could be the real cause of the inferred change in the weight of the sugar.
Indeed, the weighing scales could alter to such an extent that they
compensated for the change in the weight of the sugar, so that in
the end no
overall difference was detectable. How could Trotsky rule either of these out? Plainly, he
couldn't do so if constant change -- including that experienced by
instruments -- is a central postulate of dialectics. How could he be so
sure that the hypothetical differences he says must exist between these bags (or
between a bag and itself) weren't artefacts of the machines themselves -- or of
some other ambient cause -- as opposed to these being genuine phenomena representing
actual changes in the weight of the sugar? For all he knew
the sugar itself could remain the same for a few seconds (or minutes), with any
apparent change that had been detected being the
result of other incipient factors. In fact, as seems clear, Trotsky could
only be 100% confident that any subsequently detectable differences were always
and only the result of changes to the sugar itself because of an a priori
stipulation to that effect. And, as seems plain,
a stipulation is different from an
imposition on nature in name alone.10
Of course, that doesn't
mean Trotsky was wrong in this case. No doubt if a series of identical
experiments -- note the use of the highlighted word here -- were
conducted, differences would be detected. But, given Trotsky's stated views on
change he would have had no way of knowing whether any of them were a result of
changes in the scales, the sugar, the eyesight of the observer, the relative
strength of the surrounding gravitational field, or a combination of one or more of these
--, or, indeed, whether or not they
were attributable other proximate causes.
Some might think
the above considerations
are irrelevant;
if
things change, who cares what causes it? But, Trotsky is here appealing to the
results of an experiment
-- one that he clearly didn't carry out himself -- to substantiate a
hyper-bold claim about all objects everywhere
in the entire universe, for all of time. It now turns out that because of that thesis itself, it might
not be possible to confirm what he said. If so, we are still owed an
explanation as to why Trotsky thought it correct to say
everything changes all the time, when this thesis can't actually be verified. And
this
isn't just because
many of the above complications could cancel each other out, or mask a temporary lack of change
in other things, it is because we don't have access to the vast majority of regions of space
and time, and never will!10a
And,
as we are about to find out, any attempt to plug the gaps in
Trotsky's argument only succeed in punching even bigger holes in it.
Trotsky's Instructions
-- Followed Exactly And To The Letter?
As
we have seen, Trotsky's argument partly revolves around the accuracy of measuring a
pound bag of sugar (etc.). However, he then rather boldly extrapolated from a few (theoretical)
observations about local conditions connected with weighing that sugar to
hyper-bold, general claims about all
objects for all of time:
"[A]ll bodies change uninterruptedly in size,
weight, colour etc. They are never equal to themselves…. [T]he axiom 'A'
is equal to 'A' signifies that a thing is equal to itself if it does not change,
that is, if it does not exist…. For concepts there also exists 'tolerance' which
is established not by formal logic…, but by the dialectical logic issuing
from the axiom that everything is always changing…. Hegel in his
Logic established a series of laws: change of quantity into quality,
development through contradiction, conflict and form, interruption of
continuity, change of possibility into inevitability, etc…. All this
demonstrates, in passing, that our methods of thought, both formal logic and the
dialectic, are not arbitrary constructions of our reason but rather expressions
of the actual inter-relationships in nature itself. In this sense the
universe is permeated with 'unconscious' dialectics." [Trotsky
(1971),
pp.64-66; 107. Emphases added.]
But: how could Trotsky possibly have
known any of this? His only 'evidence' appears to have been this thought experiment!
Again, it could be objected that Trotsky was
merely drawing out the consequences of accumulated human experience of change,
deriving reasonable conclusions from thousands of years of our growing knowledge
of the
nature and society, much of it scientific.
In response to this (and in addition to the
points made in this subsection) it might be worth trying
to reconstruct the reasoning behind Trotsky's claims. Presumably he was arguing
as follows:
T1: Anyone who performs a weighing experiment
exactly as
specified -- who repeats the same procedures -- will find that no two
measurements are exactly the same.
But this imputed argument -- if it
is indeed his -- would embroil Trotsky in having to invoke the LOI yet again, only
now applied to his own
instructions, and hence to the measurements required
by anyone who wanted to test his claims (brought out by the highlighted
words in T1).
Clearly, these instructions would have to be carried
out identically and to the letter each time if they were to count as a verification of Trotsky's
predictions -- only
now aimed at demonstrating that the LOI is
defective after all, even when applied to instructions!
Of
course, given Trotsky's strictures on the LOI, no two attempts to carry out any
set of instructions would ever be the same. In that case, there would be no
accurate way to test his or anyone else's predictions!
[Once more, an appeal to
"approximately identical instructions" has been batted out of the park,
below.]
On the
other hand, if Trotsky had been faced with someone who claimed that at least two
of
their measurements were
identical,
he could only have responded in one or more of the following ways:
(1) Insisting
that this experimenter must have been mistaken.
(2) Pointing out that the machines used weren't accurate enough.
(3) Maintaining that his instructions hadn't been carried out exactly and to the letter.
(4) Arguing that identically the same experiments
hadn't been performed each
time.
In other words, in the absence of a mistake (and if the same results were
recorded on more accurate scales -- i.e., ruling out (1) and (2) above), Trotsky would only be able to criticise the
above
reported experimental verification of the LOI by an appeal
to that very same 'law',
but now applied to his
own instructions! [I.e., options (3) and (4).]
Hence, in order to counter
results that would disconfirm
his
predictions in the above manner
Trotsky would have to argue that only those who followed his instructions
identically and to the letter
could
disprove the LOI!
The irony
here is quite plain: identically
performed experiments are required to prove that nothing is identical with
anything else -- including experiments!
To be sure, anyone who only
roughly
followed his instructions (who was, perhaps, content with a wishy-washy,
"approximate-within-certain-limits" dialectical-sort-of-equality) would probably
find that many (if not most) of their measurements gave identical results
for the weight of these bags of sugar -- thus 'confirming' this 'law'!
In which case, Trotsky's predictions about
such objects would end up being refuted by anyone who adopted the
diluted DM-version of the LOI! Such experimenters would succeed in
confirming the absolute form of the 'LOI by employing an approximate version of it!
A use of 'approximate identity' would show that two or more bags of sugar
all weighed the same, and, indeed, that a bag of sugar weighed as much as
itself.
Conversely,
the more exactly an experimenter adhered to Trotsky's instructions,
the more likely it would be that they
detected non-identical weights.
In that case, they would succeed in disconfirming the absolute version of
this 'law' by applying an exact copy of Trotsky's instructions!
So, by reverse irony, they would refute Trotsky in practice by doing exactly
as he indicated, using the LOI applied to his instructions in order to disconfirm it
when
applied to bags of sugar!
In
short: relying on evidence alone,
Trotsky was certainly not justified in projecting his conclusions as far as he
thought he could --, i.e., across the entire universe for all of time -- not least
because there is no evidence that he performed these experiments himself.
And anyone who did, or who might perform them would be caught in the above
practical refutation of his criticisms of that 'law' whenever they performed
such experiments exactly as he instructed.
[It is worth
adding that the
development of science has at least suggested a much more cautious approach
should be taken to theory and evidence. On that, see
Note 11 and
Note 12,
below.]
Hence,
Trotsky's claim
that
all objects, everywhere,
change
all the time, if extrapolated beyond the aforementioned conventions and
scientific facts, would
transform
the LOI into a metaphysical truth -- that is, into a 'fundamental truth'
supposedly valid for all of space and time.
But, there could be no body of evidence
large enough to support
an extrapolation as bold as this --
or,
at least,
none that wasn't also based on those very
same
conventions relating to identically performed experiments and the use of
ordinary words for identity.
Extrapolation beyond these -- by means of them -- to universal theses
that are
applicable everywhere and everywhen would convert them into universal
and changeless truths -- the very thing Trotsky affected to disavow.
In that case, Trotsky
would have to appeal
(explicitly or implicitly)
to the LOI as a universal truth in order to justify his
general conclusions about everything in existence behaving exactly as he
said it would --, for example, with every human being measuring objects identically
throughout all of human history, in order to show that no one could actually
do this, because of his criticism of a 'law' they would have to have used in
order to do just that!
So, any evidence (either from the past or the present) to which DM-theorists
might appeal in order to undermine this 'law' would automatically call into question the methods by
means of which
that evidence had been collected, processed and checked. Without the LOI applied as a rule
of language, or as a rule guiding practice, no one would be able repeat the same
experiments to verify, or refute, earlier results, or even check measurements
and hence confirm the
accuracy of Trotsky's predictions.
Nor would they be able to learn to use the very same
theories that others had used, or appeal to the very same 'law', or
its alleged refutation (in the
way that, say, Trotsky and Hegel claimed to have done).
Without this 'law' applied as a rule of
language, or one that helped guide experiment, there would be no conceptual space within which
science or ordinary practice could develop --, and thus no reliable data, no
settled theories --, for anyone to begin even to think about confirming the DM-hypothesis of
universal change.
In
which
case, there could be no science or philosophy that questioned the application of this 'law'
as a rule of language, or of practice, while still hoping to remain viable.
That, of
course, helps explain the
source of the difficulties
highlighted
above
(in connection with the postulated refutation of
Trotsky's predictions about the weight of a bag of sugar); it also
reveals why Hegel got into such a
mess over his attempt to half accept and
half reject this 'law',
and why this entire topic became such a puzzle to
him and his epigones.
If this 'law' is treated as a metaphysical truth (which has generally been the
approach adopted by Traditional Theorists) -- i.e., as a 'necessary truth' --, then its
falsehood becomes impossible to state (as we have just seen, and as we will
continue to see throughout this Essay), at
least in comprehensible language, or in language that doesn't implicitly rely
on this very 'law' to state anything at all.10b
Of course, the 'truth' of this 'law' doesn't seem (to some) to be at all
trivial. If
it is viewed
(traditionally)
as a 'law' that is said to depict, or determine,
the fundamental nature of everything in existence,
then it appears (to
Hegelians and DM-fans)
to rule out change. But even then, this 'defect' proves impossible
to express in any language that
doesn't also rely on
this very 'law',
only
now
operating as a rule governing the use of words to make that very point! (Again,
as we have just seen.)
Alternatively, if this 'law' is viewed rightly as a rule of language, or of
practice (without which humanity couldn't have developed a single coherent
idea), then these pseudo-problems over 'identity' simply vanish. On that basis, the LOI
isn't a universal truth because of what Hegel or anyone else said about it;
it isn't
a truth to begin with!
That is because it is a rule (and a
rather badly stated rule
about our use of words for identity, sameness or difference, too),
it can't be true or false, only practical or impractical, useful or
useless.
In
fact, as we have seen, it is impractical -- or, rather, it is the height of
folly -- even to attempt to reject this rule.
In that case, without a clear idea of how to use
words for identity (etc.), it would be impossible even for DM-theorists to
begin to wonder whether or not our words were approximately stable from moment-to-moment, or if they altered in other alarming ways. If the LOI is rejected
(as a rule of language, or of practice) --
or if it is held to be an 'approximate
truth'
-- then all of the above points will have their place.
For example,
in order to be able to say whether or not something
was
true (or 'partially true'), we would need to know how to use the word "truth" in
the same way from moment-to-moment (why that is so will become clearer as this
argument proceeds), just as we would also have to know the same with respect to
our other words for identity, sameness and difference. Without some notion as to
what counts as identically the same employment in all these cases, we couldn't even begin to
say what would constitute an approximation to anything whatsoever, or, indeed,
in what way something fell short of a standard that presupposed the applicability
of words we have for identity (etc.).
[Incidentally, I have
employed "know how to use" a certain word in a pragmatic sense; there is no
suggestion that we apply
language
according to some theory we supposedly hold or follow. In fact, I have borrowed this locution from
Gilbert Ryle. On that, see here.]
Now, this fundamentally important point sailed right over Hegel's head, and it
seems that that is also the case with Engels, Lenin, Trotsky and other
DM-theorists. They regarded the LOI as a truth (even if it was one that the
"abstract understanding" employed uncritically, or which was valid
"only within certain limits"). But, it can't be a truth (for the reasons outlined above); our
use of words for identity express rules
constitutive our ability to utter sentences that we can even so much as begin
to regard as true or false (should we so choose).
[Incidentally, the above isn't a 'transcendental argument', merely a reminder that we have
no choice but to use words
to express our thoughts, and we may only do certain things with such words
because of
contingent facts about our social history and our physical constitution. On
this, see here and
here,
where I enter into this topic in
more detail.]
So,
this 'law', applied as a rule of language (or of practice), has to be employed
even to make the point that there are such things as approximate truths
(since anyone doing this would have to at least use the word "truth" in a
consistent way to make that
very point!); in which case, this 'law' can
neither be true nor false itself.
And this is what makes the comments of dialecticians
in this area valueless, just as it is also why their ideas collapse
so readily into incoherence.
All this shows why an appeal to human
experience since the beginning of time, on its own, is irrelevant. Empirical evidence
can't be used to attack the LOI
without that attack implicitly employing that very same 'law' as a rule
of language, or as a practical rule applied to experiments, the use of
instruments, Trotsky's own writings, and those of relevant scientists (etc.).
But, when
the LOI is
deployed in this manner in an attempt to expose its alleged
empirical limitations (à
la Trotsky) -- or to reveal its supposed theoretical short-comings (à
la
Hegel) --,
that attempt itself will self-destruct. For
if that 'law' (applied as a rule) is unsafe, then so are the methods used gather
any evidence aimed at questioning it, and so are the arguments used to
undermine it.
Which
is indeed what we have seen.
[More on this in
Note 15, below. See also
Note 13.]
Naturally, a grudging acceptance of the
above (linguistic and socially-sanctioned) conventions -- on the following lines "Ok, so it's a
rule, but that doesn't show that objects in the real world obey it; in
fact, they don't, they change all the time" -- would have the opposite effect.
It would involve dialecticians
using criteria that delineate the conditions required for the performance of
identical, but real experiments in this world (etc.) in order to confirm,
for example, Trotsky's point about a bag of sugar -- which would undermine
their own ideal
'thought experiments' aimed at revealing the alleged deficiencies of the LOI.
Of
course, it is up to such individuals whether or not they prefer
ideal 'thought experiments' to the identically performed, real experiments
carried out in this world to test their ideas, which, once they had been performed to
the letter, would, in that very act, refute such ill-considered 'thought experiments'
- again as e have just seen!
Now, DM-theorists might sincerely believe
that all objects constantly change, but that is all this will ever
remain: a mere belief, an act of faith. There could be no conceivable
body of evidence in favour of this leap of faith that wasn't itself dependent on conventions of
measurement, counting and comparing,
which can't
themselves
be subject to
Trotsky's
(or Hegel's) strictures.
And, as we will
soon see, that is why both Hegel and
Trotsky ended up having to use this 'law' (implicitly) in their futile endeavour to undermine it, and
why they both wound up, in practice, refuting their own criticisms of it.
Beyond this, the idea that reality is in the
grip of a universal 'Heraclitean Flux' is supported by nothing more than an
unfounded extrapolation from a few badly-worded 'thought experiments',
themselves based on a laughably superficial understanding of a seriously
mis-identified 'law'.
[Having said that, this doesn't commit the present writer to the opposite view
that nothing changes! Once again, this is an empirical matter to be settled by
evidence, not a priori stipulation or the musings of a confused Christian
mystic.]
Yet Another Misidentification
All
this, of course,
is quite independent of the fact that Trotsky seems to have confused the LOI
with something else completely different (no irony intended):
"Every worker knows that it is impossible to make
two completely equal objects. In the elaboration of a bearing-brass into cone
bearings, a certain deviation is allowed for the cones which should not,
however, go beyond certain limits…. By observing the norms of tolerance, the
cones are considered as being equal. ('A' is equal to 'A')…. Every individual is
a dialectician to some extent or other, in most cases, unconsciously."
[Trotsky (1971),
pp.65,
106.]
From this it is clear that Trotsky misconstrued his own version
of the LOI! If he had wanted to direct our attention to the lack of identity
between two different objects (the two "cone bearings" in the above
passage) he should have used the following
schema:
W1: A is equal to B.
But not:
W2: A is equal to A.
In the quotation above, Trotsky referred to the manufacture
of "cone bearings" in his argument against the unrestricted application
of his own simplified version of the LOI. Here, he was clearly interpreting
the two "A"s in W2 as standing for different (even if somewhat similar) "cone
bearings", that is, he was in fact employing W1. Naturally, this
throws into serious doubt Trotsky's ability to spot even when something is or
isn't an instance of his own garbled version of the LOI!
Some might
regard that as unfair. Surely, Trotsky's point was to
argue that just as cone bearings look very similar (but are nevertheless
distinct), the two "A"s in W2 are equally similar but distinguishable
(in some way). So, he was right to use W1.
This objection has some force -- but, fortunately, not much. That is because
Trotsky began with the following assertion:
W3: Every worker knows that it is impossible to
make two completely equal objects.
[Trotsky's point about two letter "A"s
in "A is equal to A" being non-identical themselves was tackled earlier in this Essay.]
The idea seems to be that workers often (invariably?) realise
that the LOI is of limited applicability when they make things. However, even if
that were correct, Trotsky's main point would be irrelevant. His
avowed target had been the LOI ("A is equal to A", not "A is
equal to B"), since he hoped to show that workers in their practical activity
implicitly or explicitly reject that 'law', or, at least, that they are aware of its
limitations. In order to do this, he advanced the claim that workers in general
know that it is impossible to make two objects exactly alike. But, one of his
criticisms of the LOI was that all objects change continually and hence they are
never equal to themselves. Now, even if we accept Trotsky's version of
the LOI, it doesn't refer to two separate objects being the same;
in its classical form (and sometimes even in Trotsky's version) it is manifestly about an object's
alleged relation to itself.11
If, on the other hand, Trotsky had written:
W4: Every worker knows that it is impossible to
make an object completely equal to itself,
the absurdity of what he was
saying would have been clear to
all. No worker (or anyone else for that matter) would entertain such a crazy idea.
W1: A is equal to B.
However, in W1, Trotsky's point is completely different; there he
was arguing that different objects aren't identical, and that workers
know this. In this particular case, he wasn't saying that any one specific
object isn't self-identical,
but that of any two objects, not only can workers see that they aren't
the same, they also know they can't make two that are identical. He didn't say
that workers are aware that they can't make one object the same
as itself. But, that is precisely what Trotsky needed to show, that no
worker believes that one object can be made the same as itself -- i.e., that it
is impossible to make
one that is self-identical. He manifestly failed to do this.
In any case, Trotsky's point (in W3) can't even be derived from
his own criticism of the LOI. W3 isn't even a DM-thesis! And, that is
quite independent of whether or not workers conclude everything he said they should
or would. As
seems clear, it isn't relevant to claim that workers are automatic dialecticians
because they assent to a banal truth that isn't actually part of DM.
It isn't a DM-thesis that two objects are different, only that no object is
self-identical. What is wanted here is an example taken from DM that
workers could assent to before they were persuaded to do so by a fast-talking
Dialectical Missionary. What we actually have is a truism that any
card-carrying member of the ruling-class could accept;
even George W Bush knows that two apples aren't one apple!
W3: Every worker knows that it is impossible to
make two completely equal objects.
Despite this, it could be argued that Trotsky's point is that all
workers are aware of change, since they know that the same machine, for
example, produces seemingly alike but different objects.
If that is what Trotsky meant then it is certainly
unexceptionable, but it isn't what he said. And, even if he had said
it, it wouldn't have distinguished a DM-description of reality from one
available to anyone using ordinary language, or, indeed, anyone cognizant of 'bourgeois'
science. And, we can go further: no sane Capitalist believes that all
commodities (or even any two of them) are identical or that things don't change.
[I have covered this topic extensively in Essay Nine
Part One; readers are
directed there for more details.]
'Norms Of Tolerance' Refute Trotsky, too
But, what about this comment?
"Every worker knows that it is impossible to
make two completely equal objects. In the elaboration of a bearing-brass into
cone bearings, a certain deviation is allowed for the cones which should not,
however, go beyond certain limits…. By observing the norms of tolerance, the
cones are considered as being equal. ('A' is equal to 'A')…. Every individual is
a dialectician to some extent or other, in most cases, unconsciously."
[Ibid.,
pp.65,
106.
Bold emphasis added.]
In the above,
it is clear that Trotsky failed to
notice that the alleged limitation to which he referred (concerning the making
of two identical items) doesn't appear to affect the judgement of whoever is responsible for
applying the said "norms of tolerance". According to Trotsky's own description,
workers are at least able to determine what constitutes the same
application of these norms to different cone bearings. But, that surely
means that these hypothetical workers would have to employ a norm that
encapsulated the dread LOI in
order to apply it equally, or identically, between cases. That is, they would have to know (in
practice) what constituted an identical application of these norms each time, since an approximate
application of those norms to two very similar cones might very well pass them off as
identical!
Hence, in order for a worker to do what Trotsky says,
they
would have to know precisely what constitutes the correct application of the
same norm to at least two different cone bearings. Even if these workers
rejected the LOI (which is doubtful), or, indeed, recognised its supposed limitations, they would still have to use a norm expressing
that 'law' in
order to be able to agree with Trotsky that it fails to apply to cone bearings!
In short, they could only concur with Trotsky after completing a practical
refutation of what he declared they all implicitly knew!
Wrong Anyway
Despite this, what Trotsky
actually said is patently incorrect.
His comments clearly ruled out the possibility that (i) two different objects could
become the same, that (ii) a worker could make two distinct objects into
one and the same thing, and that (iii) workers know this. In fact, ordinary language and common experience allows
for both eventualities -- (i) and (ii) -- about which workers would be well
aware, anyway.
Examples of two things becoming one include the following:
(1) Two streams can flow into the same river.
(2) Two items of cloth can be combined in the same
garment.
(3) Two cricketers or baseball
players can become the same fielder (at the
same time in different matches, or at different times in the same match), or two
soldiers or union officials could be promoted to the same rank (with similar provisos).
(4) Two scabs could become the same target of the one
brick; or two bricks could form part of the same defence against a police attack.
(5) Two
workers could form the same small picket in the same or different strikes.
(6) Two copies of
The Daily Mail
could become the lining of the same pigsty -- but, only after suitable apologies
had been extended to the pigs, of course.
Examples of two items being
made into one include the following:
(1) Two rivets can be made into the same seal between two plates
of metal.
(2) Two buckets of paint can be mixed to form the same colour
(i.e., green and red making brown).
(3) Two wooden posts can form the same support in a
mine.
(4) Two ropes can form the same towline.
(5) Two plastic pipes can
combine into the same outlet.
(6) Two miscounted Widgets can
become the same excuse for
a strike.
(7) Two sentences can form the same paragraph of the
same or different strike leaflets.
(8) Two (or more) of the above can form the same excuse for
dialecticians to ignore them.
Of course, if we are no longer restricted to considering only
two items then it would be possible to multiply the above examples indefinitely. For instance,
one hundred thousand workers could form the same revolutionary column, or two
million people could form the same march against the war in Iraq. Or even: two
thousand police officers could constitute the same panic-stricken retreat from
either of the former.
Figure One: London February 15th 2003 -- Two
Million 'Unconscious' Anti-Dialecticians?
It
could be objected here that these 'counter-examples' beg the question since, if
Trotsky were right about the defects of the LOI, none of the
above would be genuine identity statements.
However, as argued earlier, our ordinary use of words for identity (i.e., "the
same as", "exact", "similar", "identical", "not different", "precisely", etc.)
is highly complex. It is far more sophisticated than Trotsky and Hegel imagined
in their 'theoretical' deliberations -- although in their everyday speech they
couldn't have been unaware of this fact; they would have
used sentences employing terms like the above countless times throughout their
lives.
The vernacular --
which, it is worth reminding ourselves yet again, is derived from everyday,
material practice -- allows for the expression of all manner of complex
identities; the lists given above outline only a few of these. [There are
many
more of the same here -- no irony
intended.]
Anyone who failed recognise these
as examples of sameness and identity (etc.) would be deemed not to
understand their own language (since they would be incapable of recognising,
using or
comprehending the same words from that language in the same way as the rest of
us);
indeed, they might in some circumstances become a danger to themselves. In which
case, they would hardly be in a position to criticise the 'law' that supposedly
operates behind such words, or between such objects and processes.
Indeed, the employment of
such words in contexts like those outlined above tells us more about their meaning than could be
gleaned by reading
the same comments in Hegel's work an
indefinite number of times (irony intended). His extremely narrow, metaphysical
use of
less than a handful of our words for identity and change shares
nothing with their ordinary employment; as such, his theses are not only devoid
of sense, they are incoherent. [Why that is so is
explained in Essay Twelve Part One.]
Some might object that many of the above examples
fall foul of the point Heraclitus made about constant change -- for example,
that it is impossible to step into the same river twice:
"It is not possible to step twice into the same river
according to Heraclitus, or to come into contact twice with a mortal being in
the same state. (Plutarch)" [Quoted from
here.]
It is in fact impossible to make sense of this odd statement. Had Heraclitus said that it wasn't possible to step into the same body of flowing water twice, he might
have had a point. Even so, it is quite easy to step into the
same river, and many times, too! Indeed, without
that
capacity, not even Heraclitus could test his own 'theory' (or even imagine such
a test in his 'mind's eye'), for he wouldn't be able to recognise anything as "the same
river" to test it on, even in theory!
In fact Heraclitus got into a terrible mess over the criteria of identity for
mass nouns
and count
nouns. [I have dealt with these terms elsewhere in
this Essay.]
Consider the following conversation:
R1: NN -- "I swam in the
Thames
this morning, and in a different river in the afternoon."
R2: NM -- "In which river did you swim in the
afternoon, then?"
R3: NN -- "The Thames!"
R4: NM -- "But, I thought you said you had swum
in a different river in the afternoon!"
R5: NN -- "Ah, but according to Heraclitus, it
isn't possible to swim in the same river twice."
R6: NM -- "In that case, you have just refuted
him, since you swam in the Thames twice!"
R7: NN -- "Not at all. The water I swam in was
different in the afternoon."
R8: NM -- "But, it was still H2O,
wasn't it?"
R9: NN -- "I don't get your point."
R10: NM -- "You said the water was
different in the afternoon. In that case, was it chemically different --
not perhaps H2O? If it
wasn't H2O,
you didn't swim in water the second time! Perhaps you meant the water was
different in some other way?"
R11: NN -- "The water molecules were the same,
obviously, but it was just a different body of water molecules in the
afternoon."
R12: NM -- "How does that make it a different
river? Surely our concept of a river involves the fact that it flows. If it
didn't, it wouldn't even be a river! So, just because a different body of
water molecules flows along it every day, doesn't mean it's a different river."
R13: NN -- "I see your point. Perhaps Heraclitus
meant that!"
R14: NM -- "If so, it is possible to step
into the same river twice, or, indeed, a hundred times."
As
noted above, Heraclitus had clearly confused criteria of identity we have for
count nouns (same river, same molecule, etc.) with those we have for mass nouns
(same water).
So, to return to one of the
examples given earlier (slightly
modified):
(1a) Two streams can flow into the
Thames.
Even
if the water molecules were different, or the body of water were changing all the time, (1a) refers to the same river -- the Thames --
not some other river -- say, the
Severn.
In which case, the point Heraclitus wished to make (if any sense
can be made of it, that is) doesn't count against the perfectly ordinary examples given
above. If we take account of the vernacular and our ordinary ways of speaking --
and ignore the confused things Idealist Philosophers (like Heraclitus and Hegel) have
to say
--, it is quite clear that two or more things can be, or can become, or can be
made to become, identical.
Taking account of ordinary ways of speaking is, after all, what
Marx himself enjoined upon us:
"The
philosophers have only to dissolve their language into the ordinary language,
from which it is abstracted, in order to recognise it, as the distorted language
of the actual world,
and to realise that neither thoughts nor language in themselves form a
realm of their own, that they are only manifestations of actual life."
[Marx
and Engels (1970), p.118. Bold emphasis alone added.]
[I will return to the theme of constant change in Essay Eleven
Part One,
where I aim to show that this particular doctrine (in general) makes no sense, and not just when it
is applied to rivers or bags of sugar. Readers are directed there for more details.]
It could be objected that none of us use our words in the
same
way, so the above observations are misguided. However, that objection itself is
(at least) based on that very objector using the words I have employed in the
'offending' paragraphs above in the same way as I have just done. If that objector's words aren't
being used in the same way, then that
objection itself is misguided since it would be aimed at the wrong target;
manifestly they wouldn't be aimed at what I had said, but at something else (the
nature of which would be inaccessible to anyone, and probably not even the
objector her/himself). And the same
can be said of any other general attempt to advance the same objection --
since it can't be the same objection if the words it contains
are employed differently.
Of
course, this isn't to deny that we sometimes use words in different ways (or
that the meaning of words
change over time), but this can't be typical otherwise
communication would be impossible. Moreover, anyone who rejected this simple
point would, plainly, fail
to get their point across, having used words differently! Alternatively, if they
managed to get their point across, they would have used their words in the same
way as the rest of us, undermining the very point the wanted to make!
If, on the other hand, these examples fail to
tell us what our words for identity (etc.) mean -- if they are defective or
inadequate in some
way -- then even those who criticise their use must fail to
grasp what they themselves are criticising (i.e., the ordinary use of the word
"identity" and its cognates), since they won't be able to put into words what constitutes the same use either
of that word or its associated terms. [The reasons
for saying this are explained in more detail in
Note
19.]
As this Essay will show, it is
in fact impossible to decide what (if anything) Trotsky actually meant by his
criticism of the LOI. All this suggests that the above examples represent a far
more legitimate use of words for
identity than the seriously limited selection employed by Hegel, Trotsky
and his latter-day clones. Hence, as far as ordinary language is
concerned, it is easy to speak about making two or more things exactly the
same -- which is all that us non-Idealists need.
It is certainly all that workers need.
Identical A Priori Tactics
In Essay
Five we saw how Engels had
irresponsibly
extrapolated from a sketchy thought experiment about moving bodies -–
'complemented' by an
idiosyncratic understanding of ordinary words like "move", "place" and
"contradiction" -- to universal truths supposedly valid everywhere for all of time. Here, we see Trotsky doing
something similar based on his idiosyncratic interpretation of a seriously
restricted set of words for identity -- in fact only "equal"! From this he
also
attempted to derive several
substantive theses about every object and process in existence, also valid for all of space and
time, deriving
Super-scientific truths from a superficial and
misguided 'conceptual analysis' of what he assumed were the meanings of
words like "identical", "change", "equality", "time", "moment", and "measure".
Just like Engels, he based these universal conclusions on an alarmingly narrow
evidential base -- a set of words
none of which turned out to be about identity --, 'supported' by a 'thought
experiment' about bags of sugar, which (as will soon become clear) ends up undermining
his own ambitious conclusions !
And this is supposed to be cutting-edge philosophy?
yet More A Priori
Super-Science
Even when
the serious
difficulties that have already been considered are put to one side, it is clear that Trotsky's analysis is deeply flawed for other
reasons. This can be seen if consideration is give to the rejoinder Trotsky
himself advanced (in S9) to a hypothetical objection (recorded in S8):
S8: A pound of sugar is
equal to itself.
S9(a): All bodies change
uninterruptedly. (b) They are never equal to themselves.
Unfortunately, Trotsky failed to say how he knew
that both halves of S9 were true. In fact, only if he were a semi-divine being
could he possibly know that all bodies are never equal to
themselves. Even if he had access to every single observation humans
beings have made of bodies in recorded history, that would still fail to
substantiate the hyper-bold claim recorded in S9 since those observations only amount to a
vanishingly small fraction of all the bodies there are, have ever been, or will
ever be. Neither could what he asserted have been based on scientific evidence
because that body of data is equivocal, at best. For example, since the 'quantum
revolution', it is now thought that several sub-atomic particles are equal to
themselves for unimaginably long periods of time, and possibly forever. Protons, for instance, have an
estimated half-life in excess of 1033 years, which is approximately
1020
times longer than the currently accepted age of the Universe. During that time
they don't change (as far as we know), and as such
they are surely equal to themselves.12
Indeed, proton decay has yet to be observed, so it might turn out that protons
do not change at all, ever. And that isn't the only example. [On this, see the
next subsection]
Physicists Discover Identical Objects
[This used to form part of Note 11.]
Recall what
Trotsky asserted:
"Every worker knows that it is impossible to make
two completely equal objects. In the elaboration of a bearing-brass into cone
bearings, a certain deviation is allowed for the cones which should not,
however, go beyond certain limits…. By observing the norms of tolerance, the
cones are considered as being equal. ('A' is equal to 'A')…. Every individual is
a dialectician to some extent or other, in most cases, unconsciously."
[Trotsky (1971),
pp.65,
106.]
However, contrary to what Trotsky said, it is very
easy to make two identical objects -- indeed, every single one of us does so
when we throw a light switch.
Here is some
material devoted to this topic taken from
another Essay posted at this site:
Physicists tell us that every photon, for example, is identical to every other
photon (this has been neatly illustrated
here). Here is how Philosopher of Science, Steven French, put things:
"It
should be emphasised, first of all, that quantal particles are indistinguishable
in a much stronger sense than classical particles. It is not just that two or
more electrons, say, possess all intrinsic properties in common but that -- on
the standard understanding -- no measurement whatsoever could in principle
determine which one is which. If the non-intrinsic, state-dependent
properties are identified with all the
monadic
or relational properties which can be expressed in terms of physical magnitudes
associated with
self-adjoint operators that can be defined for the particles,
then it can
be shown that two
bosons or two
fermions in a joint symmetric or anti-symmetric state respectively have the
same monadic properties and the same relational properties one to another.
[French and Redhead (1988); see also Butterfield (1993).] This has immediate
implications for
Leibniz's Principle of the Identity of Indiscernibles which, expressed
crudely, insists that two things which are indiscernible, must be, in fact,
identical."
However, the above was published in 2011, but French has has now (i.e., in 2019)
re-written this follows (over at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy):
"Now, of course, both quantum and classical
objects of the same kind -- such as electrons, say -- are indistinguishable in
the sense that they possess all intrinsic properties -- charge, spin, rest mass
etc. -- in common. However, quantum objects are indistinguishable in a much
stronger sense in that it is not just that two or more electrons possess the
same intrinsic properties but that – on the standard understanding -- no
measurement whatsoever could in principle determine which one is which. If
the non-intrinsic, state-dependent properties are identified with all the
monadic or relational properties which can be expressed in terms of physical
magnitudes standardly associated with self-adjoint operators that can be defined
for the objects, then it can be shown that two bosons or two fermions in a
joint symmetric or anti-symmetric state respectively have the same monadic
properties and the same relational properties one to another. [French and
Redhead (1988); see also Butterfield (1993).] This has immediate implications
for the Principle of the Identity of Indiscernibles which, expressed crudely,
insists that two things which are indiscernible, must be, in fact, identical."
[French
(2019). Bold emphases and links added. Referencing conventions altered in
line with those adopted
at this site.]
The above passage has
been slightly modified, again; this is the new version [i.e.,
French and Bigaj (2024)]:
"Now, of course, both quantum and classical objects of the same kind -- such as
electrons, say -- are indistinguishable in the sense that they possess all
intrinsic properties -- charge, spin, rest mass etc. -- in common. However, it
may be argued that quantum objects are indistinguishable in a much stronger
sense in that it is not just that two or more electrons possess the same
intrinsic properties but that -- on the standard understanding --
no measurement whatsoever could in principle determine which one is which.
If the non-intrinsic, state-dependent properties are identified with all the
monadic or relational properties which can be expressed in terms of physical
magnitudes standardly associated with self-adjoint operators that can be defined
for the objects,
then it can be shown that two bosons or two fermions in a joint symmetric or
anti-symmetric state respectively have the same monadic properties and the same
relational properties one to another.
[French and Redhead (1988); see also Butterfield (1993), Dieks and Versteegh
(2008).] This has immediate implications for the Principle of the Identity of
Indiscernibles which, expressed crudely, insists that two things which are
indiscernible, must be, in fact, identical." [French
and Bigaj (2024). Bold emphases added.
Referencing conventions altered in
line with those adopted
at this site.]
Of course, French
offers his own solution to this difficulty, but it isn't one that challenges the
identity of quantal particles, just their lack of individuality.
And, Nobel Laureate,
Paul Dirac,
made a similar point this way:
"If
a system in atomic physics contains a number of particles of the same kind,
e.g., a number of electrons, the particles are absolutely indistinguishable. No
observable change is made when two of them are interchanged…." [Dirac (1967),
p.307.]
However, as pointed out
here, one might well wonder how anyone could
possibly know whether or not two particles had been interchanged if they are all
indistinguishable. On the other hand, Pure Mathematician that he was, Dirac
might merely be making a theoretical point on a par with the following: "If we
swap one number in this equation for another (identical) number, no change will
be observed: 2 + 3 = 5". We can see this perhaps more clearly with this example:
"Two plus three equals five" is mathematically indistinguishable from "2 + 3 =
5" even though "2" and "Two", for instance, are plainly distinguishable.
In that case, every time a worker turns on a light,
he or she makes or generates countless trillion identical objects per second
-- which must mean that they are "unconscious" anti-dialecticians, if we
apply the same sort of reasoning here as Trotsky.
Naturally, contentious claims like these can only be
neutralised by an a priori stipulation that every photon in existence
(past, present and future) must
be non-identical -- despite what scientists tell us and in abeyance of the
impossibly large (finite) amount of data that would be needed to support such a
cosmically ambitious claim. At this point, perhaps, even hardnosed dialecticians
might be able to see in this a blatant attempt to
impose DM
on reality.
