This page might take a few seconds to load because of the many YouTube videos
it has embedded
in it.
Unfortunately, Internet Explorer 11 will no longer play these videos. As far as I can tell, they play as intended in other Browsers.
However, if you have
Privacy Badger [PB] installed, they won't play in Google Chrome unless you
disable PB for this site.
[Having said that,
I have just discovered that they will play in IE11 if you have
upgraded to Windows 10! It looks like the problem is with Windows 7 and earlier
versions of that operating system.]
If you are using Internet Explorer 10 (or later), you might find some of the
links I have used won't work properly unless you switch to 'Compatibility View'
(in the Tools Menu); for IE11 select 'Compatibility View Settings' and add this
site (anti-dialectics.co.uk). Microsoft's browser,
Edge, automatically
renders these links compatible; Windows 10 does likewise.
However, if you are using Windows 10,
IE11 and Edge unfortunately appear to colour these links
somewhat erratically. They are meant to be mid-blue, but those two browsers
render them intermittently light blue, yellow, purple and red!
Firefox and Chrome reproduce them correctly.
Unfortunately, several browsers also
underline these links erratically. Many are underscored boldly in black, others
in light blue! They are all meant to be underlined in the same colour as the
link itself.
Finally, if you are viewing this
with Mozilla Firefox, you might not be able to read all the symbols I have
used. Mozilla often replaces them with an "º'.
There are no such problems with Chrome, Edge, or Internet Explorer, as far as I can
determine.
The main aims of Essay Three are outlined
here. The opening sections of this Part of Essay Three are
intended to motivate several of the more important ideas presented in the rest of this site.
However, one or two of the
things I say below might seem to some to be rather dogmatic, but they will be fully
substantiated in other Essays -- for example, Essay Twelve
Part One.
Several readers have complained about the number of
links I have added to these Essays because they say it makes them very difficult
to read. Of course, DM-supporters can hardly lodge that complaint since they
believe everything is interconnected, and that must surely apply even to
Essays that attempt to debunk that
very idea. However, to those who find these links do make these Essays
difficult to read I say this: ignore them -- unless you want to access
further supporting evidence and argument for a particular point, or a certain
topic fires your interest.
Others wonder why I have linked to familiar
subjects and issues that are part of common knowledge (such as the names of
recent Presidents of the
USA, UK Prime Ministers, the names of rivers and mountains, the titles of
popular films, or certain words
that are in common usage). I have done so for the following reason: my Essays
are read all over the world and by people from all 'walks of life', so I can't
assume that topics which are part of common knowledge in 'the west' are equally
well-known across the planet -- or, indeed, by those who haven't had the benefit
of the sort of education that is generally available in the 'advanced economies',
or any at
all. Many of my readers also struggle with English, so any help I can give them
I will continue to provide.
Finally on this specific topic, several of the aforementioned links
connect to
web-pages that regularly change their
URLs, or which vanish from the
Internet altogether. While I try to update them when it becomes apparent
that they have changed or have disappeared I can't possibly keep on top of
this all the time. I would greatly appreciate it, therefore, if readers
informed me
of any dead links they happen to notice.
In general, links to 'Haloscan'
no longer seem to work, so readers needn't tell me about them! Links to
RevForum, RevLeft, Socialist Unity and The North Star also appear to have died.
~~~~~~oOo~~~~~~
As is the case with all my
work, nothing here should be read as an attack
either on Historical Materialism [HM] -- a theory I fully accept --, or,
indeed,
on revolutionary socialism. I remain as committed to the self-emancipation of the
working class and the dictatorship of the proletariat as I was when I first became a revolutionary
thirty-five years ago.
The
difference between
Dialectical Materialism [DM] and HM, as I see it, is explained
here.
It is also important to
note that phrases
like "ruling-class theory", "ruling-class view of reality",
"ruling-class ideology" (etc.) used at this site (in connection with
Traditional Philosophy and DM), aren't meant to
suggest that all or even most members of various ruling-classes
actually invented these ways of thinking or of
seeing the world (although some of them did -- for example,
Heraclitus,
Plato,
Cicero,
and
Marcus Aurelius).
They are intended to
highlight theories (or "ruling ideas") that are conducive to, or which rationalise, the
interests of the various ruling-classes history has inflicted on humanity, whoever invents them.
Up until
recently this
dogmatic approach to knowledge has almost invariably been promoted by thinkers who
either relied on ruling-class patronage, or who, in one capacity or another, helped run
the system
for the elite.**
However, that will become the
central topic of Parts Two and Three of Essay Twelve (when they are published); until then, the reader is
directed
here,
here, and
here for
more
details.
[**Exactly
how this applies to DM will be explained later in this Essay, as well as
here and
here. In addition to the
three links in the previous paragraph, I have summarised the argument (but this
time written for absolute beginners!),
here.]
Incidentally, I have used the word "nominalisation"
throughout this Essay; why I have done this is explained
here.
It is also worth pointing out that a good 50% of my case
against DM has been relegated to the
End Notes
and Appendices. That has been done to allow the main body of the Essay to flow a little more
smoothly. In many cases, I have added numerous qualifications, clarifications,
and considerably more detail to what I have to say in the main body. In
addition, I have raised several objections to my own arguments (some of which
are rather obvious, many not -- and some
that will have occurred to the reader), which I have then
answered.
I have explained why I have adopted this tactic in
Essay One.
If readers skip this material, then my
response to any objections or qualms they might have will be
missed, as will my expanded comments and clarifications. Since I have been
debating this theory with comrades for over 30 years, I have heard all the
objections there are! [Many of the more recent debates have been listed here.]
Finally, rather like Essay Twelve Part One, this Essay is
in places rather repetitive. It has been my experience that if the points I wish to make aren't
repeated several times (maybe from different angles or in other terms) their
significance is all too easily lost. However, in future re-writes I will try to weed
out any such unnecessary duplications. In the meantime, the readers' indulgence
and understanding will be greatly appreciated.
~~~~~~oOo~~~~~~
As of May 2024, this Essay is just over 163,000 words long; a summary of
some of its main ideas can be accessed
here.
The material below does
not
represent my final view of any of the issues raised; it is merely 'work in
progress'.
Anyone using these links must remember that
they will be skipping past supporting argument and evidence set out in earlier
sections.
If your Firewall/Browser has a pop-up blocker, you will need to press the
"Ctrl" key at the same time or these and the other links here won't work!
I have adjusted the
font size used at this site to ensure that even those with impaired
vision can read what I have to say. However, if the text is still either too
big or too small for you, please adjust your browser settings!
Essay Three will
first of all explore several core tenets of DM-epistemology,
which it will then systematically demolish.
To that end, Parts One and Two of this Essay will largely focus on a
traditional philosophical 'concept' or 'method': the so-called "process of abstraction". These
two
Parts will show that little sense can be made either of the 'process' itself or
its alleged results: the various
'abstractions' that have been conjured into existence by
Traditional Philosophers and DM-theorists.
[DM = Dialectical Materialism.]
Following on from the
controversial allegations advanced in
Essay Two -- concerning the
philosophical traditionalism
promoted by every single DM-theorist
and author -- Essay Three will show exactly how this ancient doctrine, Abstractionism, has
been incorporated into Dialectical Marxism. As we will discover, the 'process of abstraction'
is a source of much of the confusion that has in its own small
way helped cripple Marxist theory, and hence
much of revolutionary socialist practice for well over a century.
[Notice the use of the word "helped",
here; it is not being claimed that other factors haven't also
contributed to the long-term failure of Dialectical Marxism. Also notice my use of the term "Dialectical Marxism", which I
distinguish from non-Dialectical Marxism (of the sort advanced at this
site). The latter form of Marxism hasn't been road-tested anywhere yet.]
In
general, DM-fans with whom I have debated Abstractionism react to
my criticism of this 'concept', 'method', or 'process' with incredulity, followed by
extremely negative, if
not highly emotive, irrational, or hostile personal abuse
-- which
means they are perhaps the most
fervent defenders
of this ancient ruling-class approach to 'knowledge'. [See, for example,
here,
here and
here.] Their reaction
isn't all that surprising given the allegations that will be advanced both in
this Essay and at this site concerning the origin of the philosophical doctrines touted by DM-fans, for instance,
here and
here.
In
Part Two, I will examine in more detail the traditional approach to
abstraction, showing that by incorporating this 'process' and its alleged 'results' into
their theories, Dialectical
Marxists have only succeeded in drawing a viper to their breast.
Part Three
will destructively analyse the peculiar idea that certain states or processes of
matter and
'Mind' "emerge" from other states or processes of matter. In Part Four, I
will focus on what
DM-theorists have had to say about truth and falsehood. In addition, I will
consider how they think human
knowledge progresses; that will also include a consideration of how they imagine their own theory
has developed out of, or has progressed in line with,
practice. [That will overlap with what I have to say in Essay Ten
Part One.] In Part Five, I will
concentrate on the 'free will' versus 'determinism'
controversy, which
is just another distinction dialecticians have unwisely imported into Marxism
from
ruling-class thought. [Two rather brief
previews of the approach I will adopt can be accessed
here and
here.] Finally, in
Part Six, I will examine the so-called 'Reflection Theory of Knowledge'.
Incidentally, when I am speaking
about the 'abstractions' upon which DM-theorists have concentrated -- and those
they have imported from Traditional Philosophy -- I will in general put the relevant
words in double
quotes (for example, the words "man" or "Being"). When I am speaking about whatever these 'abstractions' supposedly
designate, refer to, or 'reflect', I will use 'scare' quotes, or no quotes at
all (for example, 'man').
In
addition, it is worth pointing out
that since the Traditional Theorists and dialecticians I will be covering in
these Essays regularly confuse linguistic expressions with the objects to which
they supposedly refer (or, as I often make this point: where they conflate
talk about talk with talk about the world), any attempt by me to
discuss this topic will become hopelessly complicated if I have to point this
confusion out over and over again. I will, however, mention this mix-up from
time-to-time, but readers should remain aware of this age-old confusion all the
way through this Essay. Recall, I am trying to make a terminally obscure
theory clear -- or as clear as is humanly possible(!) --, so any
confusions that remain are the fault of those who invented this way of talking,
not the present author.
I can't guarantee I will always manage
to stick to these conventions consistently since it is often
unclear what DM-theorists are themselves actually saying, or even to what
they are attempting to refer. [If anyone has a clearer
idea what they are banging in about, please
contact me. On this, see also Note 1b1.]
Finally, nothing said in this Essay (or in Part
Two) is aimed at criticising the ordinary use
of so-called "abstract general nouns" (such as "courage", "wisdom",
"justice"), although it might affect how we interpret
them. Rather, these Essays are directed at the use of the word "abstraction"
(and its cognates) in both Traditional Philosophy and DM. [On
this, also see Cowley (1991), pp.85-116.]
In
Essay Two, we saw that dialecticians
were just as
ready
as any randomly-selected Idealist to impose their
a priori theories on reality, despite what
George Novack had to say about that approach:
"A
consistent materialismcannot proceed from
principles which are validated by appeal to abstract reason, intuition,
self-evidence or some other subjective or purely theoretical source. Idealisms
may do this...."
[Novack (1965), p.17. Bold emphasis added.]
Compare
that with what Engels had to say:
"It is the old story. First
of all one makes sensuous things into abstractions and then one wants to know
them through the senses, to see time and smell space. The empiricist becomes so
steeped in the habit of empirical experience, that he believes that he is still
in the field of sensuous experience when he is operating with abstractions....
The two forms of existence of matter are naturally nothing without matter, empty
concepts, abstractions which exist only in our minds. But, of course, we are
supposed not to know what matter and motion are! Of course not, for matter as
such and motion as such have not yet been seen or otherwise experienced by
anyone, only the various existing material things and forms of motions.
Matter is nothing but the totality of material things from which this concept is
abstracted and motion as such nothing but the totality of all sensuously
perceptible forms of motion; words like matter and motion are nothing but
abbreviations in which we comprehend many different sensuous perceptible
things according to their common properties. Hence matter and motion can
be known in no other way than by investigation of the separate material
things and forms of motion, and by knowing these, we also
pro tanto
know matter and motion as such.... This is just like the difficulty
mentioned by Hegel; we can eat cherries and plums, but not fruit,
because no one has so far eaten fruit as such." [Engels (1954),
pp.235-36.
Italic emphasis in the original. Link added. I have destructively analysed this
passage in Essay Thirteen
Part One.]
Which
looks like a round-about way of saying that there is no evidence at all for much
of DM -- or, at least, for the existence of all those "abstractions"! Either
that, or DM itself is pure, unadulterated Idealism -- since the 'abstractions'
Engels speaks about are based on "principles
which are validated by appeal to abstract reason, intuition, self-evidence or
some other subjective or purely theoretical source."
Anyway, Engels's words sit rather awkwardly with other things that both he and Marx
saw fit to commit to paper:
"The premises from which we begin are not
arbitrary ones, not dogmas, but real premises from which abstraction can only be
made in the imagination. They are the real individuals, their activity and the
material conditions under which they live, both those which they find already
existing and those produced by their activity. These premises can thus be
verified in a purely empirical way....
"The fact is, therefore, that definite
individuals who are productively active in a definite way enter into these
definite social and political relations. Empirical observation must in each
separate instance bring out empirically, and without any mystification and
speculation, the connection of the social and political structure with
production. The social structure and the State are continually evolving out
of the life-process of definite individuals, but of individuals, not as they may
appear in their own or other people's imagination, but as they really are; i.e.
as they operate, produce materially, and hence as they work under definite
material limits, presuppositions and conditions independent of their will....
"In direct contrast to German philosophy which
descends from heaven to earth, here we ascend from earth to heaven. That is to
say, we do not set out from what men say, imagine, conceive, nor from men as
narrated, thought of, imagined, conceived, in order to arrive at men in the
flesh. We set out from real, active men, and on the basis of their real
life-process we demonstrate the development of the ideological reflexes and
echoes of this life-process. The phantoms formed in the human brain are also,
necessarily, sublimates of their material life-process, which is empirically
verifiable and bound to material premises. Morality, religion, metaphysics,
all the rest of ideology and their corresponding forms of consciousness, thus no
longer retain the semblance of independence. They have no history, no
development; but men, developing their material production and their material
intercourse, alter, along with this their real existence, their thinking and the
products of their thinking. Life is not determined by consciousness, but
consciousness by life. In the first method of approach the starting-point is
consciousness taken as the living individual; in the second method, which
conforms to real life, it is the real living individuals themselves, and
consciousness is considered solely as their consciousness.
"This method of approach is not devoid of
premises. It starts out from the real premises and does not abandon them for a
moment. Its premises are men, not in any fantastic isolation and rigidity, but
in their actual, empirically perceptible process of development under
definite conditions. As soon as this active life-process is described,
history ceases to be a collection of dead facts as it is with the empiricists
(themselves still abstract), or an imagined activity of imagined subjects, as
with the idealists." [Marx
and Engels (1970), pp.42-48. Bold emphases added.]
"We all agree that in every field of
science, in natural and historical science, one must proceed from the given
facts, in natural science therefore from the various material forms of
motion of matter; that therefore in theoretical natural science too the
interconnections are not to be built into the facts but to be discovered in
them, and when discovered to be verified as far as possible by experiment.
"Just as little can it be a question of
maintaining the dogmatic content of the Hegelian system as it was preached by
the Berlin Hegelians of the older and younger line." [Engels
(1954),p.47. Bold emphases alone
added.]
"All three are developed by Hegel in his
idealist fashion as mere laws of thought: the first, in the first part
of his Logic, in the Doctrine of Being; the second fills the
whole of the second and by far the most important part of his Logic,
the Doctrine of Essence; finally the third figures as the fundamental
law for the construction of the whole system. The mistake lies in the fact
that these laws are foisted on nature and history as laws of thought, and not
deduced from them. This is the source of the whole forced and often outrageous
treatment; the universe, willy-nilly, is made out to be arranged in accordance
with a system of thought which itself is only the product of a definite
stage of evolution of human thought." [Ibid.,
p.62. Bold emphasis alone added.]
"Finally, for me there could be no
question of superimposing the laws of dialectics on nature but of
discovering them in it and developing them from it." [Engels
(1976), p.13. Bold emphasis added.]
"In this way, however, the whole dogmatic content of the Hegelian system is
declared to be absolute truth, in contradiction to his dialectical method, which
dissolves all dogmatism...." [Engels
(1888), p.589. Bold emphasis added.]
"The general results of the
investigation of the world are obtained at the end of this investigation, hence
are not principles, points of departure, but results, conclusions.
To construct the latter in one's head, take them as the basis from which to
start, and then reconstruct the world from them in one's head is ideology,
an ideology which tainted every species of materialism hitherto existing.... As
Dühring proceeds from 'principles' instead of facts he is an ideologist, and
can screen his being one only by formulating his propositions in such general
and vacuous terms that they appear axiomatic, flat. Moreover, nothing can
be concluded from them; one can only read something into them...." [Marx
and Engels (1987), p.597. Bold emphasis alone added. Quotation marks altered to
conform with the conventions
adopted at this site.]
Well,
perhaps there is some way of harmonising these passages that allows
DM-supporters to come up with a convincing, or even a plausible, answer to the following questions:
(a) What is the precise nature of these
DM-"abstractions"? And,
(b)
Exactly what do they 'represent' or 'reflect' in nature and society, and how
do they do it?
Satisfactory
replies to both
of the above from DM-fans would lend credence to the claim that
their ideas haven't been
"imposed" on nature and society,
after all. However, given the additional fact that DM-supporters invariably ignore such
'pedantic quibbles' (or they are hand-waved aside), readers are advised not to hold their breath waiting for an
effective, or even a plausible, response. Those same readers might like to ask DM-fans
themselves for
a clear answer to the above two
questions. They will receive no such reply.
[If, per
impossible, any of my readers do manage to receive a clear answer, please
contact me with the details. In that eventuality I'll be keeping
watch for a few
flying pigs. There should be dozens of them!]
Be
this as it may, another question now forces itself upon us:
Well, in this Essay we will find out how
they manage to avoid the latter by unfortunately careering headlong into the
former -- i.e., by the way they allproceed "from
principles which are validated by appeal to
abstract reason, intuition, self-evidence or some other subjective or purely
theoretical source" (to
quote George Novack, again),
despite their frequent protestations.
In Essays Nine Parts
One and
Two, and Twelve Parts One
to Seven, we will discover exactly why they do it.
To be sure, DM-theorists claim that their
theory is thoroughlymaterialist and they vigorously resist any imputation to the
contrary. Far from imposing their ideas on nature, dialecticians argue that
scientific knowledge (like theirs) advances because of a 'dialectical interplay' between
abstract knowledge on the one hand and practical activity on the other,
rendering it increasingly objective (or "concrete"), over time.
And
yet, as we
found out in
Essay Two,
there is little if any truth in this self-serving myth.
To state the obvious,
without
minds to invent them there would be no abstractions. On the surface,
therefore, it looks like any theory committed to the 'objective'
existence of 'abstractions' (or, "real abstractions") mustbe
Idealist, whatever complaints are made to the contrary. As we will see, even
when we dig 'below the surface', Idealist implications like these are difficult to
resist. In which case, the above
phrase, "looks like", itself turns out to be far too tentative, and by a
rather wide margin,
too.
If 'abstractions'
aren't 'objective' -- that is, if they aren't "mind-independent", or if they
fail to relate to (i.e., refer to) anything that exists in "mind-independent" reality --, it
is difficult to see how they could possibly assist anyone construct an accurate
or truthful theory of the world, or, at least, a theory that is supposed to be 'objective'.
Nor is it easy to see
how scientific knowledge could advance by means of 'abstractions' if they
are somehow fictional. How could fictional concepts help account
for a... -- for want of a better phrase -- ...non-fictional world?
Well, perhaps there is
a way of interpreting the nature of abstractions, or what they supposedly
'reflect' in 'reality' -- that is, if they actually 'reflect' anything other than
what is 'in the mind' of the one who invented them -- that succeeds in rescuing them from the world of
make-believe. On the other hand, could it be that their only 'legitimate'
role is to help maintain the morale of scientists and philosophers -- by making
it easier to
sell the idea that their latest theories are valid? That is,
might it not turn out that 'abstractions' simply enable those who believe in
them construct grandiose theories concerning 'fundamental features reality', valid for all of space and time, in the comfort of their own
heads? One suspects so. And if those suspicions bear fruit, much of Traditional Thought should
then perhaps be classified
as a considerably less entertaining, but far more dogmatic, version of the
collected works of the
Brothers Grimm -- that is,
as Fantasy Fiction
on steroids.
On
the other hand, if
abstractions are 'objective' -- but only 'minds' are capable of
constructing, or even of appreciating, them --, questions would naturally arise over what they could
possibly
reflect in nature. Exactly whatis it in 'extra-mental reality' that corresponds with an 'abstract idea'?
What do they capture 'in the world' if they only exist 'in the mind'?
Of course, for non-materialists and old-fashioned
Realists,
quibbles like these present few problems --, except perhaps in connection with
awkward questions raised about the precise meaning of the word "objective".
Indeed, for
Traditional Theorists the ultimate constituents of reality were in the end often taken to be either:
(i) Mind-like objects;
(ii) Non-material "concepts"; or,
(iii) "Ideas" floating about in some abstract
'mental', or even
'divine', arena.
In
that case, the word "objective" -- that is, before its meaning
flipped a couple of centuries ago (it used to mean what "subjective" now
does,
and vice versa; on this, see Daston (1994), and Daston and Galison
(2007)) -- would almost be synonymous with another word frequently used these days, namely, "Ideal". In fact,
at a fundamental level it isn't easy to distinguish old-fashioned
Realists (i.e., Platonists and neo-Platonists) from
Objective Idealists
-- except, perhaps, in the way they both view logic/change --, and, truth be told, as far
as the latter were concerned, the word "objective" clearly did no real work.
But,
the same can easily be
said of "Ideal",
and its close relative, "idealisation".
However, the same can't
be said about dialecticians -- but only if we accept
at face value their version of DM -- that is, that it represents Hegel's
'theory'/'method' put 'back on its feet', stripped of its outer 'mystical
shell'. Nevertheless, and controversially, it can and will be said of
them -- after the tangled undergrowth
surrounding much of what they do say has been cleared, its roots in
Traditional Thought exposed for all to see.
Oddly enough, we find a
DM-classicist like Lenin arguing along such familiar lines, for all the world sounding
like a born-again Realist with added Hegelian spin:
"Thought proceeding from the
concrete to the abstract -- provided it is correct (NB)… -- does not get
away from the truth but comes closer to it. The abstraction of matter,
the law of nature, the abstraction of value, etc., in short all
scientific (correct, serious, not absurd) abstractions reflect nature more
deeply, truly and completely." [Lenin (1961),
p.171. Emphases in the
original.]
"Knowledge
is the reflection of nature by man. But this is not simple, not an immediate,
not a complete reflection, but the process of a series of abstractions, the
formation and development of concepts, laws, etc., and these concepts, laws,
etc., (thought, science = 'the logical Idea') embrace conditionally,
approximately, the universal, law-governed character of eternally moving and
developing nature." [Ibid.,
p.182. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at
this site.]
Unfortunately, Lenin forgot to say how
any of this rather ambitious project is at all possible if abstractions are nothing but
the creations of the human
mind. If scientific knowledge more truly reflects the world the more
its abstractions are correct, or valid, how is that possible if
they don't actually exist 'objectively' in the material world, in some form or
other for scientists, or, indeed, for Marxist philosophers, to reflect?1a
Once
again: if abstractions don't exist in the 'outside world', what is there in nature for them
to
reflect, for them to
represent to us, or for them to refer to in
'extra-mental reality'?
Recall that for Lenin,
and those who agree with him, 'objectivity' concerns whatever exists exterior to, and independent of, the
human mind, ratified
by practice:
"The sole and unavoidable deduction to be made
from this -- a deduction which all of us make in everyday practice and which
materialism deliberately places at the foundation of its epistemology -- is that
outside us, and independently of us, there exist objects, things, bodies and
that our perceptions are images
of the external world...." [Lenin
(1972),
p.111. Bold emphasis added.]
"To be a materialist is to acknowledge objective truth, which is revealed
to us by our sense-organs. To acknowledge objective truth, i.e., truth not
dependent upon man and mankind, is, in one way or another, to recognise absolute
truth...." [Ibid.,
p.148.]
"Knowledge can be useful
biologically, useful in human practice, useful for the preservation of
life, for the preservation of the species, only when it reflects objective
truth, truth which is independent of man." [Ibid.,
p.157.]
"[T]he sole
'property' of matter with
whose recognition philosophical materialism is bound up is the property of
being an objective reality, of existing outside our mind." [Ibid.,
p.311.]
"Thus…the concept of matter…epistemologically
implies nothing but objective reality existing independently of the human
mind and reflected by it." [Ibid.,
p.312.]
"[I]t is the sole categorical, this sole
unconditional recognition of nature's existence outside the mind and
perception of man that distinguishes dialectical materialism from relativist
agnosticism and idealism." [Ibid.,
p.314.]
"The fundamental characteristic of
materialism is that it starts from the objectivity of science, from the
recognition of objective reality reflected by science." [Ibid.,
pp.354-55.]
Lenin never once repudiated the above claims.