Some might
want to argue that photons don't occupy the same spatio-temporal co-ordinates,
and so can't be absolutely identical, but this certainly isn't how Trotsky (or
even Hegel) argued. When confronted with two letters "A"s on the page, Trotsky
didn't ague that they occupied different spatio-temporal co-ordinates and hence
aren't identical, he appealed to their assumed
physical differences. But, photons are physically indistinguishable
according to the above physicists.
Independently of this, photons refute Trotsky's claim that we can't make two
identical objects (which must be located at spatio-temporal co-ordinates), for
here we can.
Despite this, hardcore DM-fans might still want to argue that the above
spatio-temporal objection means that photons aren't identical, but this
objection is based on a certain definition of identity forced on nature
in
defiance of the claim that
DM-supporters never do this.
[A recent discussion of these issues can be found in Brading and Castellani
(2003), and Castellani (1998). An even more recent discussion can be found in
Saunders
(2006) (this links to a PDF), and particularly French and Krause (2006). See
also
Hilborn and
Yuca (2002),
Ladyman and Bigaj (2010), and the Wikipedia
entry
here.]
It could further be objected that Trotsky would
surely have been unaware of developments in Physics that took place after he
died, but, as the references given above show, these facts were largely true of
classical particles, too; quantal particles merely present a more extreme
form of strict identity. And, Lenin it was who reminded us that science is ever
revisable; hence, no dialectician who agrees with Lenin could consistently rule
out the possibility that scientists would one day discover identical particles
-- as indeed they have.
Even so, Trotsky was quite happy to
impose this view on nature before all (or most of) the evidence had been
collected, in defiance of what he said elsewhere:
"The dialectic does not liberate the
investigator from
painstaking study of the facts, quite the contrary: it requires it."
[Trotsky (1986), p.92. Bold emphasis added]
"Dialectics and materialism are the
basic elements in the Marxist cognition of the world. But this does not mean at
all that they can be applied to any sphere of knowledge, like an ever ready
master key. Dialectics cannot be imposed on facts; it has to be deduced from
facts, from their nature and development…." [Trotsky (1973), p.233. Bold
emphasis added.]
And the
facts tell us that photons are identical and in all likelihood,
changeless.
I now turn
to that topic, changeless identical sub-atomic particles.
Changeless Sub-Atomic Particles
[This used
to form part of
Note 12.]
The
following material was published in
another Essay at
this site:
In fact, the half-life of a proton is
reckoned to be in excess of 1033
years -- i.e., one followed by thirty-three zeros! Estimates vary, but this is
approximately 1020
(i.e., one followed by twenty zeros) times longer than the age of the known
universe, if current theory is correct. Experimental evidence suggests its
half-life is probably longer even than this. Predicted
proton decay
hasn't actually been observed yet. Apparently, electrons are even less
'dialectical'. In that case, there could in fact be more changeless objects in
nature than there are changeable. The point is, of course, that this is an
empirical
matter, not -- as Engels, Plekhanov, Lenin, Trotsky and Mao seem to have thought
-- an
a priori truth based on the musings of an Idealist who died over 2500
years ago (i.e.,
Heraclitus).
As far as protons are concerned, we
are told the following:
"Along with neutrons, protons make up the nucleus, held together by the
strong force. The proton is a
baryon
and is considered to be composed of two up
quarks
and one down quark.
"It has long been considered to be a stable particle, but recent developments of
grand unification
models have suggested that it might decay with a
half-life
of about 1032 years. Experiments are underway
to see if such decays can be detected. Decay of the proton would violate the
conservation of
baryon
number, and in doing so would be the only known
process in nature which does so." [Quoted
from here.]
Wikipedia
adds:
"In
particle physics, proton decay is a
hypothetical form of
radioactive decay
in which the
proton
decays into lighter
subatomic particles, usually a neutral
pion
and a
positron. Proton decay has not been observed.
There is currently no evidence that proton decay occurs."
[Accessed 29/07/2015.]
One
Professor of theoretical physicist had this to say:
"The only known stable particles in
nature are the electron (and anti-electron), the lightest of the three
types of neutrinos (and its anti-particle), and the photon and
(presumed) graviton (which are their own anti-particles). The presumed
graviton, too, is stable. The other
neutrinos,
the proton, and many atomic nuclei (and their
anti-particles.... I'm going to stop mentioning
the anti-stuff, it goes without saying) are probably not stable but are
very, very, very long-lived. Protons, for instance, are so long-lived that at
most a minuscule fraction of them have decayed since the
Big
Bang, so for all practical purposes they are probably stable. The
other rather long-lived particle is the
neutron,
which when on its own, outside an atomic nucleus, lives just 15 minutes or so.
But neutrons inside many atomic nuclei can live far longer than the age of the
universe; such nuclei provide them with a stable home. Finally, I should add
that if
dark matter is made from particles, then those particles, too, must
be stable or very, very long-lived.
"Why
are these
particles stable? It turns out that our world imposes some rules on particle
behaviour, ones not visible to us in the physics of waves and vibrations that we
encounter in daily life, that prevent some particles from decaying, either
rapidly or at all. The fundamental rules are 'conservation laws', statements
that certain quantities in the universe never change in any physical
process. (These quantities include energy, momentum, electric charge, and a few
others.) There are also some approximate conservation laws, stating that certain
quantities only change very rarely. Conservation laws do not appear from
nowhere, imposed out of thin air by theorists; they are related to other
properties of the world. For example, if the laws of nature do not change over
time, then it follows (thanks to a theorem of the mathematician Emmy
Noether) that energy is conserved. Meanwhile, the stability of the
matter out of which we are made provides strong tests of these conservation
laws, as we'll see.
"Combining these laws with the
properties of particles leads to a set of simple rules that determine when
particles simply cannot decay, or when they can at most decay very rarely. And
these rules are (almost) entirely sufficient to explain the stability of the
particles out of which we are made, and those that we interact with most often."
[Matthew
Strassler, quoted from
here; accessed 19/02/2014. Quotation marks altered to conform with
the conventions adopted at the site. Spelling adjusted to agree with UK English;
several links added. Italic emphases in the original. The professor then
proceeds to spell out those rules, which I have omitted.]
Another Physics site also added this comment (in October 2014):
"Protons live a long time but perhaps not forever.
Several theories predict that protons can decay, and a handful of
experiments have tried to detect such an event. The
Super-Kamiokande experiment in Japan has the longest track record in the
search for proton decay, and its researchers have now published a new lower
bound on the proton lifetime that is 2.5 times greater than their previous
bound. The proton's observed stability places constraints on certain
extensions of the standard model of particle physics.
"Proton decay is an expected outcome of most
grand unified theories, or GUTs, which meld together the
three main particle forces -- strong, weak, and electromagnetism -- at
high energy. A certain class of GUTs, for example, predicts that a proton
should decay into a positron and
π meson with a lifetime of about 1031
years, which means roughly 1 decay per year in a sample of 1031
protons. Experiments have already ruled this possibility out.
"Other GUTs that incorporate
supersymmetry
(SUSY), a hypothetical model that assumes all particles have
a partner with different spin, predict that the proton decays into a
K meson
and a neutrino with a lifetime of less than a few times 1034
years. The Super-Kamiokande collaboration has looked for
signs of this decay in a 50,000-ton tank of water surrounded by detectors. If
one of the many protons in the tank were to decay, the K meson's decay products
(muons,
π mesons) would be detectable. The researchers simulated such proton decay
events but found no matches in data spanning 17 years. From this, they conclude
that the proton lifetime for this SUSY-inspired decay pathway is greater than
5.9 x 1033
years." [Quoted from
here, accessed 23/08/2015; bold emphasis and links
added.]
Update,
09/08/21: The following report, from Nature Reviews Physics, is
dated January 8, 2021:
"Does the proton decay? The proton could decay into a
positron and a pion and if so the predictions of some beyond standard model
grand unified theories would be confirmed. Since the 1980s underground
experiments have been looking for signs of such decay. No proton decay has
yet been spotted, but one of the experiments, the Kamioka Nucleon Decay
Experiment...detected neutrinos from the
supernova
SN1987a instead. Its successor, the Super-Kamiokande, set the best current
lower-limit for proton lifetime: 1.6 x 1034
years. Some grand unified theories predict proton lifetimes up to around 1036
years so there is still room for surprises. Upcoming neutrino experiments also
have proton decay measurements planned and are expected to push the limits on
the proton lifetime. These measurements will take place at Deep Underground
Neutrino Experiment (DUNE)
currently under construction [at the] Jiangmen Underground Neutrino Observatory
(JUNO)
which is almost completed and Hyper-Kamiokande whose
construction received the green light last year." [Quoted from
here; accessed 09/08/2021. One link and bold emphasis added.]
Much of the universe, it seems,
doesn't 'understand' dialectics, either.
Even Peter Mason, an otherwise enthusiastic champion of DM,
had to admit the following (while criticising fellow Trotskyists, Woods and
Grant):
"Although dialectics certainly suggests that science
will find a time limit beyond which protons will decay in some way, and teams of
scientists are testing to find that limit -- nevertheless the proton is stable
over very long periods. A twelve-year experiment, started in 1989, suggested
that the proton has a lifetime of at least ten million billion billion billion
years (1034
years -- a one with 34 zeros after it). It does not ceaselessly change, as Woods
asserts." [Mason
(2012), p.14.]
Of course, it could
be objected that particles such as protons (i.e.,
hadrons) are composed of even more fundamental particles, which do
enjoy a contradictory life of their own 'inside' each host 'particle'; their
interactions would therefore mean that apparently
changeless protons are in fact changing 'internally' all the time. But, this
response simply pushes the problem further back, for these other, more
fundamental particles (i.e.,
quarks --, in
the case of protons, two "up"
and one "down"
quark), are themselves changeless, as far as is known. Moreover, these quarks
certainly have no 'internal contradictions' of their own to worry about.
Moreover, since protons are
baryons --
i.e., they are composed of three
quarks --, it isn't easy to see how their inner lives are in any way
'contradictory' (with three terms?). That is quite apart from the
additional fact that DM-theorists have yet to establish that every single proton
has a ceaselessly changing internal life of its own. Have they looked inside
every single one?
Even more difficult
to account for dialectically are
electrons and photons (which are
leptons and
gauge bosons
respectively), since they have no known internal structure (but see
below). Unless acted upon
externally, their 'lifespan' is, so we are told, infinite; hence,
if
they change, it isn't because of any 'internal contradictions'. [Although
there
are reports that
electrons
have been, or can, split.]
An appeal to
antiquarks here, to save the dialectical day, would be to no avail, either.
That is because quarks don't struggle with and then turn into antiquarks, nor
vice versa, which is what the Dialectical Holy Books tell us should happen
to all such 'opposites'. [On that, see
here.] When they interact
they annihilate one another. Furthermore, DM-theorists
equivocate over the meaning of "internal". Sometimes they mean by this word,
"logically internal", while at others they mean, "spatially internal". The
latter interpretation would be fatal to DM (on that see
here);
the former is far too confused to
make much sense of, anyway.
Someone might object that these particles are always moving, and hence changing.
Again, the evidence that every single particle in the universe -- past, present
and future -- is/was/will always be moving has yet to be produced. But, even if
they are/were/will be always moving, that would simply mean that the distance
between particles was changing, not the particles themselves.
It seems, therefore, that the picture of reality painted by dialecticians is
more
Jackson Pollock than it is
Van Eyck.
Figure Two: The 'DM-View' Of Nature
Figure Three: Genuine Science 'Pictures'
The World Rather More Precisely
[On
protons, see
here and
here; on
electrons,
here;
leptons,
here; photons,
here.]
Moreover, every electron is identical with every other electron, and the same
applies to other elementary particles (such as photons).
[On
this topic in general, cf., Perkins (2000),
French and Bigaj (2024), French and Krause (2006) -- but more specifically
Saunders
(2006)
(this links to a PDF). See also
Dieks and Versteegh (2007/2008),
Ladyman and Bigaj (2010), and Caulton and Butterfield (2012), and
above.]
In
fact there appear to be two schools at work here; those who hold that all such
particles are identical and indiscernible (rather like the dollars or pounds in
your bank account, not the dollars or pounds in your wallet or pocket), and those
who claim they are identical but discernible. [On this, see the above references
as well as Muller and Seevinick (2009), and Muller and Saunders (2008).]
"Discernible" appears to mean different things to different philosophers,
too (no
pun intended). In practice it seems to imply that while such objects are
identical, nevertheless they aren't!
Naturally, dialecticians might want to object to the above on the lines that
electrons, for example,
aren't really particles --, or that they are probability
waves or perturbations in the field, or that they are this or they are that. Perhaps so, but, once again,
whatever they are, they are identical with that, and they change equally
quickly as they themselves do.
And,
if they change, that can't be because of their
'internal
contradictions'
-- which DM-fans have yet to show they have.
[This
comment puts paid to much of the confused ruminations on sub-atomic 'particles'
found in, for example, Woods and Grant (1995/2007). More details on this will be
posted in Essay Seven Part Two at a later date. On change through 'internal
contradiction', see Essays Seven Part
Three and Eight Parts
One, Two and
Three.]
Of
course, the above considerations will only offend those who,
for some odd reason, might prefer to foist dialectics on nature.
But,
who on earth would want to do that?
Finally, it could be argued that since the relations
between particles are always altering, even if certain particles are
seemingly
changeless, those particles will be changing all the time as a result.
This issue is
discussed in more detail in Essays
Six,
Seven,
Eight Part One, and Eleven
Part Two. Suffice it to say here that:
(a) If this
contention were correct, most of the elementary objects in the universe wouldn't
be self-developing, but would be affected by external causes. In
that case, this particular idea would support one strand of DM by torpedoing
another. Indeed, it would also introduce into nature a "bad
infinity" (as
Hegel would have called it) as these external causes stretch off into the
blue beyond. In that case, and once more, yet another a priori
dialectical thesis will have been holed below the waterline. [On Hegel and the
infinite, see Houlgate (2006).]
(b), there is
no evidence that every particle in nature has an effect on every other, which
supposedly changes it, or them. [So-called "Quantum
Entanglement" is discussed
here.]
And:
(c) As noted
earlier, even if this were correct, it would simply mean that the
relations between these particles changed not the particles themselves.
If,
on the other hand, change is defined in such a way that an alteration to
the relations between objects also counted as a change
to
those objects themselves (these are often called "internal
relations" by assorted Idealists and DM-fans alike) then, once more, that re-definition
would be no different from an imposition onto nature of something that it might
not have. If dialecticians have any evidence that there are indeed such
"internal relations" in nature and society (or which affect everything in the
universe in this way), then they need to produce it, or resist the temptation to
keep advancing such
claims.
Of
course, there are DM-theorists (mainly of the
HCD
persuasion) who employ a handful of 'arguments' culled from the
aforementioned Idealists, which are aimed at showing that such relations
do indeed exist between objects and processes; but they would, wouldn't they? They
are Idealists. They prefer 'conceptual arguments' over evidential proof any
day of the week -- as George Novack
pointed out.
Indeed, the more they try to defend "internal relations" with a priori
arguments like this, the more they confirm Novack's allegations.
Plainly, such bogus reasoning wouldn't be needed if DM-fans had any
scientific evidence to back up these ancient, mystical dogmas.
It
is, of course, a
Hermetic doctrine that everything is
interconnected, and is a
union of opposites,
as Magee noted:
"Another parallel between Hermeticism and Hegel is the doctrine of internal
relations. For the Hermeticists, the cosmos is not a loosely connected, or to
use Hegelian language, externally related set of particulars. Rather, everything
in the cosmos is internally related, bound up with everything else.... This
principle is most clearly expressed in the so-called Emerald Tablet of
Hermes Trismegistus, which begins with the famous lines "As above, so below."
This maxim became the central tenet of Western occultism, for it laid the basis
for a doctrine of the unity of the cosmos through sympathies and correspondences
between its various levels. The most important implication of this doctrine is
the idea that man is the microcosm, in which the whole of the macrocosm is
reflected.
"...The universe is an internally related whole pervaded by cosmic energies."
[Magee (2008),
p.13. More on this
here, and
here.]
Bertell Ollman's recent book is just the latest example of this mystical genre
-- Ollman (2003). Ollman's work
has been analysed in more detail in Essay Three
Part Two.
["Internal relations" will be destructively criticised in Essay Four Part Two, when it
is published.]
As of August 2023,
the above is still the case: Proton decay has yet to be observed.
Moreover, we have
already seen that ordinary language
itself contains countless expression (simple and complex) that
allow speakers to talk about objects and processes that not
only can but do remain
identical, sometimes over many years. Hence, neither human experience nor scientific theory agrees with
Trotsky's hyper-ambitious claims.
An Everyday Example Of
Absolute Identity
Consider the following scenario: two
individuals, NN and NM, board the same train at the
same time and remain on it for two hours. While these two are still on that train,
whatever changes it experiences or undergoes as it speeds along (and this
includes changes to all its contents and its relations with the
entire universe in this two hours),
this will always be true: NN and NM are on an absolutely identical
train
as each other.
More precisely:
A1: During temporal
interval, T -- lasting m hours --, a set of predicates, P, is true of, or
can be used to form true propositions about, (i) Train, L, (ii) All
on board, and (iii)
L and
the relation its contents have with everything in the universe
-- where P is comprised of the following elements:
{P1,
P2, P3,..., Pn},
and where n is indefinitely large (m
ε
ℝ).
A2: NN and NM
are both passengers on L during any sub-interval, tk,
of T, of arbitrary length.
A3: During tk,
a subset of P, namely {Pi..., Pk},
can be used to form true propositions about (i) L, (ii) All
on board, and (iii)
L and
the relations its contents have with everything in the universe, including any changes that occur
to one or both, during tk.
A4: So, during tk,
NN and NM are on absolutely identically the same train as one another,
since, while they are on L, the valid applicability of every element of {Pi,..., Pk} remains the case throughout.
Now, every element of {Pi,...,
Pk}
-- i.e., these
predicates, or what they 'reflect' -- can change 'dialectically' all the time,
but that won't alter the result, since any changed element of {Pi,...,
Pk}
will
also be an element of that sub-set, by the above definitions.
So, here we have an example of absolute
identity that would remain such even in a
Heraclitean universe.
[I have tried to use DM-phraseology here wherever possible (e.g.,
"reflect", "dialectically", as well as "L and
the relation its contents have with everything in the universe") so that this argument doesn't become
needlessly controversial by the employment of too
much non-DM terminology. Its use, however, doesn't imply I accept its validity;
it is merely being employed in order to assist in its long-overdue demise.]
Finally, what applies to passengers on trains applies in like
manner (irony intended) to those in or on ships, boats, aeroplanes, spacecraft,
buses, taxis, rickshaws, bikes, cars and skateboards at the same time. Indeed, it applies in equal
measure (more irony intended) to individuals in the same cinema, theatre, café,
restaurant, hotel, hostel, house, office, hospital, waiting room, stadium, palace,
mansion, igloo, cave, tree house, park, and graveyard, at the same time -- just as it
applies to all of us on the same planet, at the same time. And if we go for
broke, it applies to everything in the universe at the same time.
[I have added another detailed example of this sort of identity,
concerning two climbers on the same mountain at the same time,
below.]
So, far from being a rather rare occurrence (or even an
impossibility according to DM-fans) absolute identity like this is as common as
sand in the Sahara.
Of course, it could be objected that this sort of identity isn't
the sort that interests dialecticians, so the above comments aren't just beside the
point, they are irrelevant. But, as we will see as this Essay unfolds, we don't yet know what
DM-theorists mean by the odd things they say about identity, so not even they
may consistently advance that objection this side of saying for the very first
time, with any clarity, what they do mean.
One thing is clear, neither Trotsky's nor Hegel's criticisms
of the LOI are successful against the above sort of identity.
Using The LOI To Criticize The LOI
Same 'Moment'
However, even if Trotsky were right,
and everything in the entire universe changed all the time,
it would still be unclear what he was trying to say.
"But, one can object, the
question is not the size or the form of the letters, since they are only symbols
for equal quantities, for instance, a pound of sugar. The objection is beside
the point; in reality a pound of sugar is never equal to a pound of sugar -– a
more delicate scale always discloses a difference. Again one can object: but a
pound of sugar is equal to itself. Neither is true (sic) -– all bodies change
uninterruptedly in size, weight, colour etc. They are never equal to themselves.
A sophist will respond that a pound of sugar is equal to itself at 'any given
moment'…. How should we really conceive the word 'moment'? If it is an
infinitesimal interval of time, then a pound of sugar is subjected during the
course of that 'moment' to inevitable changes." [Trotsky
(1971), p.64. Bold emphasis added.]
For instance, it is
far from certain what he had in mind when he asserted S9(b) (repeated
below). Consider the
following interpretations of S8 as possible targets of his:
S8: A pound of sugar is equal to
itself.
S10: Let A1
be a pound of sugar at time, T1.
S11: Let A2
be a pound of sugar at time, T2.
[T2
> T1.]
S12: S8 means A1
is equal to A1.
S13: S8 means A1
is equal to A2.
S1: A is equal to
A.
S9(b): [All bodies] are never equal to
themselves.
At first sight, it seems that Trotsky
might have had S13 in his sights when he asserted S9(b), since it compares
a pound bag of sugar with itself as it changes over time, which is
perhaps the normal way of regarding change. But, S13 doesn't even
look like a classical formulation of the LOI; nor does it look like
Trotsky's own simplistic version (recorded in S1), either. It more closely
resembles a quasi-empirical claim about the temporal continuity of material
bodies. Clearly, if Trotsky had wanted to use S9(b) to refute S13, then S12
(which is surely a more likely target) would have been left unscathed. This suggests
that S13 wasn't the interpretation
that Trotsky had in mind. He must have read S8 as equivalent to (i.e.,
identical with -- note the irony here!) S12, which
he plainly thought was refuted by S9(b):13
S8: A pound of sugar is equal to
itself.
S12: S8 means A1
is equal to A1.
S9(b): [All bodies] are never equal to
themselves.
If so, it is quite clear that
Trotsky had to assume the truth of the LOI in order to declare it false; that
is, he had
to assume the LOI was reliable in order to try to show it was unreliable. Clearly,
that means this 'demonstration' is radically defective, since Trotsky's 'analysis'
only succeeded in undermining itself.
To see this more clearly it is worth making S9(b)
a little more precise, perhaps along the following lines:
S14: For any object, A,
at any time, t, A at t is not equal to A at t.
[I have avoided the construction: "For
all objects, A,
at any time, t, A at t is not equal to A at t"
since it is a stylistic monstrosity. Not much hangs on the difference.]
Given the above
caveat, S14 expresses the content of S9(b) a little
more clearly; indeed, Trotsky himself employed a tensed ordinary language
quantifier expression in S9(b)
-- viz., "never".13a
"Again one can object: but a pound of
sugar is equal to itself. Neither is true (sic) -– all bodies change
uninterruptedly in size, weight, colour etc. They are never equal to
themselves." [Ibid. Bold emphasis added.]
Unfortunately, this change of
emphasis introduced a serious problem Trotsky failed to notice. This
can be seen if we refer back to S1, S9 and S14:
S1: A is equal to
A.
S9(a): All bodies change
uninterruptedly. (b) They are never equal to themselves.
S14: For any object, A,
at any time, t, A at t is not equal to A at t.
S9(b): [All bodies] are never equal to
themselves.
Clearly, S9(b) -- when interpreted along the lines
suggested by S14 -- implies that S1 must be rejected because:
S15: It is never true that
A is equal to A.
However, S15 appears to imply the following:
S16: For any time, t,
and any A, A at t is not equal to A at t.
But, this now transfers the emphasis onto the
temporal aspects of identity, which underlines the points Trotsky himself
tried to make about time and change:
"Again one can object: but a pound of
sugar is equal to itself. Neither is true (sic) -– all bodies change
uninterruptedly in size, weight, colour etc. They are never equal to
themselves. A sophist will respond that a pound of sugar is equal to itself
at 'any given moment'…. How should we really conceive the word 'moment'? If it
is an infinitesimal interval of time, then a pound of sugar is subjected during
the course of that 'moment' to inevitable changes. Or is the 'moment' a
purely mathematical abstraction, that is, a zero of time? But everything exists
in time; and existence itself is an uninterrupted process of transformation;
time is consequently a fundamental element of existence. Thus the axiom 'A' is
equal to 'A' signifies that a thing is equal to itself if it does not change,
that is if it does not exist." [Trotsky
(1971), p.64. Bold emphases added.]14
It is here that Trotsky unwittingly
introduced the serious difficulty alluded to above, one that is now connected with the
identity
of temporal instants. This is highlighted by his use of the phrase "that
'moment'" (which clearly means "that same moment", no
matter how short it is), during which an
object supposedly changes. But, in referring to time this way, the phrase "that moment"
suggests that we can make sense of the following schematic sentence:
S17: For some instant, t,
t is identical to t.
[S17 is just a
more formal paraphrase of
"that [same] 'moment'".]
If Trotsky did in fact rely on S17, it
would be fatal to his argument since it claims that the instant in question is self-identical
and hence subject to the LOI!
That being so, Trotsky's argument clearly requires
something to remain the same (i.e., an instant in time during which an
object changes) so that his
objection to the LOI can gain some purchase. The serious problems Trotsky's
analysis now faces become a little clearer just as soon it is realized that the
following sentences follow from S16:
S16: For any time, t, and any A,
A at t is not equal to A at t.
S18: There is a time, t1,
and an A, such that A at t1 is not equal to A
at t1.
S19: At one and the same
instant, A is not equal to A.
Now, the phrase "instant in time" --
represented in S18 by the use of "t1" --
is just as legitimate a substitution instance as the phrase "pound bag of sugar" for the "A"s in S1.
This can be seen if the following are compared (and if we wave for the time
being the fact that "identical" isn't identical to "equal"):
S20: t1 is
equal to t1.
S1: A is equal to
A.
S17: For some t, t
is identical to t.
[S20 of course is just a
less specific version of
S17, but it is nevertheless a legitimate version of S1.]
This
means that Trotsky
requires S20 to be true so that he can reject the LOI as false! As noted
above, this implies that he needs the LOI to apply in an
unrestricted sense to certain things (i.e., temporal instants) so that he can
deny it of others (i.e., pound bags of sugar, or even distinguishable letter "A"s).
It could be objected here that Trotsky was
merely criticising the LOI as it applies to objects and processes that change
in time; his argument was certainly not about "temporal instants", which are
abstractions anyway. Indeed, he was simply pointing out that no matter how
narrow the time frame, change still takes place. That is abundantly clear from what he said:
"How should we really
conceive the word 'moment'? If it is an infinitesimal interval of time, then a
pound of sugar is subjected during the course of that 'moment' to inevitable
changes. Or is the 'moment' a purely mathematical abstraction, that is, a zero
of time? But everything exists in time; and existence itself is an uninterrupted
process of transformation; time is consequently a fundamental element of
existence. Thus the axiom 'A' is equal to 'A' signifies that a thing is equal to
itself if it does not change, that is if it does not exist." [Trotsky
(1971),
p.64.]
Or so a response might proceed.
Nevertheless, if "that moment" is interpreted
exactly as Trotsky
indicates, he
still has to be able to refer to that very same moment during which the object
in question changes; if "that moment" weren't the same, then his argument would
plainly fall flat, for the assumed change in question would have taken place
in a different moment. Clearly, no one would object to that.
Moreover the
counter-claim that moments in time are abstractions won't work
either; if bags of sugar can be weighed and
found to vary, moments in time can be measured and shown to differ, too -- if
Trotsky's other assertions about measuring things are taken as read. Temporal
intervals
are just as measurable as the weight of bags of sugar. It isn't easy to see how
Trotsky could consistently criticize the LOI on the basis of the hypothetically
differing weight of these bags without this spilling over
into a general criticism of anything at all that is capable of being measured,
such as time. If time is to be exempted from his critique of measurement, why not weight?14a
It seems, therefore, that
Trotsky's argument relies on these measurable intervals staying the same while those
measurable bags of sugar don't!
In fact, no matter how short the interval
within which a given change is supposed to occur, Trotsky has to be able to
refer to identically the same one to make his case. Without this his
whole analysis collapses. So, whether or not these "moments" are extensionless
temporal points, or extended intervals in time, Trotsky still has to employ
the LOI so
that he can assert that at least one of these is the very same moment during in which
the assumed changes occur.
A Turn To The
Concrete
However, even if the
above serious problems were
put to one side, and it is conceded that reference to identical temporal
instants is in the end an unfair criticism of Trotsky, and S14 is examined without the
quantifier switch
(this links to a PDF)
expressed in S16, the same conclusions follow (no irony intended).
Consider this putative
substitution instance of S14 expressed in S21(a):
S14: For any object, A, at any time,
t, A at t is not equal to A at t.
S21(a): There is an A and a
time, t1,
such that A at t1 is not
equal to A at t2.
S21(b): There is an A
and a time, t1,
such that A at t1 is
not equal to A at
t1.
[S16: For any time, t, and any A,
A at t is not equal to A at t.]
As the reader will no doubt have noticed,
S21(a) is in fact an illegitimate substitution instance of S14 because
the variable letters "t1"
and "t2"
aren't identical, which violates certain conventions governing the
interpretation of
bound variables in quantified contexts
(in MFL).
[MFL = Modern Formal Logic.]
Now, Trotsky has to
make use of something like S21(b) -- or its colloquial equivalent -- if his criticisms of the LOI
are to succeed. This means that even if the objections noted
above (about abstract "temporal instants" etc.) are either ignored or rejected, Trotsky's argument still
has to rely on the identity of quantified tensed variables -- or their
equivalent in ordinary language (such as "same moment") -- if it is to
work. In short, he has to use the same material objects -- words or
symbols, written on paper or reproduced on a screen -- to make his point.
In that case, his argument depends on
either one or both of the
following:
S20(a): Variable t1
is equal to (or identical with) variable t1.
S20(b): In referring to the same moment
during which an object changes, critics of the LOI have to use the identical
phrase "same moment", and they all have to mean exactly the same by it each
time.
But, an appeal to the identity
of symbols like these -- the linguistic expression of which must surely
count as concrete and material -- would be just as good an instance of the application
of the LOI as any Trotsky himself examined.15
Furthermore, Trotsky's analysis can't be seen as
an 'immanent critique' -- i.e., as one undermining the LOI from
within
-- as it were. That is because his argument depends on this 'law' being
absolutely correct while he is using it, and absolutely
true after he has used it. If it is limited (or relativised) in any way, then
he automatically loses the right to talk about the "same moment" or the "same
interval" in which the alleged changes take place. Moreover, if the words he
employed aren't identical in meaning as and when he used them, then his conclusions fail,
too.
[Identity criteria
for words (as opposed to letters) are considered in more detail
below.
Objections to the above, based on the 'relative stability' defence, have been
neutralised in Note 15, and
here.]
In that case, it
is difficult to
see how Trotsky's attack on the LOI can either proceed or succeed -- expressed in any
language (technical, scientific or ordinary) -- without an implicit or explicit use of the very
'law' under scrutiny. In order to reject the LOI as it relates to objects,
it now looks like Trotsky has to admit that it applies either to temporal
instants or to tensed variable letters -- or, to ordinary words that give
expression to either. In the latter two cases (i.e., variable letters and
ordinary words), this will involve a
use of very real material objects (written in ink or even pixels on your screen),
just like those
"A"s, to which Trotsky took exception.
Either way, Trotsky's analysis is now
involved in intractable problems; identity criteria for temporal instants (even if
these interpreted as discrete) are notoriously difficult to define -– even if you
accept the LOI. They are far more problematic than identity criteria for
material objects.16
And, of course, those governing the
concrete employment of tensed variables are governed by convention. In which case, it looks like Trotsky has to
appeal to the identity of tensed variables -- or to identical marks on the
page, or ordinary words that have been identically applied -- if his argument is to work
against the very same 'law' he used in his criticism of it!
Hence, in order to make
his case, Trotsky had to ignore in practice what he had earlier concluded in
theory, undermining what he said about the LOI by disregarding his own
strictures against it.
So, if truth is confirmed in practice,
Trotsky effectively scuppered his entire criticism of the LOI by having to
apply, in practice, that very same 'law'.
It
seems, therefore, that it isn't
possible to attack this 'law' as it applies to any specific case without also appealing to its unrestricted application somewhere
else.
Trotsky's Analysis --
Incomprehensible, Or Just Trivial?
On the other hand, if Trotsky had been aware
of these problems and had still rejected the LOI (as it supposedly applies to
temporal instants, tensed variables or even the application of ordinary words for identity), his
criticisms would have either been (i) rendered far less grandiose than they
might otherwise seem, or they
would have (ii) collapsed into incomprehensibility.
As far as (i) is concerned, if reference to
absolutely the same instant (or the same anything) is to be regarded as
illegitimate (since it would clearly require yet another application of the
LOI, as noted above), then Trotsky could only have meant one or more of the following:
S22(a): No
object is identical with itself at a
later time.
S22(b): No object is
identical with itself at a
different time.
[S13: S8 means A1
is equal to A2.]
[S21(a): There is an
A and a time, t1
such that A at t1
is not equal to A at t2.]
But, both S22(a) and S22(b) express the banal
truth expressed in S13 and S21(a), with which few would want to quarrel.
Clearly,
therefore, S22(a) and S22(b) are almost certainly not what Trotsky had in mind;
he surely wanted to argue that no object is self-identical at the same
instant -- presumably because all objects are subject to their own internal
struggles each of which is generated by a UO.
Unfortunately, as we have just seen, without an (implicit, or even explicit)
appeal to the LOI applied to temporal instants, tensed variables or their
ordinary language equivalents, he can't assert this.
[UO = Unity of Opposites/Unities of
Opposites, depending on the context; IED = Identity-in-Difference
(i.e., 'Improvised Explanatory Device').]
On the other hand, option (ii) would
apply whenever, say, each and every reference to
the LOI was dialectically 'made and un-made', as it were, at the same
time. That is, it would apply where "same" and "different"
were said to
"interpenetrate" one another, as in "same and non-same", or "the same and not
the same" (using the IED ploy). This would then have Trotsky meaning one or
other
of the following:
S23(a): No object is self-identical at
the same non-self-identical instant in time.
S23(b): No object is self-identical at
the same and not the same self-identical instant in time.
But, as we have
already seen with other dialectical principles, this threatens to explode in
the following manner:
S23(c): No object is self-identical at
the same and non-same non-self-identical instant in time.
S23(d): No object is self-identical at
the same and not the same and not the same and not the same
self-identical instant in time.
Where the word "same", as it appears in
S23(a)
and S23(b), has been replaced in italics by its (assumed) 'dialectical' meaning
-- "same and non-same", or "same and not the same" -- in S23(c) and
S23(d)
respectively, in order to make explicit the radical confusion this option would
create.
But, what could any of these
possibly mean? What precisely is a "same and non-same non-self-identical instant
in time"? Either it surreptitiously employs the LOI again by the use of
the word "same", or it is meaningless.
[Of course, only those who
reject the IED ploy, and hence those who repudiate classical DM, will object
(successfully) at this point.]
Any who feel
confident in their ability to explain what S23(c) could possibly mean should not
be given the benefit of that
considerable doubt until they have managed to do likewise with S23(d). But, what on earth could this
mean: "the same and not the same and not the same and not the same
self-identical instant in time"?
If now the same word "same" is given similar
treatment in S23(d), it rapidly collapses into the following linguistic mess:
S23(e): No object is
self-identical at the same and not the same and not the same and not the same
and not the same and not the same and not the same and not the same
self-identical instant in time.
As each "same" in
S23(d) is
replaced with its 'dialectical meaning': "same and not the same".
[As should seem clear, this process of
'dialectical' explication can be continued indefinitely. However, an "excessive
tenderness" for my readers' eyesight and sanity prevents me from
extending it any further.]
Of course, some might feel that the above is a ridiculous
explication of "same" as that word is used in
DL. Maybe so, but until
dialecticians tell us what they do mean by their sloppy use of such words, it will
have to do.
Moreover, it would be to no avail to argue that
bags of sugar, for example, are the "same, yet different" (employing the
IED-gambit, again) since Trotsky had already scuppered that
response by declaring that all things are never the same:
"Again one can object: but a
pound of sugar is equal to itself. Neither is true -- all bodies change
uninterruptedly in size, weight, colour etc. They are never equal to
themselves." [Trotsky
(1971), p.64. Italic emphasis added.]
If objects and processes are never the same,
they can't be "the same, yet different", they can only be "different, yet
different". Of course, if they are indeed the "same, yet
different" then it can't also be true that they are never the same, "never
equal to themselves". Either way, any employment of this IED explodes it in the face of those reckless enough to
try to use it.
It
could be objected that Trotsky really meant that objects couldn't simply be the same, but that they are always the same yet
different. However, we have seen in Essay Four that that option results in even
greater confusion!
In that case,
it is now clear that it is impossible to refute the
LOI in the same crude way attempted by Trotsky (irony intended). As the
above shows, this can't be done without using the LOI in any endeavour to do just
that. Hence, anyone
wishing to argue on exactly the same lines as Trotsky (or Hegel) will be
forced to use the LOI twice -- first: by having to reproduce an
identical copy of that argument; second: by using the LOI applied to tensed
variable letters (or their equivalent in ordinary language) to establish their case.
The question now is: How might anyone who
agrees with Trotsky accomplish the 'very same' task without falling into this
double trap?
By means of
semaphore,
telepathy or
Aldis Lamp?
Did Trotsky
Understand Identity?