That can only mean DM-abstractions can't be 'objective'. Plainly, that is because
they don't exist
"outside our minds".
On the other hand,
if we simply ignore
'annoying quibbles' like these -- and even if we were to suppose that
abstractions actually exist in the 'outside world' so that abstract general words can and do refer to them, or
which can and do 'reflect' them --,
what form do any such 'abstractions' take? Of what are they composed? Worse still: where
do they exist? And how can they possibly interact with human thought? As soon as
they are capable of being experienced they become particular, not general. In
that eventuality, the
whole point of inventing them (i.e., to rise above the particular by ascending to the general
-- as we will see below)
would be lost. It seems that, because of their nature, they can't be 'objects
of experience'. What then are they?
Are we
somehow 'mentally linked' (or can we even be 'linked') with, or to, them? Is
that the case? But, as we have just seen, there appears to be no conceivable way they could be
physically connected to us, or could even physically interact with us,
without automatically losing their status as abstract general 'concepts'.
Or, do we perceive them by
what is in effect the equivalent of a 'non-physical'
Third Eye? [As we will see in
Part Two, this is indeed (roughly) how
Rationalist Philosophers tended to approach this topic; readers are directed
there for more details.]1b
Perhaps so; indeed, as August Thalheimer let slip (in relation to another of this
theory's core precepts):
"Only a person trained
in dialectics will perceive the permeation of opposites. Of course, this does
not depend only upon training in dialectics, but also upon the class viewpoint,
the social viewpoint which the individual adopts." [Thalheimer
(1936), p.164.]
Maybe
that is also true of DM-abstractions? Only the faithful, only those with the 'eyes to see',
can 'see' them.
As we
will find out in Essay Nine
Part Two, the above "class position"
(at least in 'dialectical' philosophy) has almost exclusively been
adopted by petty bourgeois and déclasséprofessional revolutionaries; that is,
by those who imported
this ruling-class theory into our movement, and who weren't workers.
Perhaps this is being a little too hasty? Maybe dialecticians
are capable of seeing
or apprehending 'abstractions' by a special 'act of cognition'. If so, the Idealist implications of
that source of knowledge would be plain for all
to see (no pun intended). Indeed, it finds immediate echo in
Plato:
"If mind and true opinion are two distinct classes, then I
say that there certainly are these self-existent ideas unperceived by sense, and
apprehended only by the mind; if, however, as some say, true opinion differs in
no respect from mind, then everything that we perceive through the body is to be
regarded as most real and certain. But we must affirm that to be distinct, for
they have a distinct origin and are of a different nature; the one is implanted
in us by instruction, the other by persuasion; the one is always accompanied by
true reason, the other is without reason; the one cannot be overcome by
persuasion, but the other can: and lastly, every man may be said to share in
true opinion, but mind is the attribute of the gods and of very few men.
Wherefore also we must acknowledge that there is one kind of being which is
always the same, uncreated and indestructible, never receiving anything into
itself from without, nor itself going out to any other, but invisible and
imperceptible by any sense, and of which the contemplation is granted to
intelligence only." [Plato (1997c), 51e-52a,
pp.1254-55. I have used
the on-line version here. Bold emphases added. The published edition translates
the third set of highlighted words as follows: "It is indivisible -- it cannot be perceived
by the senses at all -- and it is the role of the understanding to study it."
Cornford renders it thus: "[It is] invisible and otherwise imperceptible;
that, in fact, which thinking has for its object." [Cornford (1997), p.192.]
As
far as Idealists are concerned, Plato's comments present
few immediate difficulties -- although, Essay Three Part Two (Sections
One and
Two), will show this dogmatic approach to
knowledge introduces serious problems
of its own.
Nevertheless, this
leaves dialecticians with more than a few annoying headaches,
the origin and cause of which Essay Three (in all its Parts) aims to expose.
To that end, and in order to make genuine progress, we will need
something a little more helpful than Lenin's enigmatic prose
to light our way. Surprising as this might seem to those still living under
a rock,
DM-theorists have to this day remained studiously silent on these issues
-- saving, of course, where they are content merely to repeat
Lenin's words verbatim in the vain hope that repetition will generate clarity
where enigmatic prose on its own manifestly can't.
Traditional Theorists viewed abstractions (or
the 'Forms'/'Universals')
as a 'reflection', or an expression, of "essential"
features of the world, which, according to them, were inaccessible to the
senses and lay 'behind' appearances -- with that over-used
metaphor also left conveniently obscure for over two thousand years.
[Later,
we will have occasion to question
the aptness of these figures of speech, even when they are employed by avowed materialists --
i.e., DM-fans.]
In stark contrast to the particulars we meet in everyday life -- a table, a chair,
a cat, a relative... --, abstractions aren't just universal
inform, they are also supposed to be general in fact. Indeed, the use
of 'abstractions', so we are told, allows human 'cognition' to rise above
and beyond immediate experience, enabling it to construct an increasingly universal,
law-governed picture of
(underlying) reality. As the late Fraser Cowley pointed out:
"The notion of a universal and with it the celebrated
problem of universals was invented by Plato.... The distinction of particulars
and universals is complemented in many doctrines since Plato with the
distinction and division of labour between the senses and the reason or
intellect, or understanding. According to these doctrines, what is given to the
bodily senses is merely particular, and the understanding or reason alone
apprehends, or constructs or derives, the universal. Many philosophers take the
problem of universals to be that of the meaning of general terms without
realising that what makes the meaning of general terms a problem is the very
concept of a universal." [Cowley (1991), p.85.
Spelling modified to agree with UK English.]
Hence, it seemed to more than a few Traditional Thinkers that abstractions (like those 'universals')
were necessary if human beings were to (a) comprehend the
generality supposedly found in nature, (b) both establish and consolidate
scientific knowledge, or (c) uncover a countless 'necessary
truths' buried 'under the surface' or which lie 'behind 'appearances'. DM-theorists merely added
an extra flourish: their theory allows them to understand the
'concrete world' more fully in order to help change it. But, as we will
discover, their approach to such Cosmic Verities owes
much more
to early modern forms of
Rationalism and those who paved the way for Hegel
than it does to science itself:
"Already with
Fichte
the
idea of the unity of the sciences, of system, was connected with that of finding
a reliable starting-point in certainty on which knowledge could be based.
Thinkers from
Kant
onwards were quite convinced that the kind of knowledge which came from
experience was not reliable. Empirical knowledge could be subject to error,
incomplete, or superseded by further observation or experiment. It would be
foolish, therefore, to base the whole of knowledge on something which had been
established only empirically. The kind of knowledge which Kant and his followers
believed to be the most secure was a priori knowledge, the kind embodied in the
laws of Nature. These had been formulated without every occurrence of the
Natural phenomenon in question being observed, so they did not summarise
empirical information, and yet they held good by necessity for every case; these
laws were truly universal in their application." [White (1996), p.29. Bold
emphasis added.]
Each (genuine) abstraction therefore seems to operate like some
sort of 'conceptual key' capable of unlocking secrets that govern the
'inner workings' of the entire universe, an artefact of thought that
supplies each mind prepared to indulge in this ancient sport with universally valid principles
-- important components of which, oddly enough, don't actually exist anywhere in
'extra-mental reality'!
However, in order to exert a little more pressure on the opposing idea (that 'abstractions'
actually do exist somehow, somewhere...), it might
prove helpful to raise a handful of additional questions:
(d)
If
abstractions are general in form, and do in fact exist in the
'outside world', how does that 'generality' actually express itself?
(e)
Is an abstraction somehow 'spread out', as it were -- like some sort of
'metaphysical liquid' or 'force field' -- in, or over, the 'concrete particulars' that supposedly
instantiate it, uniting the diversity we see all around us, perhaps by a
'mysterious power'/'influence' as yet unbeknown to us?
(f)
Or, are abstractions merely an aspect of the complex tales human beings tell one another? Are they
simply subjective stories
in pseudo-objective drag, but which are essential for the successful
advancement of knowledge (even though they aren't really 'real' in themselves)?
Unfortunately,
the questionable origin of the traditional approach to knowledge (in the
theories developed by openly Idealist
Philosophers) has done little to improve its image among materialists,
nor does it inspire much confidence.1b0
Small wonder then that consistent materialists have, in general, regarded abstract
ideas as guilty
until proven even more guilty.
Nevertheless, more work will need to be done before it becomes clear whether or
not
'abstractions' aren't simply useful fictions, handy at least for
maintaining the morale of scientists, or, indeed, for giving dialecticians something over which they can endlessly
perseverate --, and,
if we are brutally honest, precious little else.
Short of burying this entire topic under layers of impenetrable
Hegelian jargon, dialecticians haven't advanced much beyond the 'subjective
stage',
if such it may be called. In fact, as we will see, the way they conceive of abstractions, and the 'process' by
which they have been given life, underminesthe
very generality they had all along been introduced to explain.
As should now seem reasonably clear: if true, that accusation would
completely undermine
the DM-theory of knowledge.
This
ironic 'dialectical inversion' -- whereby DM-abstractions end up killing the
very theory that spawned them -- will be the subject of the rest of this Essay
-- and Part Two.
Abstractions Are Merely The Proper Names Of 'Abstract
Particulars'
Admittedly, when
language is viewed
in a
traditional light,
it appears to predispose or even motivate its users into entertaining the idea that 'abstractions' are universal in form;
the words that supposedly denote them appear to be, or to express, general ideas, categories
and concepts.1b1
Even
so, things are rarely this straight-forward. The problem here
revolves around the fact that the
terminology Traditional Theorists use to talk about abstractions turns out to be
far from general. Indeed, such theorists in the end use what turn out to be the
Proper Names of the aforementioned "Universals", or
they are the Proper Names of the "Forms", of "Concepts", "Categories", "Essences", and "Ideas".
Now, this might at first sight appear to be a relatively insignificant point, hardly worth
mentioning, in fact; but this seemingly minor detail turns out to be the exact opposite.
That is because this
linguistic move implies that these
Universals (etc.) aren't in fact general in form or content but are particulars
of some sort or other, named now by
abstract nouns such as "Manhood", "Cathood", or "The Population",
"Being", conjured into existence by the 'process' of abstraction -- a
'process' that defies clear explanation even to this day, as the first two Parts
of Essay Three will demonstrate.1b2
The
question now confronting us is the following:
(h)
How is it possible for
an abstraction to be both
general and particular at one and the same time?
Well, are abstractions like classes?
Classes are
abstract particulars of a rather peculiar sort: they are
singular in form, supposedly compound in nature, but no less Ideal.1c If Universals
are like classes -- which somehow seem to
'exist' anterior
to material reality -- it would suggest they were
ghostly containers of some sort, populated by what are supposed to be
the
material objects they (metaphorically) collect together.1d
But, does
this intellectualist approach to reality not now commit us to the existence
of classes over and above their members? Indeed, is such a 'theory' little more
than
bargain basement
Platonism? As the late Fraser Cowley pointed out:
"The open sentence 'x is a spider' determines a class only
because 'spider' signifies a kind of thing. It is by being one of that
kind...that a value of x is a member of the class. To identify something as a
spider, one must know what a spider is, that is, what kind of thing 'spider'
signifies. Kinds of things can come to be or cease to be. The chemical elements,
kinds of substances, are believed to have evolved. The motorbike -- the kind of
vehicle known as a motorbike -- was invented about 1880. The dodo is extinct.
There is no obvious way of producing sentences equivalent to these in terms of
classes. The class of dodos and the class of dead dodos are not identical:
though all dodos are dead, a dead dodo is not a dodo....
"Since a kind is to be found wherever there are particular
things of the kind, it can have various geographical locations. The lion is
found in East Africa. Lions are found in East Africa. It makes no difference
whether we say 'the lion' or whether we say 'lions': what is meant is the kind
of animal. To say that it can be seen in captivity far from its remaining
natural habitats does not contradict the statement that it is found in East
Africa. A kind is not a class: the class of lions is nowhere to be found."
[Cowley (1991), p.87. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions
adopted at this site.]
So,
what we say about an individual of a certain sort (such as a spider), or even
kinds of things (such as spiders), can't sensibly said of classes. You might
find spiders in your loft, garage or bath, but you will nowhere find the class
of spiders in your neighbourhood, or anywhere else, for that matter. Not even the most
enthusiastic hunter
will stalk the class of elks or the class of pheasants. Spiders, as a kind, are to be found
dispersed across this planet, but not the class of spiders. TV documentaries
will happily film spiders, but no one has ever videoed the class of these
eight-legged beasties, or has even tried to do so.
And yet, what are classes apart from their members?
Indeed, what were they before their members existed? Was there, for
example, a class of tigers existing somewhere (maybe for billions of
years), waiting for these magnificent
beasts to evolve just to give that class some sort of material content --, and,
perhaps, provide theoretical distraction for
taxonomists?