Learning About Identity In A World Where There Supposedly Isn't Any
As seems reasonably plain, in
order to draw conclusions from a putative identity statement like S1, Trotsky
must have been able to understand the words it contained -- even if he
subsequently claimed that such propositions weren't strictly or always true. Clearly,
therefore, Trotsky had to be able to comprehend the LOI before he
could criticise it -- and the same goes for Hegel, too.17
S1: A is equal to
A.
But, this raises another serious question:
From where did Trotsky's understanding of the LOI originate? It isn't easy
to see how it was possible for him to have grasped the concepts involved if he only ever
encountered them in false sentences, or if their use was never
absolutely legitimate, as was claimed in S9:
S9(a): All bodies change uninterruptedly. (b) They are never equal to themselves.
On the
surface, it would seem impossible for anyone to learn what something meant if
all they ever experienced
weren't
examples of the very thing they were being taught, or if they were all incorrect
instances of it.18
The Sting In The Tail
Of course, it could be objected here that
Trotsky's ability to understand everyday words for identity is irrelevant since
the concepts they express are only valid "within certain limits"; even
dialectical concepts only approach the truth "asymptotically".19
Hence, although Trotsky clearly knew how to
use ordinary language, it could be argued that
DL reveals that the
vernacular is in fact ill-suited to depict change adequately. Indeed, the whole point of philosophical criticism is
to demonstrate that everyday notions (which are perfectly legitimate in their
own sphere of application) are incapable either of reflecting fundamental
aspects of change or the fluid nature of reality. This has nothing
to do with understanding or even with failing to understand anything.
Or so an objection
might go.
However, this problem doesn't
just affect the vernacular; the same considerations apply to technical and
scientific languages. They would be unusable unless it was
possible to specify the conditions under which their empirical propositions were
true or the conditions under which they were false (should there be any). [Why this is so will be examined in
Essay Twelve Part One. Those who
might be tempted to refer to Hegel's criticisms of the
LEM should read
this, and then perhaps think
again.]
But,
if identity statements can't ever
be true -- not just as a matter of fact, but of logic --, it
would surely be impossible for anyone to comprehend them. Even assuming identity
statements are only ever approximately true, no one would be able to
grasp their content, if that were the case. That is because it would be impossible for anyone to
comprehend in what way such ordinary identity statements could fall short of
something (i.e., "absolute identity") that was never anywhere
instantiated in reality; hence, no one would have the slightest idea what "approximate
identity" actually approximated to.
This point isn't easy to see, so some elaboration is necessary.
Trotsky described
objects and processes as follows:
"[A]ll bodies change
uninterruptedly in size, weight, colour etc. They are never equal to
themselves…. For concepts there also exists 'tolerance' which is established
not by formal logic…, but by the dialectical logic issuing from
the axiom that everything is always changing…. Hegel in his
Logic established a series of laws: change of quantity into quality,
development through contradiction, conflict and form, interruption of
continuity, change of possibility into inevitability, etc…." [Trotsky
(1971),
pp.64-66. Bold emphases added.]
If, as a matter of logic, 'absolute
identity' is nowhere instantiated in reality (which seems to be the
significance of the use of the word "axiom", above; indeed, Trotsky is merely
paraphrasing a bogus 'logical' argument
Hegel
cobbled-together), how would anyone
be able to declare with any confidence
that approximate identity failed to match this ideal by so much or so little?
Worse still, if no one had any grasp at all of perfect identity, how
could
dialecticians be so sure that it is never instantiated in nature or society?
In such circumstances, exactly what is being ruled out?
It is no good, either, appealing to sentences
like S1a to answer queries like this since all such sentences are material objects
in their own right, and because of that are surely susceptible
to Trotsky 'lens argument'. On that view, no material copy of S1 or S1a would
identical to itself, or to any subsequent copy of it, and no copy of S1 or S1a would stay
the same over time -- since "They [too] are never equal to themselves". In that case,
S1a-type sentences can't actually inform us of exactly
what Trotsky and/or Hegel were ruling out. Clearly, in order to do so, their content
would have to remain the same, which possibility is something S9a, S9b
and S1a exclude.
So, we have as yet no idea what 'absolute', or even 'abstract', identity could
possibly be, since no material embodiment of it would fully express this
'concept', given this view.
S1: A is equal to
A.
S1a: A is both equal
to non-A and to non-non-A.
S9(a): All bodies change uninterruptedly. (b) They are never equal to themselves.
[Here, in this
Hegelianesque
'proposition', the "non-non-A" refers to the negation of the negation of
A, as new content 'emerges'. (The 'relative stability of words and meanings'
response will be considered presently.) See also,
Note 15.]
Again, that is because, if we now represent S1a
by the propositional letter "P", we are instantly faced with serious problems,
as S1a is applied to its own material embodiment -- the very material
sentence expressed by P:
S1b: P is equal to
non-P and to non-non-P.
And then, if we replace each "P" with what it is
'dialectically' identical with, we would have:
S1c: Non-P is equal to
non-non-P and to non-non-non-non-P.
S1d: Non-non-P is equal to
non-non-non-P and to non-non-non-non-non-non-non-non-P.
And so on, ad infinitem.
And, there is little point irritated DM-fans arguing that this is
ridiculous, since the Hegelian rule (expressed in S1a) directly implies the bowl of
logical spaghetti represented by S1d. Hence,
only the rejection of
S1a will prevent this logical bindweed from propagating itself.
Worse still, such material embodiments can't tell us what
'approximate identity' is even an approximation to.
And, if identity statements are never
absolutely true (in this material world), how could anyone learn what the
implications of accepting or rejecting sentences like S1 amounted to? Again, what exactly would they be
accepting or rejecting?
[Note the significance of the italicised
word, "exactly" above. No irony was intended, just a reminder that we can't evade or
side-step the use of the
LOI as a rule of language if we are to understand one another. If anyone knew
exactly what they were rejecting by repudiating absolute identity, then
they would have to use, and hence implicitly accept, the LOI (as a rule of language) in that very act of repudiation!]
Even to ask the question requires a use of
the dread LOI. If no one has a clue what absolute identity is (and on this
theory, just as soon as anyone claimed they did have just such a clue, that very idea
would itself change, if DL
were correct),
the question naturally arises:
What precisely is being rejected by the
repudiation of sentences like S1?
S1: A is equal to
A.
If, on the other hand, the LOI encapsulates
what is in effect merely an empirical
truth -- even if only an approximate one -- we would still be owed an
explanation of what this empirical truth approximates to. And how could that be
ascertained in
this world if we never encounter the absolute limit of identity -- and
worse: if we don't know what it is,
even in theory, and (supposedly) can't express it in any known language?
It is no use, either,
appealing to a more rigorous definition of this 'law' -- such as Leibniz's --
since any material embodiment of that 'law' must change even as it is being written,
spoken or thought about, if Trotsky and Hegel are to be believed. In which case,
if DL is correct, we couldn't even theorise a correct application of this 'law',
or imagine an 'absolute' version of it so that we might then rule one or both
out as 'empirically limited', or 'true only within certain limits'.
Questions like these apply equally well to
any rejection of propositions expressing identity (as false, or as only
partially/relatively true) -- just as they apply to
the thoughts and/or words (which would also change just as soon as they were
formed/thought) of those that raise doubts about the material application of this 'law' (again, as
supposedly correct 'within certain
limits'); the negation of an identity
statement requires an understanding of what would make it true so that it
might legitimately be rejected as false
--,
even if this is only to point out how limited or "one-sided" it is.
But, if there is
no way of saying what would make an identity statement true, its denial must
lack a sense, for, once more, no one would have the slightest idea what was
being ruled out.
Hence, the earlier question about what Trotsky did or didn't
understand is relevant after all.
It could be argued that it is possible to say what would
make an identity statement true; it is just that they are never absolutely true.
However, as we will soon see, in order for anyone to be able to say that such
statements are never true, the content of at least one identity statement would
have to remain exactly the same over that same length of time, otherwise, anyone
who criticised the absolute application of the LOI wouldn't be using, or appealing to,
the same principle from moment-to-moment, day-to-day, or year-to-year. In this,
it is quite easy to see there are several applications of the LOI (as a rule of
language), and over many years, too.
Once more, any rejection of the LOI self-destructs, for if it isn't possible for
at least one identity statement to remain exactly the same over a given length
of time, then that will apply to any sentence a putative objector might think to use,
too. In that case, what Hegel had to say about this 'law' must also have changed
-- implying that we can't now access what he really meant to say. On the other
hand, if what he had to
say hasn't changed, then what Hegel had to
say was false.
[Abstract identity will be
discussed below.]
Again, it could be objected that identity
statements are in fact both true and false (this would seem to be the
implication of repudiating the LEM as it is believed to apply without
qualification -- and it seems to be what underlies S1a). But, it is entirely unclear what
even that
could mean in relation to the LOI. It
would either imply that material identity only
approximates to absolute identity (since no one would then have a clue what absolute identity was, on
this view), or if it is false then material identity would still only approximate to
absolute identity, because, again on this view, identity propositions are
merely, we are told, approximations.
Either way, no identity statement would be absolutely true.
S1a: A is both equal
to non-A and to non-non-A.
[LEM = Law of Excluded Middle.]
But,
both of these amount to the same criticism of the LOI (i.e., that it only captures
approximate identity in this world), and since we still have no idea
what ordinary identity approximates to, this particular objection is
itself completely
empty. We still remain in the dark over exactly what is being ruled in or out (that is, we
still have no idea what it is that approximate identity approximates to) -- with or without an
appeal to the truth or falsity of the LEM.
So: even if the LOI were both true and
false, and the LEM was as unsafe to use (unrestrictedly) as we have been told by
dialecticians, what exactly would the ascriptions
contained in any material example of the LOI be both true and false of?
But, no answer to that can be given short of a clear grasp of absolute identity,
which, alas, no one is supposed to have.
In that case, this new set of
'difficulties' is independent of
whether the LEM is safe, unsafe, or both.
Again, it could be pointed out that we do
have a clear idea what absolute identity amounts to; it is just that it doesn't
apply to anything in reality. And the following is what we associate with it:
S1: A is equal to
A.
We can surely have a clear idea of something even if it is never
true, if it is only partially true, or if it is never instantiated in reality.
Or so an objection might go.
But, in that case, as pointed
out above, if DL is valid, even that 'clear idea' will have to remain the same from
moment-to-moment, year-to-year,
generation-to-generation, and if that is itself so, then there is something in
reality that instantiates an absolute application of the LOI, namely this
'clear idea'. On the other hand, if this 'clear idea' doesn't remain the
same over many centuries, or even from moment to moment,
then we wouldn't have a 'clear idea' of absolute
identity!
Once again, it could be objected that propositions about identity
could still be true and false, so that one option (i.e., the truth of
identity statements) needn't necessarily mean that the other must be set in
opposition to it. Maybe so, but if we still have no idea what absolute identity
is then neither option is viable, whatever anyone does with it. In that
case, if no one has a clue what the subject of both this denial and this
affirmation amount
to,
if no one knows what the 'concept' of absolute identity is, then nothing true or
false (or both, or neither) could be said of 'it'.
In order to see this, the reader should try to say something true or false
about Meskonators (over and above a handful of trivialities,
perhaps relating to the spelling of
that word, for instance).
["Meskonator" is a meaningless word; a pure
invention of mine!]
Plainly, if no one knows
what a Meskonator is, then no one could possibly know if anything
approximated to 'it', or what was absolutely identical to, or totally different
from, 'one of them'.
Of course, with identity itself,
the situation
is even worse, for the last sentence couldn't even be formulated coherently if
"Meskonator" is replaced by "identity", and no one knew what absolute identity
was. The latter term would then be implicated in its own lack of meaning, as
opposed to being implicated in that of another word.
To be
sure, identity isn't an object -- but who
says 'a' Meskonator is? If we have no 'clear idea' of the nature of either of
these, or, indeed,
no idea at all, then we would be in no position to say anything coherent about them. Worse still,
given the way that relational terms (such as "identical") are depicted in DM (i.e., as abstract objects
-- we saw this in Essays Three
Part One,
Four Part One, and Eight
Part Three), dialecticians are the last ones who may legitimately raise this particular objection.
However, the situation is even worse
than the above might suggest. As hinted earlier, if
dialecticians are correct, just as soon as anyone claimed they had an idea of
absolute identity (via 'abstraction', or whatever), that idea itself (which must be embodied
in some form or other in this changing material world, or in the central
nervous system) must alter, and hence become different
-- since all objects and processes "are never
equal to themselves" (bold added).
But in that case, how could anyone tell whether that idea had changed without being
able to compare that altered idea of absolute identity with another idea
of absolute identity that hadn't
changed? Without that comparison, no one would be in any position to say whether their idea
of absolute identity (a) coincided
with absolute identity itself, (b) fell short of it, or (c) was totally different from it.
And, concentrating on words
or concepts 'in the
mind' -- contemplated or not by 'speculative reason',
à
la Hegel --, would be to
no avail, either. If DM is correct then nothing remains the same: not
words, not thoughts (whether these are, or aren't, about absolute identity, or even about
this wishy-washy
DM-approximation to it), not anything. Now, if that is true, then
not even the last sentence could be securely grasped, for it, too, contains a phrase we
have yet to comprehend: "absolute identity" -- since it would change just as soon as
it was either perceived, conceptualised or vocalised.19a
Furthermore, if words
or concepts actually remained the same (even if only temporarily), then Trotsky's (and Hegel's)
criticisms of the LOI would be seriously compromised. Hence, an appeal to the
'relative' stability of words and concepts would be of little assistance to
beleaguered DM-fans. If we have no idea what the original phrases "absolute
identity" and "approximate identity" relate to (i.e., if we have as yet no clue
how far short of, or how close to, the intended target they lie), then we would surely have
no way of knowing if and when such words remained stable --, i.e., "absolutely
identical", or even "approximately identical", with themselves over time. Hence,
if the DM-view of the LOI is correct, 'relative stability' is itself parasitic
on a concept we don't as yet comprehend:
identity in any of its forms.
And, it is little use
arguing that minor changes in
words over short periods of time can be ignored, for on this view we would have
no way of knowing by how far or how little each word has or hasn't altered if we
still haven't a clue what absolute identity is so that we might compare such
altered words with exemplars of them that haven't changed.
Some might want to argue that it is
reasonable to assume our words remain the same from moment-to-moment;
but, on this view, since we don't yet understand the word "same" (let
alone "assume"), no one would know if
anyone else was employing that word in the 'same' way as anyone else, or even in the
'same' way as they themselves had used it only a few seconds earlier!
Unless, of
course, we grant our brains and our memories with an exemption certificate in
this respect.
[There is more
on this in the next sub-section.]
Once identity is questioned
(at any level),
all such
comparisons and contrasts fail.
In short, there is no way out of the
Dialectical
Hole Hegel dug for all those who believe exactly the same
about identity as him (irony intended).
'Abstract'
And 'Approximate' Identity
In response, it could be
objected that
the above comments are completely misguided since Trotsky's argument was aimed
at showing how no absolute sense could be made of the LOI when applied to
objects and processes in
material reality. He only needed to appeal to
approximate identity in the first instance -- the sort of identity we meet
in everyday life (from which the LOI has been abstracted) -- to underline
the limitations of the Ideal or abstract version of LOI when it is confronted with
concrete reality and change. The same perhaps could be said of Hegel (no
irony intended).
[To save on needless repetition, whenever I refer to "absolute
identity" I also mean "abstract identity" (as DM-theorist appear
to understand both terms), and vice versa.]
To that end, therefore, the relative
apparent stability of material objects allowed Trotsky to refer coherently to such
things as the "same" instant, or the "same" object changing over time, and so
on -- perhaps employing the IED
argument, once more. This certainly
didn't commit him to using the LOI in order to
criticise it. Trotsky was obviously arguing dialectically, accessing
everyday notions to show how they become contradictory when they are applied
beyond the usual boundaries of commonsense.
Or, so the argument might go.
However,
and once again, if sense is to be made of
approximate identity, some grasp must surely be had of absolute identity so
that a vague idea might be formed of what this watered-down version of it
actually approximates to. If this is to be achieved by a retreat
into the abstract then we are no further forward.
Indeed, if there is a problem about material
(or even approximate) identity in this world, there must surely be an even more intractable one
about the nature of abstract identity in an Ideal world. In the
absence of a clear account of this abstract notion of identity, we would still
have no idea what ordinary identity is approximating to. But, how might
that be determined without another surreptitious appeal to the LOI?
Hence, we
would surely need to know by how much or how little approximate identity
was or wasn't absolutely identical to absolute identity itself before we could even
begin to 'abstract' absolute identity into existence. Waving a phrase about (i.e.,
"abstract identity") in no way helps anyone understand what concrete identity
is supposed to
approximate to.
Consider this sentence:
A1: Approximate identity is approximately
identical with absolute identity.
Until we understand absolute identity, any approximation to it
will remain an
empty notion.
Moreover, and more concretely: Just how is the sense of
this abstract notion of identity fixed so that two or more references to it at
different times might pick out identically the same target, as opposed to
nearly the same target? How might even a latter day Hegel determine whether the
notion he had formed one day of absolute identity was or was not absolutely (or
even approximately)
identical with the one he had accessed on another?
Consider further these sentences:
A2: Comrade NN means by "abstract identity"
exactly the same as comrade NM.
A3: Comrade MM means by "abstract identity"
approximately the same as comrade MN.
A4: Comrade NP means by "abstract identity" exactly the same as
she did yesterday.
A5: Comrade PN means by "abstract identity" approximately the
same as he did yesterday.
A6: Comrade PQ's memory of "abstract identity" is exactly the same as it was
yesterday.
A7: Comrade NQ's memory of "abstract identity"
is approximately the same as it
was yesterday.
How
could anyone determine what the word "same" meant in any of the above contexts before they knew what the intended goal was
(i.e., identity itself)? For
all anybody knew, an
intentional target
like this could be entirely different in the minds of two different abstractors,
or even in the mind of one of them. It isn't as if either of them could
check inside each other's skulls, or access their present or past thoughts to monitor their
precision. But, how do dialecticians themselves lock on to
identical ideas of abstract identity, those they supposedly share exactly
the same with one
another (or with Hegel, or with Trotsky, or with Lenin...) -- even before they
had managed to determine what the supposed
target of their words happens to be -- and, indeed, whether there is in fact one target
here, or many -- or if
there is in fact anything there at all? Is it just luck? Or, do they know something the rest of us
don't?
Moreover, if memory were
capable of accessing what each of us meant by "identity" --, say, even the day
before (never mind several years ago) --, how might any of us ascertain if we recalled this
word
the same, or differently, each time? Or, the even same from moment-to-moment? Plainly, in order to do
that we would have to have access to a concept of identity that didn't change
-- that is,
we would have to appeal to the only thing in the entire dialectical universe
that had received a Developmental Exemption Certificate from the hand of
Heraclitus himself: the word "identity" (or our 'idea' of it).
And we can't simply assume
this is possible; if no one knows what absolute
identity is, then an assumption to the effect that it means this, or it means
that, would be about as useful as
assuming that (a?) Meskonator is, say, a new brand of deodorant. Nor can
we appeal to
ordinary language for assistance. If this theory undermines the vernacular --
which we have seen it does -- then it can't possibly help rescue the very thing that caused the
problem.
To be sure, as language users we already know
what our words for
identity and difference mean -- that is, we know how to use them. This can be seen from the fact that few readers
who have made it this far
will have failed to grasp the import of the examples of the use of these terms
in everyday contexts given earlier in this Essay. However, in these new and rarefied 'dialectical' contexts, where
vagueness, obscurity and ceaseless change rule the day, ordinary terms fare rather badly. Even worse,
the jargonised
expressions dialecticians inherited from Hegel survive not at all. In
fact, they commit
hara-kiri, as we have just seen.
Plato, Hegel, Trotsky And The Concept
Of 'Abstract Identity'
[This material used to appear in Note 20.]
The
serious problems associated with abstractionism
were rehearsed in Essay Three Parts
One and
Two.
However, for present purposes, consideration need only be given to the following
question: How could anyone possibly abstract into existence the -- or even
a -- concept of
absolute or abstract identity?
[Again, I will merely refer to
'Absolute Identity', but this should be taken to include 'Abstract
Identity'.] If absolute identity is nowhere to be found in
reality, what is there for novice abstractionists to begin to work on? At least
cats have the decency to exist as cats -- not 'approximate cats' -- in the natural
world so that even a vague idea of the Abstract Cat could be assembled
(so we are told). With such accommodating felines, abstractionists at least have
something to get their metaphysical teeth into.
And, it isn't as if absolute identity is
"what
all forms of material identity have in common" (since according to DL they
don't -- nothing in reality instantiates absolute identity, so nothing
could possibly share it),
as the Abstract Cat is supposed to be what all cats have in common.
Absolute identity can't underlie all forms of approximate identity
(otherwise they wouldn't be approximate versions of it!). This 'concept' isn't
the 'general form of identity', either. If it were, then everything would
instantiate it. There thus seems to be no grist for
the 'dialectical mill' to grind away at, here.
It could be objected that mathematicians,
for example, regularly abstract into
existence points, lines and planes (and other such objects) that nowhere exist
in reality. If so, what is the problem?
But, no mathematical point, line
or plane shares any of its features with material points, lines or
planes -- for example, points have no shape, circumference, diameter, thickness
and they aren't made of anything -- so they can't have been abstracted from
them, nor can 'abstract points line and planes' be applied to their
supposed physical correlates as a general law, as we are told should be the case
with 'abstract concepts' in 'dialectics'. [More details about this will be given in a later
Essay. Until then, see
here, but more specifically,
here.] The same goes for other mathematical concepts and objects. What
mathematicians actually do is to make use of a publicly accessible language (albeit one that has
often been translated into
their own symbolic code
or shorthand); they then extend the terms already in use by
analogy, metaphor, re-definition, etc. If this weren't so, they wouldn't
be able to agree among themselves what their proofs actually demonstrated. That
explains why mathematicians don't even think to scan each other's brains when they check
new proofs; nor do they indulge in psychometric testing to assess the work of
other theorists in their field. But, they would have to do this if they were dealing with
abstractions. And it is no use appealing to a common mathematical language here,
since, if abstractionism were true, the meaning of the terms in that language
would be given by the abstract ideas in each individual mathematician's skull.
In which case, no mathematician would mean the same
by the words they use
as any other in the field.
Communication would be impossible. [This is quite apart from the fact that the
entire abstractionist case grew out of
bourgeois individualist epistemology -- on that, see
here.]
[I have said more
about mathematical abstraction and 'mental arithmetic',
here and
here.]
Furthermore, how would it be possible to abstract into existence, say, the
Complex
Plane, an
Abelian
Group or
Hermite Polynomials? Or
even, as noted earlier, a
mathematical point? In material reality, what would there be for anyone to
'mentally slice' up in this regard? Worse still, how would anyone know if and
when they had reached, or created, the right 'mental' target? Does a bell ring or a
light go on when each lone abstractor hits the 'correct idea'?
Indeed, how would it be possible for
dialectical abstractors to know when they, too, had succeeded in abstracting the
right concept? How would they know whether their individual ideas of
absolute identity are absolutely identical with 'absolute identity itself' -- or identical with the ideas abstracted into existence by fellow
abstractors of the 'same' notion --, without already having a
concept of absolute identity by means of which they could compare it, or them?
Once again, approximate identity
would be of no use here since that notion could only tell aspiring abstractors
that they had approximated to a concept they hadn't yet derived or obtained. And, how
might they become aware of their having fallen short even of that ideal target if they
don't already possess it?
It is little help knowing that abstractors have approximated to a
'who-knows-what?' sort-of-concept if no one knows what this 'who-knows-what?' sort
of concept is, which they were supposedly approximating to.
As should seen clear, the word "identity" in the phrase "approximate identity"
will as yet have no meaning, or no "determinate" meaning (on this view
-- I am not expressing my own opinions here!)
until that concept (i.e., 'identity itself') had been 'obtained'.
And, how might
anyone know they had managed to do that correctly without already knowing what
absolute identity is so that they could determine if the concept they had 'obtained' is
(or isn't) identical with its supposed target? In that case, the phrase "approximate identity"
would be both meaningless and useless.
And, manifestly the word "identity" can't itself also mean "approximate identity", otherwise "approximate
identity" would then have to become
"approximate approximate identity". Not only does that odd phrase still
use the problematic word, "identity", it has now been buried underneath another layer of
approximations -- and,
it is worth recalling,
these are still approximations to
'who-knows-what?'
Once more, the phrase "approximate identity"
must surely remain meaningless until absolute identity has itself been 'abstracted into
existence'. But, given this theory, how would a single abstractor know what she
or he was looking for if all they have to guide them is
this permanently meaningless phrase?
To use an analogy: you can look for your keys if you don't know where they are,
but not if you don't know what they are.
Try looking for, say, a
Meskonator
(sic).
No luck?
Well, now try abstracting one, or the 'concept' of one!
Or, even an 'approximate Meskonator',
just
for starters.
Still no luck?
Perhaps you don't 'understand'
dialectics!
It could be objected that
'Meskonators' don't already feature either in language or in the world, so this
analogy misfires. However, the point of raising that analogy was to underline the
fact that it isn't possible to abstract something if no one has a clue what any of the
words that are supposedly being used to depict it, or search for it, actually
mean. And since no one has a clue what absolute identity is (given the truth of
this theory), it can't therefore be abstracted into existence -- and hence, neither
can 'approximate identity'.
To be sure, we already use words for identity, and these feature in practices
around which various rules for the use of this narrow vocabulary have grown over the
centuries.
But, it is our use of these words that tells us what identity is, not some 'law',
nor yet some 'concept' of 'absolute identity' -– still less the obscure writings
that Hegel conned his publishers into publishing. [On this, see Note 20a,
below.]
In that case, howsoever it is conceived, the process of
abstraction is surely surplus to requirements; in order to abstract absolute
identity successfully into existence abstractors would already need to have
access to that very concept
in order to be able to decide if they had arrived at the right
target. They will need to know whether or not any of the concepts they have lined-up in their
thoughts ready to assume the legitimate title is the rightful heir, or is just a
pretender
to the throne. And, how are they going to do that without already having the
'concept' they were looking for?
Imagine for a
moment that Abstractor NN was searching for a concept she called
'Absolute Identity' -- or, "AB", for short. Let us suppose she
had managed to form a concept she called "CD" in her search for AB. The
question would then be: Is CD absolutely identical to AB? How might NN
decide without already having 'in her mind' the right concept, AB,
so that she could decide if her concept was identical with it?
Now, vary the
question slightly: Is CD approximately identical with AB? Again, how
might NN decide if she wasn't already in possession of the concept, AB,
but merely had an approximation to 'it' -- and when she can't even raise
that specific question without already having AB?
So, even if there were such a thing as 'the process of
abstraction', it would be of no use.
In fact, the same comments apply to the attempt to
abstract into existence any concept whatsoever; in order to form it
correctly, each concept would have to be known already.
So much was clear at least to
Plato.
It is worth pointing out here that this doesn't mean
I agree with Plato, only that this way of regarding abstract
ideas (or the names thereof) makes them resemble physical objects (or
the names thereof)
in the material world
so that it makes sense to pose the conundrum: "If you are looking for something
you must already know what it is. So, if you are looking for a concept,
you must already
have it. Otherwise you won't know what to look for."
This is a very short paraphrase of an argument in Plato's dialogue, Meno, and is
known as "Meno's
Paradox":
"Meno: And how will you
enquire, Socrates, into that which you do not know? What will you put forth as
the subject of enquiry? And if you find what you want, how will you ever know
that this is the thing which you did not know?
"Socrates: I know, Meno,
what you mean; but just see what a tiresome dispute you are introducing. You
argue that a man cannot enquire either about that which he knows, or about that
which he does not know; for if he knows, he has no need to enquire; and if not,
he cannot; for he does not know the very subject about which he is to enquire.
[Quoted from
here. Capitals in the original.]
A recent translation renders this passage as follows:
"Meno: How will you look for it,
Socrates, when you do not now at all what it is? How will you aim to search for
something you do not know at all? If you should meet with it, how will you know
that this is the thing that you did not know?
"Socrates: I know what you want to
say, Meno. Do you realise what a debater's argument you are bringing up, that a
man cannot search either for what he knows or for what he does not know? He
cannot search for what he knows -- since he knows it, there is no need to search
-- nor for what he does not know, for he does not know what to look for." [Plato
(1997b), p.880; 80 d5-e5.]
The confusion of concepts with objects in this way creates insoluble 'problems'
like this. Hegel's
'solution' was to invent concepts that 'self-develop' (predicated on a clear analogy
with objects that plainly do develop).
But, that is no solution, since we
still don't know if they are the correct
'concepts'! And
Hegel gave up the right to argue they were the right ones the moment he began to question
the LOI.
[This topic is
discussed in detail in Essay Three Parts
One and
Two, so the reader is
directed
there for more details. See also, Essay Four Part One (here,
here and
here) for my thoughts on the
general confusion of concepts with objects, which crippled Traditional
Philosophy for well over two thousand years.]
For Plato,
Identity
was a Form that exists in an ethereal world we inhabited before we were
born, and which he claimed explained how we
already
possessed this concept by the time we were born --
but then only vaguely after
that --,
since we had been acquainted with it in this pre-existing state. The shock of
birth all but wiped such concepts from our memories. The role of Philosophy was
therefore to remind us of what we already know, if we but knew it!
In
Plato's case, knowing the Forms was a type of recognition,
somewhat like recalling the faces of old friends. So, knowledge for Plato
was
recollection, a recalling to mind of the
'faces of long lost concepts', as it were,
reified (as
quasi objects!) in Platonic Heaven, which all
of us had encountered before birth. In that pre-existent state we all 'knew' the
Forms
because, as denizens of that Ideal World, we could see them, face-to-face, since they, too,
were in fact Ideal Objects (or as 'Exemplars' somehow masquerading as
Ideal Objects; Plato commentators are divided on this one!). It was a case of like recognising like
-- a pre-existent soul recognising a fellow 'Ideal Object'.
The
above dialogue continues:
"Meno:
Well, Socrates, and is not the argument sound?
"Socrates:
I think not.
"Meno: Why
not?
"Socrates:
I will tell you why: I have heard from certain wise men and women who spoke of
things divine that --
"Meno: What
did they say?
"Socrates:
They spoke of a glorious truth, as I conceive.
"Meno: What
was it? and who were they?
"Socrates: Some of them were priests
and priestesses, who had studied how they might be able to give a reason of
their profession: there have been poets also, who spoke of these things by
inspiration, like
Pindar, and many others who were inspired. And they say -- mark, now, and
see whether their words are true -- they say that the soul of man is immortal,
and at one time has an end, which is termed dying, and at another time is born
again, but is never destroyed. And the moral is, that a man ought to live always
in perfect holiness. 'For in the ninth year
Persephone
sends the souls of those from whom she has received the penalty of ancient crime
back again from beneath into the light of the sun above, and these are they who
become noble kings and mighty men and great in wisdom and are called saintly
heroes in after ages.' The soul, then, as being immortal, and having been born
again many times, and having seen all things that exist, whether in this world
or in the world below, has knowledge of them all; and it is no wonder that she
should be able to call to remembrance all that she ever knew about virtue, and
about everything; for as all nature is akin, and the soul has learned all
things; there is no difficulty in her eliciting or as men say learning, out of a
single recollection all the rest, if a man is strenuous and does not faint; for
all enquiry and all learning is but recollection. And therefore we ought not to
listen to this sophistical argument about the impossibility of enquiry: for it
will make us idle; and is sweet only to the sluggard; but the other saying will
make us active and inquisitive.
"Meno: Yes, Socrates; but what do you
mean by saying that we do not learn, and that what we call learning is only a
process of recollection? Can you teach me how this is?
"Socrates: I told you, Meno, just now
that you were a rogue, and now you ask whether I can teach you, when I am saying
that there is no teaching, but only recollection; and thus you imagine that you
will involve me in a contradiction." [Quoted from
here. Links added.]
[There
can be no generality associated with 'concepts' like this located in this Ideal
World: they are 'abstract objects' (and were thus singular in form), reified in our
'previous presence'. The importance of that observation was underlined in Essay
Three
Part One.
These comments will be connected with criticism of "Representationalism",
another dominant
ruling-class form-of-thought based on just this confusion (i.e., of
concepts with objects), in Essay Thirteen
Part Three.]
So, for Plato,
knowledge is based on recollection.
[Indeed, even for
Descartes, knowledge was based on a form of recollection; recollecting the
forms (his "clear and distinct ideas") that 'God' had planted in us all. In fact, this
is true of all forms of rationalist epistemology, even those that were propounded
by erstwhile atheists. So, for Chomsky, grammar (or 'unbounded
Merge') had been implanted in us all (i.e., in humanity) long before we were born, the result of
a mega-mutation in the brain of one of our ancestors, a theory as miraculous as
anything one finds in
The Book
of Genesis. So, we don't actually learn a language, we 'sort of remember
it' when we are inducted into a speech community as infants. (I have criticised Chomsky's theory in Essay Thirteen
Part Three. Readers are directed
there for more details.)]
[On this, see
Fine (2000, 2003b, 2007, 2018), Moravcsik (1971), and Scott (1999, 2007).]
Now, in modern
English we don't really have a word for this sort of knowledge (i.e., knowing
someone) -- "acquaintance"
is the closest we have, but it is far too weak (for example, not all your acquaintances
are your friends, and you are more than merely acquainted with the
latter).
We used to
have two such terms in
Old English (as they still do in German):
"witten" and "kennen"
(the latter word shows up in the song: "Do
you ken John Peel" -- I owe this point to
Peter Geach),
and there are two
in modern French:
savoir and
connaitre.
[On this, see
here
and
here.]
Knowing a Concept, or Form, was for
Plato like knowing (connaitre) a friend. Hence, in this life you couldn't
know that something was the correct Form unless you had already met it (and,
presumably, seen it, 'face-to-face'); for
him that was in this pre-existing state.
Unfortunately, this just confused propositional knowledge
(savoir) -- "NN knows that p" -- with personal knowledge (connaitre)
-- "NN knows MM" --, conflating both as different varieties of
acquaintance (this confusion crops up in Bertrand Russell's theory of 'Knowledge
by Acquaintance', but it is implicit in all empiricist theories of knowledge
-- a sort of obverse mirror image equivalent of rationalist theories, which
depend on 'innate knowledge' -- they are based on the conflation of objects
and concepts). So, this confusion has to a greater or lesser extent dogged
Epistemology ever since
Plato made it explicit (although from what he says, it seems it was implicit in
Greek religion and poetry long before).
Knowledge is thus viewed as a relation of some sort -- this is a relation we are said to have with the ideas, thoughts, 'representations', or 'qualia'
we supposedly have in our heads. Alternatively, it is a relation we have with
facts, propositions, statements, sentences, concepts, categories -- all in our
heads, or in 'heaven' (in the 'Mind of God'), or even in this world
somewhere, which we reflect in our heads. It resurfaces in this famous comment
of Marx's:
"To
Hegel, the life process of the human brain, i.e., the process of thinking,
which, under the name of 'the Idea,' he even transforms into an independent
subject, is the
demiurgos of the real world, and the real world is only the external,
phenomenal form of 'the Idea.' With me, on the contrary, the ideal is nothing
else than the material world reflected by the human mind, and translated into
forms of thought." [Marx
(1976),
p.102. Quotation marks
altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Link added.]
So, what had been for Hegel 'self-developing
concepts in the mind' were now 'objects in the world reflected in our minds',
just like ordinary objects are. It is the same confusion in reverse. All forms
of 'knowledge by reflection' depend on this ancient conflation.
So, objects of knowledge, since Plato's day (at least),
have been interpreted along these lines, that is, as
entities
referred to by Proper Names (abstract or even concrete), or other singular terms, which is why
abstract particulars
have become one of the most important factors in what is taken, by many, to be
'genuine' philosophical
knowledge (and hence in DM, too -- again as we saw in Essay Three
Part One). Here
is why:
"The ideas of the ruling class are in
every epoch the ruling ideas, i.e. the class which
is the ruling material force of society, is at the same time its ruling
intellectual force. The class which has the means of material production at its
disposal, has control at the same time over the means of mental production, so
that thereby, generally speaking, the ideas of those who lack the means of
mental production are subject to it. The ruling ideas are nothing more than
the ideal expression of the dominant material relationships, the dominant
material relationships grasped as ideas; hence of the relationships which make
the one class the ruling one, therefore, the ideas of its dominance. The
individuals composing the ruling class possess among other things consciousness,
and therefore think. Insofar, therefore, as they rule as a class and
determine the extent and compass of an epoch, it is self-evident that they do
this in its whole range, hence among other things rule also as thinkers, as
producers of ideas, and regulate the production and distribution of the ideas of
their age: thus their ideas are the ruling ideas of the epoch...." [Marx and
Engels (1970), pp.64-65, quoted from
here. Bold emphases added.]
[I have explained how
and why these ideas serve the interests of the ruling-class in Essay Three Parts
One and
Two.]
This meant that knowledge was in fact a relationship between the
'Knower'
and the 'Known' -- which
pair of 'objects' now faced each other like two acquaintances
--
just as it deflected attention away from the special nature of propositional (and
hence scientific) knowledge.
This in turn meant that both propositional and scientific
knowledge
were interpreted along similar lines, as a relation between the Knower and a
peculiar sort of object, a proposition -- now objectified and/or
reified
(as an object -- either a sort of shadowy entity in extra-mental reality or as
something lodged 'in the brain'). So, these days,
such reified objects are called "facts", or "truthmakers", and knowledge becomes a relation between
the
'Knower' and just such a fact ('in the head' or outside it). [On this, see also
here.]
[Incidentally,
this is also partly how the phrase "objective knowledge" entered
philosophical
currency. On that, see here. Notice, too, how this
model keeps cropping up all over the place: everything has to be 'objectified' or
given a Proper Name. This picture has held us captive for over two thousand years (to paraphrase
Wittgenstein). Exactly why
both Traditional-, and DM-theorists have fixated on this name-relation is explored in
Essay Twelve (summary here).]
This
ancient error also re-surfaces in
Engels's confused musings about the alleged relationship between
"thinking" and "being" --
in LF, for example -- where he too pictures knowledge as a relation between the knower
and the known, objectifying both, just like Plato.
This paradigm also lies behind his
asymptote metaphor: absolute knowledge is pictured as an Ideal sort of object
(or limit), toward which humanity is
ever moving. This is in effect a sort of reverse Platonism: instead
of being born into this world having (all but) forgotten the Forms, on this
view, humanity is collectively struggling toward them, this prolonged
dialectical meander subsequently(?) re-birthing humanity in a future
Ideal State of 'Objective Knowledge',
à
la
Hegel. So, DM is not so much 'upside
down' Hegelianism, as back-to-front Platonism! Not so much Hegel 'on his feet'
as Plato
Moon Walking!
[LF =
Ludwig Feuerbach And The
End Of Classical German Philosophy;
i.e.,
Engels (1888).]
So, the DM-Elect, gathered at some distant terminus,
atop 'Epistemological
Mount
Olympus' at 'the end of time' -- that is, should any make it that far -- will all know (connaitre), by direct acquaintance,
that they have arrived at
Epistemological Nirvana because they will recognise
it for the object it is. Failing that, a helpful Dialectical Guru
will lift the scales from their eyes allowing 'dialectical enlightenment' to
flood in.
This means that DM is a form of
Teleological
Platonism; humanity will regain what it lost by their 'epistemological fall from
grace' -- or, to use the buzz word, it will wave 'goodbye' to 'partial' and 'relative'
knowledge, and ascend to the sunny uplands of 'absolute knowledge'.
[Admittedly,
we have also (implicitly) been told that
humanity will never attain to this Blessed State, but it
is still the goal for any self-respecting DM-Truth-Seeker -- hence the term "Teleological Platonism".]
The other form of knowledge
(i.e., savoir, or propositional knowledge) can't be squeezed into this
bourgeois
individualist straight-jacket, and more
naturally harmonises with familiar social aspects of science.
[That was
one of the main topics of Essays Three Parts
One
and
Two.]
[However, for Hegel, knowledge also appears to
be a form of recollection -- on this see Magee (2008), pp.86-99. This ancient
nostrum
is thus no respecter of "genius".
(There is a summary of this
section of Magee's book, published at
a right-wing site (note especially the précis of Chapter Three of that book),
here.)
See also,
here.]
This then
'allows' Hegelians (and 'materialist'
dialecticians) to talk about concepts 'developing' as knowledge grows, since for
them propositional knowledge (savoir) has now been fused (à la Plato)
with some sort of personal knowledge
(connaitre) of concepts -- which also seem somehow to have developed in a
'Collective Mind' of some description,
as 'objects' of a special kind, right before our eyes --, at least in so far as
these 'concepts' or 'objects' have been illuminated by the light of 'speculative reason'.
The 'objective' and the 'subjective' are then joined together in a grandiose version of
the infamous 'Chymical
Wedding of Christian Rosenkreutz' (which
fantasy
was highly influential on Hegel's thought -- also detailed in Magee's
book, especially, pp.21-83; 223-257; the Introduction to that book has been
posted here).
[Concerning
the Hermetic and Rosicrucian background to all this (in addition to Magee (2008)), see
Essay Four Part One,
here.]
This also accounts for the
popularity of abstraction among dialecticians, since they, too, have
adopted this
bourgeois
individualist form of epistemology, even if they have stripped away much of
the mystical garbage Hegel dumped all over it.
From such seemingly insignificant 'linguistic false turns', large
metaphysical 'tumours' have grown. [More about this, too, in Essays Three Part Four
(when it is published), and
Twelve
Part One.]
Now, as
should seem obvious from other Essays at this site, I reject this entire way of
speaking about knowledge. I am employing these notions here in order to help undermine yet
another conservative thought-form that dialecticians have
imported into our movement
from Traditional Philosophy.
It is certainly not the case that I think we need to
know our concepts before we know them! But it is a very real paradox implied
by DM-Epistemology.
Some
might be tempted to appeal to the 'dialectical development' of concepts, but there is nothing here for
dialecticians
to begin with so that the DM-bandwagon can't even start to roll.
And yet, even if it could
begin to lumber on, there
would be no way of knowing whether, of any two dialecticians, that they had developed the very
same notion of absolute identity as any other DM-fan (without having a third
notion of it (possibly the same, possibly different) with which to compare
their results!). Plainly, in order to compare comrade NN's concept of Identity* with
comrade NM's concept of Identity**, we would need to have access to absolute
identity in order to decide whether or not they were approximately, or fully, identical --, as, indeed,
would be the case with
NN and MM.
[Asterisks were used in the previous paragraph to
indicate that these two 'concepts of identity' might be totally different in
each case -- and if DM-theorists are to be believed --, they will be different.
Because of Heraclitean change, coupled with Hegel and Trotsky's criticism of the
LOI, they can't be the same.]
Of course, if concepts have a sort of
life of their own (as they seem to have in Hegel's scheme-of-things), there would be less of a
problem (except perhaps one of accounting for their uncanny ability to regiment
themselves, lock-step, in the minds of those they colonise, with no one to
check on their progress). But, one would have thought materialists would pause at this point. In this
material world, with respect to absolute identity, there is nothing for abstraction to
begin with. According to Hegel and Trotsky nothing in material reality is
absolutely identical with anything else (or even with itself!). That being the
case, no concept of absolute identity could appear at the beginning of this process
(applied as some sort of 'law of cognition'), or even emerge at the end, for reasons explored earlier.
Not only that, but there isn't even an identical
terminus where all dialectical travellers must aim toward, let alone alight, which destination would help
them
decide whether or not one and all had abstracted the right concept(s) into existence, or even
whether or not they had done any of it to
very same concept all along -- or even to an approximate version as
they themselves had entertained, or as any
other dialectician wrestling with their own batch of individualistically
processed 'concepts', had.
And, as we have seen, the phrase "approximate identity" would be no use here since
it contains a word ("identity") that must forever remain empty until the right
objective had finally
been reached. And how might
that be decided upon?
Of course, the 'solution' to this
Platonic/Hegelian quandary is to dissolve it. [That
will attempted in Essay Twelve Part Six.]
In advance of that, the
reader is encouraged to think of a concept, not as a 'mental construct', or as a
rather strange sort of 'object' (in 'the mind', or anywhere else for that
matter), but the use of which is an expression -- or better, the use of which
depends on the
exercise of a specific linguistic skill, which has had to
be acquired through socialisation. This change of emphasis redirects attention away from a
mysterious, hidden, inner world of
'abstracted objects' (and, indeed, away from socially-isolated, lone abstractors beloved of bourgeois
ideology), back toward the public arena where such skills are
acquired (in the open), and are subject to scrutiny and correction.
The above (very brief!)
HM account of concepts relocates their source
(which tradition would have it, used to be in a pre-existing world of Forms and
Abstractions) and places it in a pre-existing linguistic community,
which
community
socialises every single one of us in the above manner
(albeit heavily distorted by class-division).
We can now see that the role of Philosophy
isn't to inform us of the
Super-scientific
Truths of Traditional Philosophy, but to clear away the confusions created in our thought when we
allow ourselves to stray away from the
linguistic resources the above community has passed on to us -- when we allow "language to go on holiday", to paraphrase Wittgenstein.
That is, when we
forget to use the vernacular in the way we do in ordinary life. The key here is,
of course, to return to using the resource with which we are all familiar,
ordinary language; indeed, as
Marx himself enjoined.
Hence, the role of Philosophy is still
to remind us of what "we already know" (to paraphrase Wittgenstein,
again), and this it does by reminding us, in this case, that we already know how to use ordinary
words for identity,
and that we only end up confusing ourselves when we forget this and begin (mis-)using
words in the same way as Philosophers:
"Learning philosophy is really recollecting. We remember that we really use
words in this way. The aspects of...language which are philosophically most important are hidden
because of their simplicity and familiarity. [One is unable to notice something
because it is always (openly) before one's eyes.]" [Wittgenstein (1993), p.179.
Paragraphs merged.]
Dialectical Dilemma
As we
also discovered in Essay Three Parts
One and
Two, theorists who rely on the existence of "abstract concepts"
(in order to help justify the "objectivity" of human knowledge) find themselves caught in a serious
dilemma at this point.
Either:
(1)
They admit that such concepts already
exist (independently of us), toward which human knowledge advances or
is approximating, or,
(2) They concede that it is we who construct such
notions out of experience by a mysterious process of 'abstraction' (which
still awaits explication).20
Option (2), it seems, underlies the proffered 'dialectical' response
rehearsed above, reiterated
by Lenin:
"Cognition is the eternal, endless approximation
of thought to the object." [Lenin (1961),
p.195.]
"Knowledge
is the reflection of nature by man. But this is not simple, not an immediate,
not a complete reflection, but the process of a series of abstractions, the
formation and development of concepts, laws, etc., and these concepts, laws,
etc., (thought, science = 'the logical Idea') embrace conditionally,
approximately, the universal, law-governed character of eternally moving and
developing nature.... Man cannot comprehend = reflect = mirror nature as
a whole, in its completeness, its 'immediate totality,' he can only
eternally come closer to this, creating abstractions, concepts, laws, a
scientific picture of the world...." [Ibid.,
p.182. Bold emphasis alone added.]
On the other hand,
(1) barely conceals its Platonic/mystical provenance, but which also appears to lie
behind Engels's (hopelessly unclear) asymptote metaphor:
"'Fundamentally, we can know only the
infinite.' In fact all real exhaustive knowledge consists solely in raising
the individual thing in thought from individuality into particularity and from
this into universality, in seeking and establishing the infinite in the finite,
the eternal in the transitory…. All true knowledge of nature is knowledge of the
eternal, the infinite, and essentially absolute…. The cognition of the
infinite…can only take place in an infinite asymptotic progress." [Engels
(1954),
pp.234-35.
Bold emphasis alone added;
paragraphs merged.]
"The identity of thinking and being, to
use Hegelian language, everywhere coincides with your example of the circle and
the polygon. Or the two of them, the concept of a thing and its reality, run
side by side like two asymptotes, always approaching each other but never
meeting. This difference between the two is the very difference which prevents
the concept from being directly and immediately reality and reality from being
immediately its own concept. Because a concept has the essential nature of the
concept and does not therefore prima facie directly coincide with
reality, from which it had to be abstracted in the first place, it is
nevertheless more than a fiction, unless you declare that all the results of
thought are fictions because reality corresponds to them only very circuitously,
and even then approaching it only asymptotically…. In other words, the unity of
concept and phenomenon manifests itself as an essentially infinite process, and
that is what it is, in this case as in all others." [Engels to Schmidt
(12/03/1895), in Marx and Engels (1975), pp.457-58, and Marx and Engels (2004),
pp.463-64. Bold emphasis added.]
Attentive readers
will no doubt have noticed how Engels treats the object of knowledge and
knowledge itself as "concept"-based:
"the
concept of a thing and its reality, run side by side like two asymptotes, always
approaching each other but never meeting.
This
difference between the two is the very difference which prevents the concept
from being directly and immediately reality and reality from being
immediately its own concept." [Ibid; bold added.]
While it isn't too
obvious what Engels is trying to say here, it is nevertheless reasonably clear that he seems to think
"reality" can be "its own concept", which can only mean that for him those
concepts are actually independent of our knowledge of them, in that they
are "reality". How would it be possible to approach them "asymptotically" if
that weren't so? In which case, they must predate human existence in some form.
Of course, it would
be unwise (and unfair) to place too much weight on these words of his -- an irredeemably unclear passage from
an unpublished letter -- and read some form of Platonism into it.
However, having said that, we have already seen (again, in Essay Three
Part One), that Traditional
Philosophers (including Hegel, and hence DM-classicists like Engels) regularly
confused talk about talk with talk about the world -- that is,
they ran together questions about how
language works with what language is supposedly about. More specifically,
they imported an ancient Greek and Medieval view of predicates both as (a)
Linguistic expressions, and (b) What those expressions refer to in
'extra-mental reality' -- and they then proceeded to fuse them together (under
Hegel's influence).
Briefly, here is the train-of-thought that led
DM-theorists by the nose in that direction (covered in extensive detail in the
above Essay):
The reconfiguration of predicate expressions as the
Proper Names of 'Abstract
Particulars' (by Ancient Greek Theorists) was greatly expanded and
elaborated upon in the Middle Ages by Roman Catholic Philosophers by means of
their newly-invented 'Identity
Theory of Predication', This was used to 'reveal' that what we might at
first sight take to be an ordinary predicative sentence (employing an otherwise
innocent-looking
copula
-- the verb "to be" --, for instance, in "John
is a man", Lenin's example) in fact expresses an identity relation between
the predicate expression and the subject term, or indeed, what they supposedly
'reflected' extra-linguistically. So, "John is a man " became "John is identical
with Manhood"; just as "John" refers to an extra-linguistic 'object', predicate
expressions (like "a man") also refer to something extra-linguistic
(traditionally this was one or more of the following: 'Platonic Forms', 'Universals',
'concepts', 'Ideas', 'abstractions'. Exactly where these were supposed to
exist depended on how consistent an Idealist a given philosopher happened to be.
This slide helped motivate the above confusion of
linguistic expressions with whatever they supposedly refer to
extra-linguistically. Hegel swallowed that confusion whole:
"To define the subject as that of which
something is said, and the predicate as what is said about it, is mere trifling.
It gives no information about the distinction between the two. In point of
thought, the subject is primarily the individual, and the predicate the
universal. As the judgment receives further development, the subject ceases to
be merely the immediate individual, and the predicate merely the abstract
universal: the former acquires the additional significations of particular and
universal, the latter the additional significations of particular and
individual. Thus while the same names are given to the two terms of the
judgment, their meaning passes through a series of changes." [Hegel (1975)
§169, p234.
Bold emphases added.]
"To say 'This rose is red'
involves (in virtue of the copula 'is') the coincidence of subject and
predicate. The rose however is a concrete thing, and so is not red only: it has
also an odour, a specific form, and many other features not implied in the
predicate red. The predicate on its part is an abstract universal, and
does not apply to the rose alone. There are other flowers and other objects
which are red too. The subject and predicate in the immediate judgment touch, as
it were, only in a single point, but do not cover each other.... In pronouncing
an action to be good, we frame a notional judgment. Here, as we at once
perceive, there is a closer and a more intimate relation than in the immediate
judgment. The predicate in the latter is some abstract quality which may or
may not be applied to the subject. In the judgment of the notion the
predicate is, as it were, the soul of the subject, by which the subject, as the
body of this soul, is characterised through and through." [Ibid., p.237, §172. Bold emphases added.]
Plainly, for Hegel, predicate expressions don't just
refer to 'universals',
they are 'universals', and are 'abstract' into the bargain -- in which
case, they thereby cease merely to be linguistic.
The rapid slither from there to the doctrine that
predicates are extra-linguistic, extra-mental entities in their
own right was further accelerated by the invention of the 'reflection theory of
knowledge' by dialecticians. Predicate expression now somehow, in some
as-yet-unexplained way, 'reflect' real material objects and processes in the
world. So, as we also saw in Essay Three Part One, it then became all to easy
for DM-theorists to run together linguistic expressions with what they
supposedly referred to or 'reflected' extra-mentally. [I have entered into this
in more detail,
here.]
For the above dialecticians, predicate expressions
now referred to 'abstractions'/'concepts' apprehended by, or cobbled-together
in, 'the mind' (depending on which DM-theorist one attended to) -- and this was
accomplished by the mysterious 'process of abstraction'. Unfortunately, that now
presented DM-theorists with the knotty problem in the shape of the
above dilemma, but with an added
twist -- the problem of explaining where exactly these
'abstractions'/'concepts' are supposed to exist. If they exist only 'in the
mind', what 'objectivity' do they possess? Alternatively, if they exist
extra-mentally, what form do they take? And where exactly do
they exist?
As we saw in Essay Three Parts One and Two, those
questions remain unanswered to this day.
However, in order for these 'abstractions' to be
able to deliver, or form part of, 'objective knowledge', they too had to be
'objective':
"Thought proceeding from the
concrete to the abstract -- provided it is correct (NB)… -- does not get
away from the truth but comes closer to it. The abstraction of matter,
the law of nature, the abstraction of value, etc., in short all
scientific (correct, serious, not absurd) abstractions reflect nature more
deeply, truly and completely." [Lenin (1961),
p.171. Bold
emphasis alone added.]
"Knowledge
is the reflection of nature by man. But this is not simple, not an immediate,
not a complete reflection, but the process of a series of abstractions, the
formation and development of concepts, laws, etc., and these concepts, laws,
etc., (thought, science = 'the logical Idea') embrace conditionally,
approximately, the universal, law-governed character of eternally moving and
developing nature." [Ibid.,
p.182. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at
this site.]
"Logical concepts are subjective so long as they
remain 'abstract,' in their abstract form, but at the same time they express the
Thing-in-themselves. Nature is both concrete and abstract, both
phenomenon and essence, both moment and relation. Human
concepts are subjective in their abstractness, separateness, but objective as a
whole, in the process, in the sum-total, in the tendency, in the source." [Ibid.,
p.208. Bold emphases alone added.]
Here we see this confusion (between linguistic
expressions and what they supposedly 'reflect' extra-linguistically)
in all its glory, for nature is now said to be abstract, just as human
concepts are supposed to be 'objective'! Of course, these ideas do not sit at
all well with what Lenin had said about 'objectivity' a few years earlier:
"To be a materialist is to
acknowledge objective truth, which is revealed to us by our sense-organs. To
acknowledge objective truth, i.e., truth not dependent upon man and mankind,
is, in one way or another, to recognise absolute truth." [Lenin (1972),
p.148. Bold
emphasis added.]
"Knowledge can be useful
biologically, useful in human practice, useful for the preservation of
life, for the preservation of the species, only when it reflects objective
truth, truth which is independent of man." [Ibid.,
p.157. Bold emphasis added.]
So, it seems that if an 'abstraction' (or a
'concept') is to be 'objective', or if it is to contribute to 'objective truth',
it must be independent of the human mind -- and if that is so, many of
them must have pre-existed the evolution of the human species.
I can see no way of avoiding that conclusion.
[If anyone does,
please let me know.]
We see this confusion (between linguistic
expressions and what those expressions supposedly refer to) float to
the surface in George Novack's truly awful book (about the 'Logic of Marxism'),
and his bizarre 'analysis' of the by-now-familiar sentence, "John is a
man":
"This law of identity of opposites, which so perplexes and
horrifies addicts of formal logic, can be easily understood, not only when it is
applied to actual processes of development and interrelations of events, but
also when it is contrasted with the formal law of identity. It is logically true
that A equals A, that John is John…. But it is far more profoundly true that A
is also non-A. John is not simply John: John is a man. This correct proposition
is not an affirmation of abstract identity, but an identification of opposites.
The logical category or material class, mankind, with which John is one and the
same is far more and other than John, the individual. Mankind is at the same
time identical with, yet different from John." [Novack (1971), p.92.
Bold emphases added.]
The supposed predicate "a man", which is a
linguistic expression, has now been transformed into a "category", and, just
as John is an 'extra-mental object', so is "mankind". So, the term, "a man", is
now both a linguistic expression and an extra-linguistic entity in its
own right. The two have now been run-together; which is the only reason the
predicate can be inserted into an identity relation with John. Plainly, John
can't be identical with a linguistic expression, but he can be said to be
identical with another extra-linguistic entity (conjured into existence by
this confusion, and by it alone).
[The "is" of predication (in "John is a man") has
also been reconfigured as an "is" of identity, and that in turn has been
transmogrified into an 'abstraction' -- "abstract identity". I have given
several further examples of this confusion of linguistic expressions with
extra-linguistic entities in the work of other DM-theorists in Essay
Three Part One -- especially,
here,
here, and
here. I have also subjected the above passage of Novack's to searching
criticism,
here.]
But, whichever horn of
this dilemma dialecticians finally grasp (if they ever actually make their minds
up, or are finally much clearer than Engels ever was), neither is welcome
news to those who accept the 'dialectical analysis of Identity' -- Trotsky's or Hegel's version.
There are at
least two main reasons for saying this about their take on identity:
(a) If there is an 'abstract concept' of
absolute identity towards which our knowledge slowly edges then presumably that
goal must remain the 'same' while it is being targeted. In that case, the LOI
must apply to it (since,
ex
hypothesi, it doesn't change).
But, no self-respecting DM-theorist
can possibly agree with a Platonic view of
abstract concepts like this, even though their 'asymptotic approach' metaphor,
and what has been argued in the last few paragraphs suggests that
they should. Admittedly, this is a controversial claim, but it may only
be neutralised when it becomes clear what this metaphor implies --
more pointedly, when it becomes clear whether or not it means that as far as
individual dialectical truth-seekers are concerned, there is indeed a goal (identical
in the case of each
dialectical pilgrim), which they have correctly targeted -- collectively or
severally -- toward which they are all slowly gravitating. Naturally, a positive
answer here would sink the dialectical analysis of the LOI,
since it would (i) make plain that this metaphor implies that there is
something unchanging called "absolute identity" that all dialectical
truth-seekers are homing in on, and upon which all are already --, or about
which they will be --, in equal agreement.
On the other hand, a negative response would undermine DL equally quickly; if there is no such goal then
(ii) approximate identity must approximate to
nothing at all.
(b) Alternatively, if human knowledge is
dialectically conditioned, and there are no abstract concepts that exist
independently of our knowledge of them, then there would be no objective way to
decide whether or not any two randomly selected dialecticians were aiming at the very same
intentional target. Indeed, they would be hard-pressed to say what could count as
the same goal in such circumstances (that is, without surreptitiously using the LOI in order to
help them decide). But, if such dialectical truth-seekers haven't
locked on to the very same target, then the second of the above
conclusions (i.e., point (a(ii)) above) must surely apply. In
that case, their search is, to put it bluntly, aimless.
It is headed nowhere, since there is nowhere for it to head. On the other hand, if there is a way of delving into the minds of any two
randomly selected dialectical abstractionists, and ask what it is that enables one
or both to
decide whether they are in pursuit of an identical goal, the first of
the above points would then apply (i.e., (a(i))) -- for it would then be
obvious
that these truth-seekers had used the LOI to identify exactly the same
intentional target,
and, indeed, had done it with equal accuracy.
In fact, if
anyone were to advocate, or even
reject, one or other of the above options, they would still have to appeal to the very
same 'law' in question in order to maintain the belief that approximate identity
is
more-or-less identical with abstract identity (whether or not "abstract identity"
was understood Platonically, or as a quasi-Hegelian/'dialectical' construct/abstraction),
or whether it isn't more-or-less identical with abstract identity. Of
course, this concept (i.e., abstract identity) would have to remain locked, rock solid
-- frozen in 'mental' or 'conceptual' space -- while it was being approximated
to.
If
that weren't so, this 'target' must surely have been
misidentified by anyone foolish enough to blaze an intentional path toward
such a mutating 'object'. As was argued in the last sub-section, unless dialecticians
were able to specify under what
conditions their notion of absolute (or abstract) identity doesn't change
over time -- but remains absolutely self-identical in the minds of
supporters and critics alike, and over many centuries, for them to be able to
say with confidence that they are talking about the same thing as one
another (or even the same thing as Hegel or Trotsky) --, any
reference to 'it' by critic and believer alike would be entirely empty.
Otherwise, they should acknowledge their irresolvable differences, and cease
their pointless blather.
And, even if
the concept of 'abstract identity' were to change (as it is apprehended by one
or all), then in order to express that very fact, some way must
be found to
declare that it was no longer absolutely identical with whatever it
used to be absolutely identical with. In that case, access to an unchanging version of absolute identity
would still be needed to classify any mutated version of absolute identity as a mutant.
Without that, of course, they would lose the right to say that absolute identity
has, or might
have, changed.
Indeed,
as should now seem obvious, we would need it not to change in order to say that it had!
[Once more,
this just underlines the intimate connection there is in language between change
and identity, contrary to what dialecticians will tell you -- if you were even bothered to listen.]
Moreover, an
implicit
reference to the LOI would have to be made as part of each and every claim that any randomly-selected dialectical
abstractionist or truth-seeker had a concept of 'abstract identity' which was identical with that of
any other, so that it could be said that they were referring to the same 'abstract concept'
when
making the 'same' point even about "approximate identity" --,
and that would have to be the case
even if
they were disagreeing!
But,
if these assumed ideas of "abstract identity" (or even of "approximate
identity") weren't exactly the same, then
agreement and disagreement over what they were talking about would be
illusory, too. On the other hand, of course, if these ideas were 'absolutely identical'
across two or more dialectical heads, then these criticisms of the LOI would
plainly self-destruct.
Which
explains the reference to
hara-kiri,
earlier.
Furthermore, if the
presumptive subject of enquiry here were only 'roughly identical' in the minds of the
many DM-fans sat round the dialectical table, not only would that fact be
both untestable and
unverifiable, it would mean that the topic of discussion would be
indeterminate, too -- and for the same reason. Again, this would mean that any
and all criticisms levelled against the LOI would have been misdirected, That is
because not only would no
one know exactly what "abstract identity" was so that it could be criticised
equally the same -- and by the use of identical arguments -- by those
who don't, shall we say, believe in the absolute validity of the LOI, no two critics of the
LOI would be able to say that they had the very same thing in mind when they
were even so much as pointing out its possible or actual limitations!
Indeed, they couldn't even use the word
"same" with any clear meaning in this or any other context --, and, annoyingly,
that would be so for the same reason.
On the other hand, if it were now conceded
that any two notions of strict (or even approximate) identity were exactly the
same in the minds of any two intrepid dialectical abstractors, so that it
could be said of one or both that they were talking
about the very same thing, there would be no point in criticising the
LOI, for it would be valid -- and admitted to be such -- at least here,
by its severest critics.
Worse still, if were denied
that anyone had an exact notion of strict identity (based on the claim that
everyone holds only an 'approximate copy' of it), we should still
want to know exactly what was being ruled out. In that case we
(they) would have to have an idea of strict identity to be able to deny they
(we) had any such idea!
Identity Schmidentity!
In order to underline this point, it might
prove helpful to consider an analogy: let us suppose that someone introduced a
word into the language -- say "schmidentity" -- but couldn't provide a single
example of anything in reality that exhibited "schmidentity".
If we were then told that
certain things were only "approximately schmidentical" (or even "schmidentical within certain limits") we would
still have no clear idea what this new word meant. If we don't know what
"schmidentity" is, we certainly don't know what "approximate schmidentity" is.
And calling this new 'concept' "abstract schmidentity",
"absolute schmidentity" -- or even "relative schmidentity"
-- would be equally
futile.20a
It could be objected that the
words we have for abstractions are merely extensions to words we already use in
language, so the analogy with "schmidentity" is inapt. In that case, abstract or
absolute identity would be an extrapolation from our ordinary words for
identity, etc. [This point has in fact been covered in the last few subsections.]
Even so, let us change the example. Suppose
someone introduced the phrase "absolute cat-hood" into the language, but
couldn't say what an 'absolute cat' was, or by how much the average moggie
differed from this quintessential feline.
I think we would judge this person radically confused;
we certainly wouldn't be inclined to adjust scientific, philosophical or ordinary
language to accommodate them.
In that case, until we are told by how much or how
little absolute or even abstract identity differs from our everyday words for
identity, we would be wise, I think, to adopt the same policy.
And, even though there are abstract nouns in ordinary language, their mode of
signification can't be assumed to be the same as that
of any allegedly analogous, or even typographically identical,
philosophical terms that have been thrown into the ring by Traditional Thinkers.
Indeed, we can say more than this: in view of the argument
in Essay Three
Part One, since ordinary
general terms retain their generality in everyday contexts -- whereas
these philosophical monstrosities don't --, the two are definitely not identical
(irony intended). Nor could one be an extension of the other if one of them destroys
or undermines what is unique to the other -- in this case,
an ability to express generality.
Of course, any dialecticians who disagree with this will have to abandon Trotsky's critique of the LOI, for if the two
sorts of terms
are identical, then the 'LOI' applies to them, at least.
[This commits me neither to a belief in absolute or abstract identity, but it does succeed in exposing the DM-'concept' as empty
at best, or
incoherent at worst.]
In that case, when
dialecticians presume to tell us that a set of words in ordinary
language connected with sameness and identity, which we all know how to use,
doesn't mean what we usually take it to mean (and they then proceed to highlight
its limitations, implying that our understanding of this set is defective to some extent, howsoever nuanced that
turns out to be), then the
onus would be on them to tell us what these dialecticians do mean by this set of words. Until they do,
they might as well be talking about schmidentity.21
Again, it is little point referring to Hegel's criticisms of the LOI.
As I have
demonstrated here,
he badly misconstrued this 'law', compounding his folly with a series of crass
errors over the nature of predication, among other things.
Indeed, for all DM-fans know, they could very well be talking about schmidentity -- or,
far more likely, nothing at all.
For example, how do they know that their 'notion of
identity' isn't 'absolutely identical' with schmidentity? Or, indeed with nothing?
The fact that I haven't defined "schmidentity" is no objection. They have yet to
tell us what they mean by their use of words for identity. In fact, they
mis-identify this word from the get-go -- and, what is even more interesting, they copied this exact
misidentification from Hegel! [Irony intended.]
In which case,
they probably are talking about nothing whatsoever.
Nevertheless, there are several other serious
problems that confront the objection outlined at the beginning of
the last subsection. What these are can be seen
when we consider the exact words Trotsky himself used to
criticise the LOI over 70 years ago (irony intended, once more).
Trotsky's Exact Words Dialectically
Implode
The claim that our concepts are only
approximately true -- if true itself -- would undermine DM more
effectively than anything that has been argued at this site.
In order to see this, let us introduce
the term "adequate" to describe the language belonging to, or used by, any
given theory, but
understood in the following manner:
S24: A language is adequate to a theory
if, when expressed in that language, the empirical propositions of that theory
can be deemed true (by appropriate means).
However, if it is impossible to
develop a language adequate to a theory no matter what we do, then it
would surely be impossible to grasp that theory's content, or determine
what it implied, or was even about. In the case of identity and DM, this problem is
particularly acute.
With respect to the matter-in-hand, this
fatal defect can be underlined by a consideration of Trotsky's own words:
"The
Aristotelian logic of the simple syllogism starts from the proposition that 'A'
is equal to 'A'…. In reality 'A' is not equal to 'A'. This is easy to prove if
we observe these two letters under a lens -– they are quite different to each
other. But one can object, the question is not the size or the form of the
letters, since they are only symbols for equal quantities, for instance, a pound
of sugar. The objection is beside the point; in reality a pound of sugar is
never equal to a pound of sugar -– a more delicate scale always discloses a
difference. Again one can object: but a pound of sugar is equal to itself.
Neither is true (sic) -- all bodies change uninterruptedly in size, weight,
colour etc. They are never equal to themselves." [Trotsky
(1971), pp.63-64.]
The question
here is: Are the above words
identical to the ones Trotsky actually wrote? Now, even though I have
carefully copied the above quotation of Trotsky's words from my own copy of IDM
(in fact I copied and pasted them from the on-line version), and
checked them against the versions found in TAR and RIRE, as no doubt others have done with their
own copies of these words --,
which copies themselves were copies of successive generations of further copies
of the originals --, despite all this, in one sense they aren't the very same words that
Trotsky committed to paper over seventy years ago: they are just copies! So, in that
sense they aren't exactly his words. Hence, if we count words as ink marks on
the page, or collections of pixels on a screen, they are manifestly not physically identical with the
originals. How could they be?
[IDM = In Defense of Marxism; i.e.,
Trotsky (1971); TAR = The Algebra of Revolution (i.e., Rees (1998); RIRE
= Reason in Revolt (i.e., Woods and Grant (1995/2007);
UO = Unity of Opposites/Unities of
Opposites, depending on the context.]
On the other hand, in another
perfectly ordinary sense of the term, the words quoted above are
identical with the originals; they are Trotsky's words, and that is why his
followers constantly quote them. We have criteria of identity for words
(and also for ink marks), which Trotsky also had to rely on, or observe, in order to present his case
against the LOI to
anyone interested in reading it, and upon which his followers also depend.
Otherwise he wouldn't have written them!
And, I am now about to use
those words against
him (and his epigones).
The fatal consequences mentioned above
revolve around the import of the last few sentences
above, and centre on the paradoxical conclusions that arise if we reject what they say -- as it seems
DM-critics of the
LOI must do to remain consistent with their own precepts.
For example, an acknowledgement that the
above quoted words are identical with Trotsky's own would mean that
anyone reading them now, and accepting his case against the LOI as
valid, must have (implicitly) employed that very 'law' in order to criticise
it! They would have to say (in effect) that in their copy these words are
exactly the same as the ones Trotsky typed or penned all those years ago,
which words now undermine an absolute application of the very 'law' they had just used to arrive at that conclusion!
Clearly, Trotsky and his epigones
failed to take into account this perfectly ordinary sense of identity: anyone who reads Trotsky's words today has before them
material objects (i.e., ink marks on the page or pixels on a screen) that are clearly identical with
countless other such objects separated from one another in space and time (i.e.,
other ink marks on paper or pixels on a screen that represent still other copies of the very same
article he wrote), by means of which an indefinite number of readers may access
the very same ideas that Trotsky intended they should, but which marks
aren't numerically, or materially, identical to the ones he originally penned.
This is as clear a case of ordinary 'identity-in-difference' as one should wish
to find, but one that doesn't commit us to a belief in those terminally obscure DM-UOs
(in fact, there are none here) -- and, as will become plain, this is an example of
'identity-in-difference' that completely undermines
Trotsky's criticism of the LOI.
In this case, countless manifestly (and
optically) different material objects -- separated in space and time --
are nonetheless uncontroversially identical. That fact could only be denied by those
who possess a defective copy of Trotsky's writings! Moreover, the
admission of this fact does nothing to undermine anyone's belief in
change.
[Annoyingly, that belief itself
could remain the same even while agreement with Trotsky on the LOI changed as a
result of the above argument!]
Of course, anyone who disagreed with
the above conclusions would then perhaps be committed to the view that the
words in their copy of Trotsky's writings weren't identical with those
that Trotsky authored seventy or more years ago. Indeed, that idea might itself have
been prompted
by Trotsky's own writings and the message they conveyed, and which is
what that message seems to express -- that is, that nothing is identical with itself, or with
anything else,
including those very words, or his message!
Someone could object:
(α) the above considerations actually support Trotsky's case, for
here we have several objects that we ordinarily call identical, which are manifestly not
the same. So, our ordinary grasp of identity isn't as secure as some might
imagine.
In response, it is worth pointing out that we count certain words,
phrases and symbols as identical even though they use different letters, or none
at all. For example, few of us would say most or even all of the following aren't
the same word or symbol, or that they didn't mean the same:
B1: (i) Cat, CAT,
Katze,
gato,
gatto, and
chat; (ii) Trotsky and TROTSKY;
(iii) colour and color; (iv) maths and
math; (v) In Defence of Marxism and In Defense of Marxism;
(vi) Das Kapital
and Capital; (vii) vixen and female fox; (viii) one, eins, un, uno, een, en,
and egy; (ix) 10 minus 9, 2 divided by 2, and 1; (x) 3 multiplied by 2, and 6;
(xi) February 12th and 12th of February; (xii) 02/06/21 (in
the USA) and 06/02/21 (in
the UK), (xiii) Beta and β; (xiv) dog and
chien; (xv) red and
red;
(xvi)
red and
red;
(xvii) red and rot;
(xviii) bold and bold;
(xix) italic and italic; (xx) and and and; (xx) a short empty space on a
page, and
; (xxii) arrow, →,
←, and
↓; (xxiii) 6 and upside down 9;
(xxiv) half
full and half empty; (xxv) non and uou, written upside down; (xxvi) dot and .;
(xxvii) dash and —; (xxviii) aluminium and aluminum; (xxix) xxix and 29; (xxx) etc., and
and so on...
That is because our
criteria of identity for words, symbols and letters aren't in every case the same (no irony intended). With respect to words and symbols,
a whole host of criteria apply; physical form is clearly not the only one (as
the above objection -- (α) -- seems to assume). Hence, even though the physical form of
the words and symbols used might be (totally) different, we nonetheless
recognise most or all of them as identical.
Furthermore, it can't be
the meaning of some or all the words and symbols in B1 that makes them identical, although
this is certainly true in some cases. Hence, we would regard
"schmidentity" and "Schmidentity" as identical words or
inscriptions even though they have no meaning. That in turn can't be because
they both lack a meaning,
otherwise, on that basis, "schmidentity" and "Meskonator" would have to be counted as the
same word!
Of course, when
meaning is introduced
into the equation, the situation
becomes even more problematic for dialecticians.
In that case, the
meaning of Trotsky's words today must be identical to the meaning they
had seventy odd years ago, even if their physical form isn't --
otherwise, it
would suggest that what Trotsky intended to convey (e.g., that nothing is
self-identical over time, for instance) must itself mean that that very message
wasn't the same as the
one he propagated all those years ago. That is because his message implies that not even messages
are identical over time! If, therefore, a reader had
actually accessed and read the identical message put out by Trotsky that urged them to come to
the (same!) conclusion that even Trotsky's message must change over time, then
they can't have understood that message
accurately if they now
agree with a corrupted or changed copy of it -- which original, for all they know,
might support an absolute, unqualified belief in the LOI! And that possibility
can't be ruled out if we accept the idea that:
"...all bodies change uninterruptedly in size, weight, colour etc. They are
never equal to themselves..." [Ibid.]