Does nature 'plan ahead' in this way? For Platonists, maybe it does; but for
materialists? Surely not.
On the other hand, are
classes
somehow
material in form, like a table, a chair, a rock, a pair of cuff links or
a TV set? If they are
indeed material in some way, of what are
they composed? If they are made of something, why call them
abstractions? That particular word doesn't even look right.
Abstractions (or abstract ideas/concepts) are constructed -- so the story
goes -- either (a) By means of some sort of mental subtracting
process,
in the course of which theorists progressively ignore certain particular (or
even general) features of material objects
in their desire to ascend to
something more general, or (b) By means of a law-like,
generalising process, which each intrepid abstractor brings to reality, a priori -- rather like the "concrete
universal" idea that Hegel borrowed from
Aristotle.1d1
"Aristotle again and again reverts to
the claim that if the forms are to serve as universals, then they cannot be
separate from the entities of which they are properties. Aristotle agrees with
Plato that universals, like the forms, are the objects of scientific study....
Where Aristotle differs from Plato was in holding that universals are not
identical with the things of which they are properties, they exist only by
virtue of the existence of the things of which they are properties. If
universals existed independently, they would take their place alongside the
things that instantiate them. Separate existence is just what would make
universals like other particulars and thus no longer universal. But doesn't this argument show Aristotle to be confused?
If universals can be talked about, they can be referred to. Yet whatever can be
referred to is a particular. Confusion seems to have set in: universals are both
particulars and at the same time necessarily distinct from particulars."
[Davidson (2005), pp.89-90. Bold emphasis added; paragraphs merged.]1e
Of course, this simply labels the problem
since it is still unclear what any one of these "universals" actually is.
Compare that with
calling what we now know as Oxygen, "dephlogisticated
air". That term simply labelled a problem in 18th
century Chemistry, which, fortunately, the scientists of the day didn't try to
solve simply by inventingyet more jargon, unlike Philosophers. [I will develop
that theme throughout this Essay
and this site.]
Nevertheless, whichever
one of (a) or (b) above is
the correct approach to the invention of these 'abstractions', exactly
how this highly
individualised skill is mysteriously coordinated across an entire
population of intrepid abstractors, and over many centuries, is an even deeper
mystery. No doubt there is an abstraction covering that, too.
But, if (a) were the
case, in the limit, one would expect abstractions to be more like
Mother Hubbard's Cupboard,
not the
Old Woman's Shoe -- i.e., empty
of all content. As we will
see,
this was indeed the 'thinking' that motivated Hegel's reduction of generality
and Marx's criticism of it.
On the other hand, if (b)
were the case, nature couldn't be anything other than Ideal, as Hegel himself maintained
and as Marx also famously criticised.
[Those specific topics will be the main subject of much of
Part Two.]
Anyway,
should dialecticians be tempted to adopt strategy (b),
they won't be able to avoidimposing
the resulting abstractions on reality, something they said they
would
never do. Indeed, that
is precisely why, in these Essays, DM is accused of being a thoroughly Idealist theory; because dialecticians have in fact imposed an a priori dogma on nature
and society
their theory couldn't be anything other than Ideal.
[Again,
that allegation was fully
substantiated in Essay Two.]
Maybe
these aren't even the right questions to ask?
Perhaps a closer examination of the actual process of abstraction
will tell us more.
Abstraction is widely held to
be a process that all (or
maybe most) human beings are capable of performing,
accessing, or using, and which enables those so
minded to extract or form 'abstract ideas' almost at will.2
One
interpretation of this allegedly 'universal skill' involves the additional belief
-- among Marxist dialecticians, it seems -- that
abstractions already exist in reality somehow waiting for intrepid mental
gymnasts to 'discover' by the operation of 'reason' alone -- otherwise they wouldn't
be 'objective'. Again, as
Lenin noted:
"[T]he sole
'property' of matter with
whose recognition philosophical materialism is bound up is the property of
being an objective reality, of existing outside our mind." [Lenin (1972),
p.311.]
"To be a materialist is to acknowledge objective truth, which is revealed
to us by our sense-organs. To acknowledge objective truth, i.e., truth not
dependent upon man and mankind, is, in one way or another, to recognise absolute
truth...." [Ibid.,
pp.148.]
"Knowledge can be useful
biologically, useful in human practice, useful for the preservation of
life, for the preservation of the species, only when it reflects objective
truth, truth which is independent of man." [Ibid.,
p.157.]
So, if 'abstractions' are to be
considered 'objective', or are capable of reflecting 'objective' features of 'reality',
they must have pre-dated human existence. There appears to be no other way of
interpreting Lenin, here.
The only other alternative, it would
seem,
is to view these 'abstractions' in a way that would
make them both 'objective' and 'mind-dependent', all in one go -- an odd
combination, to be sure, but one we will find resists all serious attempts at
explanation. Here is Lenin, again:
"Logical concepts are subjective so long as they
remain 'abstract,' in their abstract form, but at the same time they express the
Thing-in-themselves. Nature is both concrete and abstract, both
phenomenon and essence, both moment and relation. Human
concepts are subjective in their abstractness, separateness, but objective as a
whole, in the process, in the sum-total, in the tendency, in the source." [Lenin
(1961) p.208. Bold emphasis alone added.
Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]
Good luck to anyone
trying to make sense of that! One
might well wonder how nature could be abstract as well as
concrete.
Lenin nowhere explained what he meant by this rather odd, nay, entirely puzzling,
assertion. I will, however, try to make some
sort of sense of it
later on in this Essay.
In summary, the
above
approach to knowledge appears to suggest that:
(i) Most, if not all, 'abstractions' (or what
they supposedly 'refer to' or 'reflect') pre-date human existence;
but also that,
(ii) They require some mind or other to think
them into existence, or, at least, 'represent' them to 'consciousness'.
In which case, the following conclusion seems inescapable:
(iii) Human minds must have pre-dated themselves!
Or,
even,
(iv) 'Mind-in-general', or some 'Mind-in-particular', pre-dated humanity.
Small wonder then that
these 'abstractions' are the proud offspring of the hyper-ambitious thoughts and
theories of the many Idealists and
'God'-botherers that the class war regurgitated and then dumped on humanity. What they are
doing here in Lenin's thought is therefore something of a mystery. This is hardly the sort of metaphysical company for self-respecting
materialists to keep. Unfortunately, sound advice like this has
arrived on the scene far too late, for this is just the sort of
intellectual company
dialecticians have been frequenting for generations, as Lenin himself admitted:
"The theory of socialism,
however, grew out of the philosophic, historical, and economic theories
elaborated by educated representatives of the propertied classes, by
intellectuals. By their social status the founders of modern scientific
socialism, Marx and Engels, themselves belonged to the bourgeois
intelligentsia. In the very same way, in Russia, the theoretical doctrine of
Social-Democracy arose altogether independently of the spontaneous growth of the
working-class movement; it arose as a natural and inevitable outcome of the
development of thought among
the revolutionary socialist intelligentsia." [Lenin
(1947), pp.31-32. Bold emphases added.]
"The history of philosophy and the history of
social science show with perfect clarity that there is nothing resembling
'sectarianism' in Marxism, in the sense of its being a hidebound, petrified
doctrine, a doctrine which arose away from the high road of the
development of world civilisation. On the contrary, the genius of Marx consists
precisely in his having furnished answers to questions already raised by the
foremost minds of mankind. His doctrine emerged as the direct and immediate
continuation of the teachings of the greatest representatives of
philosophy, political economy and socialism.
"The Marxist doctrine is omnipotent because it is true. It is comprehensive
and harmonious, and provides men with an integral world outlook irreconcilable
with any form of superstition, reaction, or defence of bourgeois oppression. It
is the legitimate successor to the best that man produced in the nineteenth
century, as represented by German philosophy, English political economy and
French socialism." [Lenin,
Three Sources and Component Parts of Marxism. Bold emphases alone
added.]
Nevertheless, using their 'natural' abstractive skills, intrepid abstractors are
supposed to be able to do one or more of the following:
(A)
Progressively ignore certain features, properties, or aspects of material objects, enabling them to form
increasingly
general ideas or concepts.
(B) Access 'abstract concepts' which (i) each
abstracter (somehow?) already possesses, or which (ii) 'inheres' in every object of a given type. However, these mysterious 'objects'/'concepts' are
only capable of being 'brought to the surface' if philosophical 'reason' is
allowed free
reign and given licence to speculate.
And yet, by shear coincidence, these 'concepts' emerge in each mind
only if exactly the same jargonised expressions (such as "Being", "Nothing", "Becoming",
"Substance", "Determination", etc.) are pressed into action -- which terminology,
by
yet another almost miraculous coincidence, had already been dreamt up by
previous generations of Philosophers, Idealists and Mystics. This might suggest
to neutral observers that the intrepid abstractors mentioned at the beginning of
this paragraph weren't in fact in possession of
these notions before they had been talked into adopting them by a smooth-talking
traditionalist.
Either way, abstract ideas appear to emerge in each
individual head in miraculously the same way.
Nevertheless, whatever their provenance, these
'creatures of thought' may then be used to cast
each material particular in an entirely new light.
Or,
at least, that
is what the Metaphysical Brochure would have us believe.
But,
materialists should be suspicious of such moves. And for good reason:
(C) How
could abstractions conjured into existence in this way be material (in any sense of that word) if adepts
have to disregard (or rise above) all aspects of material
reality in order to derive (or ascend to) some idea of them?
(D) How
could abstractions even be materialist notions if only a select --
nay, exclusive -- class of human beings (of the 'right' sort) are capable of
'apprehending' them, or of enlisting the right a priori categories,
concepts and laws to that end, which allegedly determine the nature of every material object
in the entire universe, for all time? At the very least, this approach to
knowledge would seem to imply that physical objects in are 'real' only because of the
'existence' of an Ideal world underpinning them, which 'world' is more 'real'
than the material universe we see around us, and which 'world' is accessible to thought alone,
as Plato maintained all
along. As we
will see, this would imply that the 'concrete' is only 'concrete' because of these 'abstractions'. In
other words, only the abstract world isreally real! Maybe that is what
Lenin meant?
Hence,
if, according to Lenin, materiality is bound up
with "objective existence" outside the mind, and if
it requires the
exercise of specially-choreographed mental gymnastics to conjure abstractions into existence,
how could a single one of them be material?
More to the point: how could any of them be
"objective" -- i.e., "mind independent" if they are all in
fact "mind-dependent"?
Or, is this
just another 'dialectical contradiction' we are supposed merely to "grasp",
sweep under the non-dialectical carpet, and then continue on our merry way?
To be sure,
the above remarks appear to ignore at least four key DM-ideas:
(1)
The distinction between
"concrete" and "abstract" universals,2a
(2)
The flip-side of the dialectical coin,
"concrete particulars" (before and after they have been
'dialectically processed').
(3) The distinction between "subjective" and "objective"
dialectics, and,
(4)
The "dialectical relation" between the "abstract" and the "concrete",
as well as that between "the knower" and "the known".
As far as (2) is concerned:
if anything, 'concrete particulars' are even more difficult to comprehend.
So, it is far from clear how this term helps in any way.
Consider a familiar enough example of one possible candidate: a cat. Is each of these furry mammals a concrete
particular? DM-theorists would perhaps want to argue that a single cat isn't
such until it has
been comprehended against a background of all its
interconnections, these
being infinite in number. But, that would surely meannothing could ever
be viewed as a concrete particular, which in turn implies that nothing
would be a concrete particular unless an Ideal Observer (or,
Abstractor) viewed it against just such an infinite back-drop. This now
suggests that concrete objects are only concrete in the Ideal limit. Here
is Lenin again:
"A
tumbler is assuredly both a glass cylinder and a drinking
vessel. But there are more than these two properties and qualities or facets to
it; there are an infinite number of them, an infinite number of
'mediacies' and inter-relationships with the rest of the world…. [I]f we are to have true knowledge of an object
we must look at and examine all its facets, its connections and 'mediacies'.
That is something we cannot ever hope to achieve completely, but the rule of
comprehensiveness is a safeguard against mistakes and rigidity….
[D]ialectical logic requires that an
object should be taken in development, in change, in 'self-movement' (as Hegel
sometimes puts it). This is not immediately obvious in respect of such an object
as a tumbler, but it, too, is in flux, and this holds especially true for its
purpose, use and connection with the surrounding world." [Lenin
(1921), pp.92-93. Bold emphases
alone added;
paragraphs merged.]
Perhaps this is what Lenin meant when he argued as follows:
"Logical concepts are subjective so long as they
remain 'abstract,' in their abstract form, but at the same time they express the
Thing-in-themselves. Nature is both concrete and abstract, both
phenomenon and essence, both moment and relation. Human
concepts are subjective in their abstractness, separateness, but objective as a
whole, in the process, in the sum-total, in the tendency, in the source." [Lenin
(1961) p.208. Bold emphasis alone added.
Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]
If
that is the case with respect to familiar feline occupants of the
universe, it would seem that the
more we know about them the more Ideal they should appear to be! Abstract cats;
who would have thought?
That can't be right. And yet it
looks like that is
the clear implication of this rather odd approach to knowledge.
[There is more on this in
Part Two, and in Essay Ten
Part One, where we will see
that this approach to knowledge soon collapses into overt scepticism, since the difference between
a finite number of facts and an infinite number is itself
infinite. Naturally, that implies humanity will always be infinitely ignorant
about everything and anything!]
On the other hand, if this approach is correct,
it looks like the class of concrete
objects would: (i) Only ever have aspiring, but never successful, members, or it
would (ii) Look increasingly ephemeral, resembling a metaphysical
version of the
Cheshire Cat
-- the more we knew about this class, or this Cheshire Cat, the less substantial it would
appear to be. [On that,
see below.]
Furthermore, given this way of seeing things, no
abstractor (novice or skilled adept alike)
would ever have the remotest idea what could possibly count as the genuine article, since
bona fide 'concrete particulars' will only emerge from this Ideal Dungeon
at the end of an uncompletable, infinitary exercise in interconnection -- again
just as Lenin
argued.2b
And,
indeed, as
both Engels and Trotsky concurred:
"The identity of thinking and being, to
use Hegelian language, everywhere coincides with your example of the circle and
the polygon. Or the two of them, the concept of a thing and its reality, run
side by side like two asymptotes, always approaching each other but never
meeting. This difference between the two is the very difference which prevents
the concept from being directly and immediately reality and reality from being
immediately its own concept. Because a concept has the essential nature of the
concept and does not therefore prima facie directly coincide with
reality, from which it had to be abstracted in the first place, it is
nevertheless more than a fiction, unless you declare that all the results of
thought are fictions because reality corresponds to them only very circuitously,
and even then approaching it only asymptotically…. In other words, the unity of
concept and phenomenon manifests itself as an essentially infinite process, and
that is what it is, in this case as in all others." [Engels to Schmidt
(12/03/1895), in Marx and Engels (1975b), pp.457-58, and Marx and Engels (2004),
pp.463-64.]
"Shachtman
obviously does not take into account the distinction between the abstract and
the concrete. Striving toward concreteness, our mind operates with abstractions.
Even 'this,' 'given,' 'concrete' dog is an abstraction because it proceeds to
change, for example, by dropping its tail the 'moment' we point a finger at it.
Concreteness is a relative concept and not an absolute one: what is concrete in
one case turns out to be abstract in another: that is, insufficiently defined
for a given purpose. In order to obtain a concept 'concrete' enough for a given
need it is necessary to correlate several abstractions into one -- just as in
reproducing a segment of life upon the screen, which is a picture in movement,
it is necessary to combine a number of still photographs.
"The
concrete is a combination of abstractions -- not an arbitrary or subjective
combination but one that corresponds to the laws of the movement of a given
phenomenon." [Trotsky (1971),
p.147. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this
site.]
However, if Lenin were correct, no 'concrete' dog could ever be said to walk, sit or stand
in front of Trotsky until an infinite number of interconnections had been
established between it and the rest of the universe. If so, the 'dog' to
which Trotsky referredwas always abstract. Indeed, given this
approach, a fully accurate depiction of the very first
'concrete particular' in the whole of human history(!) will only ever leap from the Ideal page on 'Epistemological
Judgement Day', so to speak -- at the 'end of time'! Because of this, it looks like no mortal being will
ever be in a
position to form a clear idea of a single 'concrete particular'. On that
score, humanity is doomed never to know what the nature is of even one of
these (now) obscure 'entities', these 'concrete particulars', these cats and
dogs. Indeed, if Lenin is right, humanity will be
infinitely ignorant of any and all of them, forever. Worse still, if we are infinitely ignorant of, say, cats and dogs, could we
even say with confidence that they are in fact real cats and real dogs?
And if they aren't, what the dickens are we supposed to be interconnecting here?
What is there for an intrepid abstractor to work on if it isn't clear what we
are supposed to begin with?
Unfortunately, this means that abstractions themselves are based on, or must be applied to, nothing at all if they are
supposed to be grounded on these infinitely elusive 'concrete particulars'. Abstractions must, it seems,
be applied, or constructed, in almost total ignorance, using ethereal
bricks to build each ghostly building. If there are no reallyreal concrete particulars, no real dogs and no real cats, how can a single abstraction
be made of them? What
exactly is being abstracted -- and of what is it being abstracted?
In
that case,
Lenin, Engels and Trotsky's enigmatic comments are no
help
at all. If we have no idea what abstractions and concrete particulars actually are,
and no idea what they will ever be, then
it is little use being told that "The
concrete is a combination of abstractions," is it?
Indeed, Trotsky, for example, might just as well have
said: "The
schmoncrete is a combination of schmabstractions."
[Several
objections to this
unexpected turn of events have been neutralised
here and
here.]
To be sure, dialecticians will take exception to these
controversial allegations and claim, perhaps because the above considerations ignore not only the dialectical interplay between the knower and the
known, but also the link between the abstract and the concrete, and the
link both have with practice. They also seem to
confuse "subjective" with "objective" dialectics.
Naturally, this brings us
back to
items (1), (3) and (4),
outlined
earlier. However, further ruminations on the complex relation between these epistemological Siamese twins (i.e., the abstract
and the concrete) will be left for
later on in Essay -- as well as in Parts
Two, Three and Six.
The
question before us now is: Despite the inversion that Hegel's system is said to
have undergone at the hands of dialecticians, does an acceptance of the
existence of abstractions mean that DM is little more
than Upside Down Idealism? Is there anything to support
(or even refute)
this contentious allegation?
As will
soon become apparent, this infant suspicion will not only mature alarmingly, it will grow into full adulthood throughout
the rest of this Essay, and this site.
[While the following section this Essay presents what
might at first sight appear to be a series of unsupported assertions,
allegations and inferences about the
nature and provenance both of Traditional Thought and DM, they will all be fully
substantiated as the rest of this Essay, and, indeed, this site, unfolds. It is
also worth pointing out again that this main sub-section is a little repetitive,
hence I am continually re-writing it in order to put that right. So, as noted in
the Preface, the reader's indulgence is required here a little more than
elsewhere.]
There is a
clearly identifiable thread running
through the entire history of Traditional Philosophy: the idea that substantive
(i.e., non-trivial, metaphysical or necessary) truths about 'reality' can
be derived from thought alone, or the meaning of a handful of
specially-selected concepts, ideas or words -- indeed, as Marx himself
suggested:
"The philosophers would only
have to dissolve their language into the ordinary language, from which it is
abstracted, to recognise it as the distorted language of the actual world,
and
to realise that neither thoughts nor language in themselves form a realm of
their own, that they are only manifestations of actual life." [Marx
and Engels (1970), p.118. Bold emphasis alone added.]
Naturally, few Traditional Theorists will be willing to admit that this is all they ever do (or all they
have ever done) -- i.e., spin complex metaphysical tales solely from
thought/language. Outside
of the
Rationalist Tradition, even fewer theorists
would be willing to concede that in so doing they were in effect treating
language as some sort of 'Secret Code', deeper knowledge of which allowed them to
derive profound truths about fundamental
features of 'Reality', valid for all of space and time -- or, indeed, sometimes reaching beyond
even that, with theories about every
possible world, and even of the 'mind' of the 'Deity' 'Himself', all from
thought alone.
Nevertheless, this is indeed what
every single onehas
been doing.
However, over the last two-and-a-half thousand years, and perhaps in order to
disguise that fact, this
approach to
Super-Knowledge has motivated Traditional Philosophers into inventing various
subterfuges, ruses and likely stories aimed at 'justifying' their
semi-godlike ability to derive substantial truths about "Being" from
a consideration
of the supposed meaning of a few carefully chosen (and often artificially
doctored)
expressions.
[There is no
suggestion, however, that every single one of them did this duplicitously.]
Among these are the following
hardy perennials (several of
the following overlap somewhat, which means that the material below will be a little more
repetitive than much of the rest of this Essay):
The widely-held doctrine that the world was created by a
'Divine Being', 'Person', 'Mind', or by 'god'/'gods' 'justified'
the further belief that reality has an underlying 'rational' structure,
which was either a creation, a reflection or an "emanation" of one or more of
those supernatural 'entities'. Classic examples of this metaphysical doctrine can be found in the work of
Plato, Aristotle,
Plotinus,
John Scotus Eriugena,
Anselm,
Aquinas,
Nicolas of
Cusa,
Descartes,
Jakob
Boehme,
Leibniz,
Kant -- and, of course, Hegel
himself.
As I noted in Essay Thirteen Part Three:
Umberto Eco
points out the following (in relation to the 'western' Christian tradition):
"God spoke before all things,
and said, 'Let there be light.' In this way, he created both heaven and earth;
for with (sic) the utterance of the divine word, 'there was light'.... Thus Creation
itself arose through an act of speech; it is only by giving things their names
that he created them and gave them their
ontological status....
"In Genesis..., the Lord
speaks to man for the first time.... We are not told in what language God spoke
to Adam. Tradition has pictured it as a sort of language of interior
illumination, in which God...expresses himself....
"...Clearly we are here
in the presence of a motif, common to other religions and mythologies -- that of
the
nomothete, the
name-giver, the creator of language." [Eco (1997), pp.7-8. Bold emphasis
added.]
Language was a vehicle for the "inner illumination" of the 'soul'; a
hot-line to
'God'. Unsurprisingly, the theories concocted by countless generations of
ruling-class hacks turned out to be those that, 'coincidentally', you
understand, almost
invariably rationalised or 'justified' the status quo, alongside
obscene
inequality and systematic oppression.
[On
this, see Bono (1995). There is more on this
in Essay Twelve (summary
here).]
Dogma [1] above in turn implied that only those
with the 'right' intellectual powers -- or, to be more honest, only those
with the right social standing, adequate means, indulgent patrons,
sufficient leisure time
and a flair for inventing of jargon -- were capable of 'discovering' these 'Super-Truths'.
Fortunately
enough for these 'intellectual hacks' their Super-Theories could be
obtained by the sole exercise of the mind, as we saw
Plato
insist.
Indeed, those capable of performing impressive verbal tricks found
that they could unearth any number of 'Cosmic Verities', which will forever
remain way beyond the comprehension of the great 'unwashed', by the simple
expedient of unravelling the 'implications' of their own jargon.
Often these verbal tricks were 'fortified' by the liberal use of
stipulative and
persuasive definitions.
So, in order to elaborate upon this impressive skill Traditional
Thinkers invented increasingly arcane and baroque terminology, which, in the
distant past, had been
regarded as a gift of the 'gods' (as
Umberto Eco noted), which might help explain its prolixity.
'Divinely-inspired' jargon
'naturally' gave spurious substance to the highly abstract prose these theorists
continually cranked out, the allegedly superficial aspects of this material world
having been peremptorily 'abstracted away', cast aside as inferior and
beneath
contempt by generations of boss-class
Idealists and Mystics.
Clearly, there is no way that 'surgically-enhanced'
jargon like this could have been the product collective labour and communal
life (on that, see Essays Three
Part Two, Nine
Part One and
Twelve Part One),
nor could it have been grounded on the material world, or even have been the product of social practice.Hence, the 'verbal spaghetti'
Traditional Theorists cooked up
not only had a very limited sphere of influence -- stretching about as far as the
ideas of other socially-isolated 'thinkers' playing the same game
--, it was the sole patronage
of a highly exclusive clientele. And
deliberately so. Only a lexicon of 'sanctified' words with such an
exclusive and elevated pedigree could possibly act as an intermediary between this
self-selected group of 'superior' human beings and the 'Deity'. By such
means these theorists
were able to uncover
with relative ease a series
'necessary truths' about "Essence", "Being",
and, of course, the 'Rational Order of Reality'. It is no surprise therefore to
see that this "ruling idea" idea still
motivates much of 'popular science' and
amateur metaphysics.
In this way, therefore, theories
that explored
the relationship between "Thought" and "Being" were merely an extension to Theology, as Marx himself noted:
"Feuerbach's
great achievement is.... The proof thatphilosophy is nothing else but
religion rendered into thoughtand expounded by thought, i.e., another form
and manner of existence of the estrangement of the essence of man; hence equally
to be condemned...." [Marx
(1975b), p.381. I have used the on-line version, here. Bold emphasis
and link added.]
Lenin expressed
a similar opinion;
here he is quoting Dietzgen:
"J. Dietzgen had not the slightest doubt that the 'scientific priestcraft'
of idealist philosophy is simply the antechamber to open priestcraft.