In
either case, such a critic wouldn't be
able to ascertain exactly what Trotsky had written or meant, even
while they feigned assent to the exact import of what he said in order to arrive
at that sceptical conclusion -- and which
had just prompted those very doubts about messages corrupting over time!
Alarmingly, that must mean that
any such latter-day critic of the LOI
must have
access to Trotsky's precise thoughts by other means, over and
above the physical text they will now have to concede can't be exactly the same as that which
Trotsky originally penned. This alternative route to Trotsky's thoughts must
therefore go beyond the confines of the physical document itself --,
since the latter (on this view) exists now in this ever-changing world in
corrupted form.
This
'alternative means
of communication' could only be 'ethereal' or 'telepathic'. So, such Telepathic Trotskyists
and Ethereal Epigones seem to be able to intuit Trotsky's
exact meaning -- which now unfortunately prompts them to question any such
exactitude!
But, even this
would imply that while this 'ethereal' message (issuing somehow from Trotsky)
was
identical to the original he transmitted through the ether all those years ago
-- enabling these very doubts about identity to be accessed
exactly and with no loss of meaning over the years in such an esoteric manner by contemporary recipients
-- the physical message wasn't!
Naturally, that would
still commit such individuals to the validity of LOI -- only now applied to
'occult' messages and ethereal identities!
An Attack On The LOI
Unequal To The Task
A
moment's thought will confirm the fact that the idea that our concepts are
somehow inadequate to the tasks we set them can't
be correct, even if the LOI were as defective as DM-dreamers would have us
believe. That is because, if
our words are inadequate in some way then so were Trotsky's when he
criticized the LOI, and so are those of anyone who now echoes such doubts. But,
that in turn would mean all such attacks on language are
defective in virtue of that very assault. Indeed, any words that
expressed
even an abstract disquiet about the adequacy of the vernacular would be inadequate to that task
-- which means, plainly,
that such inadequacies could never be adequately expressed!
Short of
saying nothing at all, this impasse will always block the thoughts and ideas of anyone who
thinks their words are permanently inadequate to any task set for them. Of
course, that would imply that sceptical doubts about the adequacy of language (howsoever mildly expressed)
must either be disingenuous or self-refuting. [Those who still harbour doubts
should read this,
and then perhaps think again.]
[And that includes
anyone who tries to impugn ordinary language, howsoever nuanced and indirect it
might be -- as we will see in Essay Twelve. Some thoughts on this are
expressed in Note
19, below, others can be found in
Essay Three Part Two, and
by following the link at the end of the previous paragraph.]
Furthermore, if what Trotsky had intended to say about the limitations of the
LOI were in principle
impossible to express in any language, if even its physical embodiment wasn't
identical with his thoughts as they were taking physical shape (i.e., when he
was committing them to paper) -- because
of his claim that all objects (including words forming 'in the mind', or those
being committed to
paper) are "never equal to themselves", let alone anything else --,
then Trotsky himself couldn't have intended to mean anything by them! That is because
there would have been nothing for him to have intended to have meant in such
circumstances. A faded simulacrum of his own thoughts about the LOI would have been
of no use even to Trotsky. Hence, not one nanosecond after being
thought, Trotsky's very own words would be non-self-identical. On paper, or in the
mind, they wouldn't be the same as those he had thought
micro-seconds earlier, and he would then have no access to his own precise
intentions, and for the same reason -- unless, that is, we are supposed to exempt
memory from Heraclitean change, claiming perhaps that it is the only thing in the entire universe that isn't
susceptible to the following:
"...all bodies change uninterruptedly in size, weight, colour etc. They are
never equal to themselves..." [Ibid.]
If
not, and the above strictures apply across the board, Trotsky's own thoughts would be forever lost
-- as if they had
never existed.
Hence, if what Trotsky said were correct then
not even he could
have affirmed, or confirmed, whether or not he was criticising the same 'law' from
moment-to-moment -- without surreptitiously, or implicitly, appealing to the very
same 'law' (as a rule of language), while he was attempting to do just that.
More generally: if it is
impossible to specify what it is that is being attacked (on the basis that
whatever is thought about 'it' is in principle not identical to what had
just been thought about 'it' micro-seconds earlier), no intention to criticise 'it' can crystallise,
for there would be no such 'it' to denigrate.
Once again, an appeal to 'approximate identity' might
suggest itself here, but that would be to no avail. As was argued earlier,
approximate identity is parasitic on concepts of identity not
semantically-challenged in this Idealist manner. Hence, we would need some idea of what was
being approximated to if the notion of 'approximate identity' is capable of
doing any real work. But, ex hypothesi, that can't be accessed without an
appeal being made to the validity of the LOI as a linguistic rule (but
not a metaphysical truth) -- and, what is more, to the very same rule applied
repeatedly. [Irony intended.]
Trotsky (or Hegel -- or, indeed, anyone who
is in exact agreement with either or both of them), would be forced to use
(implicitly or explicitly) such
linguistic criteria to formulate their self-refuting Idealist notions about a
'law' they seriously misidentified
to begin with!
Yet More Materially-Induced
Dialectical Misery
Unfortunately, these fatal defects don't stop there: anyone who consults Trotsky's words today, and who
agrees with his case against the LOI, owes us an explanation why, on the
one hand, the "A"s in S1:
S1: A is equal to
A
are
subject to the following strictures:
"But in reality 'A' is
not equal to 'A'. This is easy to prove if we observe these two letters under a
lens -– they are quite different from each other...," [Trotsky
(1971), p.63.]
when
Trotsky's own words (written many years ago) aren't. Such a person would in effect be saying:
I agree that the
abstract version of the LOI is defective because of what Trotsky's words say.
That is because the marks on paper that I am now
reading in IDM express exactly what Trotsky was thinking all those years
ago; they convey the very same message he intended. And yet, in at least
this respect the LOI must be correct for me to understand Trotsky, agree with
him, and arrive at exactly the same conclusion he did, and which he
intended his readers should. That allows me now to disagree with the LOI that I have
just used in arriving at identically that result!
On
the other hand, if my conclusions are only approximately the same as his, I must have some
grasp of his exact intentions so that I may truthfully say with what my own
opinions are
in fact an approximation. And this I must know, for I assent to
the idea that all identity statements are approximations because I agree with
exactly what Trotsky says. Without his words I would still be under the
illusion that identity was absolute -- er..., which it must be if I have just used
the LOI to arrive at to this very point....
But, if the LOI is correct at least once,
and the same person arrives at exactly the same conclusion as Trotsky -- only
decades later -- then what Trotsky says in S9, for example, can't itself be true:
S9(a): All bodies change uninterruptedly. (b) They
are never equal to themselves.
[And, of course, words are also "bodies".]
In that case, such a person could only
agree with Trotsky's criticism of the LOI by appealing (implicitly) to the
validity of the very same defective 'law' every time they accessed his words,
drawing identical conclusions from it, many times over, throughout their
no doubt very confused dialectical
lives. Naturally, this would mean that anyone agreeing with Trotsky, who
derived the same conclusion, would only be able to do so on condition
that they then promptly disagreed with Trotsky in practice, implying that the exact opposite result was correct
--,
a result, which because of this,
is not
now
identical with the one Trotsky had obtained!
This
further implies that Trotsky's claims are right only if they aren't, and that if what he had
intended to say were true, it would then become impossible for anyone (including
Trotsky) to determine what it was he wanted to say, whether it was right or
wrong, or whether it had been committed to paper accurately, transposed
correctly between copies -- or even whether these questions are themselves
defective or not --, and for the same reasons.
Once more:
profound
dialectical confusion has been exposed for all to see in actual practice.
This new (and ironic) dialectical inversion
(whereby a rejection of the LOI depends on its successful application in
practice by anyone trying to ascertain exactly what Trotsky, or Hegel,
thought he/they wanted to say)
just confirms how complex the conventions of ordinary language really are
(to paraphrase Wittgenstein), and how it isn't possible to criticise those
conventions without that attack itself falling apart for want of words with
which it might be accomplished!
Clearly, this paradoxical result is a
consequence of the cavalier attitude adopted by dialecticians (like Trotsky) toward ordinary language,
seriously compounded by a direct assault on the LOI. It isn't possible to criticise that 'law' in this manner -- that is, by treating it
as a putative truth.
Traditional
Thinkers have always
regarded the LOI a deep metaphysical truth about everything in existence --
that is, as a 'necessary truth'. However, as will be argued in Essay Twelve
Part One, all
such metaphysical theses are non-sensical and incoherent. Indeed, their denial is equally non-sensical
(irony intended).22
Small wonder, then, that Trotsky's
'analysis' collapses so readily into incoherence.
The weaknesses of the
LOI in fact lie elsewhere.23
The Anti-Dialectical Knock-Out
Punch
Finally, it is worth noting that the fact that objects in the world undergo
constant change can't in general be used to
refute any of the above points since, no matter how fast anything changes,
whatever it is identical with will change equally quickly.
In that case, the LOI is no enemy
of change.
With that observation, much
of 'materialist dialectics' falls apart.
[Further details
are spelled out in
Note 5b, and in Essay Eight
Parts One,
Two, and
Three.]
Traditional Versus
Modern FL
Traditional Logic Defective?
There is a serious,
non-academic point at stake here. Traditional
AFL, criticised by Trotsky, not only ignored complex inferences
inexpressible in
syllogisms, it
totally failed to cope with
relational
expressions,
quantifiers expressing
multiple generality, internal and external
negation and
scope ambiguity.
[This links to a PDF.] That was partly because of the way that quantifier
expressions themselves had been interpreted by earlier logicians, who, with their slavish
adherence to the traditional grammar of
subject and predicate, helped
cripple logic for over two thousand years.
[On the origin of some of these confusions, see Barnes (2009).]
It is no exaggeration to say that
much of Traditional Philosophy (i.e., Metaphysics) depends on antiquated and
garbled logic
like this. In which case, over two millennia of philosophical confusion --
including much that is found in Hegel -- largely derives from what is in effect
sub-Aristotelian Logic.
Now, many of the 'difficulties' outlined in the
last three Essays
(i.e., Essays Four and
Five, as well as this one) are a
direct consequence of the crude way that quantifiers, relational expressions and
tense operators had been interpreted (or ignored) by traditional
and by dialectical
logicians. In fact, progress toward unravelling pseudo-problems like this could only
begin after
Frege had completely re-laid the foundations of FL 130
years ago. As noted earlier, this salient fact has
yet to
register with most dialecticians -- no matter how many times they are
apprised of it.
At first sight, considerations like
these might appear to be dry, impractical and academic, of no interest to
revolutionaries. However, if Marxists plan to use a radically flawed system (DL)
in their endeavour to help change the world then this is relevant.24
Indeed, the
long-term lack of success
'enjoyed' by Dialectical Marxism for the best part of a century suggests that
DL has in fact been a millstone around
its neck.
History has so far delivered an
unambiguous verdict in this respect: DL has been tested in practice and
found wanting.
DL Superior To FL?
Essay Four
began by asking which one of the two
rival logics (DL or
FL) is the more
adequate for use in science, and which could most easily accommodate change,
identity and motion. It is now quite clear (from
Essays Four to Seven Part Three) that DL is vastly inferior to FL in every single department; it
is incapable of handling even the simplest
forms of change, to say nothing of more complex developments -- or even of describing them!
This is partly because (i) it relies on a garbled version of AFL, compounded by a confused
metaphysic which has itself been hobbled by the impenetrable jargon invented by
Hegel, and partly because (ii) its devotees unwisely
undermine ordinary language.
In fact, DL is so fundamentally
defective that it
can't even cope with a simple bag of sugar
-- let alone "long drawn out processes".
Small wonder then that it has
seriously hindered the scientific
development of Marxism.
FL
And A Fragmented And Static View Of Reality
It
might be felt at this stage that it is hardly surprising that the
views expressed here and elsewhere at this site reach the conclusions they do since they depend on
analysis -– that is, they are based on a fragmentary view of reality
which
splits the world and its contents into separate and un-mediated compartments. Naturally, when divorced from the
whole, reality is going to appear paradoxical. Only against a wider
background is it possible to comprehend the world correctly. In broader
contexts, at different levels of abstraction and generality, the contradictory nature of objects and processes
becomes much easier to appreciate, as
indeed are the inadequacies of FL and the LOI.
This objection introduces the centrally
important DM-concept: the "Totality". This terminally nebulous notion will be discussed
in detail in Essay Eleven Part One. The idea that FL (ancient or modern)
trades on a static view of the world was batted out of the park in Essay
Four Part One.
Be this as it may, many
DM-advocates direct our attention toward the 'three laws of dialectics' which
Engels helped codify. These 'laws' they feel more accurately encapsulate the
core ideas expressed in DM.
It is to this topic that I now turn.
Notes
1.
As we will see, Hegel did at least mention identity in
his critique of the LOI, even though it is clear from what he said that not only had
he given this topic insufficient thought, he advanced superficial and erroneous
claims about it. [A fuller consideration of Hegel's 'analysis' of identity can be found in Essays Twelve
(summaries
here,
here
and
here), and Eight Part
Three. I have also added
additional thoughts on this topic to
Appendix D of Essay Three Part One.]
Hegel's alleged denial of the LOI and the
LOC are examined in
Pippin (1978), Hanna (1986), and Hahn (2007). Even though these two authors struggle
heroically to make Hegel comprehensible on this and other issues, it is difficult
to tell whether they have succeeded or not, or both. [I will add some thoughts
on these confused attempts to Essay Eight Part Three.]
It is also worth pointing out that
the LOI was unknown to
Aristotle.
[Unfortunately, since this Essay was originally published, the
article at the above link has been changed; the one I referenced above can be found
here. On this, see also
here.]
After Another Edit: The
Wikipedia article
now
attributes this 'law' to Aristotle's Metaphysics, but it is quite clear
that it hasn't been
stated there in its hackneyed form (i.e., A = A). Indeed, if anything,
Aristotle derides this 'law':
"Now 'why a thing is itself' is a meaningless
inquiry (for -- to give meaning to the question 'why' -- the fact or the
existence of the thing must already be evident -- e.g., that the moon is
eclipsed -- but the fact that a thing is itself is the single reason and the
single cause to be given in answer to all such questions as why the man is man,
or the musician musical, unless one were to answer 'because each thing is
inseparable from itself, and its being one just meant this' this, however, is
common to all things and is a short and easy way with the question)."
[Metaphysics
Book VII, Part 17.
This can be found in Aristotle (1984b), p.1643. Bold added.]
Quoting this as an example of the use of, or
as an allusion to, this 'law' would be to distort what Aristotle says; so I have
added the following
comment
to the Wikipedia article (slightly edited):
And the quotation takes
this 'law' out of context, for not only does Aristotle not mention 'identity',
he specifically talks about predication (and since identity is a relation, he
can't be talking
about identity here):
"Let us state what, 'i.e. what kind of thing, substance should be said to
be', taking once more another starting-point; for perhaps from this we shall get
a clear view also of that substance which exists apart from sensible substances.
Since, then, substance is a principle and a cause, let us pursue it from this
starting-point. The 'why' is always sought in this form -- 'why does one thing
attach to some other?' For to inquire why the musical man is a
musical man, is either to inquire -- as we have said why the man is musical, or
it is something else. Now 'why a thing is itself' is a meaningless inquiry (for
-- to give meaning to the question 'why') the fact or the existence of the thing
must already be evident -- e.g. that the moon is eclipsed -- but the fact that a
thing is itself is the single reason and the single cause to be given in answer
to all such questions as why the man is man, or the musician musical, unless
one were to answer 'because each thing is inseparable from itself, and its being
one just meant this'; this, however, is common to all things and is a short and
easy way with the question). But we can inquire why man is an animal of such and
such a nature. This, then, is plain, that we are not inquiring why he who is a
man is a man. We are inquiring, then, 'why something is predicable of
something' (that it is predicable must be clear; for if not, the
inquiry is an inquiry into nothing). E.g. why does it thunder? This is
the same as 'why is sound produced in the clouds?' Thus the inquiry is about the
predication of one thing of another. And why are these things, i.e. bricks
and stones, a house? Plainly we are seeking the cause. And this is the essence
(to speak abstractly), which in some cases is the end, e.g. perhaps in the case
of a house or a bed, and in some cases is the first mover; for this also is a
cause. But while the efficient cause is sought in the case of genesis and
destruction, the final cause is sought in the case of being also." [Ibid., bold
emphasis added.]
So, I think the article needs amending.
Finally, since this 'law' is foreign to Aristotle, how can the author of this
article say the following?
"The law of identity has deep impact on
Aristotle's ethics as well. In order for a person to be morally praiseworthy
or blameworthy for an action, he or she must be the same person before the act
as during the act and after the act. Without the law of identity, Aristotle
notes, there can be no responsibility for vice."
Personal identity isn't the same as the 'law of identity'.
However, I couldn't find in the
Nicomachean Ethics
anything like this reference to personal identity; so perhaps the author of this
article will provide an exact reference?
In fact the
Wikipedia article is highly
misleading. For example, it attributes this phrase to Aristotle, which can't be
found in Metaphysics VII Part 17: "a fixed constant
nature of sensible things", and as such misrepresents what he was saying.
Update August 2011: I have just read Deborah
Modrak's book on Aristotle (i.e., Modrak (2001)); this author devotes an entire section
to Aristotle's views on identity -- i.e., pp.194-98. However, Modrak in fact concentrates on
Aristotle's views on sameness; identity is conspicuous by its absence.
Certainly, there is no mention of the LOI.
[Incidentally, I have
added detailed comments
on the only two other passages found in Aristotle's work (i.e., from
Topics
and from
De Sophistici Elenchi), which could conceivably be recruited to the cause
of saddling him with this
Medieval 'Law', to Essay Four
Part One.]
Nevertheless, the
defects of the LOI lie elsewhere; these
are outlined in Wittgenstein (1972), pp.97, 105-07, and Wittgenstein (1958), pp.84-85,
91, 111. [Cf., Glock (1996), pp.164-69.]
The best analysis of
Wittgenstein's
criticisms of identity can be found in White (1978). See also Marion (1998),
pp.48-72 for an extended discussion. On identity in general, see Geach (1967,
1968, 1973, 1975, 1990), Griffin (1977), Noonan (1980, 1997,
2022) and Williams
(1979, 1989, 1992). See also
Deutsch (2018).
There is as yet no definitive account of Wittgenstein's use words
for identity;
however
Roger White's long-awaited book should cast considerable light on this
topic. [Cf., White (2006), and (forthcoming).]
There is an excellent summary in Glock
(1996), pp.256-64, a more considered account in Diamond (1991) and
in several articles published in Crary and Read (2000) -- for example, Conant
(2000). See also Goldfarb (1997) and McGinn (1999).
Here are
just a few examples of the
extremely
repetitive nature of this part of dialectics:
"[T]he first of [the
universal Laws of Thought], the maxim of Identity, reads: Everything is
identical with itself, A = A…." [Hegel (1975),
p.167, §115.]
"In this remark, I will
consider in more detail identity as the law of identity which is usually adduced
as the first law of thought.
"This proposition in its positive expression
A = A is, in the first instance, nothing more than the expression of an empty
tautology." [Hegel (1999),
p.413,
§875.]
"Abstract Identity (a = a…) is
likewise inapplicable in organic nature. The plant, the animal, every cell is at
every moment of its life identical with itself and yet becoming distinct from
itself….The law of identity in the old metaphysical sense is the
fundamental law of the old outlook: a = a." [Engels (1954),
pp.214-15.]
"The 'fundamental laws of
thinking' are considered to be three in number: 1) The Law of Identity… [which]
states that 'A is A' or A = A…." [Plekhanov (1908),
p.89.]
"…Hegel elucidates the
one-sidedness, the incorrectness of the 'law of identity' (A = A)…." [Lenin
(1961),
p.134.]
"Formal Logic starts from the
proposition that A is always equal to A. We know that this law of identity
contains some measure of truth…. Now…when we go to reality and look for evidence
of the truth of the proposition: A equals A…we find that the opposite of this
axiom is far closer to the truth." [Novack (1971), pp.32-33.]
"Formal Logic asserts:
'A is A'.
Dialectical Logic is not saying 'A is not-A'…. It says: A is indeed A, but A is
also not-A precisely so far as the proposition 'A is A' is not a tautology but
has real content." [Lefebvre (1968), p.41.]
"The Law of identity is
usually expressed in the form, A is A. That is, each thing is identical with
itself." [Somerville (1946), p.183.]
"The Aristotelian conception
of the laws basic to correct thinking may be stated as follows: 1. Law of
Identity: Each existence is identical with itself. A is A…." [Somerville (1967),
pp.44-45.]
"Classical, Aristotelian
logic takes as its fundamental premise the Law of Identity, the statement that a
thing is identical with itself. Expressed in a formula: A is A…. In Aristotle's
formal logic A is A, and never non-A. In Hegel's dialectics A is A as well as
non-A." [Baghavan (1987), pp.75-76.]
"The biggest contradiction of
all lies in the fundamental premises of formal logic itself…. The basic
laws…are:
1) The law of Identity ('A' =
'A')…." [Woods
and Grant (1995/2007),
pp.90-91.
(This is found on p.95 of the 2nd edition.)]
"Dialectics, or the logic of motion, is distinct from formal or static logic.
Formal logic is based on three fundamental laws:
"(a) The
law of identity: A is equal to A; a thing is always equal to itself." [Mandel
(1979), p.160.]
"The laws
of logic are based on two main propositions. The first is that of identity or of
self-conformity. The proposition very simply states: 'A is A,' that is, every
concept is equal to itself. A man is a man; a hen is a hen; a potato is a
potato. This proposition forms one basis of logic. The second main proposition
is the law of contradiction, or as it is also called, the law of the excluded
middle. This proposition states: 'A is either A or not A.' It cannot be
both at the same time. For example: Whatever is black is black; it cannot at the
same time be black and white. A thing -- to put it in general terms -- cannot at
the same time be itself and its opposite. In practice it therefore follows that
if I draw certain conclusions from a given starting point and contradictions
arise, then there are errors in thinking or my starting point was wrong. If from
some correct premises I come to the conclusion that 4 is the same as 5, then I
deduce from the law of contradiction that my conclusion is false.
"So far
all appears to be clear and certain. What can be a clearer law than that man is
man, a rooster a rooster, that a thing is always the same thing? It even appears
to be absolutely certain that a thing is either large or small; either black or
white, that it cannot be both at the same time, that contradictions cannot exist
in one and the same thing.
"Let us
now consider the matter from the standpoint of a higher doctrine of thought,
from the standpoint of dialectics. Let us take the first law which we have
developed as the foundation of logic: A is A. A thing is always the same thing.
Without testing this law, let us consider another one which we have already
mentioned, the law of Heraclitus which says 'Everything is in flux,' or 'One
cannot ascend the same river twice.' Can we say that the river is always the
same? No, the law of Heraclitus says the opposite. The river is at no moment the
same. It is always changing. Thus one cannot twice nor, more exactly, even once
ascend the same river. In short: the law 'A is A' in the last analysis is valid
only if I assume that the thing does not change. As soon as I consider the thing
in its change, then A is always A and something else; A is at the same time
not-A. And this in the last analysis holds for all things and events." [Thalheimer (1936),
pp.88-89.]
"The first
principle [the 'Law of Identity' -- RL] , then, declares that A is A, or to
speak mathematically, every quantity is equal to itself. In plain English: a
thing is what it is; no thing is what it is not....
"[The old
logic] insists on its first, second and third law, on its identity, its law of
contradiction and excluded third, which must be either straight or crooked, cold
or warm and excludes all intermediary conceptions." [Dietzgen (1906),
pp.386-89.]
"The central principle on
which formal logic is built can be expressed in a simple formula that at first
glance appears to be a self-evident truth 'A equals A'." [Conner (1992), p.22.]
"The basic principles of this
Aristotelian or formal logic were the 'law of identity' and the 'law of
non-contradiction'. The 'law of identity' stated, in symbolic terms, that A is
equal to A, or an ounce of gold equals an ounce of gold, or, taking a
unique object..., Leonardo da Vinci's Mona Lisa is equal to Leonardo da
Vinci's Mona Lisa. The 'law of non-contradiction' stated that A cannot be
equal to non-A, it makes no sense to say that an ounce of gold is not an ounce
of gold or the Mona Lisa is not the Mona Lisa. On the basis of
these apparently 'obvious' propositions a system of logic or sound reasoning was
erected, exemplified by the syllogism." [Molyneux (2012), p.43. Quotation marks
altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Italic emphases
in the original.]
"Dialectics
is quite simply the logic of motion, or the logic of common sense to activists
in the movement. We all know that things don't stand still, they change. But
there is another form of logic which stands in contradiction to dialectics,
which we call 'formal logic', which again is deeply embodied in capitalist
society. It is perhaps necessary to begin by describing briefly what this method
implies.
"Formal
logic is based on what is known as the 'law of identity', which says that 'A'
equals 'A' -- i.e. that things are what they are, and that they stand in
definite relationships to each other. There are other derivative laws based on
the law of identity; for example, if 'A' equals 'A', it follows that 'A' cannot
equal 'B', nor 'C'....
"Whereas
the formal logician will say that 'A' equals 'A', the dialectician will say that
'A' does not necessarily equal 'A'. Or to take a practical example that Trotsky
uses in his writings, one pound of sugar will not be precisely equal to another
pound of sugar. It is a good enough approximation if you want to buy sugar in a
shop, but if you look at it more carefully you will see that it's actually
wrong." [John
Pickard, quoted from
here.]
"The
philosophical underpinning of this pursuit of knowledge was grounded in the
empirical method, which guided the scientific inquiry into the interactions
conceived of as external to these discrete and now well-defined entities. The
law of identity was critical to the project: A thing is always equal to or
identical with itself. Or stated in algebraic terms (sic): A equals A. One
corollary of the idea that A is always identical to A is that A can never equal
not-A."
[Quoted from
here;
accessed 21/05/18.]
Examples like
these can be multiplied almost
indefinitely. Even though there are several minor differences in emphasis
between them, the basic point of the above comments is reasonably clear:
DM-theorists have fixated on a superficial
form of the LOI, one they copy from each other generation after generation. Seldom do they bother to check that what they are criticising
even remotely resembles
anything taken from a logic text written in the last 120 years,
or even one
written by Aristotle!
In at least this respect, DM-authors are
(ironically) identical. And, as we will see, in response
to Hegel (here),
identity statements aren't tautologies. Moreover, as we will see in this
Essay, the LOI doesn't preclude change.
As Essay
Four Part One
demonstrated in
detail, this tactic is part of a long and disreputable tradition religiously
observed by 'Materialist
Dialecticians': Define the basics of
logic in a completely fanciful way, ridicule them, and then proclaim the
superiority of DL over this straw man. Here is John Molyneux again:
"Marxist materialism is
repeatedly attacked by the method of oversimplifying and caricaturing it to the
point where it is obviously false...." [Molyneux (2012), p.36.]
And
yet, this is precisely what DM-apologists do with respect to
FL!
Novack's prize-winning entry
in this respect, however, goes as follows:
"There are three fundamental
laws of formal logic. First and most important is the law of identity. This law
can be stated in various ways such as: A thing is always equal to or identical
with itself. In algebraic terms: A is equal to A.… If a thing is always and
under all conditions equal or identical with itself, it can never be unequal or
different from itself. This conclusion follows logically and inevitably from the
law of identity. If A always equals A, it can never equal non-A." [Novack
(1971), p.20. Paragraphs merged. What this has to do with 'algebra' Novack
annoyingly kept to himself.]
Clearly Novack failed to consider these
counter-examples to his 'logical' conclusion:
N1: The number of volumes of Das
Kapital is equal to the number of goals in a hat-trick.
N2: There were equal numbers of Union and
non-Union members at the meeting last night.
N3: Although NN and MM have different
disabilities they came equal first in the 100 metres final at the Para-Olympics,
sharing the Gold Medal.
N4: Those two comrades sold equal
numbers of papers on two different demonstrations last week.
N5: The author of
Novack
(1971) is identical to the comrade who penned the words in the last quotation
above.
None of these suggests that the items they
allude to can never change -- but, when they do change, anything identical to them
will change equally quickly.
Otherwise, they weren't identical -- or, of course, they will cease to be identical with whatever
they
used to be!
Apart from Woods and Grant (1995/2007),
none of the above theorists referred their readers to a single logic text (save those
written by Hegel and other 'dialectical logicians'); worse still, not one of them
bothered to quote Aristotle, even though many attribute this idea to him!
However,
several of the above dialecticians at least mentioned the word "identity", but
they then confused it
with equality. Hence, most of the criticisms levelled against Trotsky
in this Essay
apply equally
to them (no pun intended).
But, Woods and Grant go further:
"Firstly, let us note that the appearance of a
necessary chain of reasoning, in which one step follows from another, is
entirely illusory. The law of contradiction merely restates the law of identity
in a negative form. The same is true of the law of the excluded middle. All we
have is a repetition of the first line in different ways. The whole thing stands
or falls on the basis of the law of identity ('A' = 'A'). At first sight this is
incontrovertible, and, indeed, the source of all rational thought. It is the
Holy of Holies of Logic, and not to be called into question. Yet called into
question it was, and by one of the greatest minds of all time (sic).
"There is a story by
Hans-Christian Andersen
called The Emperor's New Suit of Clothes, in which a rather foolish emperor is
sold a new suit by a swindler, which is supposed to be very beautiful, but
invisible. The gullible emperor goes about in his fine new suit, which everyone
agrees is exquisite, until one day a little boy points out that the emperor is,
in fact, stark naked. Hegel performed a comparable service to philosophy in his
critique of formal logic. Its defenders have never forgiven him for it." [Woods
and Grant (1995/2007), p.91. (This can be found on pp.95-96 of the 2nd
edition.) Quotation marks altered to conform with the
conventions adopted at this site.]
This is typical hyperbole from Woods and Grant, who seem to think
that modern logicians will be in any way fazed by the confusions that litter Hegel's
badly
misnamed book (on 'logic'). Indeed, the vast majority of them pay no more attention to
Hegel, or Woods and Grant, than
Woods and Grant themselves pay to the work of, say,
Frédéric
Bastiat
(and probably for the same reason). Furthermore, based on Woods and Grant's
execrable book -- even if any Logicians could be bothered to read it -- in this respect they
aren't likely to change (irony intended).
Moreover, as we will see
here, the LOC
and the LOI aren't connected in the way that Woods and Grant clearly think they are.
They have simply copied this idea off Hegel and Engels without bothering to check whether
the 'negative form of the LOI' one implies the LOC.
And, as we saw in Essay
Four,
neither AFL nor MFL is based on the LOI (although there are several systems of
logic where the LOI plays a key role).
In their haste to blame FL for
everything but the
Black Death
and the demise of the Dinosaurs, Woods and Grant failed to acknowledge this
salient fact -- always assuming they were
even aware of it. [On this, also see
my comments
over at Wikipedia.]
[LOC = Law of Non-Contradiction; FL =
Formal Logic; AFL =
Aristotelian FL; MFL = Modern FL.]
2.
There is evidence that Trotsky read and studied Hegel's Logic
(see the Introduction to Trotsky (1986), and the reference to the Logic
in Trotsky (1986) itself -- e.g., p.98). Nevertheless, even if questions
about the accuracy of the title of Hegel's two books on 'logic' are put to
one side, it is
reasonably clear that apart from the Hegel's Logic Trotsky seems not
to have consulted a single logic text before he began issuing
ex cathedra pronouncements about it.
Having said that,
Isaac
Deutscher tells us that in the early 1930s, in preparation for a book he
intended to write on Lenin, Trotsky "went back to classics of logic and
dialectics, Aristotle and Descartes, but especially to Hegel" (Deutscher (1970),
p.267). If so, Trotsky might have studied Aristotle's logical texts; if he
did, it is plain that his view of Aristotle was heavily skewed by Hegel's
misrepresentations and errors.
It is
also possible that
Jean
van Heijenoort, a member of Trotsky's entourage, subsequently an expert
logician, gave him some advice; but if he did, there is precious little
evidence that much of it sank in. On this, see Van Heijenoort (1978), and Feferman
(1993).
In this respect Trotsky wasn't alone; DM-theorists in general are only too happy
to regale us with their home-spun ideas about FL, fables whose pristine
simplicity hasn't been compromised by the arduous task of opening a
single book devoted to AFL, let alone MFL.
Finally, those who think that AFL
is based on the LOC (etc.) should consult Lear (1980), pp.98-114, where they
will find a more balanced and scholarly account.
2a.
Although I used part of the following quotation earlier, there is a passage in Engels's
DN which closely
resembles what Trotsky was saying:
"Abstract
identity (a = a; and negatively, a cannot be
simultaneously equal and unequal to a) is likewise inapplicable in
organic nature. The plant, the animal, every cell is at every moment of its
life identical with itself and yet becoming distinct from itself, by
absorption and excretion of substances, by respiration, by cell formation and
death of cells, by the process of circulation taking place, in short, by a sum
of incessant molecular changes which make up life and the sum-total of whose
results is evident to our eyes in the phases of life -- embryonic life, youth,
sexual maturity, process of reproduction, old age, death. The further physiology
develops, the more important for it become these incessant, infinitely small
changes, and hence the more important for it also the consideration of
difference within identity, and the old abstract standpoint of formal
identity, that an organic being is to be treated as something simply identical
with itself, as something constant, becomes out of date.
[In the margin of the manuscript occurs the remark: 'Apart, moreover, from the
evolution of species.'] Nevertheless, the mode of thought based thereon,
together with its categories, persists. But even in inorganic nature identity as
such is in reality non-existent. Every body is continually exposed to
mechanical, physical, and chemical influences, which are always changing it and
modifying its identity. Abstract identity, with its opposition to
difference, is in place only in mathematics -- an abstract science which is
concerned with creations of thought, even though they are reflections of reality
-- and even there it is continually being sublated. Hegel, Enzyklopädie,
I, p. 235. [This is a reference to Hegel (1975),
pp.169-70, §117;
see below -- RL.] The fact that identity contains difference within itself is
expressed in every sentence, where the predicate is necessarily
different from the subject; the lily is a plant, the rose, is red,
where, either in the subject or in the predicate, there is something that
is not covered by the predicate or the subject. Hegel, p.231. [This is a
reference to Hegel (1975),
pp.166-68, §115;
see below -- RL.] That from the outset identity with itself requires
difference from everything else as its complement, is self-evident.
"Continual
change, i.e., sublation of abstract identity with itself, is also found in
so-called inorganic nature. Geology is its history. On the surface, mechanical
changes (denudation, frost), chemical changes (weathering); internally,
mechanical changes (pressure), heat (volcanic), chemical (water, acids, binding
substances); on a large scale – upheavals, earthquakes, etc. The slate of today
is fundamentally different from the ooze from which it is formed, the chalk from
the loose microscopic shells that compose it, even more so limestone, which
indeed according to some is of purely organic origin, and sandstone from the
loose sea sand, which again is derived from disintegrated granite, etc., not to
speak of coal.
"The
law of identity in the old metaphysical sense is the fundamental law of the
old outlook: a = a. Each thing is equal to itself. Everything was
permanent, the solar system, stars, organisms. This law has been refuted by
natural science bit by bit in each separate case, but theoretically it still
prevails and is still put forward by the supporters of the old in opposition to
the new: a thing cannot simultaneously be itself and something else. And
yet the fact that true, concrete identity includes difference, change, has
recently been shown in detail by natural science (see above).
"Abstract
identity, like all metaphysical categories, suffices for everyday use,
where small dimensions or brief periods of time are in question; the limits
within which it is usable differ in almost every case and are determined by the
nature of the object; for a planetary system, where in ordinary astronomical
calculation the ellipse can be taken as the basic form for practical purposes
without error, they are much wider than for an insect that completes its
metamorphosis in a few weeks. (Give other examples, e.g., alteration of species,
which is reckoned in periods of thousands of years.) For natural science in its
comprehensive role, however, even in each single branch, abstract identity is
totally inadequate, and although on the whole it has now been abolished in
practice, theoretically it still dominates people’s minds, and most natural
scientists imagine that identity and difference are irreconcilable opposites,
instead of one-sided poles which represent the truth only in their reciprocal
action, in the inclusion of difference within identity." [Engels (1954),
pp.214-16. Bold
emphases alone added.
Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]
Which
only serves to confirm the allegation made above that
DM-theorists uncritically copy ideas off one another.
Here are the relevant sections of Hegel's Shorter Logic:
"Difference is first of all (1) immediate difference, i.e.
Diversity
or Variety. In Diversity the different things are each individually what they
are, and unaffected by the relation in which they stand to each other. This
relation is therefore external to them. In consequence of the various things
being thus indifferent to the difference between them, it falls outside them
into a third thing, the agent of Comparison. This external difference, as an
identity of the objects related, is Likeness; as a non-identity of them, is
Unlikeness.
"The gap
which understanding allows to divide these characteristics is so great that
although comparison has one and the same substratum for likeness and unlikeness,
which are explained to be different aspects and points of view in it, still
likeness by itself is the first of the elements alone, viz., identity, and
unlikeness by itself is difference.
"Diversity
has, like Identity, been transformed into a maxim: 'Everything is various or
different': or 'There are no two things completely like each other'. Here
Everything is put under a predicate, which is the reverse of the identity
attributed to it in the first maxim: and therefore under a law contradicting the
first. However, there is an explanation. As the diversity is supposed due only
to external circumstances, anything taken per se is expected and
understood always to be identical with itself, so that the second law need not
interfere with the first. But, in that case, variety does not belong to the
something or everything in question: it constitutes no intrinsic characteristic
of the subject: and the second maxim on this showing does not admit of being
stated at all. If, on the other hand, the something itself is, as the maxim
says, diverse, it must be in virtue of its own proper character: but in this
case the specific difference, and not variety as such, is what is intended. And
this is the meaning of the maxim of
Leibnitz
(sic).
"When understanding sets itself to study Identity, it has
already passed beyond it, and is looking at Difference in the shape of bare
Variety. If we follow the so-called law of Identity, and say, The sea is the
sea, The air is the air, The moon is the moon, these objects pass for having no
bearing on one another. What we have before us therefore is not Identity, but
Difference. We do not stop at this point, however, or regard things merely as
different. We compare them one with another, and then discover the features of
likeness and unlikeness. The work of the finite sciences lies to a great extent
in the application of these categories, and the phrase 'scientific treatment'
generally means no more than the method which has for its aim comparison of the
objects under examination. This method has undoubtedly led to some important
results; we may particularly mention the great advance of modern times in the
provinces of comparative anatomy and comparative linguistics. But it is going
too far to suppose that the comparative method can be employed with equal
success in all branches of knowledge. Not -- and this must be emphasised -- can
mere comparison ever ultimately satisfy the requirements of science. Its results
are indeed indispensable, but they are still labours only preliminary to truly
intelligent cognition.
"If it be the office of comparison to reduce existing
differences to Identity, the science which most perfectly fulfils that end is
mathematics. The reason of that is that quantitative difference is only the
difference which is quite external. Thus, in geometry, a triangle and a
quadrangle, figures qualitatively different, have this qualitative difference
discounted by abstraction, and are equalised to one another in magnitude. It
follows from what has been said formerly about mere Identity of understanding
that, as has also been pointed out (s.99),
neither philosophy nor the empirical sciences need envy this superiority of
Mathematics.
"The story is told that when Leibnitz (sic) propounded the
maxim of Variety, the cavaliers and ladies of the court, as they walked round
the garden, made efforts to discover two leaves indistinguishable from each
other, in order to confute the law stated by the philosopher. Their device was
unquestionably a convenient method of dealing with metaphysics -- one which has
not ceased to be fashionable. All the same, as regards the principle of Leibnitz
(sic), difference must be understood to mean not an external and indifferent
diversity merely, but difference essential. Hence the very nature of things
implies that they must be different." [Hegel (1975),
pp.169-70, §117.]
"The
Essence lights up in itself or is mere reflection: and therefore is only
self-relation, not as immediate but as reflected. And that reflex relation is
self-identity.
"This
identity becomes an Identity, in form only, or of the understanding, if it be
held hard and fast, quite aloof from difference. Or, rather, abstraction is the
imposition of this Identity of form, the transformation of something inherently
concrete into this form of elementary simplicity. And this may be done in two
ways. Either we may neglect a part of the multiple features which are found in
the concrete thing (by what is called analysis) and select only one of them; or,
neglecting their variety, we may concentrate the multiple character into one.
"If we
associate Identity with the Absolute, making the Absolute the subject of a
proposition, we get: The Absolute is what is identical with itself. However,
true this proposition may be, it is doubtful whether it be meant in its truth:
and therefore it is at least imperfect in the expression. For it is left
undecided, whether it means the abstract Identity of understanding- abstract.
that is, because contrasted with the other characteristics of Essence -- or the
Identity which is inherently concrete. In the latter case, as will be seen, true
identity is first discoverable in the Ground, and, with a higher truth, in the
Notion. Even the word Absolute is often used to mean more than 'abstract'.
Absolute space and absolute time, for example, is another way of saying abstract
space and abstract time.
"When the
principles of Essence are taken as essential principles of thought they become
predicates of a presupposed subject, which, because they are essential, is
'everything'. The propositions thus arising have been stated as universal Laws
of Thought. Thus the first of them, the maxim of Identity, reads: Everything
is identical with itself, A = A: and negatively, A cannot at the same time be A
and Not-A. This maxim, instead of being a true law of thought, is nothing
but the law of abstract understanding. The propositional form itself contradicts
it: for a proposition always promises a distinction between subject and
predicate; while the present one does not fulfil what its form requires. But the
Law is particularly set aside by the following so-called Laws of Thought, which
make laws out of its opposite. It is asserted that the maxim of Identity, though
it cannot be proved, regulates the procedure of every consciousness, and that
experience shows it to be accepted as soon as its terms are apprehended. To this
alleged experience of the logic books may be opposed the universal experience
that no mind thinks or forms conceptions or speaks in accordance with this law,
and that no existence of any kind whatever conforms to it.
"Utterances after the fashion of this pretended law (A planet is a planet;
Magnetism is magnetism; Mind is Mind) are, as they deserve to be, reputed silly.
That is certainly a matter of general experience. The logic which seriously
propounds such laws and the scholastic world in which alone they are valid have
long been discredited with practical common sense as well as with the philosophy
of reason.
"Identity is, in the first place, the repetition of what
we had earlier as Being, but as become, through supersession of its
character of immediateness. It is therefore Being as Ideality. It is important
to come to a proper understanding on the true meaning of Identity; and, for that
purpose, we must especially guard against taking it as abstract identity, to the
exclusion of all Difference. That is the touchstone for distinguishing all bad
philosophy from what alone deserves the name of philosophy. Identity in its
truth, as an Ideality of what immediately is, is a high category for our
religious modes of mind as well as all other forms of thought and mental
activity. The true knowledge of God, it may be said, begins when we know him as
identity -- as absolute identity. To know so much is to see all the power and
glory of the world sinks into nothing in God's presence, and subsists only as
the reflection of his power and his glory. In the same way, Identity, as
self-consciousness, is what distinguishes man from nature, particularly from the
brutes which never reach the point of comprehending themselves as 'I'; that is,
pure self-contained unity. So again, in connection with thought, the main thing
is not to confuse the true Identity, which contains Being and its
characteristics ideally transfigured in it, with an abstract Identity, identity
of bare form. All the charges of narrowness, hardness, meaninglessness, which
are so often directed against thought from the quarter of feeling and immediate
perception rest on the perverse assumption that thought acts only as a faculty
of abstract Identification.
"The Formal Logic itself confirms this assumption by
laying down the supreme law of thought (so-called) which has been discussed
above. If thinking were no more than an abstract Identity, we could not but own
it to be a most futile and tedious business. No doubt the notion, and the idea
too, are identical with themselves: but identical only in so far as they at the
same time involve distinction." [Ibid.,
pp.166-68, §115.
Bold emphasis added.]
There are
similar, even longer and considerably more opaque passages in Hegel (1999).
Hegel's
confused attempt to 'analyse' the LOI is examined in
detail in Essays Eight Part Three
and Twelve Parts Five and Six (not yet published).
3.
That is, if they are even aware of
them! On this, see Note
8, below.
4.
In fact, Trotsky's
version went as follows:
S1(a): 'A' is equal to 'A'.
However, since not much seems to hang on
Trotsky's use of single quotation marks (over and above his rather odd reference
to the microscopic examination of the letters in question), I have largely ignored them
in what follows.
5.
Change in, or to, NN is irrelevant here; that is because, howsoever much her two
roles alter, since NN occupies both at the same time it will always be true that "The Unison rep is identical with the
STWC Treasurer".
The same
point applies,
mutatis
mutandis, to the other examples listed in the main body of
this Essay. [See also Note 5b,
below.]
5a.
A substantival term is a common
noun that in general (but not always) admits of number (i.e., it has a plural form)
--, e.g., three books, two
people, five comrades -- and where they do admit of number, they are often
called 'count nouns'. Their distinguishing mark centres on
the
criteria of identity we use in each case. The following is what
Professor Lowe had to say
about this topic:
"...[N]ot
all general terms are common names -- for instance, adjectival or characterizing
general terms such as 'red' and 'circular' are not, nor are abstract nouns such
as 'redness' and 'circularity' (if indeed the latter are deemed to be general
terms, for an alternative view is that they are singular terms referring to
abstract individuals). The distinguishing feature of common names -- sometimes
also called substantival or sortal general terms -- is that they
have associated with them, as a component of their meaning, a
criterion of
identity for the individuals to which they apply (see Lowe 1989, Ch. 2). A
criterion of identity for individuals of a kind K is a principle which
determines, for any individuals x and y of kind K, whether
or not x and y are one and the same K. Thus, the criterion
of identity for cities tells us that Paris and London are different
cities, since they occupy different locations; and the criterion of identity for
rivers tells us that
the Isis and the Thames are the same river, since
they flow from the same source to the same mouth. Different kinds of
individuals, denoted by different sortal terms, very often have different
criteria of identity governing them -- and in some cases there is philosophical
debate as to precisely what these criteria are (for example, in the case of
persons). Credit is once more due to
Frege for recognizing the important
role that criteria of identity have to play in the semantics of sortal terms."
[Lowe, Internet Resource [2].]
Count
nouns are to be distinguished from other common nouns which don't admit of number, e.g.,
mass nouns (such as chalk,
cabbage, meat, etc. -- it makes no sense to refer to "two meat", or "three
chalk". Of course, these can be converted into count nouns, as in "two
cabbages", "three chalks" or "four meats" (the latter two of which are in
general short for "three pieces or sticks of chalk" or "two varieties, portions, slices,
or cuts of meat"). However, some mass nouns are also substantivals, e.g., gold,
lead, and plastic.
Many of the mistakes dialecticians make
in relation to
identity originate in their failure to notice the different logic that applies
to these two sorts of nouns. [The same lack of attention to detail vitiates, for
example, Heraclitus's
comments about stepping into a river. I will say more about that
later in this Essay. I
am told that Greek makes no distinction between mass and count nouns; maybe so,
but then no Greek would ask another to count chalk, rain, or wine.]
On this in general, see
here and
here.
However, as with most things in philosophical
logic, things are never quite so simple. On this, see
Geach (1968), pp.39-41
(this in fact links to the 3rd
edition, so the pages are different:
pp.63-64),
and Lowe (1989, 2015). [The complex logic of mass nouns has proven to be particularly
difficult for modern logicians to grapple with. Although
much progress has been made over the last forty of fifty years, I am far from
convinced there is a definite work on this topic. It might indeed be a mistake
to look for a single logic of mass nouns.]
The above
quoted passage has since disappeared from the Internet, but its author,
Professor Lowe, has published something similar in one of his books:
"It is a plausible contention --
although one that I shall seek to qualify shortly – that for any given sort
of individuals there is a criterion of identity for individuals of
that sort. Linguistically, the point is reflected in a distinction emphasized by
P. T. Geach between
those general terms that are and those that are not 'substantival'. For Geach,
the mark of a substantival general term is precisely that it has associated with
its use -- as indeed a component of its very sense -- a criterion of identity
for instances falling under it. By such a criterion, Geach means 'that in
accordance with which we judge whether identity holds' in assessing the truth or
falsehood of an identity statement concerning individuals. So, for instance,
'man' and 'gold' are by this account substantival general terms -- or, as I
prefer to call them, in deference to John Locke, sortal terms -- because
it seems that there are, at least in principle, ways of determining whether, if
x and y are men or quantities of gold, they are the same
man or the same gold. But a general term like 'red thing' is not for
Geach substantival, precisely because it has no such criterion of identity
associated with its use.
"A sufficient, but not necessary,
condition for a general term's being a sortal is that there should exist some
principle for counting or enumerating individual instances falling
under it. Thus, there are ways of counting the number of men or tables
or books in a given room, but no way of counting the number of red
things that there are. And this is not because there is such a
number, but one beyond our powers of determining -- as in the case of the number
of atoms in the room – but rather because it apparently does not even
make sense to speak of such a number until the sort or sorts of
red thing that one is to count have been specified. Suppose, for example, that
the room contained a red table: then that, it might be urged, is clearly one
red thing. But what about its red top and its red legs, or the red knob on
one of its red drawers? Are these to be counted as different 'red things'
in the room in addition to the red table itself? And what about, say, the
red paint covering one of the table's legs: is that also to count as a
distinct 'red thing’ in its own right? It rapidly becomes apparent that there is
no principled way of deciding these matters, until we are told what sorts
of red thing we are supposed to be counting.
"Suppose, however, that we were
instructed to count every sort of red thing in the room: would that
in principle lead us to a determinate maximal number of red things in the
room – perhaps, indeed, an infinite number, but still determinate? One
problem arising here is that of providing criteria for the identity and
diversity of sorts. Another is that of providing criteria for determining
when two distinct sorts are disjoint, since one must avoid counting the
same individual twice because, say, it is both a red φ
and a red χ. A still more fundamental problem arises, however, once we
acknowledge quantities or portions of red stuffs (such as portions of red
ink) to qualify as red things in the room, as I believe we should. For there is
clearly no principled way of determining how many such portions there are
in a given place, in view of the indeterminate extent to which any such portion
is divisible into further portions.
"For the foregoing reason, general
terms such as 'man', 'table', and 'book' (but not 'thing') have the
logical -- and not just the grammatical -- status of count nouns, and
they form, as I say, a subset of sortal terms. But, to repeat, the countability
of instances falling under it is not a necessary condition for a general term's
being a sortal, since so-called mass nouns like 'gold' and 'water'
apparently have criteria of identity associated with their use, despite the fact
that it makes no sense to ask how many instances of gold or water exist
in a certain place. Significantly, though, it does make sense to ask
how much gold or water exists in a given place. The general tenor of my
remarks is not without venerable historical precedent. If we were to ask what it
is that sortal terms denote, a plausible answer would seem to be that they
denote what Aristotle in
the Categories called secondary substances: that is, species and
genera -- or, in other words, sorts or kinds. Correspondingly,
what Aristotle called primary substances we may refer to as
the individuals or particulars instantiating such sorts or kinds.
But an important point to appreciate here is that the notions of individual
(or particular) and sort (or kind) are, very arguably, interdependent
and mutually irreducible. Individuals are recognizable only as individuals of
a sort, while sorts are intelligible only as sorts of individuals."
[Lowe (2015), pp.12-14. Italic emphases in the original. Links added;
several paragraphs merged.]
5b.
The material that used to be
here has now been moved the main body of the
Essay.
6.
Hegel's egregious logical blunders have been exposed
here,
here, and
here (and they will be completely
demolished in Essay Twelve Parts Five and Six -- summaries
here and
here).
The material
that used to be here has been moved to
the main body of this Essay.
7.
However,
as is the case with other philosophical 'problems', Trotsky is in good company;
philosophers
and modern logicians also succeed in confusing equality with identity. In fact, this is a
still
highly neglected area in the Philosophy of Logic. There are signs, though, that this
might be beginning
to change;
on that, see
Sanford (2005).
In fact, astute logicians have been aware of
such complexities for years, but have been opposed by traditionalists reluctant
to change (no irony intended). On this, see Geach (1967, 1973, 1975, 1990), Griffin (1977), and
Noonan (1980, 1997,
2022).
See also
Deutsch (2018).
8.
As
pointed out
above, DM-theorists' comments on
FL are exceedingly repetitive
and almost
entirely garbled
(Graham Priest's work being a notable exception
in this regard). In
stark contrast to their
attempts to master other areas of knowledge -- for example,
classical and modern economics, science, history, politics and current affairs --,
when it comes to FL, dialecticians
display little or no comprehension even of
Elementary Logic.
Indeed, their writings almost invariably contain highly superficial and
inaccurate characterisations of what turn out to be obsolete forms of
AFL. Not surprisingly, such
'logical straw men' are easy to knock over.
[On this, see Essay Four,
here and
here.]
It is instructive to compare this dishonest
approach to FL with the justifiable condemnation that the very same DM-theorists level at analogously
distorted views of revolutionary socialism found in the writings
of the vast majority of Marx's bourgeois critics. Here, again, is John
Molyneux:
"Marxist materialism is
repeatedly attacked by the method of oversimplifying and caricaturing it to the
point where it is obviously false...." [Molyneux (2012), p.36.]
And yet this is precisely
what he and other DM-fans regularly do when they attempt to summarise, discuss
or criticise FL.
[For some reason, the words "sauce", "goose",
and "gander" come to mind here.]
In this regard, it is quite clear that John
Rees, for instance, can't possibly have checked a single logic text
(other than those
mis-titled works written by Hegel, perhaps) before he wrote what he did about
FL and the LOI in
TAR. As also seems to
be the case with most other Marxist critics of FL, Rees appears
to have confined his 'research' on this topic to reading only what
previous dialecticians had written about it, simply copying what he found
there. [Indeed, a supporter of this site tried to point this out to him at a
large public meeting in London in 1990; that was clearly a waste of breath. I
tried to point this out to him a few weeks ago on Twitter, and he
promptly blocked me!]
In modern symbols, one form of
Leibniz's Law
is
as follows:
[1] (∀x)(∀y)((x
= y) º
(Fx
®
Fy)).
[1]
is otherwise known as the
Indiscernibility of Identicals.
Translated, it roughly reads: "Any two objects are identical if and only if they
share the same properties" -– or, "…whatever is true of one is true of the
other." This particular 'Law' won't be
defended here for reasons outlined in Note
1. Its translation into ordinary language isn't happy on any
reading. That alone shows it isn't equivalent to the ordinary use of "equal
to", "the very same as", "identical with", or even "numerically identical with".
[For complications, see Gallois (2003).]
Nevertheless, it is important to note
that the use of the "=" sign in [1] has been strengthened by the presence of the
bi-conditional "º";
hence, it isn't identical to Trotsky's use of the former sign, either (no irony
intended).
Contrast [1] with the following version of
the same 'Law':
[2] (∀x)(∀y)((∀F)(Fx
º
Fy)
®
(x = y)).
[2]
is otherwise known as the
Identity of
Indiscernibles.
[Unfortunately,
Internet Explorer 10 doesn't seem able to display all the symbols the
above linked article uses; IE 11 appears to be able to cope with them, though.
Edge
also reproduces them correctly.]
Loosely translated [2] reads: "Any two objects that share every
property in common are identical." However, this version requires
quantification across properties, which is controversial.
One of Trotsky's mistakes was to suppose that
this 'Law' is empirically testable -- where, for
example, (i) he supposed that the truth of S1 [i.e., "A is equal to A"]
could be checked directly by the use of an eyeglass, and where (ii) he referred to
the weighing of
bags of sugar. Trotsky clearly regarded the failure of S1 to pass such tests as
sufficient grounds for rejecting this 'Law' (or, at least, an 'absolute'
application of it, especially where change is involved). However, it didn't seem to occur to
him that an empirical test of Leibniz's Law is wholly
inappropriate; it would be just as misguided as an empirical test of, say,
"a + b = b + a" (i.e.,
commutativity
over addition) in Mathematics. Anyone who thought to check such a rule in the
same manner as Trotsky (irony intended) would be regarded as hopelessly
confused, and rightly so.
[On the other hand,
when this 'Law' is regarded as
the
expression of a rule, the temptation to think it can be tested
in such a crude manner vanishes. On this, see Note 10,
below. Of course, it is possible to use this 'Law' to test whether or not
two or more bodies are identical, but that is a different matter (no irony
intended!).
Incidentally, on this issue it won't do to point out that certain operators in
mathematics don't
commute since no one in their
right or left mind would empirically test these, either. Of course, tests might be
performed to see whether or not certain systems in nature displayed
commutativity -- or, rather, whether certain rules adequately coped with such
systems (for example, in
Matrix Mechanics)
-- but no test would or could be run on
the principle itself. And, despite what dialecticians say, the same goes
for the LEM, as it has allegedly been used/refuted in/by QM. More on that later.]
[QM = Quantum Mechanics;
LEM = Law of Excluded Middle.]
Compare the two versions of Identity
outlined above with the following:
[3]
j(y)
º
[(∃x)((x
= y) & j(x))].
[3] appears in Griffin (1977), p.1, which
also contains a strengthened version of Leibniz's Law:
[4] (∀x)(∀y)[(x
= y) º
(∀j)(j(x)
º
j(y))].
[4] roughly reads: "Any two objects are
identical if and only if for any property, one has it if and only if the other
also has it." Griffin gives several other versions of [1] and [2] above, (ibid., p.2).
Incidentally, [3] roughly says "Anything true of some object is equivalently
true of any object identical to it." [In fact, I have used this version in
the present Essay to show that identity is no enemy of change. Because this rule
doesn't require quantification
across properties, it is, in my view, preferable to both [2] and [4].]
["∀"
is the universal
quantifier, equivalent to
"All", "Any" or "Every"; "∃"
is the existential quantifier, equivalent to "Some" or "At least one"; "º"
is the sign for logical equivalence, i.e., "If and only if"; "j"
and "F" are predicate variable letters; "®"
is the implication arrow, equivalent to "if...then"; "x" and "y" are
"bound" quantifier
variables. For more on this, see, for example, Priest (2000) and
Tomassi (1999). On quantifiers, see
Note 13a.
However, for an important word of warning about variables, see
here.]
8a.
And the same could be said -- but, with slightly less justification -- about
Hegel; at least he used the right word, even if it is clear that he
failed to grasp the complexity of this logical 'law', just as he failed to do
justice to the ordinary words we have for identity and difference, etc.
8b.
Incidentally, this doesn't confuse identity with identification, it merely
reminds us that mastery of the latter requires a certain level of proficiency
concerning
the vocabulary associated
with the former.
9. This
is from The Guardian newspaper (Wednesday, 18/10/1995):
"K2 appeared over the 40 million years or so
that India has been colliding with greater Asia. It was 'discovered' (i.e., by
the British) and designated K2 (Karakoram Peak 2) in 1856. The peak was granted
the name [Mount Godwin-Austen] in 1888, after its first surveyor, Col Henry
Haversham Godwin-Austen (1834-1923). The previous title is now preferred as
being less imperialistic. Ordinarily a mountain would revert to its local name,
but K2 is so remote that it appears never to have gained one." [Letter from
S. McDiarmid, reprinted in Notes and Queries. See also
here.]
This is perhaps a more interesting
example of ordinary ascriptions of identity than those considered by Frege (for
instance, with
respect to the Evening Star and the Morning Star,
etc.), in Frege (1892). [On that, see, for example,
here and
here (the latter links to a PDF).]
From the same newspaper:
"In Nepal they
call it Sagarmatha. To the people of Tibet, it is
Chomolungma,
though the ruling Chinese prefer the variant Qomolangma. When the British
first began mapping India, they knew it as Peak B, then as Peak XV.
But in 1865, to honour the surveyor-general of India who first mapped it,
Peak XV was given the name Mount Everest. And Everest the
mountain has remained throughout much of the rest of the world to this day.
"Now China is
launching a fresh effort to outlaw the name Everest. Accusing British
colonialists of 'raping the sacred mountain of Tibetans by giving it a false
name', Chinese newspapers are calling on the world to 'respect Tibetans' by
using the 50th anniversary of the first ascent next year to recognise the
mountain henceforward as Qomolangma.
"At first
sight, the proposal does not seem unreasonable. There are, after all, lofty
precedents for such renaming. The highest point in Africa, the summit of
Kilimanjaro, which was once known as
Kaiser Wilhelm Spitze, properly became Uhuru Peak. The world's
second-highest peak, once Mount Godwin-Austen to the British, has become
K2 (ironically this also dates from imperial survey days). But doubts
about the new proposal soon creep in. If Everest is unacceptable, why should the
world not prefer the Nepalese name to the Chinese or Tibetan one? Who are the
Chinese, of all people, to accuse others of raping Tibet? And how is the
'English language hegemonism' of which China complains worse than its Chinese
language equivalent?
"We hold no
great brief for the name Everest, though it has to be said that the word
has a fine ring to it. But the answer is to live and let live. If people prefer
Chomolungma, let them use that name. If others want to stick with
Everest, let them do so too. We have no problem with diversity, though the
Chinese may. In the end, the world's greatest mountain is surely more important
than any name that mere mortals give to it." [The
Guardian,
20/11/02.
Italics added; quotation marks
altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]
So, here we have several perfectly ordinary
identities:
Everest is identical to
Chomolungma, Qomolangma, Peak B
and
Peak XV; Kilimanjaro is identical to Kaiser Wilhelm Spitze,
Mt
Cook
is identical with Aoraki, and so on. Of course, we would
ordinarily say things like "Everest
is Chomolungma", or "Kilimanjaro is Kaiser Wilhelm Spitze", and
the like, using the "is" of identity, here.
Furthermore, and as noted earlier,
The
Isis (not to be confused with those violent insurgents in the Middle East!)
is identical to the
River Thames
as it flows through Oxford (UK). Hence, whatever change The Thames undergoes in
this stretch of the river, The Isis undergoes identically. [This again shows
that identity is no enemy of change.]
Other examples come rapidly
to mind: Vladimir Ilyich Ulyanov is Lenin,
Lev Davidovich Bronstein is Trotsky,
Yigael
Gluckstein is Tony Cliff,
Cicero is Tully,
George Eliot
is Mary Anne Evans,
Carter
Dickson is John Dickson Carr,
Currer
Bell is
Charlotte Brontë,
Edgar Box is
Gore Vidal,
Mumbai is Bombay,
Calcutta is
Kolkata,
Peking is Beijing,
Siam is Thailand,
Burma is Myanmar,
Gold Coast is Ghana,
Ceylon is Sri
Lanka,
Persia is Iran, Upper Volta is Burkina Faso, Ayers
Rock is Uluru,
The First Battle of Manassas is The First Battle of Bull Run,
The
Battle of Sharpsburg is the Battle of Antietam --, and, in August 2015,
President
Barak Obama told us that
Mt
McKinley is now Denali, and so on.
[Dozens of examples of pen names
and pseudonyms are listed
here.
My current favourite re-naming is the
Kuiper Belt
object, Ultima Thule, which is now
486958 Arrokoth. It was renamed because "Ultima Thule" was the
name given by the Nazis to a mythical
homeland for the 'Aryan people'.]
In
addition, the
ordinary
examples given earlier about absolute identity apply in this case too: so,
whatever is true of Mt Everest is absolutely identical to whatever is
said about
Chomolungma.
Even if this mountain changes (which it plainly does), those changes will apply
(absolutely) equally to Everest and
Chomolungma. Indeed, anything true of anyone climbing Everest is
identically true of that person climbing Chomolungma.
So, concerning any two
individuals, NN and MM, climbing
Chomolungma, the following will be true:
Let NN and NM begin to climb the same
mountain at the
same time and also let them remain on it for two days. While still on that
mountain, whatever changes it experiences (and this includes
changes to all its properties and relations over these two days),
this will always be the case: NN and NM are on identically the same
mountain
as each other.
More precisely (adapting an argument from
earlier):
A1a: During temporal
interval, T -- lasting m hours --, a set of predicates, P, is true of, or
can be used to form true propositions about, (i) Mountain, M, (ii)
All
who climb it, and (iii)
M, all
on that mountain during
T,
and their relations with everything in the universe
-- where P is comprised of the following elements:
{P1,
P2, P3,..., Pn},
and where n is indefinitely large.
A2a: NN and NM
are both climbing M during any sub-interval, tk,
of T, of arbitrary length.
A3a: During tk,
a subset of P, namely {Pi..., Pk},
can be used to form true propositions about (i) M, (ii) All
on M, and (iii)
M, all
on that mountain during
T,
and their relations with everything in the universe, including any changes that occur
to one or both during tk
(m
ε
ℝ).
A4a: So, during tk,
NN and NM are on absolutely identically the same mountain as one another,
since, while they are on M, the valid applicability of every element of {Pi,..., Pk} remains the case throughout.
Now, every element of {Pi,...,
Pk}
-- i.e., these predicates, or what they 'reflect' -- can change 'dialectically'
all the time, but that won't alter the result, since any changed element of {Pi,...,
Pk}
will
also be an element of that sub-set, by the above definitions.
So, here we have an example of absolute
identity that would remain such even in a
Heraclitean universe.
[The same comments are also true of the
other items listed above. The reader is left to work out the details for
herself.]
Instead of
consulting Trotsky
on identity -- or
even worse, Hegel --, DM-fans would do well to begin their study of
identity by reading Frege. [I.e., Frege (1892).
However, it
has to be said, even Frege tended to confuse identity with equality!]
Excellent introductions
to Frege's thought can be found in Kenny (1995), Noonan (2000) and Weiner
(1990, 1999); for a useful guide to the philosophical issues involved, see Linsky (1977).
[For a much more detailed bibliography, see
here.]
We
now read the following in a
relatively recent issue of the
New Scientist:
"In 2003, at team...[in]
Moscow discovered two distant elliptical galaxies just a whisker apart. Detailed
analysis of the twins known as CSL-1, suggested that they were images of the
same galaxy.
The team suggested that the
duplicate images were being created by a 'cosmic string'.... If one of these
cosmic strings were to pass between Earth and a giant galaxy, the warping of
space-time by the string would create a
gravitational lens
and form two
identical images of the galaxy -- exactly like CSL-1.... Unfortunately for the
proponents of cosmic strings, observations with
Hubble
on 12 January have
revealed that CSL-1 is actually two different galaxies...." [New Scientist
189, 2537, 04/02/2006, p.21. Quotation marks
altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Paragraphs merged.]
Now, this is an
excellent example of genuine science at
work. Instead of 'solving' this problem in an a priori manner (à
la
Trotsky, or
à
la Hegel), declaring that things are never equal to themselves,
astronomers were able to show that these images weren't of the same object, but of two
different galaxies.
[However, one wonders what dialecticians would
have said if these two images had been shown to be of the same galaxy.]
In the
article posted at the above link (to the New Scientist) several examples were given of multiple images
of identically the same object.
In relation to which, consider the following line-of-argument:
G1: Image I1
is identical to image I2.
G2:
Image I1
and image I2
are both of the same object.
G3:
But, image I1
is an image of object O1.
G4: Image I2
is an image of object O2.
G5: Therefore, O1
is identical to O2.
[I
hasten to add that this isn't the line-of-argument employed by the scientists
mentioned in the above article!]
It isn't easy to see how dialecticians would be able to tell G1 and G2 apart
(if these scientists had in fact found they were of the same object),
nor account for the conclusion recorded in G5.
And, it would be no use pointing to the alleged limitations of the LOI
here, since, no matter how much, or to what extent, objects
O1
and O2
changed, they would still be identical,
since they would change at an identical rate as 'one another' (being one object,
not two)! Certainly, the images of these objects may or may not be identical,
but these 'two' objects can't fail to be, since there is only one of them!
[As
should now be obvious, this is just another example of the sort given
earlier, which also underlines the fact
that identity is no enemy of change.]
Of course, if it were now
maintained that,
on the basis of what Trotsky or Hegel said, objects
O1
and O2
were nonetheless not identical
(or they were both identical and not identical(!)), then that would
fatally undermine this part of Astrophysics since it would
at the very least throw into doubt the use of gravitational lensing in the above manner. If these
objects were always non-identical, then images
I1
and I2
would plainly be of two different objects,
and the above inference would fail.
As noted earlier, it isn't
easy to see how dialecticians can hold on to their criticism of the LOI without
compromising, at a minimum, this part of Physics.
Furthermore, as we will see later, a desperate appeal to "approximate
identity" would be to no avail here, either.
Here is another recent example of the ordinary use
of words for identity in one of the sciences:
"More than 600,000 plant species have been
deleted from the dictionary of life after the most comprehensive
assessment carried out by scientists.
"For centuries, botanists from different
parts of the world have been collecting and naming 'new'
plants
without realising that many were in fact the same. The
humble tomato boasts 790 different names, for example, while
there are 600 different monikers for the oak tree and its
varieties. The result was a list of more than 1
million flowering plant species. Although experts have long
known that it included many duplicates, no one was sure
how many. Later this year, the study team, led by UK and US
scientists, will announce that the real number of flowering
plant species around the world is closer to 400,000.
"The project -- which has taken nearly
three years -- was the number one request made by the 193
government members of the
Convention on Biological Diversity at their meeting in 2002. There were concerns that without this
work, it would be impossible to work out how many plants were
under threat and how successful conservationists were in saving
them. The information will also be vital for
any organisation or researcher looking at 'economically
important' plants, such as those for food and nutrition or
medicine, said Alan Paton, assistant keeper of the herbarium at
the
Royal Botanic Gardens at Kew,
west London, one of the four leading partners in the project.
"'On average, one plant might have
between two and three names, which doesn't sound a great
deal, but if you're trying to find information on a plant, you
might not find all [of it] because you're only looking at one
name,' Paton said. 'That's even more critical for economically
useful plants: because they are more used, they tend to have
more names.'
"In one example, researchers calculated
that for the six most-used species of
Plectranthus, a
relative of the basil plant, a researcher would miss 80% of
information available if they looked under only the most
commonly used name. On another database, they found only 150 of
500 nutritionally important plant species using the names cited
in current literature. 'By going for one name, we missed the
majority of information mankind knows about that plant, which
isn't too clever,' said Paton. 'What's really a breakthrough is
we have a place which allows people to search through all the
names used.'
"Kew Gardens joined up nearly three years
ago with
Missouri Botanical Garden in the US, and experts on two of the biggest and most valuable
plant families: legumes, or peas and beans, and
Compositae,
which include asters, daisies and sunflowers. They have since attempted to search
existing plant lists and work out an 'accepted' name for each
species, and then list all known variations. One of the
databases was originally set up using £250 left in the will of
Charles Darwin. The full results will not be published until the
end of the year, but so far the researchers have found 301,000
accepted species, 480,000 alternative names, and have 240,000
left to assess.
"Although work will continue to assess
smaller plant groups in more detail and check for missed
duplications, Paton said they now believe that the true number
of plant species will turn out to be '400,000 or just over. You can't give an absolute number of
names, but we have narrowed the possibility,' he said. Previous
estimates, without the help of a full assessment, put the figure
at between 250,000-400,000.
"Most of the work of the study group was
sifting and sorting different names allocated to one species,
often because scientists were simply not aware of the work of
rivals and colleagues who had previously 'described' the plant
in a scientific journal, or because of confusion caused by
superficial differences such as different sized leaves in
different climates. In some cases, plants thought to be the same
have also been judged to be different species because of
differences which have been revealed by later scientific
discoveries, such as DNA.
"As well as the likely 400,000-odd
flowering plants, there are thought to be 15,000 species of
ferns and their allies, 1,000
gymnosperms
such as conifers, and
23,000 mosses and allies making up the plant kingdom. For
comparison there are more than 1 million species of insects
listed by science, 28,000 living species of fish, 10,000 birds
and 5,400 mammals.
"A
meeting of the Convention on Biological Diversity in October in
Japan is likely to declare that
targets to halt biodiversity loss by this year failed and set
tougher new aims to halt the problem." [The
Guardian, 20/09/10, p.1. Quotation marks altered to
conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Bold emphases added.
Several paragraphs merged.]
It isn't too clear how
DM can accommodate several plant names all naming the same
species. Once more, an appeal to 'abstract' and/or 'approximate'
identity won't help,
as we will soon see.
10.
Some of these
observations, of course, depend on the said weighing scales changing at the same
rate as the sugar being weighed, which, while unlikely, isn't beyond the bounds
of possibility.
The point is, of course, that this is an empirical matter that can't be settled
a priori, as Trotsky and Hegel both imagined it could.
10a.
Anyone tempted to think that the present writer is an "empiricist" -- or even
a "positivist" --
on
the basis of the constant demand for confirmation should read this,
and then perhaps think again.
10b.
It is also important to point out that the 'truth' if this 'law' is
equally
problematical as its 'falsehood' (no irony intended), for both of these depend on treating the LOI
as a sort of Super-Empirical Truth.
[There is more on this in
Essay Twelve Part One,
and Note 17, below.
Why
this is so is connected with Wittgenstein's comments about 'rule-following'; again,
on this see the references given in Essay Twelve
Part One, and in Essays on the
nature of language to be published at a later date -- for example,
here.]
11.
The Material that used to be here has been moved
to the main body of
the Essay.
12.
The Material that used to be here has been moved
to the main body of
the Essay.
13.
The reader will no doubt have noticed that in order to interpret Trotsky we have
had to use the
dread LOI. In that case,
a decision must be taken as to whether or not S8 is equivalent to (i.e.,
identical with) S11 or S12.
S8: A pound of sugar is equal to
itself.
S9(b): [All bodies] are never equal to
themselves.
S10: Let A1
be a pound of sugar at time, T1.
S11: Let A2
be a pound of sugar at time, T2.
[T2
> T1.]
S12: S8 means A1
is equal to A1.
S13: S8 means A1
is equal to A2.
Of course,
it is reasonably clear that Trotsky believed that a complete understanding of change (even if
humanity never actually attained to it) would require the employment of concepts
more adequate to the task -– i.e., those found in DL. Many of these 'more
adequate concepts'
have been examined throughout this site where they have been shown to be no less
vague, confused, or just plain incoherent.
[IDM = In Defense of
Marxism (i.e.,
Trotsky (1971)); DL = Dialectical Logic.]
However, in his Notebooks,
Trotsky added a number of important qualifications to his comments on the LOI
found in
IDM. Among which are the following:
"a = a is only a particular case of the law
of a
¹
a…. Formal Logic involves stationary and unchanging quantities: a = a.
Dialectics retorts: a
¹
a. Both are
correct. A = a at every given moment. A
¹
a at two different moments. Everything flows, everything is changing." [Trotsky
(1986), pp.86-87.]
This suggests that Trotsky might have
accepted a version of S13 or S21(a):
S13: S8 implies A1
is equal to A2.
S21(a): There is an A and a
time, t1
such that A at t1 is not
equal to A at t2.