'Scientific priestcraft,' he wrote, 'is seriously endeavouring to assist
religious priestcraft' (op. cit., p.51). 'In particular, the sphere of
epistemology, the misunderstanding of the human mind, is such a louse-hole'...in
which both kinds of priests 'lay their eggs.' 'Graduated flunkeys,' who with
their talk of 'ideal blessings' stultify the people by their
tortuous...'idealism' (p.53) -- that is J. Dietzgen's opinion of the professors
of philosophy. 'Just as the antipodes of the good God is the devil, so the
professorial priest...has his opposite pole in the materialist.' The materialist
theory of knowledge is 'a universal weapon against religious
belief' (p.55), and not only against
the 'notorious, formal and common religion of the priests, but also against the
most refined, elevated professorial religion of muddled...idealists' (p.58).
"Dietzgen was ready to prefer 'religious honesty' to the 'half-heartedness'
of freethinking professors (p.60), for 'there at least there is a system,'
there we find integral people, people who do not separate theory from practice.
For the Herr Professors 'philosophy is not a science, but a means of defence
against Social-Democracy...' (p.107). 'All who call themselves philosophers,
professors, and university lecturers are, despite their apparent freethinking,
more or less immersed in superstition and mysticism...and in relation to
Social-Democracy constitute a single...reactionary mass' (p.108). 'Now, in
order to follow the true path, without being led astray by all the religious and
philosophical gibberish..., it is necessary to study the falsest of all
false paths..., philosophy' (p.103)." [Lenin
(1972), pp.413-14. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions
adopted at this site.]
Of
course, it is arguable that Lenin was referring to the philosophers of his day, but, give or take a few qualifications,
his comments apply equally well to the whole
profession stretching (in the 'West') right back to the Ancient Greeks. Granted
he would have seriously questioned that unqualified extrapolation of his words,
but, Essay Twelve will show it is no less
apt for all that (summary
here). Just as it is no less pertinent when applied to DM itself.
Of
course, the above
is no mere supposition; the History of Philosophy
fully supports such deflationary conclusions.
[On that, see Essays Twelve and Fourteen (summaries
here,
here,
and
here).]
Even Hegel admitted as much:
"Every philosophy is
essentially an idealism or at least has idealism for its principle, and the
question then is only how far this principle is carried out." [Hegel
(1999), pp.154-55; §316.
Bold emphasis added.]
Hence, no expensive equipment or convoluted experiments were required.
In
fact, no
real engagement with the material world was necessary --, that is, over and above
a comfortable armchair, some writing material and maybe a little too much wine. Wealth, patronage,
more than your fair share of leisure-time, a lively imagination --, and, of course, a flare for
inventing jargon --
are
all that the aspiring Philosopher required.
This
ancient and (originally) aristocratic approach to 'knowledge' has
surfaced many times, in many different guises, in diverse Modes of Production
that have come and gone since the Ancient World, both 'East' and 'West'. It is indeed the common thread that unites every shade
of ruling-class thought, despite its re-packaging as and when the exigencies of the class
war required.
Some may object that philosophical ideas can't have remained the
same for thousands of years, across different Modes of Production. Surely, that idea
itself runs
counter to core ideas in
HM? But, we don't argue the same
for religious belief. Marx put no time stamp on the following, for
example:
"The foundation of irreligious criticism is:
Man makes religion, religion does not make man. Religion is, indeed, the
self-consciousness and self-esteem of man who has either not yet won through to
himself, or has already lost himself again. But man is no abstract
being squatting outside the world. Man is the world of man -- state,
society. This state and this society produce religion, which is an inverted
consciousness of the world, because they are an inverted world.
Religion is the general theory of this world, its encyclopaedic compendium, its
logic in popular form, its spiritual point d'honneur, its enthusiasm, its
moral sanction, its solemn complement, and its universal basis of consolation
and justification. It is the fantastic realization of the human essence
since the human essence has not acquired any true reality. The struggle
against religion is, therefore, indirectly the struggle against that world
whose spiritual aroma is religion.
"Religious
suffering is, at one and the same time, the expression of real suffering
and a protest against real suffering. Religion is the sigh of the
oppressed creature, the heart of a heartless world, and the soul of soulless
conditions. It is the opium of the people.
The abolition of religion as the illusory
happiness of the people is the demand for their real happiness. To call
on them to give up their illusions about their condition is to call on them to
give up a condition that requires illusions. The criticism of religion
is, therefore, in embryo, the criticism of that vale of tears of which
religion is the halo." [Marx
(1975c),
p.244.
Italic emphases in the original. Some paragraphs merged.]
The above remarks applied in Ancient Babylon and Egypt,
just as they did in China and India, in Greece and Rome, in the Middle Ages, and
they have done so right across the planet ever since. So, despite what some
might conclude about the implications of HM, Marx certainly thought that certain
"ruling ideas" and other thought-forms could survive such profound social
transformations.
The same is the case with the core forms of thought found throughout Traditional
Philosophy -- that there is an invisible, 'abstract' world, accessible to thought
alone that is more real than the material world we see around us --, especially since, as we have
already seen, Marx also believed that:
"[P]hilosophy is nothing else but
religion rendered into thought and expounded by thought...". [Marx
(1975b), p.381.]
Some
might argue that there have been (and still are) ancient, early modern and
contemporary materialists, which fact alone undermines the above rather
sweeping generalisations. However, those theorists are
philosophical materialists, who also derived their ideas from thought alone,
which situates them well inside the perimeter of the above generalisations. To be sure,
there have been theorists who claimed to have based their ideas on scientific
evidence, but their materialism has to be imposed on science, it
doesn't follow from it.
[I
will say much more about that in Essay Thirteen Part Two.]
Unfortunately, the theses that litter DM show similar signs of what can only be
called linguistic megalomania: the belief that (i)
A handful of words invented on this planet can unmask the deepest 'secrets' of 'Being' and (ii) The human brain lies at the very centre
of the 'meaning universe' -- i.e., the belief that it follows somehow from the perennial desire to find meaning in a
'meaningless universe' that there must indeed be meaning 'out there',
after all, and the thought of a few specialist theorists is capable of capturing
and then revealing
it to the rest of us. So, philosophers and amateur metaphysicians alike just have to think hard
enough to access this 'Cosmic Motherlode' of meaning. Since human beings can
access it, that puts us at the centre of the meaning universe; the entire
shooting match was somehow intended for our benefit. The Earth might no longer be at the
centre of the Universe, but our minds still are, according to this
world-view. DM-theorists have clearly bought into since they have adopted the
same approach to knowledge, outlined in (i) above.
Option (ii) often re-surfaces as a more secular version of Marx's famous words quoted
six or seven paragraphs ago.
[On
this topic, see Stove (1991),
pp.83-177, which is, I think, one of the most coherent and powerful
statements, and condemnations, of this world-view I have ever read. Having said that, I hesitate
to reference Stove's work because of his objectionable, reactionary political
opinions; I distance myself, therefore, from many of the remarks
he expresses, especially those found on p.96. On that, see also
here.]
The search for religious and philosophical
consolation isn't, therefore, confined to the open and honest god-botherers among us.
DM-fans unfortunately show similar a
predilection.
In
the 'West', since early Greek times, 'linguistic megalomania' of the sort
just described has dominated the thought-processes of the elite, their hangers-on and
their "prize-fighters" (as Marx termed these ideologues) -- manifesting itself
in a
series of interconnected philosophical theories that gave expression to the "ruling
ideas" of each epoch:
"The ideas of the ruling class are in every epoch
the
ruling ideas, i.e. the class which is the ruling material force of society,
is at the same time its ruling intellectual force. The class which has the means
of material production at its disposal, has control at the same time over the
means of mental production, so that thereby, generally speaking, the ideas of
those who lack the means of mental production are subject to it. The ruling
ideas are nothing more than the ideal expression of the dominant material
relationships, the dominant material relationships grasped as ideas; hence of
the relationships which make the one class the ruling one, therefore, the ideas
of its dominance. The individuals composing the ruling class possess among other
things consciousness, and therefore think. Insofar, therefore, as they rule as a
class and determine the extent and compass of an epoch, it is self-evident that
they do this in its whole range, hence among other things rule also as thinkers,
as producers of ideas, and regulate the production and distribution of the ideas
of their age: thus their ideas are the ruling ideas of the epoch...." [Marx and Engels (1970), pp.64-65, quoted from
here. Bold
emphases added.]
Notice how Marx
pointed out that:
"The class which has the means
of material production at its disposal, has control at the same time over the
means of mental production, so that thereby, generally speaking, the ideas of
those who lack the means of mental production are subject to it.... Insofar,
therefore, as they rule as a class and determine the extent and compass of an
epoch, it is self-evident that they do this in its whole range, hence
among other things rule also as thinkers, as producers of ideas, and regulate
the production and distribution of the ideas of their age...."
[Ibid. Bold emphases added.]
Hence,
this class, or
their ideologues, rule as
"thinkers", and they do so in "its whole range".
This 'philosophical personality disorder' is indeed part of a wider array of
ruling-class, 'theoretical character traits' that have dominated all forms of
what are regarded as 'acceptable'
examples of
philosophical thought ever since --
even
by Marxists.
One of the most
important implications of Traditional Thought was the idea that the Super-Truths invented by
ruling-class hacks
mustof necessity apply to all of reality, for all of time. This
doctrine has manifested
itself in different forms of LIE, which include the even more ancient idea that reality is in
effect merely 'condensed language', the result of the activities of the 'Word of
God'.
Again, by sheer coincidence, the 'philosophical
gems' mined as a result turned out to be those that 'justified' or rationalised
the interests of the many and diverse ruling-classes humanity has had imposed on it.
[LIE = Linguistic
Idealism (explained
further
below).]
Logic
was viewed as the study of "the laws of thought", or "the science of
thought/cognition" itself, which was in turn somehow capable of reflecting the 'essential
nature of Being'. This time-honoured idea was augmented by the parallel belief that there
were countless 'secrets' lying 'below the surface of appearances', which could be uncovered by an examination of the
'logical structure' of suitably 'doctored' sentences -- but only if they wereburied beneath layers of unintelligible jargon, and packed with just enough speculative flights-of-fancy to distract
and confuse the unwary.
Or,
these days, if they contained sufficient enough obscure terminology to impress Marxist 'intellectuals':
"Logic is the science of the
thought process. Logicians investigate the activities of the though process
which goes on in human heads and formulate laws , firms and interrelation of
those mental processes." [Novack (1971), p.17.]
"Hegel insisted on a Logic which was not something separate from
the reality which confronted man, a Logic which was identical with the richness
and movement of all reality, a Logic which expressed the whole process of man's
growing consciousness of reality, and not just a dry summary of formal
principles of argument, reflecting only one brief phase in the definition of
reality by thinking men." [Slaughter
(1963), p.9.]
In
this, they agreed with the DM-classicists:
"Modern materialism is essentially
dialectical.... What independently survives of all former philosophy is the
science of thought and its laws -- formal logic and dialectics." [Engels
(1976),
p.31. Bold emphases added.]
"In every epoch, and
therefore also in ours, theoretical thought is a historical product, which at
different times assumes very different forms and, therewith, very different
contents. The science of thought is therefore, like every other, a historical
science, the science of the historical development of human thought. And this is
of importance also for the practical application of thought in empirical fields.
Because in the first place the theory of the laws of thought is by no means an
'eternal truth' established once and for all, as philistine reasoning imagines
to be the case with the word 'logic'." [Engels
(1954), p.43. Quotation marks
altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Bold emphases
added.]
"Logic is the science of
cognition. It is the theory of knowledge…. The laws of logic are the reflections
of the objective in the subjective consciousness of man.... [These] embrace
conditionally, approximately, the universal, law-governed character of eternally
moving and developing nature."
[Lenin (1961),
p.182.
Bold emphasis alone added..]
"Hegel himself viewed
dialectics precisely as logic, as the science of the forms of human
cognition.... What does logic express? The
law of the external world or the law of consciousness? The question is posed
dualistically [and] therefore not correctly [for] the laws of logic express the
laws (rules, methods) of consciousness in its active relationship to the
external world.... Thought operates by its own
laws, which we can call the laws of logic...." [Trotsky (1986), pp.75, 87, 106.
Trotsky is apparently referring to Hegel's Introduction to The Science
of Logic (i.e., Hegel (1999),
pp.43-64.
Bold emphases added; paragraphs merged.]
So,
not
only were Logic and Epistemology regarded as two sides of the same bent coin, the
idea prevailed that Logic was in fact a higher form of
Psychology -- indeed, the study of the "laws of thought" -- a
doctrine that only
makes sense if 'reality' is indeed the product of 'Thought', which is why it was
imagined that logic
could reflect it.
In
relation to this theory I pointed out the following over at
Wikipedia:
Why
are these called 'laws of thought' (over and above the fact that it
is traditional to do so)? Does anyone seriously think that
people actually cogitate in syllogisms, or that they use the formal
calculi found in
Principia Mathematica when they reason?
If
logic were the science of what went on in people's heads, logicians would busy themselves with brain scans, surveys,
psychometric tests, and the like. They certainly would not bother
with all those useless theorems and proofs.
And
in reply to an individual who claimed he didindeed think in syllogisms, etc., I
had this to say (slightly edited):
I didn't speculate whether or not there
were maverick individuals on the planet who might at least claim they
thought in syllogisms (a remarkably useless and inefficient way to think, anyway)
or the calculi of Principia; however, I retain a healthy scepticism that you
actually think using symbols like this:
~[(P →
Q) v (P → R) ↔
(P → (Q v R))], or this ~[~(Ex)(Fx & ~Gx)↔(x)(Fx → Gx)], but
I seriously doubt whether
"people" do this, i.e., the majority of the population. And if they don't, then
logic can't express 'laws of thought', otherwise we'd all be at it, and we'd
have been doing it for thousands of years before Russell and/or Aristotle were
thought of. [Ibid.]
[Where "P", "Q" and "R" are propositional variables, "F" and "G" are predicate
letter variables, "(Ex)" is the existential quantifier (equivalent to "Some...", or
"There exists..."), "~" is a
negation operator (i.e., "It is not the case that..."), "v" is the disjunction sign
(equivalent to the inclusive "or", i.e., "and/or"), "&"
obviously stands for "and", "→" is the conditional sign (equivalent to
"if...then"), and "↔" is the biconditional sign (equivalent to "if and only
if" or its abbreviation, "iff").]
The
theory that Logic mirrors the
deep-structure of reality also motivated another widely held idea that it is
some sort of Super-Code, a source of
Super-Knowledge, which
can be used to reveal the 'hidden
secrets' of nature,
way beyond the reach of the senses -- and even of
the sciences proper. In one form or another, the vast majority of Traditional Thinkers
accepted this dogma, for centuries viewing Logic as an expression of the
Logos, or 'God's Mind Itself',
and hence a reflection of the underlying 'Cosmic Order'.
As noted above, many still find it impossible
to abandon the comforting idea that humanity sits at the
very centre of the
meaning universe, a special creation of a
'Super-Logician', a Super
Mathematician2c
-- or, in its DM-form, as a special creation of the
NON (with 'Being', 'Nothing' and 'Becoming' forming a sort of Logical Trinity
in this Cosmic Drama)
--, so that their thoughts were somehow possessed of Cosmic Significance.
Few asked how it could be that human thought (on its own) might have such
profound consequences, or how language might have such implications built into
it, other than that it was 'the will of god'. Although that idea has
largely disappeared from Philosophy, it has its left indelible mark behind. So,
these days few even ask those questions let alone try to answer them.
Hence, even though science has rendered obsolete such ancient fancies,
metaphysicians (and DM-fans, for whom DL actually runs the entire
Universe) still imagine they can derive Super-Facts from
words alone.
[NON = Negation of the Negation; DL =
Dialectical Logic.]
Again, as the late
Umberto Eco
noted (my words and paraphrase, not his!),
Traditional Philosophers found such ideas especially appealing. For
obvious reasons, this approach to Super-Knowledge invariably assumed linguistic form.
Hence, if human beings are of special importance to 'Being'/'God', and if
language originally constituted and now governs both nature and society, then
language and thought must be interlinked with the fundamental nature of 'Being Itself'.
This
view in turn 'legitimated' the authority of the State -- as a reflection of the Cosmic Order,
as this commentator notes:
"Heraclitus, along with
Parmenides, is probably the most
significant philosopher of ancient Greece until
Socrates
and
Plato; in fact,
Heraclitus's philosophy is perhaps even more fundamental in the formation of the
European mind than any other thinker in European history, including Socrates,
Plato, and Aristotle. Why? Heraclitus, like Parmenides, postulated a model of
nature and the universe which created the foundation for all other speculation
on physics and metaphysics. The ideas that the universe is in constant change
and that there is an underlying order or reason to this change -- the
Logos -- form the
essential foundation of the European world view. Every time you walk into a
science, economics, or political science course, to some extent everything you
do in that class originates with Heraclitus's speculations on change and the
Logos....
"In reading
these passages, you should be able to piece together the central
components of Heraclitus's thought. What, precisely, is the Logos? Can it be
comprehended or defined by human beings? What does it mean to claim that the
Logos consists of all the paired opposites in the universe? What is the
nature of the Logos as the composite of all paired opposites? How does the Logos
explain change? Finally, how would you compare Heraclitus's Logos to its later
incarnations: in the
Divided Line in Plato, in foundational and early
Christianity? How would you relate Heraclitus's cryptic statements to those of
Lao Tzu?"
[Quoted from
here.
Bold emphasis added.]
[Of course, the short answer to the above questions is: The ideas of the ruling-class
are always the ruling ideas!
The long answer is little different.]
The specially-concocted jargon mentioned above had to fulfil another
pre-condition: it must be capable of connecting 'finite minds' to
the 'Ultimate Ground Of Meaning' (which is the principle aim of all mystical
thought, a dogma that resurfaced as the "Subject/Object" problematic of
German
Idealism and
later still as a central concern of 'Materialist Dialectics'
-- on that,
see below).
As a result, a seemingly endless series of 'truths' could now 'legitimately' flow from the meaning of a handful
of words. For each theorist,
Super-Knowledge accessed in the comfort of their
heads.
Traditional
Philosophers were only too eager to latch onto the belief that human thoughts were universally
significant -- i.e., that what went on in certain heads was the best,
if not the
only guide to 'Absolute Truth' --, and which also supplied a key to solving
the very 'problems' they themselves had concocted.
Keith Thomas notes a similar tactic
adopted by 16th
century magicians:
"It would be tempting to
explain the long survival of magical practices by pointing out that they helped
provide many professional wizards with a respectable livelihood. The example of
the legal profession is a reminder that it is always possible for a substantial
social group to support itself by proffering solutions to problems which they
themselves have helped to manufacture. The cunning men and wise women had an
undoubted interest in upholding the prestige of magical diagnosis and may by
their mere existence have helped to prolong a mode of thinking which was already
obsolescent." [Thomas (1972), p.295.]
The bottom line was that they alone -- Traditional Theorists
-- had access to the 'hidden knowledge' superhighway,
a back-channel that penetrated right into the
heart of 'Being', which 'enabled' them to derive necessary truths from
jargon they themselves had invented for that specific purpose. This
'allowed them to generate philosophical theories that couldn't
fail to be true, which, for that reason needed no evidence in support.
Acting as judge and jury in their own case, these 'thinkers' declared these Super-Verities "self-evident", arguing that only "crude materialists" would
think to challenge such a 'self-confirming' and
self-serving approach to 'knowledge'. In which case, the history of Traditional Thought has amounted to
little more than
collective indulgence
in protractedself-deception.
Unfortunately however, this 'highway to Super-Knowledge'
was based on what was in effect a contingentfeature
of a minor aspect of the grammar of
one particular language-group -- the
Indo-European
family --, in which most of these fairy-tales have been, and still are being,
spun.
In Ancient Greece, "subjects" and "predicates"
suddenly became cosmically significant.2d
Unfortunately, the "abstraction" of a strictly limited set of
these predicate
expressions -- which are supposed to express generality -- only succeeded in turning them into
singular terms incapable of expressing anything, let alone generality. As
this Essay unfolds we will discover that linguistic magic like this re-configured these
general terms as the
Proper Names of Abstract
Particulars. The intractable problems these moves then created
were compounded by the bizarre
Hegelian-, and later DM-idea
that it was possible for an individual to be identical with
a 'Universal'!
But, whatever their
origin or provenance happened to be, these
abstract,
Ideal Forms (or what they allegedly 'reflected') were supposedly
more real than objects and processes in the natural and social world
around us. In
fact, this meant the material universe was somehow 'unreal', 'inferior', 'ephemeral', a 'mere appearance'. Those
invisible, underlying 'essences' (just like the 'gods' of old) were the only really
real world.
Access to
nature's secret names
(all those
'abstractions') 'allowed' Traditional Theorists to forge a mystical,
intellectual link between their thought and the underlying, non-material 'essences' that governed all of reality, 'behind the scenes'
as it were. Indeed, it was a
near-universal belief that this 'secret knowledge' would help those 'in the
know' gain a special sort of control over nature itself (which, of course, is one of the
core principles of ancient, medieval and contemporary forms of magic and
alchemy). Far more importantly, 'secret knowledge'
like this helped 'rationalise' state power and hence the status quo. For
if the status and power of the elite were guaranteed by -- indeed, were a reflection of
-- The Cosmic Order,
class division and oppression could be 'justified' as an irrevocable feature of 'Being'.
Or,
at least as far as Hegel was concerned, an integral component in the
development of 'Being'.
In
that case,
theorists skilled in the art of 'jargon-juggling' and 'word magic' could
accrue to themselves no little
prestige -- if not power -- as skilled 'legitimators' of the
ruling
elite.
A metaphysical
Rumplestiltskinnow walked the earth,
and was well paid for its services. If reality had an
a priori structure, which the
State
also mirrored, then Philosophy and ruling-class legitimacy could be, and were,
intimately
inter-linked.
If religious affectation is the
opiate of the
oppressed, rationalising suffering in its wake, then deep-seated
motivating forces behind the need to concoct metaphysical abstractions
underpinned these analogous opiates of the oppressor -- 'justifying' and rationalising the power
and wealth of the very class
that helped create the need for such opiates in the first place.
[Concerning the
consolation that Traditional Thought provides those held in its thrall, see, for
example, Stove (1991),
pp.83-177. A classic in this genre is
perhaps Boethius's,
Consolations of Philosophy, accessible
here.]
As will be demonstrated in this Essay, and
throughout the rest of this site (especially
here), the
aprioristic tradition in 'Western' Philosophy seduced Marxist
dialecticians into thinking they had successfully flipped Hegelian Idealism
through 180º, so that it was now the "right way up" -- allegedly transforming it into its materialist alter ego:
'Materialist Dialectics'.
A change
of name, perhaps;but a ruse by any other name is still a ruse.
Philosophy
was now viewed as a unique and special source of Super-Knowledge --
knowledge that is not just anterior
to, it is even more fundamental than, anything the sciences could possibly deliver.
It is "Superscientific"
because its theories reveal
Super-Necessities that underpin 'Being' itself, knowledge of which is
only attainable by the application of 'reason'. As
Immanuel Kant noted:
"First, concerning the sources of
metaphysical cognition, it already lies in the concept of metaphysics that
they cannot be empirical. The principles of such cognition (which include
not only its fundamental propositions or basic principles, but also its
fundamental concepts) must therefore never be taken from experience; for the
cognition is supposed to be not physical but metaphysical, i.e., lying beyond
experience. Therefore it will be based upon neither outer experience, which
constitutes the source of physics proper, nor inner, which provides the
foundation of empirical psychology. It is therefore cognition
a priori, or from pure understanding and
pure reason.... Metaphysical cognition must contain nothing but judgments a
priori, as required by the distinguishing feature of its sources." [Kant
(1953), pp.15-16. (This links to a PDF.) I have quoted the on-line
version which is a different translation to the one I have referenced. Bold
emphases added; link added and paragraphs merged.]
"Lying beyond
experience", of course, implies philosophical knowledge is superior to anything
science has to offer.
However, as we will see, the
actual origin of these
'Cosmic Verities' was rather more mundane: 'philosophical reasoning' turns out to be little more than the creative and idiosyncratic
use of a limited range of words, specially-concocted as the need arose.
Naturally, this means that
Superscientific
Knowledge
like this can only be
'confirmed' by an appeal to Super-Evidence -- obtained, of course,
Super-Naturally (i.e., not from nature) -- either by means of a series of 'thought
experiments', or from yet more creative word-juggling. Unsurprisingly,
as noted above, the Super-Theories that Traditional Philosophers invented
also lay way
beyond any possibility of empirical verification or falsification.3a
Perversely, this is still regarded by many
as one of Philosophy's greatest strengths -- as these two authors pointed out:
"Empirical,
contingent
truths have always struck
philosophers as being, in some sense, ultimately unintelligible. It is not that
none can be known with certainty…; nor is it that some cannot be explained….