S13 was in turn dependent on S8, S10 and S11:
S8: A pound of sugar is
equal to itself.
S10: Let A1
be a pound of sugar at time, T1.
S11: Let A2
be a pound of sugar at time, T2.
[UO = Unity of Opposites/Unities of
Opposites, depending on the context.]
The above
would appear to mean that Trotsky was only committed to the idea that an
object isn't identical with itself at some
later time, as opposed to adhering to the stricter principle that objects
aren't self-identical at any given moment -– the latter of which options is in
turn based on the doctrine that all objects are contradictory UOs. If so, the
above passage would seem to suggest that Trotsky was rejecting a core DM-thesis:
that is, that there is at least one UO in every object and process, which drives
change because UOs
somehow cause, constitute or create
'internal contradictions'. Clearly, it is highly unlikely that Trotsky denied this
core DM-idea. For example, his emphasis on the contradictory nature of the
former USSR
(elsewhere in IDM) strongly suggests he accepted this doctrine.
On the other hand, since Trotsky
nowhere (to my knowledge) refers to the idea that change is the result of the
struggle between UOs, it is possible that he did reject, or didn't
fully accept, this part of the theory.
[For a contrary inference from the same Notebooks,
see below.
Having said that, there are several things Trotsky does say later on in these
same Notebooks,
that suggest he did view everything as a UO; e.g., p.103 -- on that, see
here.]
Nevertheless, since the above quotation is taken
from notebooks which weren't intended for publication it would be unwise to rely too
heavily on what they contain as an accurate picture of Trotsky's intentions. This
is especially so since it (rather fittingly) appears to contradict what was said in IDM:
A1: "In reality 'A' is not equal to 'A'…. [O]bserve these two letters under a lens
-- they are quite
different from each other." [Trotsky
(1971), pp.63-64.]
S9(a): All bodies change
uninterruptedly. (b) They are never equal to themselves.
Compare this with a passage from the
Notebooks (quoted above) where Trotsky now seems to say the opposite:
A2: "A = a
at every given moment." [Trotsky (1986), p.87.]
If A1 and S9(a)(b) were correct, A2 couldn't be.
At best, A2 would only tell half the story.
For example, in A2, the two letter "A"s
are easy to distinguish without the aid of a lens: the second letter is in the
lower, while the first is in the upper case. But here, in A2, Trotsky now argues that these
"A"s
are equal at "every given moment" -- even though they look different to
the naked eye!
Conversely, in A1 Trotsky claims
that the opposite of this is
true with respect to two letter "A"s, which not only look identical
but also are in the same upper case! He claims that the two capital
letters in A1 above look different if examined under a lens, while a lower case "a"
and a capital "A" in A2 are equal at every moment!
If A2 were correct,
then Trotsky's reference in A1 to the physical appearance of these two letter
"A"s
when viewed under an eyeglass would be completely pointless. The only reasonable conclusion
here seems to be that since A1 was intended for publication it must
contain Trotsky's more considered thoughts.
Furthermore, as noted above, A2
seems to be inconsistent with the claim that change is the result of internal
contradictions: that is, with the idea that at any given moment an object
both is and is not self-identical, constituting a UO -- in the present case,
presumably a unity of "A and not A" (i.e., "pound bag of sugar and not pound bag
of sugar" -- or, maybe, "pound bag of sugar and pound bag of non-sugar", or
even "pound bag of sugar and non-pound non-bag of non-sugar" (it is
far from clear which of these is implied by what Trotsky said), if, as we are
told, everything, including weights, bags and sugar change all the time and are
"never equal to themselves"), or that a pound bag of sugar is both identical and not identical
with its 'other',
as Hegel might have put it. [On this, see Essay Eight
Part Three,
and Essay Twelve (summary
here). On the confusions Hegel's ideas will always introduce in this
area, see here.]
A2: "A = a
at every given moment." [Trotsky (1986), p.87.]
[Precisely
what one of these 'Hegelian others' is of a pound bag
of sugar is somewhat unclear. A pound bag of tea? A half pound bag of tea?
A pound bag of
Quinine? However,
if a pound bag of sugar
has no 'other' (and
no dialectical-logical 'other', either)
then,
according to the
DM-classicists,
it can't change.
To be sure,
sugar and what
can happen to it are highly
complex; there are any number of things it can and does change into, so it must
have countless 'others' (which fact rather makes a mockery of Hegel's 'analysis'
of change, one would have thought). More on that here.]
In addition, A2 is itself rather
badly worded. When Trotsky wrote:
A3: "A = a at every
given moment" (italic emphasis added),
he must have meant:
A4: "A = a at any
given moment."
This is because the wording of A3 implies
that "A" never changes; i.e., that at all times "A =
a" --
something Trotsky certainly didn't believe. [Of course, he might have
been alluding to the IED-thesis,
that every object is both identical and different from itself. However, I have batted
that idea out of the park, here.]
On the other hand, A3
might contain an indirect allusion to Trotsky's point about 'abstract moments' in
time:
"A sophist will respond that
a pound of sugar is equal to itself at 'any given moment'…. How should we really
conceive the word 'moment'? If it is an infinitesimal interval of time, then a
pound of sugar is subjected during the course of that 'moment' to inevitable
changes. Or is the 'moment' a purely mathematical abstraction, that is, a zero
of time? But everything exists in time; and existence itself is an uninterrupted
process of transformation; time is consequently a fundamental element of
existence. Thus the axiom 'A' is equal to 'A' signifies that a thing is equal to
itself if it does not change, that is if it does not exist." [Trotsky
(1971),
p.64.]
But,
according to this, if Trotsky were referring to 'abstract moments', it would mean that
the objects and processes to which he was alluding couldn't exist.
If so, it would be
unclear how
A3 itself could ever be true
-– that is, always assuming Trotsky meant it to
apply to these non-existent
'abstract moments'.
A1: "In reality 'A' is not equal to 'A'…. [O]bserve these two letters under a lens
-- they are quite
different from each other."
A2: "A = a
at every given moment."
A3: "A = a at every
given moment" (italic emphasis added).
A4: "A = a at any
given moment".
Of course, if A2 and A3 were
merely about letter variables (not their supposed denotations -- i.e., what they
supposedly refer to) it might
be
possible to re-interpret them in a more viable form.
One such re-configuration would see
A2 and A3 recording the fact that while objects in the world change, letters
depicting them don't. But that would make Trotsky's other assertions
about the "A"s in A1 decidedly odd, for the aim there had been to argue that
these letters weren't in fact "equal" irrespective of what they
referred to, and that was because, upon close examination, we would always find there were
minor differences between them. That was the whole point of Trotsky's appeal to ocular inspection.
And, since letters are physical objects in their own right, his claim surely was
that they are just as susceptible to change and diversity as the things to
which they supposedly refer. So, this option (that while objects change, letters
referring to them don't) doesn't look like it is a reliable interpretation of
Trotsky's intentions.
On the other hand, if Trotsky had wanted to
argue for something more complex in this regard it would prove
impossible to comprehend his point. For example, if he had meant something like
the following:
T1: Variable
letters and what they refer to both change, and that they do so as
follows:
(a) Each letter "A" no longer refers
to whatever it used to refer to moments earlier, and,
(b) The object that each old letter "A"
once denoted is no longer the same as it was when first identified, and,
(c) Earlier and concurrent
manifestations of any and all letter "A"s are never the same as the
'same' new letter "A"
now on the page/screen (which page/screen also changes), and,
(d) Any two or more
concurrent letter "A"s
on the 'same' line (which also changes) are not only different from each other,
they change at different rates, and,
(e) Each letter individually denotes in a
different and changing manner objects in reality, which objects are also
different and are all changing at different rates themselves.
If
something like this had been Trotsky's intention then his entire point would
become too obscure to make much sense of, for we
wouldn't have a clue what the hell he was banging on about. And yet, if
everything
changes uninterruptedly in every respect (as Trotsky himself claimed),
he must have 'meant' this!
It could be
objected that Trotsky only needs to appeal to the relative stability of
medium-sized objects in reality to neutralise criticisms like this. Hence, if
both language and most medium-sized objects are relatively stable, points
(T(a)) to (T(e)) above don't apply.
But, how could anyone
committed to this theory know whether or not language
is 'relatively stable'
-- especially if they also believe that everything is
in the grip of the
Heraclitean Flux?
In fact, as soon as language itself is implicated in this 'Flux', everything
that might seem semantically solid must melt into thin air. In that case, it would be no good appealing to
evidence (drawn from dictionaries, textbooks, personal memory, common usage, etc.) in
support of the claim that language is 'relatively stable', for if everything is
changing then so is the language in which this evidence is itself expressed, so are the
notebooks and/or primary data sheets from which it has been retrieved, and so are the memories
upon which all
of these depend. Given this way of looking at things, for all anyone knows, every single word could change its
meaning every fraction of a second (along with any and all memories of, or about, the objects
that seem familiar to us, like dictionaries, journals and textbooks).
This extreme view of the mutability of language was in fact endorsed by
Voloshinov:
"[T]heme must be unitary, otherwise we would have
no basis for talking about any one utterance. The theme of an utterance is
individual and unreproducible, just as the utterance itself is
individual and unreproducible. The theme is the expression of the concrete,
historical situation that engendered the utterance. The utterance 'What time is
it?' has a different meaning each time it is used, and hence, in accordance
with our terminology, has a different theme, depending on the concrete
historical situation ('historical' here in microscopic dimensions) during
which it is enunciated and of which, in essence, it is a part." [Voloshinov
(1973), p.99. Bold emphases added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the
conventions adopted at this site.]
[And, as we will see in Essay Thirteen
Part Three, several other
comrades seem to be of the same opinion (no pun or irony intended).]
Of
course, it could be objected in response that if the above were the case, the world would be
far too crazy and confusing for anyone to make any sense of. But, the fact that
we can makes sense of the world tells us that this interpretation (i.e., that
Trotsky's theory is inconsistent with relative stability) can't be correct.
In
fact, Trotsky and other DM-theorists said the following:
"[A]ll bodies change uninterruptedly in size,
weight, colour etc. They are never equal to themselves.... [E]verything
exists in time; and existence itself is an uninterrupted process of
transformation….
"For concepts there also exists 'tolerance' which
is established not by formal logic…, but by the dialectical logic issuing from
the axiom that everything is always changing….
"Dialectical thinking analyses all things and
phenomena in their continuous change….
"Dialectics…teaches us to combine syllogisms in
such a way as to bring our understanding closer to the eternally changing
reality." [Trotsky
(1971), pp.64-66. Italic emphases added.]
"Dialectics…prevails throughout nature….
[T]he motion through opposites which asserts itself everywhere in nature,
and which by the continual conflict of the opposites…determines the life of
nature." [Engels (1954),
p.211. Italic emphases added.]
"[Among the elements of dialectics are the
following:]…internally contradictory tendencies…in this [totality]…and
unity of opposites…. [E]ach thing…is connected with every other…[this
involves] not only the unity of opposites, but the transitions of
every determination, quality, feature, side, property into
every other….
"In brief, dialectics can be defined as the
doctrine of the unity of opposites. This embodies the essence of dialectics….
"The splitting of the whole and the cognition of
its contradictory parts…is the essence (one of the 'essentials', one of
the principal, if not the principal, characteristic features) of dialectics….
"The identity of opposites…is the recognition…of
the contradictory, mutually exclusive, opposite tendencies in all
phenomena and processes of nature…. Development is the 'struggle' of opposites.
"…The unity…of opposites is conditional,
temporary, transitory, relative. The struggle of mutually exclusive opposites is
absolute, just as development and motion are absolute." [Lenin (1961),
pp.221-22,
357-58. Emphases in the original.]
"According to Hegel, dialectics is the
principle of all life…. [M]an has two qualities: first being alive, and
secondly of also being mortal. But on closer examination it turns out that
life itself bears in itself the germ of death, and that in general
any phenomenon is contradictory, in the sense that it develops out of
itself the elements which, sooner or later, will put an end to its existence and
will transform it into its opposite. Everything flows,
everything changes; and there is no force capable of holding back this
constant flux, or arresting its eternal movement. There is no force
capable of resisting the dialectics of phenomena….
"At a particular moment a moving body is at a
particular spot, but at the same time it is outside it as well because, if it
were only in that spot, it would, at least for that moment, become motionless.
Every motion is a dialectical process, a living contradiction, and
as there is not a single phenomenon of nature in explaining which we do
not have in the long run to appeal to motion, we have to agree with Hegel, who
said that dialectics is the soul of any scientific cognition. And this
applies not only to cognition of nature….
"And so every phenomenon, by the
action of those same forces which condition its existence, sooner or later, but
inevitably, is transformed into its own opposite….
"When you apply the dialectical method to the
study of phenomena, you need to remember that forms change eternally
in consequence of the 'higher development of their content'….
"In the words of Engels, Hegel's merit consists
in the fact that he was the first to regard all phenomena from the point
of view of their development, from the point of view of their origin and
destruction…." [Plekhanov
(1956), pp.74-77,
88,
163. Bold emphases alone added.]
"'All is flux, nothing is
stationary,' said the ancient thinker from Ephesus. The combinations we call
objects are in a state of constant and more or less rapid change….
"…[M]otion does not only make objects…, it is
constantly changing them. It is for this reason that the logic of
motion (the 'logic of contradiction') never relinquishes its rights
over the objects created by motion….
"With Hegel, thinking progresses in consequence
of the uncovering and resolution of the contradictions inclosed (sic) in
concepts. According to our doctrine…the contradictions embodied in
concepts are merely reflections, translations into the language of thought,
of those contradictions that are embodied in phenomena owing to the
contradictory nature of their common basis, i.e., motion….
"…[T]he overwhelming majority of phenomena
that come within the compass of the natural and the social sciences are among
'objects' of this kind…[:ones in which there is a coincidence of opposites].
Diametrically opposite phenomena are united in the simplest globule of
protoplasm, and the life of the most undeveloped society…." [Plekhanov (1908),
pp.93-96. Bold emphases alone added.]
"Everything in motion is continually
bringing forth this contradiction of being in two different places at the same
time, and also overcoming this contradiction by proceeding from one place to
the next….
"A moving thing is both here and there
simultaneously. Otherwise it is not in motion but at rest….
"Nothing is permanent. Reality is
never resting, ever changeable, always in flux. This unquestionable
universal process forms the foundation of the theory [of dialectical
materialism]….
"According to the theory of Marxism,
everything comes into being as a result of material causes, develops through
successive phases, and finally perishes….
"Dialectics is the logic of movement, of
evolution, of change. Reality is too full of contradictions, too elusive, too
manifold, too mutable to be snared in any single form or formula. Each
particular phase of reality has its own laws…. These laws…have to be discovered
by direct investigation of the concrete whole, they cannot be excogitated by
the mind alone before material reality is analysed. Moreover, all reality
is constantly changing, disclosing ever new aspects….
"If reality is ever changing,
concrete, full of novelty, fluent as a river, torn by oppositional forces, then
dialectics…must share the same characteristics….
"Nature cannot be unreasonable or
reason contrary to nature. Everything that exists must have a necessary and
sufficient reason for existence….
"The material base of this law lies in
the actual
interdependence of all things in their reciprocal interactions…. If
everything that exists has a necessary and sufficient reason for existence,
that means it had to come into being. It was pushed into existence and forced
its way into existence by natural necessity…. Reality, rationality and
necessity are intimately associated at all times….
"If everything actual is necessarily
rational, this means that every item of the real world has a sufficient reason
for existing and must find a rational explanation….
"But this is not the whole and final
truth about things…. The real truth about things is that they not only
exist, persist, but they also develop and pass away. This passing away of
things…is expressed in logical terminology by the term 'negation'. The whole
truth about things can be expressed only if we take into account this opposite
and negative aspect….
"All things are limited and changing….
In logical terms, they not only affirm themselves. They likewise negate
themselves and are negated by other things…. Such a movement of things and of
thought is called dialectical movement….
"From this dialectical essence of
reality
Hegel drew the conclusion that constitutes an indispensable part of his
famous aphorism: All that is rational is real….
"[M]ovement…from unreality into reality
and then back again into unreality, constitutes the essence, the inner
movement behind all appearance….
"Everything generates within itself
that force which leads to its negation, its passing away into some other and
higher form of being….
"This dialectical activity is
universal. There is no escaping from its unremitting and relentless embrace.
'Dialectics gives expression to a law which is felt in all grades of
consciousness and in general experience. Everything that surrounds us may be
viewed as an instance of dialectic. We are aware that everything finite, instead
of being inflexible and ultimate, is rather changeable and transient; and
this is exactly what we mean by the dialectic of the finite, by which the
finite, as implicitly other than it is, is forced to surrender its own immediate
or natural being, and to turn suddenly into its opposite.' (Encyclopedia,
p.120)." [Novack (1971), pp.41, 43, 51, 70-71, 78-80, 84-87, 94-95; quoting
Hegel (1975), p.118, although in a different translation from the one used here.
Bold emphases added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions
adopted at this site.]
[Many more passages like the above have been reproduced in
Essay Two.]
It is
hard to seen how anything could remain the same, even if only temporarily, given
what the above have to say -- after all, Trotsky tells us that "All
bodies change uninterruptedly in size, weight, colour etc. They are never
equal to themselves...."
and that it is an "axiom" that
"everything is always changing."
The other DM-theorists say more-or-less the same (no irony intended, once more).
Indeed, Engels characterised as "metaphysical" the belief that things are identical with
themselves:
"To the metaphysician, things and
their mental reflexes, ideas, are isolated, are to be considered one after the
other and apart from each other, are objects of investigation fixed, rigid,
given once for all. He thinks in absolutely irreconcilable antitheses. 'His
communication is "yea, yea; nay, nay"; for whatsoever is more than these cometh
of evil.' For him a thing either exists or does not exist; a thing cannot at
the same time be itself and something else. Positive and negative absolutely
exclude one another, cause and effect stand in a rigid antithesis one to the
other." [Engels
(1976), p.26. Quotations marks altered to conform with the conventions
adopted at this site, Bold emphasis added.]
The above
is a direct consequence of the doctrine that everything is a UO, a combination
of what it is and what it is not; what it is and what it is changing into. Any who deny this are branded
"metaphysicians" by Engels.
[I
have said much more about this topic in Essay Eleven
Part One;
readers are directed there for more details.]
In
view of the above, and because we can make (even limited) sense of the world,
that must mean the opinions of these DM-worthies are about as wide of the mark
as any could be.
Indeed, as Plato himself recognised, the
Heraclitean Flux is no respecter of theories; in fact it completely mangles them.
[On that, see
Note 10 above, and
Note 15
below -- and, in this case,
Essay Thirteen
Part Three,
where Voloshinov's ideas are subjected to sustained and destructive criticism.
On Plato, see Note 49
of Essay Eleven Part One.]
Furthermore, the reasoning
in the Notebooks appears to be somewhat confused:
"a = a is only a particular case of the law
a
¹
a." [Trotsky (1986), p.86.]
It is difficult to see how "a
= a" could be a particular case of the 'law' "a
¹
a", any more than "a + b = b + a", for instance, could
be a particular case of the rule "a + b
¹
b + a"".
If "a
¹
a" is a
'law', then "a = a" refutes it; it doesn't instantiate it. Of
course, this would be the case unless the word "refute" has in the
meantime changed its meaning. [Perhaps because of the local effects of the pesky Heraclitean Flux?]
Naturally, in such a madcap Heraclitean world
it isn't easy to see exactly what would or could either stay the same or change -- or,
indeed, for how long a decision about even that possibility would
itself remain stable!
And yet, contrary to what was intimated earlier, the above quote could be an indirect reference on
Trotsky's part to a UO operating, namely this: the fact that
"a = a" and "a
¹
a". If so, Trotsky's criticism of the LOI would collapse into irredeemable
confusion. If "a" doesn't equal "a", that is, if "a" is
in fact also "not a", then the
following must be true:
C1: "a is not a" -- or "a = not
a".
In which case, we can
substitute "not a" every time we see an "a", giving this series of dialectical
oddities (but using capital letter "A"s to make the point a 'little
clearer'):
C2: "A = not A".
C3: "Not A = not (not A)".
C4: "Not (not A) = not (not (not
A))".
C5: "Not (not (not A)) = not (not (not (not
A)))".
C6: "Not (not (not (not A))) = not (not (not (not
(not A))))".
C7: "Not (not (not (not (not A)))) = not (not
(not (not (not (not A)))))".
And
so on, substituting "not A" for each "A" in
each C(n), to
yield C(n+1).
But, worse: whatever is true of "A" must also be true of "=" and
"not" (and even "is"!), yielding the following ever-expanding bowl of dialectical
spaghetti (as each "not" and each equal sign is replaced by its 'dialectical
equivalent', "not (not)" and "= and
¹",
in each case --
and then, of course, by "not not (not (not))", and "not (not = not and not
¹)", respectively):
C8: "A = not A".
C9: "Not A (= and
¹)
not not (not A)".
C10: "Not Not (Not A) not (not = not and not
¹)
not not not not (not not (not A))".
C11: "Not Not Not Not (Not Not (Not
A) not not
(not not not = not not not and not not not ¹)
not not not not not not not not (not not not not (not not (not A)))."
And so on.
[The
above also ignores the fact that each bracket, quotation mark, full stop,
C(n), and space between each letter and word, should also be
'negated',
à
la Trotsky/Hegel -- but that task can be left to the reader to complete.
(If letters are "never equal to themselves", the spaces between them aren't,
either, and neither are brackets and other punctuation marks!)]
If "A" is never equal to itself (and nothing else is,
either), then the above must follow -- which dire dialectical dénouement
can only be avoided by those who reject Trotsky and Hegel's crazy ideas about
identity and change.
But, we have been here
already.
[Again,
the 'relative stability' defence has been neutralised,
here,
here and
here.]
Moreover, several other things Trotsky said in
IDM indicate that the above passage from his Notebooks isn't a reliable
guide to his thinking:
"A sophist will respond that
a pound of sugar is equal to itself at 'any given moment'…. How should we really
conceive the word 'moment'? If it is an infinitesimal interval of time, then a
pound of sugar is subjected during the course of that 'moment' to inevitable
changes. Or is the 'moment' a purely mathematical abstraction, that is, a zero
of time? But everything exists in time; and existence itself is an uninterrupted
process of transformation; time is consequently a fundamental element of
existence. Thus the axiom 'A' is equal to 'A' signifies that a thing is equal to
itself if it does not change, that is if it does not exist." [Trotsky
(1971),
p.64.]
This at least confirms the accuracy
of the interpretation put on Trotsky's analysis of the LOI in this
Essay
-–
that is, in so far as any sense can be made
of it.
Finally, what TAR itself says about Trotsky's
argument seems to agree with the interpretation given here, as do other
commentators. [Cf., Rees (1998),
p.273. See also: Novack (1971) and Woods and Grant (1995/2007).]
13a. Quantifiers in language are words like
"all", "every", "any", "some", "most", "nothing", and "none", etc. Tensed quantifiers are
terms like
"always", "never" and "sometimes". On this, see
here,
here
and
here.
14. It could be
objected to this that "moments in time" aren't objects; time
is, it seems, one of the "modes of existence of matter" -- that is an inference of
mine based on what Engels said:
"Motion is the mode of existence of matter.
Never anywhere has there been matter without motion, nor can there be….
Matter without motion is just as inconceivable as motion without matter.
Motion is therefore as uncreatable and indestructible as matter itself; as
the older philosophy (Descartes)
expressed it, the quantity of motion existing in the world is always the same.
Motion therefore cannot be created; it can only be transmitted…." [Engels (1976), p.74.
Italic emphasis in the original.]
It is
difficult to see that time isn't a "mode of the existence of matter" if it is so
intimately connected with motion.
Be
this as it may, if time can
be measured (rather like bags of sugar can be weighed) then Trotsky's criticisms must apply to
time,
too. Moreover,
if we accept what Lenin said about matter (i.e., that it is whatever exists
"objectively outside the mind" (a doctrine examined in detail in Essay Thirteen
Part One)),
time must be material, too -- unless, of course, time 'exists' only in the mind.
If that were so, time couldn't be 'objective':
"Recognising the existence of objective reality, i.e.., matter in
motion, independently of our mind, materialism must also inevitably recognise
the objective reality of time and space, in contrast above all to
Kantianism, which in this question sides with idealism and regards time and
space not as objective realities but as forms of human understanding....
"'Space
and time,' says
Feuerbach, 'are not mere forms of phenomena but essential conditions...of
being' (Werke, II, S. 332). Regarding the sensible world we know
through sensations as objective reality, Feuerbach naturally also rejects the
phenomenalist (as Mach would call his own conception) or the agnostic (as Engels
calls it) conception of space and time. Just as things or bodies are not mere
phenomena, not complexes of sensations, but objective realities acting on our
senses, so space and time are not mere forms of phenomena, but objectively real
forms of being. There is nothing in the world but matter in motion, and
matter in motion cannot move otherwise than in space and time. Human conceptions
of space and time are relative, but these relative conceptions go to compound
absolute truth. These relative conceptions, in their development, move towards
absolute truth and approach nearer and nearer to it. The mutability of human
conceptions of space and time no more refutes the objective reality of space and
time than the mutability of scientific knowledge of the structure and forms of
matter in motion refutes the objective reality of the external world." [Lenin
(1972), p.202-03. Bold emphasis alone added. Quotation marks altered to
conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Link added.]
Hence, it
seems that not only is matter 'objective', so are time and space, according to Lenin; and if they are
'objective', they can be measured. In that case,
even if time isn't an 'object', as we have seen, it can be measured. [On this,
see Note 14a. More on this
presently, too.]
14a.
On the various systems for measuring time, see
here.
It could be argued that since moments in time follow on from each
other, it isn't possible to measure one of them in order to compare it with any
other -- since the earlier one will no longer exist to make the comparison! This
isn't the case with
respect to objects that have to be weighed; they clearly exist side-by-side during the entire process, facilitating comparison.
Or, so this objection
might proceed...
But, can't moments differ even if we are unaware of it? And, can't
two objects be weighed simultaneously, and local to each other, with the duration of each weighing
instance timed
simultaneously, too, so that these durations can be compared just like their weights?
Be
this as it may, Trotsky's argument still relies on some reference to the 'same
moment', and that must involve a use of the LOI applied to time.
Concerning differing time intervals (or, at least, their
measurement), this is what a recent New Scientist article had to say:
"Clocks that gain or lose no more than a fraction of a
second over the lifetime of the universe could be on the way, thanks to a
technique for cutting through the 'heat haze' that compromises the accuracy of
today's instruments.
The most accurate atomic clock we have now is regulated
by the electrons of a single aluminium
ion
as they move
between two different
orbits
with sharply defined energy levels. When an electron goes from the higher energy
level to the lower it emits radiation of a precise frequency. That frequency is
used to mark out time to an accuracy of better than 1 part in 1017,
or 1 second in 3 billion years.
"That's pretty good, but it could be better. Infrared
photons emanating from the background cause the two energy levels to shift by
slightly different amounts, says
Marianna Safronova at the University of Delaware. That
affects the frequency of the emitted radiation to an unknown extent, adding a
small uncertainty to the clock's tick. Safronova reported this month at a conference in
Baltimore, Maryland, that by combining two different mathematical approaches,
she and her colleagues have now managed to calculate how much the energy gap
between the two levels changes.
"Using this information to correct an atomic clock could
in principle increase its precision to around 4 parts in 1019,
or about 1 second per 80 billion years. Such a clock could test whether the
fundamental constants of nature are changing, Safronova suggests." [New
Scientist 210, 2813, 21/05/2011, p.15. Bold emphases added.
Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.
Several paragraphs merged.]
Even with this new method, time intervals
(or at least the processes by means of which we measure them) clearly change over
billions of years, just as weights do (over shorter periods).
15.
Again, it could be
argued that all Trotsky requires is
the relative stability of the words he used, which won't have changed
significantly during the short intervals involved.
Unfortunately, Trotsky holed that response well below the water line, declaring that:
"[A]ll bodies change uninterruptedly in size, weight,
colour etc. They are never equal to themselves… But everything exists in time;
and existence itself is an uninterrupted process of transformation….
Thus
the axiom 'A' is equal to 'A' signifies that a thing is equal to itself if it
does not change, that is if it does not exist." [Trotsky
(1971), p.64. Bold added.]
In that
case, since words are also material objects they must "change uninterruptedly"
(as must their meanings) and hence they are "never equal to themselves".
So, if,
according to Trotsky, every letter "A" is subject
to the Heraclitean Flux from moment-to-moment and each is "never equal" itself, words
and entire sentences stand no chance.
So, not only does this theory (DM) imply that there is no way of knowing whether or not
words (and/or their meanings) have changed dramatically --, even while they are
being uttered (including any of the words that might be used to argue
for or against either possibility) --, it also implies that, whether we
know it or not, they have changed in the above way.
[We saw earlier that Voloshinov
also
appeared to hold this view.]
Consequently, the word "identity" (and its meaning) must itself fail to be
self-identical at one and the same moment (if Trotsky were to be believed), since everything (including
every meaning, one supposes) is a unity of itself and its 'opposite' (its
"other",
according to Hegel
and Lenin).
Plainly, that implies the word "identical" must also mean
and not
mean "not identical", at the
same time!
If that weren't the case, then dialecticians would have no way of
accounting for the change in meaning of the word "identity" itself, which,
according to
their own theory, has to change, and it can only do that because of
one or more of the following factors: (i) Its own 'internal
contradictions', (ii) The 'internal contradictions' of (or in) the meanings we attribute to it,
or (iii) A response to 'contradictions' in society-at-large (which we are told are reflected
in language). So, given the truth of DM, unless "identical" now
means "not identical", its meaning couldn't change.
The same argument
in turn applies to anyone who uses
this word. So, by "identical" they, too, must mean "identical"
and "not identical". Moreover, assuming DM is true, it isn't easy to see how the understanding of
these changed and changing meanings, allied with altered and altering
intentions, could possibly be coordinated across an entire population of
dialecticians, let alone the wider community. Naturally, that would completely undermine inter-personal communication, which in turn
would prevent DM-theorists from communicating their ideas to the rest of
humanity, or even to one another, since they would all mean something different
by their use of this particular term, or, indeed, any word.
The
same argument applies to anyone who uses
this word. So, by "identical" they, too, must mean "identical"
and "not identical". Moreover, if, for the purposes of argument, we
assume DM is true, it isn't easy to see how the comprehension of
these changed (and continually changing) meanings, allied with altered (and
continually altering)
intentions, could possibly be coordinated across an entire population of
dialecticians, let alone the wider community. Everyone would mean something
increasingly different by every word they used, and that would also be different
from their own previous use of the 'same' words. Clearly, this would scupper inter-personal communication, which in turn
would prevent DM-theorists themselves from communicating their ideas to the rest of
humanity, never mind one another. They too would continually mean something different
by their use of "identity", or, indeed, any word.
This would further imply that no one would
or could possibly "understand" dialectics -- not Hegel, not Marx, not Engels, not
Plekhanov, not Lenin, not Trotsky..., since the meaning of every single term
used would
be subject to unspecified changes, and hence consequent indeterminacies. Even
worse, given the truth of DM,
there is nothing that could be done to rectify the situation. Any attempt to do
so would also be subject to very same the tender mercies of the dread Heraclitean Flux.
[Irony intended.]
Furthermore, if
we now apply DM consistently across the board,
any such a 'rectification' (should one be attempted) would be both a 'rectification' and 'not a
rectification' at the same time!
[On that,
also see Essays
Three Part Two, Eleven
Part One and Thirteen Part Three.]
The only way to avoid 'ridiculous' conclusions
like these is to abandon the doctrine that all things change all the time
(as a result of their 'internal contradictions') --, or admit that some things remain
identical (namely, at least the word "identical" and its meaning), indefinitely. Either way, DM would
suffer
yet another body
blow.
Hence, in order to avoid the unremitting
confusion that the Heraclitean doctrine of universal change would introduce into DM itself, Trotsky needed the LOI to apply to his own
words and their meanings (as a rule of language or of practice) while he was using them.
In addition, that would have to
have been true for many years (possibly even for several centuries),
too, so that his supporters/epigones would be able to understand him correctly (or,
indeed, at all!). That would be the case especially when he hoped to employ
certain words to question the application of identically same law to
those letter "A"s and
bags of sugar! [Irony intended, once more.] Otherwise, for all he knew, his words and their meanings
could
be non-self-identical from moment-to-moment. [His theory
implies that anyway.]
In addition,
anyone consulting Trotsky's words today must be able to read them with
their original meanings intact or they wouldn't be able to agree with the
originally intended
content/message, and hence with what Trotsky had attempted to argue. If so, contemporary dialecticians who read Trotsky's words (or,
indeed,
Hegel's) must in effect take any argument against the application of a strict version of the
LOI with a pinch of salt
or risk failing to grasp the exact message Trotsky (or Hegel) had intended.
Alternatively, they would have to admit that what those two had to say about identity
and change can't be grasped by anyone if what they claimed about the LOI were
the case.
So, if
Trotsky and Hegel's words about identity and change (etc.) were correct, the message
they intended to convey wouldn't now be accessible, having changed in
untold ways over the years -- possibly (probably!) into its opposite! Indeed,
definitely into its opposite, if we were to believe what the
DM-classics have to say about change.
It could be objected that our words do in
fact remain relatively stable, so the above comments are entirely
misguided. However, if Hegel and Trotsky are to be believed, there would be
no way that either of them (or anyone else, for that matter) could possibly
determine
whether or not words remain 'relatively stable'. Indeed, if
their theory were true, even the words in the previous sentence,
along with their
meanings, will have changed!
As should now seem obvious, if DM were
a valid theory, there would be nothing to which anyone could appeal in order to base a single secure thought.
Hence, if Trotsky and the
other DM-theorists quoted earlier
were speaking the truth, this couldn't be true:
"[A]ll bodies change uninterruptedly in size, weight,
colour etc. They are never equal to themselves… But everything exists in time;
and existence itself is an uninterrupted process of transformation….
Thus
the axiom 'A' is equal to 'A' signifies that a thing is equal to itself if it
does not change, that is if it does not exist." [Ibid. Bold emphasis added.]
If nothing
in the entire universe -- including thoughts, words and their meanings -- is ever
"equal to" itself, then there can be no secure foundation for a single
DM-proposition, let alone anything else.
On the other hand, if there
were something upon which DM-theorists could ground their thoughts, then Trotsky, Hegel
and Heraclitus must have been mistaken, since, in that case, at least
something would remain
unchanged long enough for it to be of any use -- namely whatever it is that we
could ground even that thought upon. So, given the validity of Trotsky's
argument -- that nothing stays the same, that all things
change uninterruptedly and are never equal to themselves, they are never self-identical
-- there can't be any such grounding. An appeal to the
memory we might have of a given word (of its use or its meaning), for
example, would be to no avail, either. If
everything is changing, then memory itself can hardly remain unscathed. Not even
Cartesian 'clear
and distinct ideas' would be available to anchor a single
DM-cognition on solid epistemological bedrock. The words, concepts, and ideas
retrieved in order to formulate these comforting 'Cartesian certainties' would
themselves be non-self-identical
from moment-to-moment, subject to unremitting and continual change, in like
manner.
A moment's thought (no pun intended!) will
confirm that even the phrase "relatively stable" must itself be subject to change
-- along with its meaning -- if we were to believe what
DM-theorists
try to tell us. How could dialecticians to rule that out? In fact, it is implied by their
own theory! This must be so if everything is subject to relentless change in the way
that Heraclitus, Hegel, Lenin,
Trotsky and all the rest imagined. In which case, it is the DM-doctrine of
constant, universal change that must be rejected to save this theory from its
own absurd implications and easy self-refutation. Of course, the only way
to do that would involve an invocation of the
LOI, interpreted now as a rule of language or of practice, not as a metaphysical,
or any other sort of, truth.
Once again, DM-fans would have to appeal to
FL
and/or ordinary language to
rescue their theory from itself.
Alternatively, if it is indeed a fact that language is stable, then the
DM-theory of change must be wrong (and for reasons rehearsed
above; see also
here and
here), since, at a minimum,
A will equal A (even if only for few moments),
thus refuting Trotsky,
Hegel and all the rest.
As I point out in Essay Eleven
Part One:
Of
course, as is the case with other linguistically competent human
beings, DM-apologists understand perfectly well how to use words for identity –-
such as, "similar", "equal", "equivalent", "same", and "identical" -- along with
their appropriate qualifiers (e.g., "exactly", "precisely",
"accurately", "very", "nearly",
"approximately" and "almost").
Plainly, a grasp of terms like these arises out of their employment in everyday life
by each language user, not
from a supposed 'law'. Nor does this facility follow from the 'negation', nor
yet the double 'negation', of the LOI. [There is more on that
here.] In fact, this
everyday facility with words for identity (etc.) is what enables DM-theorists
themselves to engage in a pretence that the LOI is
either false or only 'approximately true' when it is applied to objects and
processes in concrete reality. As competent language-users they understand the LOI perfectly well, and yet it is their misinterpretation of the socially-conditioned rules
we have for the use of terms like the above as if they represented empirical
truths about any object and itself that ultimately misleads them.
In
short: dialecticians mistake the misinterpreted content of a social norm for reality itself,
and then make a fetish of the result.
[I hasten to
remind the reader that the above does not mean that I think there is no
change anywhere in the universe! As I have noted already, this is an empirical
question to be settled by science, not the confused musings of mystics.]
16. Again it could be
argued that identity criteria for temporal instants could be
specified by
mapping them onto the
Real Numbers;
since the latter are distinguishable, the former must be, too. Given this scenario,
such instants would be
isomorphic
to the Reals.