Rather is it that all explanation of empirical truths rests ultimately on brute
contingency -- that is how the world is! Where science comes to rest in
explaining empirical facts varies from epoch to epoch, but it is in the nature
of empirical explanation that it will hit the bedrock of contingency somewhere,
e.g., in atomic theory in the nineteenth century or in
quantum mechanics
today. One feature that
explains philosophers' fascination with
truths of Reason
is that they seem, in a
deep sense, to be fully intelligible. To understand a necessary proposition is
to see why things must be so, it is to gain an insight into the nature of
things and to apprehend not only how things are, but also why they cannot be
otherwise. It is striking how pervasive visual metaphors are in philosophical
discussions of these issues. We see the universal in the particular (by
Aristotelian intuitive induction); by the Light of Reason we see the essential
relations of
Simple Natures; mathematical truths are
apprehended by Intellectual Intuition, or by
a priori insight. Yet instead of examining the use of these arresting
pictures or metaphors to determine their aptness as pictures, we build
upon them mythological structures.
"We think of necessary
propositions as being
true or false, as objective and independent of our minds or will. We
conceive of them as being about various entities, about numbers even
about extraordinary numbers that the mind seems barely able to grasp…, or about
universals, such as colours, shapes, tones; or about logical entities, such as
the truth-functions or (in Frege's
case) the truth-values. We naturally think of necessary propositions as
describing the features of these entities, their essential characteristics.
So we take mathematical propositions to describe mathematical objects…. Hence
investigation into the domain of necessary propositions is conceived as a
process of discovery. Empirical scientists make discoveries about the
empirical domain, uncovering contingent truths; metaphysicians, logicians and
mathematicians appear to make discoveries of necessary truths about a
supra-empirical domain (a 'third
realm'). Mathematics seems to be the 'natural history of
mathematical objects' [Wittgenstein
(1978), p.137], 'the physics of numbers' [Wittgenstein (1976), p.138; however
these authors record this erroneously as p.139 -- RL] or the 'mineralogy of
numbers' [Wittgenstein (1978), p.229]. The mathematician, e.g.,
Pascal,
admires the beauty of a theorem as though it were a kind of crystal.
Numbers seem to him to have wonderful properties; it is as if he were
confronting a beautiful natural phenomenon [Wittgenstein (1998), p.47; again,
these authors have recorded this erroneously as p.41 -- RL]. Logic seems to
investigate the laws governing logical objects…. Metaphysics looks as if it is a
description of the essential structure of the world. Hence we think that a
reality corresponds to our (true) necessary propositions. Our logic is
correct because it corresponds to the laws of logic….
"In our eagerness to ensure
the objectivity of truths of reason, their sempiternality
and mind-independence, we slowly but surely transform them into truths that are
no less 'brutish' than empirical, contingent truths. Why must red exclude
being green? To be told that this is the essential nature of red and green
merely reiterates the brutish necessity. A proof in arithmetic or geometry seems
to provide an explanation, but ultimately the structure of proofs rests on
axioms. Their truth is held to be self-evident, something we apprehend by
means of our faculty of intuition; we must simply see that they are
necessarily true…. We may analyse such ultimate truths into their constituent
'indefinables'. Yet if 'the discussion of indefinables…is the endeavour to see
clearly, and to make others see clearly, the entities concerned, in order that
the mind may have that kind of acquaintance with them which it has with redness
or the taste of a pineapple' [Russell
(1937), p.xv (this links to a PDF); again these authors record this erroneously as p.v;
although in the edition to which I have linked, it is p.xliii -- RL], then the
mere intellectual vision does not penetrate the logical or metaphysical
that to the why or wherefore…. For if we construe necessary
propositions as truths about logical, mathematical or metaphysical entities
which describe their essential properties, then, of course, the final products
of our analyses will be as impenetrable to reason as the final products of
physical theorising, such as
Planck's constant."
[Baker and Hacker (1988), pp.273-75. Referencing conventions in the original
have been altered to conform with those adopted at this site.]
Indeed, anyone who questioned the validity of this dogmatic approach to
'ultimate truth' should rightly be classified as a "philistine", a "crude" materialist --
even an "empiricist", a "positivist" --, or they are simply dismissed out-of-hand,
their ideas unworthy of comment in polite company. This is, of course, just one of the reasons why
the ideas of the ruling-class always rule. Anyone who challenged such core
beliefs was vilified
for even so much as thinking to question this 'royal road' to 'knowledge'. Indeed, even today, anyone who questions the provenance of
these Semi-Divine Verities is in danger of putting
themselvesbeyond
the pale of 'acceptable' thought. Philosophy -- genuine
Philosophy
-- must be
prolix,
baroque
and, wherever possible, incomprehensible. This is one ruling-idea that
still rules, and
proudly so --, especially if you are a French 'Philosopher', your name is
Bhaskar or
Zizek.
The
downside, of course, is that if, for any reason, the unique role that
Philosophers have arrogated to themselves can be shown to be a complete fraud --, that is, if it can be shown that the complex,
Byzantine structures Philosophers have
constructed over the centuries are really "houses of cards" (to paraphrase
Wittgenstein) -- then the whole enterprise would cease to have a point.
With no reason for its existence, Philosophy would become little more than the
production of a
steady stream of tortured prose, its works fit only for gathering dust in the basement
stack of the local library --, or, perhaps better still, fit only for providing fuel
for several large bonfires, as
Hume wickedly suggested:
"If we take in our hand any volume; of divinity or school
metaphysics, for instance; let us ask, Does it contain any abstract reasoning
concerning quantity or number? No. Does it contain any experimental
reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence? No. Commit it then to the
flames: for it can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion." [Quoted from
here. Italic emphases in the original.]
[Some
have complained that book burning is something only fascists do; I am not
serious in suggesting this. The aforementioned books are fit for burning not that they should
be! They should be confined to the basement stack of a library, as indicated
above.]
However, few practitioners of this
bogus
art can afford to contemplate such an unappealing fate -- especially those
whose livelihood depends on it. Closer to home,
and for different reasons,
the above
indictment includes those Dialectical Marxists (i.e., all of them) who still refuse to see any link between the
superstitious belief that there is a "rational" order to reality and
the centuries-oldendeavour to 'legitimate' and rationalise
ruling-class power.
[As
we will see in Essay Nine Parts
One
and
Two,
the above connection was patently obvious in the shape of the state ideology
adopted by the ruling-classes of the 'really existing socialist' states in E
Europe, the former Soviet Union, China, Cuba, and elsewhere. The "ruling ideas"
promoted by that elite were plain for all to see.]
Hence, it
has always been
assumed that Philosophy must have a role to play in the
pursuit of
knowledge, even if only to provide employment for those caught up in the
production of jargon-filled books and articles --
the intellectual equivalent of digging holes just to fill them in.
If the question is now put: "Why
should there be a rational order to reality?", there seem to be only
three possible answers: to (i) impress the superstitious, motivating, 'encouraging'
and enforcing deference and subservience; (ii) legitimate the status quo;
and (iii) provide a select few with good reason to continue their search for 'Superscientific
Knowledge', thereby ingratiating themselves on those who hold the purse
strings,
"There are also Idols formed by the
intercourse and association of men with each other, which I call Idols of the
Market-place, on account of the commerce and consort of men there. For it is by
discourse that men associate; and words are imposed according to the
apprehension of the vulgar. And therefore the ill and unfit choice of words
wonderfully obstructs the understanding. Nor do the definitions or explanations
wherewith in some things learned men are wont to guard and defend themselves, by
any means set the matter right. But words plainly force and overrule the
understanding, and throw all into confusion, and lead men away into numberless
empty controversies and idle fancies....
"The idols imposed by words on the understanding
are of two kinds. They are either names of things which do not exist (for as
there are things left unnamed through lack of observation, so likewise are there
names which result from fantastic suppositions and to which nothing in reality
corresponds), or they are names of things which exist, but yet confused and
ill-defined, and hastily and irregularly derived from realities. Of the former
kind are Fortune, the Prime Mover, Planetary Orbits, Element of Fire, and like
fictions which owe their origin to false and idle theories. And this class of
idols is more easily expelled, because to get rid of them it is only necessary
that all theories should be steadily rejected and dismissed as obsolete." [Novum
Organum, quoted from
here.]
Except, of course,
these philosophical gems weren't invented by the "vulgar", as Bacon would have
it, but by elite thinkers; the "market-place" in this case would be academia.
However, these days, if you are a
DM-theorist, you just don't raise such awkward questions. You don't
even allow yourself to think them.
For if you do, someone might
call you a
philosophical radical, and then
confuse you with someone who isn't
content merely to re-package in dialectical form yet another lorry load of ruling-class
gobbledygook.3b
Why, you might even be accused of
not "understanding" dialectics!
If thought and
language are intimately
linked, and if ruling-class ideology dominates and shapes the former, it would
seem reasonable to
conclude that alienated boss-class thought would be connected
somehow with the systematic and
ideologically-motivated distortion of language. This is indeed the view that
Marx held:
"[P]hilosophy is nothing else but
religion rendered into thought and expounded by thought, i.e., another form
and manner of existence of the estrangement of the essence of man; hence equally
to be condemned...." [Marx
(1975b), p.381.]
"The philosophers would only
have to dissolve their language into the ordinary language, from which it is
abstracted, to recognise it as the distorted language of the actual world,
and
to realise that neither thoughts nor language in themselves form a realm of
their own, that they are only manifestations of actual life." [Marx
and Engels (1970), p.118. Bold emphasis alone added.]
"The ideas of the
ruling
class are in every epoch the ruling ideas, i.e. the class which is the
ruling material force of society, is at the same time its ruling intellectual
force. The class which has the means of material production at its disposal, has
control at the same time over the means of mental production, so that thereby,
generally speaking, the ideas of those who lack the means of mental production
are subject to it. The ruling ideas are nothing more than the ideal
expression of the dominant material relationships, the dominant material
relationships grasped as ideas; hence of the relationships which make the one
class the ruling one, therefore, the ideas of its dominance. The individuals
composing the ruling class possess among other things consciousness, and
therefore think. Insofar, therefore, as they rule as a class and determine the
extent and compass of an epoch, it is self-evident that they do this in its
whole range, hence among other things rule also as thinkers, as producers of
ideas, and regulate the production and distribution of the ideas of their age:
thus their ideas are the ruling ideas of the epoch...." [Ibid., pp.64-65.
Bold emphases added.]
And,
as Marx pointed out,
distortion and alienation like this doesn't grow or develop in a social and political vacuum.
Ordinary language
is a
social product devised over countless centuries by those who interface daily with the material
world and one another, mediated by cooperative labour; because of its 'lowly'
origin, it has had to endure repeated,
politically-motivated attempts at distortion, denigration and vilification. For present
purposes, however, the most significant of these arose out of, and because of, the nature and
origin of class society.
[The
details behind the transformation of ordinary discourse (at the hands of
Traditional Philosophers) into what effectively became little more than a Secret
Code
will be fully explored in Essays Twelve, Thirteen and Fourteen (summaries
here,
here, and
here).]
However, the point worth emphasising here
is that what had originally been the product of the social relation between human
beings (i.e., ordinary language) was fetishised and transformed into what were
taken to be the real relations between things,
or even those things
themselves. In this way, discourse was endowed with 'magical' power; those
in the grip of this form of linguistic megalomania (outlined in earlier sections) were by these means given alicence to speculate in 'ivory towers', free from the constraints that
social life imposes on us all. [Language "went on holiday", to paraphrase
Wittgenstein.]
If,
according to Traditional Philosophers, the "essential" nature of
'reality'
is inaccessible to experience, then they had to
appeal to the "light of reason", "intuition", "transcendental
arguments", "thought
experiments", and, of course, a surfeit of tailor-made jargon, in order to
reveal its "secrets". Fetishised in this way, language
itself became a surrogate for 'objective reality' -- or, to be more honest,
language was confused with 'reality' astalk about talk was
systematically conflated
with talk about 'things'. Language was thus transformed into an abstract,
magical code; linguistic categories (i.e., all those 'abstractions') were back-projected
onto the world, implying that 'reality' was
now in fact a
reflection of discourse rather than the other
way round. Traditional Philosophy
thus became the well-spring of
LIE,
a doctrine predicated on the idea that if language somehow contains profound truths concerning 'ultimate reality', nature must be fundamentally
linguistic, constituted by the
word of some 'god' or other.
[These ideas will be further developed in
Part Two, but
more extensively in Essay Twelve.]
The above is but a brief sketch of
the nature and provenance of the most abstract forms of ruling-class
ideology -- thought-forms that can be seen to a greater or lesser extent in all
forms of Traditional Philosophy, 'East' and 'West'. These "ruling ideas" rule
largely because they not only serve the interests of each ruling elite, they
also picture the world as that class has always wanted everyone else to see it. For them, a hidden world underlying appearances, governed solely
by 'rational principles', constitutes 'ultimate reality'. If the state
'reflects' this hidden world, or gains its 'legitimacy' from that source, and if the latter is in turn the
creation of some
'god', then the rule of the elite will have been 'legitimated'at the highest level.
Their dominion, their hegemony, is, after all, just