In response to this, several points are worth making:
(1) This view assumes that 'time itself' (as
opposed to the measurement of time) is composed of discrete units, and
that they can therefore be counted (or, at least,
mapped onto the Positive Integers/The Positive Reals). But, that sits rather awkwardly
with the idea that temporal instants can be measured, which appears to
suggest that time must be both discrete and continuous.
[Dialecticians might
be happy with that implication, but just watch them then (i) Squirm when asked to explain (in physical
terms) how that is even possible, or (ii) Reach for yet another
Nixon card.]
(2) The only 'evidence' for the validity of
such a manoeuvre derives from the proposed
isomorphism
itself. In that case, any criteria of identity for instants in time that result
from this
mapping would clearly be a
reflection of the imported properties of Real Numbers, which is precisely
the point at issue. If 'instants' in time have no identity -- that is, if
they aren't discrete (or, rather, if their ordering isn't the result of the
application of an
inductive law to a
discrete variable; or, indeed, to any
variable at all) -- an isomorphism like this would simply amount to their
conventionalised re-description.
Hence, the proposed isomorphism could end
up misrepresenting the very thing being mapped -- especially if this is
considered to be the only way to view time -- since it makes something
that appears to be continuous look as if it were discrete, imposing on time a
structure it might not possess. [To be sure, mathematicians since
Dedekind have
regarded the Reals as both
dense and
continuous. But even then, there is no
suggestion that Real Numbers merge into one another, that they have no
discrete identities or that they can't be distinguished. Cf., Sanford (2005).]
In that case once more, dividing time into temporal instants in this way would impose on
it something it might not have.
It seems, therefore, that time can only be broken up
into metaphysical instants if it is mapped onto something that is
already fragmented (in the
above sense), like the Reals. On the other hand, if time is only
continuous (and isn't composed of discrete 'instants'), then, without
distortion, it can't be mapped onto the Real Numbers, which are discrete but
continuous (again, in the
above sense -- that is, there are no 'gaps' between them, with "gap" defined
in a specific way in
Real Analysis (this links to a PDF)). Of course, any supposition to the contrary
would suggest that it isn't
in fact time which has been mapped onto Real Numbers, but Real Numbers that have
been mapped onto themselves, and then misleadingly re-labelled
"instants".
[That comment
disposes of the claim that scientists are
actually speaking about time when they talk this way. What they are in fact doing is talking about
Real Numbers in drag. (On this in general, see Read (2007), pp.79-115, on
which many of my own ideas have been based.)]
(3) A successful isomorphism
would itself depend on an application of the LOI (interpreted as a rule, not
as a
'philosophical truth'), making this attempt to patch up the argument of little use to
DM-theorists --, or, at least to those who are still concerned to observe even a
modicum of consistency.
[LOI = Law of Identity.]
Of course,
all this is independent of the fact that isomorphisms are
creatures of convention; they don't actually populate the universe. Any attempt
to use them to shore up DM would be unwise, therefore, since it would imply that
whatever is concluded about the LOI would likewise be a product of convention, and hence not at all
'objective'.
[There is an interesting, if
somewhat metaphysical, discussion of
this topic in Adamson (2002), pp.5-58. Nevertheless, Adamson's 'solution' (based
on the radically confused writings of
Henri Bergson)
seems to be far worse than the problem it was meant to solve. (It is also worth
adding
that Adamson's characterisation of
Analytic Philosophy is
highly misleading. However, I don't propose to defend that accusation here.)]
[I have
commented on this use of nested intervals of Real Numbers in
Essay Five.]
17.
Again, the reader mustn't assume that I
accept that the LOI expresses an 'absolute truth' -- or indeed any sort of
truth. The questions at this point in the main body of this Essay are directed at those who regard the LOI
either as a profound metaphysical thesis (even if it is never instantiated in
material reality -- or, at least, 'only within certain limits'), or as a highly confirmed empirical generalisation. If, as is
maintained here, the LOI is in fact a misleading way of expressing several distinct
grammatical rules (we have for sentences using words for identity and
sameness, depending on when and where the LOI is applied), then the 'problems'
associated with the traditional view of this 'law' simply disappear. There is no such
'law' to be true of anything, just a series of rules we have been
socialised into using -- and, it is worth recalling that rules can't be true or false,
just practical or impractical, useful or useless, applied or misapplied.
In this way
a whole cloud of dialectics has been condensed from a
drop of misconstrued grammar (to paraphrase Wittgenstein).
18.
This
doesn't contradict the earlier claim that Trotsky didn't comprehend the LOI. What is maintained here is that Trotsky
-- just like any other competent language-user -- understood perfectly well how to employ
ordinary words for identity, sameness, equality and difference in everyday life. It is only
when he allowed himself to be led astray by the obscure doctrines he found in Hegel's
Logic that his solidly-grounded material grasp of change was
seriously compromised.
19. This is how the contrary argument will be put in Essay
Twelve (some of this has already been posted in
Essay Four, but it is presented
here in a highly edited form):
John Rees put
things this way:
"Ordinary language assumes that things and ideas are
stable, that they are either 'this' or 'that'. And, within strict limits, these
are perfectly reasonable assumptions. Yet the fundamental discovery of Hegel's
dialectic was that things and ideas do change…. And they change because they embody conflicts which make them unstable…. It is
to this end that Hegel deliberately chooses words that can embody dynamic
processes." [Rees (1998), p.45.]
The problem with this passage is that
it gets
things completely the wrong way round. It is in fact our use of ordinary
language that enables us to speak about change, movement and development. Complex
philosophical jargon (especially terminology invented by Hegel) is completely useless in this regard, since it
is wooden, static and of indeterminate meaning, despite what Rees asserts.
[Any who think differently are invited to reveal precisely which set
of Hegelian
terms is able do what the words listed below (or their equivalent in German)
already achieve for us, only better.]
As is well-known (at least by Marxists),
human beings managed to progress because of their interaction with nature, later
constrained by the class war and the
development of the forces of and relations of production. In which case, ordinary language
-- the result of collective labour --
couldn't fail to
have invented a range of words with the logical and semantic multiplicity that
allowed its users to
speak about changes of almost limitless complexity, speed and duration.
This is no mere dogma; it is easily confirmed. Here is
a greatly shortened list of ordinary words (restricted to modern
English, but omitting simple and complex
tensed participles and
auxiliary
verbs) that allow speakers to talk about changes of almost unbounded
complexity, rapidity or scope:
Vary,
alter, adjust, adapt, amend, make,
produce, revise, rework, advise, administer, allocate, improve, enhance, deteriorate, depreciate, edit, bend,
straighten, weave, merge, dig, plough, cultivate, sow, reap, twist, curl, turn,
tighten, fasten, loosen, relax, ease, tense up, slacken, fine tune, bind, wrap,
pluck, carve, rip, tear, mend, perforate, repair, puncture, renovate, restore,
damage, impair, scratch, diagnose, mutate, metamorphose, transmute, sharpen,
hone, modify, modulate, develop, upgrade, appear, disappear, expand, contract, constrict,
constrain, shrivel, widen, lock, unlock, swell, flow, glide, ring, differentiate,
integrate, multiply, divide, add, subtract, simplify, complicate, partition,
unite, amalgamate, fuse, mingle, disseminate, connect, entwine, unravel, link,
brake, decelerate, accelerate, fast, slow, swift, rapid, hasty, protracted,
lingering, brief, heat up, melt, freeze, harden, cool down, flash, shine, glow,
drip, bounce, cascade, drop, pick up, fade, darken, wind, unwind, meander, peel,
scrape, graze, file, scour, dislodge, is, was, will be, will have been, had,
will have had, went, go, going, gone, return, lost, age, flood, swamp, overflow,
precipitate, percolate, seep, tumble, plunge, dive, float, sink, plummet, mix, separate, cut, chop, crush, grind, shred,
slice, dice, saw, sew, knit, spread, coalesce, congeal, fall, climb, rise,
ascend, descend, slide, slip, roll, spin, revolve, circulate, bounce, oscillate,
undulate, rotate, wave, splash, conjure, quick, quickly, slowly,
instantaneously, suddenly, gradually, rapidly, briskly, hurriedly, absolutely, lively, hastily,
inadvertently, accidentally, carelessly, really, energetically, lethargically,
snap, drink, quaff, eat, bite, devour, consume, swallow, gulp, gobble, chew, gnaw, digest,
ingest, excrete, absorb, join, resign, part, sell, buy, acquire, prevent, block, avert,
avoid, forestall, encourage, invite, appropriate, lose, find, search,
pursue, hunt, track, explore, follow, cover, uncover, reveal, stretch, distend,
depress, compress, lift, put down, fetch, take, bring, carry, win, ripen,
germinate, conceive, gestate, abort, die, rot, perish, grow, decay, fold, empty,
evacuate, drain, pour, fill, abduct, abandon, leave, abscond, many, more, less, fewer, steady,
steadily, jerkily, intermittently, smoothly, awkwardly, expertly, very, extremely, exceedingly,
intermittent, discontinuous, continuous, continual, emit, push, pull, drag,
slide, jump, sit, stand, run, sprint, chase, amble, walk, hop, skip, slither,
crawl, limp, swim, fly, hover, drown, submerge, immerse, break, abrogate,
dismiss, collapse, shatter,
split, interrupt, charge, retreat, assault, squash, adulterate, contaminate, purify, filter,
clean, raze, crumble, erode, corrode, rust, flake, demolish, dismantle, pulverise,
atomise, disintegrate, dismember, destroy, annihilate, extirpate, flatten,
lengthen, shorten, elongate, crimple,
inflate, deflate, terminate, finish, initiate, instigate, augment, replace, undo, redo, analyze,
synthesise, articulate, disarticulate, reverse,
repeal, abolish, enact, quash, throw, catch, hour, minute, second, instant,
moment, momentary, invent, devise, teach, learn, innovate, forget, rescind,
boil, freeze, thaw, cook, liquefy, solidify, congeal, neutralise, evaporate,
condense, dissolve, process, mollify, pacify, calm down, excite, enrage,
inflame, protest, object, challenge, confirm, deny, repudiate, reject, refute, expel, eject,
repel, attract, remove, overthrow, expropriate,
scatter, distribute, equalise, surround, gather, admit, acknowledge, hijack, assemble, attack, counter-attack,
charge, repulse, defeat, strike, occupy, picket, barricade, revolt, riot, rally,
march, demonstrate, mutiny, rebel, defy, resist, lead, campaign, educate,
agitate, organise...
[In each case, where there is
a noun form of a word its verb form
has been listed (for instance, "object" as in "to object"). Moreover, where I
have listed the word "ring", for example, I also intend cognates of
the verb "to ring"
-- like "ringing" and "rang". I have also omitted
many nouns that imply change or development, such as "river", "runner", "wind",
"lightning", "tide", "cloud", and "fire". Anyone
who didn't know such words implied changing processes in the world -- that
rivers flow, fires burn, runners run, tides ebb and flow and winds blow -- would
have thereby advertised a lack of comprehension of English (or whatever language theirs happened to be),
compounded by a dangerously
defective knowledge of the world. So, not knowing that fires burn or rivers flow, for example,
could endanger life. In addition, several of the above also have verb forms,
such as "fired" or "winding". Other nouns also imply growth and development,
such as "tree", "flower", "mouse", "day", "human being". Anyone who
thought "human being", for example, reflected a 'fixed and changeless' view of
the world would perhaps be regarded as suffering from some form of learning
disability; either that, or they were in the grip of an off-the-wall
philosophical theory of some description.]
Naturally, it
wouldn't be difficult to extend this list until it contained literally thousands
of entries -- on that, see
here and
here --, all capable of depicting countless changes in
limitless detail (especially if it is augmented with words drawn from mathematics,
science and
HM).
It is only a myth put about by Hegel and DM-theorists (unwisely echoed by
Rees, and others -- such as Woods and Grant)
that ordinary language can't depict change adequately, since it is
supposedly dominated by 'the abstract understanding', a brain module helpfully identified
for us by Hegel without a scrap of supporting evidence, a brain scan or even the
use of a consulting couch. By way of contrast,
ordinary language
performs this task far better than the incomprehensible and impenetrably
obscure jargon Hegel invented in order to fix something that wasn't broken.
Dialecticians
like Rees would have us
believe that because of the alleged shortcomings of the vernacular only the
most recondite and abstruse terminology
-- concocted by Hegel, the meaning of much
of which is still unclear, even to Hegel scholars! -- is capable of telling us what
we already know, and have known for tens of thousands of years, that
things change!
[There is much more on this
here.]
The idea that the search for knowledge can be modelled
asymptotically was a metaphor introduced by Engels,
in the following passage:
"The identity of thinking and
being, to use Hegelian language, everywhere coincides with your example of the
circle and the polygon. Or the two of them, the concept of a thing and its
reality, run side by side like two asymptotes, always approaching each other but
never meeting. This difference between the two is the very difference which
prevents the concept from being directly and immediately reality and reality
from being immediately its own concept. Because a concept has the essential
nature of the concept and does not therefore prima facie directly
coincide with reality, from which it had to be abstracted in the first place, it
is nevertheless more than a fiction, unless you declare that all the results of
thought are fictions because reality corresponds to them only very circuitously,
and even then approaching it only asymptotically." [Engels to Schmidt
(12/03/1895), in Marx and Engels (1975), p.457, and
Marx and Engels (2004),
pp.463-64.]
[Lenin
and other DM-theorists said more-or-less the same (no irony intended).]
There are many things wrong with the above,
mention of
which will have to be left for another time; but this way of depicting things is
entirely misleading. The idea of an
asymptotic approach in mathematics is
connected with the concept of a
limit --
if the limit in question can be shown
to exist.
Unfortunately, if a series has no limit, a
set of its
partial sums can't in fact "approach" anything at all. Such a series is
therefore said to be
divergent -- not convergent.
However, Engels's argument depends on the
aptness of a metaphor that pictures knowledge as
convergent on a
limit, which limit he neglected to show exists. But worse: the limit in this
case is quite unlike any
found in mathematics. In order to show that this particular limit exists, Engels
would have to have access to absolute knowledge. That would have to be
so
for him to know (not suspect, surmise or conjecture) that this
alleged limit was
indeed a limit of this particular sort (i.e., according to his own
structures on "concepts" expressed in the above passage), and that his
knowledge of it was thus absolutely reliable before he had access to it. He would thus have
to know before he knew!
[Yes,
I know that mathematicians have 'shown' that certain divergent series, those
that are
Cesàro
summable,
do 'have a sum', but this area of mathematics is controversial and it is far
from clear that it will be of any help to Engels. That is because these series
produce notoriously paradoxical and
ridiculously implausible
results -- such as the following:
1 + 2 + 3 + 4 + 5 +... = -(1/12) --
no misprint!
If any DM-fans want to go down that route,
I can only wish them good luck.
But even if they do, they have yet to show that this is the case with respect to
knowledge.]
In that case, another annoying dialectical
inversion now confronts materialist dialecticians (I am ignoring for the
present whether or not it confronts idealist dialecticians): given this
metaphor, knowledge can't be asymptotically converging on an absolute limit, but
diverging from it. If that is so, since the gap between a large finite and
an infinite body of knowledge is itself infinite, we are forced to conclude that
human beings must remain forever trapped in a bottomless pit of
infinite
ignorance -- even supposing we could assert this much with any
confidence given the infinite distance between that supposition itself and the absolute truth about it (that
is, if there is
a limit, and if we were to believe what Engels claimed about "concepts").
Of course, it could be objected that
iterative
functions
in mathematics might yield infinite sequences, and yet that doesn't mean that the
distance between any intermediate value given by a
partial sum of that function and the point toward which it
is converging is itself infinite. For example, the sequence: 1 + 1/2 + 1/4 + 1/8 +...+
1/2n-1 converges on 2
(as n
→
+∞),
but none of the
rational numbers
(formed from partial sums of this series) is infinitely far from 2.
This isn't strictly so (and that is because we are
told there is an infinite number of Rational and Reals between any two
numbers, let alone between a partial sum and the limit toward which it is
converging),
but even if it were the case, the above would
only have been an effective response had Engels bothered to prove there is
indeed a limit here (surely implied by his asymptote
metaphor); but since he didn't, it isn't.
This means that if Engels's metaphor
is apt, the sum total of our 'knowledge' of the specific characteristics
of any and all parts of the Whole (or even of the Whole itself) will always be
overwhelmingly outweighed by the black hole of infinite ignorance around
which we must forever orbit, whose grip we can never shake off.
Kant's
Noumenon by any other
name…?
[There is more on that
here.]
19a.
It is it important
to stress once again that I don't prefer this way of speaking about identity
(that is, that it can be 'identical' (or not) with 'identity'; my reasons for
saying that can
be found
here and
here
).
This manner of speaking has only been adopted to expose the hidden
non-sense lurking at the heart of traditional, metaphysical talk like this.
Moreover, both DM-, and Hegel-fans, who
themselves confuse the relational form of identity with its nominal form -- that
is, they conflate its use in sentences of the form, 'A is identical with
B' with plain and simple 'Identity'
(when they speak about "Identity" and "Difference", for example
-- on that, see the above link) --, have
little room to complain about my temporary use of such terms. They lost that
particular right when they
began to use the word "identity" as the name of the abstract idea or concept:
Identity. [On that, see
here.]
Now,
Trotsky's 'analysis' of the LOI grew out of this confused tradition
(albeit as part of what is in fact the runt of the litter of this wing of Traditional Thought,
i.e., DM itself),
treating it as a 'profound truth',
which he was
concerned to deny always (or ever(?)) applies
to objects or processes in 'concrete' reality.
So, for him (and for Hegel,
so far as can be ascertained),
the LOI is merely an 'approximate or relative truth' when
used
'concretely'. Of course, this Essay is aimed at exposing the irredeemable
confusion that arises from the shared assumption that the LOI is
either (a) absolutely true, (b) approximately true, or (c) is any sort of truth to begin
with.
[On this, see
Note 10,
Note 13,
Note 15 and
Note 20.]
If, however, the LOI is
simply a misleading expression of
the
many
rules we have in the vernacular that enable us to speak of sameness and difference in
everyday life, then
treating it as any sort of truth would be to
fetishise it.
That is, it
would amount to treating what had once been the product of the social relations
between human beings (i.e., a family of
practice-based
rules about sameness and difference) as if it were the real relation between things (or, in this case, as a relation
allegedly
between an object and itself,
even if
it is
only ever 'approximately true'), or even as those things themselves -- if we insist on
treating Identity as an
object
or
a concept named by the word "identity".
For Hegel, this fetishisation appears in his fairy tale about the incestuous
relationship between 'Being', 'Nothing' and 'Becoming'.
[In Essay Three
Part One,
we saw that that fantasy itself arose out of a crass misinterpretation of the "is" of predication
as an "is" of identity.
In Essay Eight Part
Three, we also saw this egregious error was compounded by further syntactic confusions of a rather more
radical nature.]
The ideological background to
the
fetishisation of language like this (initiated in the 'West' by Ancient Greek Philosophers,
which was later turned into an art-form by Hegel) -- and how its reappearance in
DM has helped cripple Dialectical Marxism -- is analysed in Essays Nine
Part Two, Ten
Part One, and Fourteen Part Two.
The idea that concepts are capable of changing (in the way that Hegel and/or
DM-fans imagine they can) is discussed in Essay
Four, where it was
shown that they may only do so if they have been turned into abstract objects, which unfortunately destroys their role as concepts.
Depicted in this way, DM-concepts don't in fact change,
they
vanish.
20.
The material that used to be here
has been moved to the
main body of the Essay.
20a. The material that used to be here
has been moved to the main body of this
Essay.
21.
This isn't to suggest that the words we have for identity and difference
(in ordinary language) severally
or collectively have only one meaning; the wide and expansive semantic diversity
available to us (by the use of such words) has been highlighted
by the numerous examples given in this
Essay
(for instance, here). In fact, countless alternative
connotations have been omitted.
22.
The term "non-sense" is being used here in a specific way, not in its more
usual, disparaging sense to mean "ridiculous", "patently wrong" or "mere
babble".
Nor
does it refer to syntactically-challenged symbols, such as: "the is but
of", "XXX YYY ZZZ", or even "**##&&$£**%^&&*^%".
At this site, the epithet "non-sense"
has in general been reserved for metaphysical
'propositions'. As we will see in detail in Essay Twelve
Part One,
the latter appear to communicate profound,
'Super-Empirical
Truths' about 'Reality Itself'. However, upon examination each
of them turns out to be (i) A disguised or
misconstrued rule of language, or (b) Based on a
distortion of ordinary language -- as we saw in Essay Three
Part One, for example,
where the "is" of predication was transformed into the "is" of identity
(by Hegel and subsequent DM-theorists), and
in this Essay in connection with ordinary words for identity, etc.
[There is as yet no definitive account of Wittgenstein's
analysis
of the words
we have for identity (etc.),
however Roger White's long-awaited book should cast considerable light on this
topic.
Cf., White (2006 and forthcoming).
There is an excellent, albeit brief summary in Glock
(1996), pp.256-64, with a more considered account in Diamond (1991), alongside several articles published in Crary and Read (2000) -- for example, Conant
(2000). See also, Goldfarb (1997) and McGinn (1999).]
23.
See
Note 1
, above.
24.
19th
century
mathematicians found that they couldn't
construct
a rigorous solution to problems they faced in
Real and
Complex Analysis until they had
much clearer
ideas about the nature of numbers, infinite series, limits, convergence and
continuity. As the more astute of them
began to realise, this would involve a more precise understanding of
quantifiers,
multiple generality,
scope ambiguity and the logic of
relational
expressions. This meant that many of the advances subsequently made in
Analysis and
foundational work over
the last hundred years or so wouldn't have happened
without the new
Mathematical Logic
introduced by logicians and mathematicians (such as
Boole,
Frege,
Peano,
Pierce,
Whitehead and Russell).
[On this, see Giaquinto (2004),
and Grattan-Guinness (1970, 1997, 2000a, 2000b). See also the excellent summary
in Kitcher (1984), pp.227-71.]
In addition,
as was
pointed out in
Essay Four, modern FL
has played a key role in contemporary technological innovation, in the
development of
computers, for example,
whereas
DL
has yet to motivate a single successful practical application --, save, of course, that of
radically confusing
Dialectical Marxists, or, indeed,
screwing
around with Russian agriculture.
In that case, this isn't a dry,
academic, impractical issue.
References
Several of Marx and Engels's works listed below have
been linked to the Marxist Internet Archive, but since Lawrence & Wishart
threatened legal action over copyright infringement many no
longer work.
However, all of their work can now be accessed
here.
Adamson, G. (2002), Philosophy In The Age Of Science And Capital
(Continuum).
Aristotle, (1984a),
The Complete Works Of
Aristotle,
Two Volumes, edited by Jonathan Barnes (Princeton University Press).
--------, (1984b),
Metaphysics, in
Aristotle (1984a), Volume Two, pp.1552-1728.
Baghavan, R. (1987), An Introduction To The Philosophy Of Marxism
(Socialist Platform).
Barnes, J. (2009), Truth, Etc. Six Lectures
On Ancient Logic (Oxford University Press).
Beaney, M. (1997), The Frege Reader
(Blackwell).
Brading,
K., and Castellani, E. (2003) (eds.), Symmetries In
Physics. Philosophical Reflections (Cambridge University Press).
Bukharin, N. (1925),
Historical Materialism (George
Allen
&
Unwin).
Butterfield, J. (1993), 'Interpretation And Identity In Quantum Theory',
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 24, pp.443–76.
Castellani, E. (1998) (ed.), Interpreting Bodies. Classical And Quantum Objects In
Modern Physics (Princeton University Press).
Caulton, A., and Butterfield, J. (2012), 'On Kinds Of Indiscernibility In Logic
And Metaphysics', British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 63,
1, pp.27-84.
Conant, J. (2000), 'Elucidation And Nonsense
In Frege And Early Wittgenstein', in Crary and Read (2000), pp.174-217.
Conner, C. (1992),
Dialectical Materialism. The Philosophy Of Marxism (Walnut Publishing).
Crary, A., and Read, R. (2000) (eds.), The New Wittgenstein (Routledge).
Deutsch, H. (2018), 'Relative
Identity', Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
edited by Edward N. Zalta (Fall
2018
Edition).
Deutscher, I. (1970), The Prophet Outcast. Trotsky 1929-1940 (Oxford
University Press).
Diamond, C. (1991), The Realistic Spirit (MIT Press).
Dieks, D., and Versteegh, M. (2007/2008), 'Identical
Quantum Particles and Weak Discernibility', paper deposited at the
University of Pittsburgh Philosophy of Science Archive. [This has now been
published in
Foundations of Physics 38, October 2008, pp.923-34.]
Dietzgen, J. (1906), The Positive Outcome Of Philosophy (Charles Kerr).
Dirac, P. (1967), The Principles Of Quantum Mechanics (Oxford
University Press, 4th
ed.).
Engels, F. (1888),
Ludwig Feuerbach And The
End Of Classical German Philosophy,
reprinted in Marx and Engels (1968), pp.584-622.
--------, (1954),
Dialectics Of Nature
(Progress
Publishers).
--------, (1976),
Anti-Dühring
(Foreign Languages Press).
Feferman, A. (1993), From Tarski To
Gödel. The Life Of Jean Van Heijenoort (A K Peters Ltd.).
Fine, G.
(1999) (ed.), Plato 1: Metaphysics And Epistemology (Oxford University
Press).
--------, (2000), 'Inquiry In The Meno', in Kraut (2000), pp.200-26,
reprinted with minor modifications as Fine (2003b).
--------,
(2003a), Plato On Knowledge And Forms. Selected Essays (Oxford University
Press).
--------,
(2003b), 'Inquiry In The Meno', in Fine (2003a), pp.44-65.
--------,
(2007), 'Enquiry And Discovery: A Discussion Of Dominic Scott, Plato's Meno',
in Sedley (2007), pp.331-67.
--------,
(2018), The Possibility Of Inquiry: Meno's Paradox From Socrates To Sextus
(Oxford University Press).
Frege, G. (1892), 'On Sense And Meaning', in
Frege (1980), pp.56-78; reprinted in Beaney (1997), pp.151-71, as 'On Sinn
And Bedeutung', and in Frege (1980), pp.56-78.
--------, (1980), Translations From The Philosophical Writings Of Gottlob
Frege, translated by Peter Geach and Max Black (Blackwell, 3rd ed.).
French, S. (2019),
'Identity
And Individuality
In Quantum
Theory', Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta (Winter 2019 Edition).
French, S., and Bigaj, T. (2024),
'Identity
And Individuality
In Quantum
Theory', Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta (Spring 2024 Edition).
French, S., and Krause, D. (2006), Identity In
Physics: A Historical, Philosophical And Formal Analysis (Oxford University
Press).
French, S., and Redhead, M. (1988), 'Quantum Physics And The Identity Of
Indiscernibles', British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 39,
pp.233–46.
Gallois, A. (2003), Occasions Of Identity. The Metaphysics Of Persistence,
Change and Sameness (Oxford University Press).
Geach, P. (1967), 'Identity', Review of
Metaphysics 21, pp.3-12; reprinted in Geach (1972),
pp.238-47.
--------, (1968),
Reference And Generality
(Cornell University Press, 2
nd ed.).
[This links to the 3rd
(1980) edition.]
--------, (1972), Logic Matters (Blackwell).
--------, (1973), 'Ontological Relativity And
Relative Identity', in Munitz (1973), pp.287-302.
--------, (1975), 'Names And Identity', in
Guttenplan (1975), pp.139-58.
--------, (1990), 'Identity Theory: A Reply To
Muller, Williams And Dummett', in Lewis (1990), pp.276-99.
Giaquinto, M. (2004), The Search For
Certainty. A Philosophical Account Of Foundations Of Mathematics (Oxford
University Press).
Glock, H-J. (1996), A Wittgenstein Dictionary (Blackwell).
Goldfarb, W. (1997), 'Metaphysics And Nonsense',
Journal of Philosophical Research 22, pp.57-73.
Grattan-Guinness, I. (1970), The
Development Of The Foundations Of Mathematical Analysis From Euler To Riemann
(MIT Press).
--------, (1997), The Fontana History Of
The Mathematical Sciences (Fontana).
--------, (2000a), The Search For
Mathematical Roots 1870-1940. Logics, Set Theories And The Foundations Of
Mathematics From Cantor Through Russell To Gödel (Princeton University Press).
--------, (2000b), From Calculus To Set
Theory 1630-1910. An Introductory History (Princeton University Press).
Griffin, N. (1977), Relative Identity (Oxford
University Press).
Guttenplan, S. (1975) (ed.), Mind And Language (Oxford
University Press).
Hahn, S. (2007), Contradiction In Motion. Hegel's Organic
Concept Of Life And Value (Cornell University Press).
Hale, R., and Wright, C. (1997) (eds.), A Companion To The Philosophy Of
Language (Blackwell).
Hanna, R. (1986), 'From An Ontological Point Of View. Hegel's Critique of Common
Logic', Review of Metaphysics 40, pp.305-38; reprinted in Stewart (1996), pp.253-81.
Hegel, G. (1975),
Logic, translated
by William
Wallace (Oxford University Press, 3rd
ed.).
--------,
(1999),
Science Of Logic
(Humanity Books).
Kenny, A. (1995), Frege (Penguin Books).
Kitcher, P. (1984), The Nature Of
Mathematical Knowledge (Oxford University Press).
Hilborn, R., and Yuca, C. (2002), 'Identical Particles In Quantum
Mechanics Revisited', British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 53,
3, pp.355-89.
Houlgate, S. (2006), The Opening Of Hegel's Logic (Purdue
University Press).
Kraut, R.
(2000) (ed.), The Cambridge Companion To Plato (Cambridge University
Press).
Ladyman, J., and Bigaj, T. (2010), 'The
Principle Of The Identity Of Indiscernibles And Quantum Mechanics',
Philosophy of Science 77, 1, pp.117-36.
Lear, J. (1980), Aristotle And Logical Theory (Cambridge
University Press).
Lefebvre, H. (1968), Dialectical Materialism (Jonathan
Cape).
Lenin, V. (1961),
Collected
Works, Volume 38 (Progress
Publishers).
--------, (1972),
Materialism And
Empirio-Criticism (Foreign
Languages Press).
Lewis, H. (1990) (ed.), Peter Geach: Philosophical Encounters (Kluwer
Academic Press).
Linsky, L. (1977), Names And Descriptions (University
of Chicago Press).
Lowe, E. (1989), Kinds Of Being: A Study Of Individuation, Identity And The
Logic Of Sortal Terms (Blackwell).
--------, (2015),
More Kinds Of Being. A Further Study Of Individuation, Identity And The Logic Of
Sortal Terms (Wiley-Blackwell).
Magee, G. (2008), Hegel And The Hermetic Tradition (Cornell
University Press). [The Introduction to this book is available
here.]
Mandel, E. (1979), Introduction To Marxism (Pluto
Press, 2nd ed.).
Marion, M. (1998), Wittgenstein, Finitism, And The Foundations Of Mathematics
(Oxford University Press).
Marx, K., (1976), Capital
Volume One
(Penguin Books).
Marx, K., and Engels, F. (1968), Selected Works In One Volume (Lawrence
& Wishart).
--------, (1970),
The German Ideology,
Students Edition, edited by Chris Arthur (Lawrence
& Wishart).
--------, (1975), Selected Correspondence (Progress
Publishers, 3rd ed.).
--------, (2004),
MECW,
Volume
50
(Lawrence & Wishart).
McGinn, M. (1999),
'Between Metaphysics And Nonsense', Philosophical Quarterly 49, pp.491-513.
Modrak, D. (2001), Aristotle's Theory Of Language And Meaning
(Cambridge University Press).
Molyneux, J. (2012), The
Point Is To Change It. An Introduction To Marxist Philosophy (Bookmarks).
Moravcsik, J.
(1971), 'Learning As Recollection', in Vlastos (1971), pp.53-69.
Muller, F., and Saunders, S. (2008), 'Discerning Fermions', British Journal
for the Philosophy of Science 59, 3, pp.499-548.
Muller, F., and Seevinick, M. (2009), 'Discerning Elementary Particles',
Philosophy of Science 76, 2, pp.179-200.
Munitz, M. (1973) (ed.), Logic And Ontology (New
York University Press).
Noonan, H. (1980), Objects And Identity (Martinus Nijhoff).
--------, (1997), 'Relative Identity', in Hale and Wright (1997), pp.634-52.
--------, (2001), Frege. A Critical Introduction (Polity
Press).
--------, (2022), 'Identity',
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
edited by Edward N. Zalta (Fall 2022
Edition).
Novack, G. (1965), The Origins Of Materialism (Pathfinder
Press).
--------,
(1971),
An Introduction To The Logic Of Marxism (Pathfinder
Press, 5th
ed.).
Ollman, B. (2003), Dance Of The Dialectic: Steps In Marx's Method
(University of Illinois Press).
Perkins, D. (2000), Introduction To High
Energy Physics (Cambridge University Press).
Pippin, R. (1978), 'Hegel's Metaphysics And The Problem Of Contradiction',
Journal of the History of Philosophy
16, pp.301-12; reprinted in Stewart (1996), pp.239-52.
Plato, (1997a),
Complete Works,
edited by John Cooper
(Hackett Publishing).
--------, (1997b),
Meno, in Plato (1997a), pp.870-97.
Plekhanov, G. (1908),
Fundamental Problems Of Marxism
(Lawrence & Wishart). [The Appendix to this work -- which in fact
formed part of Plekhanov's Introduction to Engels (1888) -- can be found
here
under the title 'Dialectic and Logic'. It can also be found in
Plekhanov (1976), pp.73-82.]
--------, (1956),
The Development Of The
Monist View Of History (Progress Publishers). This is reprinted in
Plekhanov (1974), pp.480-737.
--------, (1974), Georgi Plekhanov. Selected Philosophical
Works, Volume One (Progress Publishers, 2
nd
ed.).
--------, (1976), Georgi Plekhanov. Selected Philosophical
Works, Volume Three (Progress Publishers).
Priest, G. (2000), Logic. A Very Short
Introduction (Oxford University Press).
Read, R. (2007), Applying Wittgenstein,
edited by Laura Cook (Continuum Books).
Rees, J. (1998),
The Algebra Of Revolution (Routledge).
[This links to a PDF.]
Sanford, D. (2005), 'Distinctness And Non-Identity', Analysis 65,
4, pp.269-74.
Saunders, S. (2006), 'Are Quantum Particles Objects?', Analysis 66,
1, pp.52-62. [This links to a PDF.]
Scott, D.
(1999), 'Platonic Recollection', in Fine (1999), pp.93-124.
--------,
(2007), Plato's Meno (Cambridge
University Press).
Sedley, D.
(2007) (ed.), Oxford Studies In Ancient Philosophy, Volume XXXII (Oxford
University Press).
Somerville, J. (1946), Soviet Philosophy (Philosophical Library).
--------, (1967), The Philosophy Of Marxism (Random
House).
Stewart, J. (1996) (ed.), The Hegel Myths And Legends (Northwestern University
Press).
Thalheimer, A. (1936),
Introduction To Dialectical Materialism. The Marxist
World-View (Covici, Friede Publishers).
Tomassi, P. (1999), Logic (Routledge).
Trotsky, L. (1971),
In Defense Of Marxism
(New
Park Publications).
--------, (1973), Problems Of Everyday Life (Monad Press).
--------, (1986), Notebooks, 1933-35
(Columbia University Press). [Parts of this book can be accessed
here; this links to a PDF.]
Van Heijenoort, J. (1978), With Trotsky In Exile.
From Prinkipo To Coyoacán (Harvard University Press).
V
lastos,
G. (1971) (ed.), Plato. A Collection Of Critical Essays. 1: Metaphysics And
Epistemology (Doubleday Anchor).
Voloshinov, V. (1973), Marxism And The
Philosophy Of Language (Harvard University Press). [Chapters One and Two can
be found
here.]
Weiner, J. (1990), Frege In Perspective (Cornell
University Press).
--------, (1999), Frege (Oxford
University Press).
White, R. (1978), 'Wittgenstein On Identity',
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 78, pp.157-74.
--------, (2006), Wittgenstein's Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. A Reader's
Guide (Continuum).
--------, (forthcoming), The General Form Of A Proposition.
Williams, C. (1979), 'Is Identity A Relation?',
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 80, pp.81-100.
--------, (1989), What Is Identity? (Oxford
University Press).
--------, (1992), Being, Identity, And Truth (Oxford
University Press).
Wittgenstein, L. (1958), The Philosophical
Investigations, translated by Elizabeth Anscombe (Blackwell, 2nd
ed.).
--------, (1972),
Tractatus
Logico-Philosophicus, translated by David Pears and Brian McGuinness
(Routledge, 2nd ed.).
--------, (1993), Philosophical Occasions, 1912-1951, edited by James Klagge and
Alfred Nordmann (Hackett Publishing Company).
Woods, A., and Grant, T. (1995/2007),
Reason In Revolt. Marxism And Modern Science
(Wellred Publications 1
st/2nd
ed.). [The online version still appears to be the First Edition.]
Internet Articles
[1]
French, S. (2019),
'Identity
And Individuality
In Quantum
Theory', Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta (Winter 2019 Edition). [This
has now been re-written as
French and Bigaj (2024).]
[
2] Lowe, E. (No date),
Philosophical
Logic.
[Accessed
16/09/11.] [This link no longer works.]
Word Count: 72,200
Latest Update: 15/11/24
Return To
The Main Index
Back To The Top
© Rosa Lichtenstein 2024
Hits Since March 2007: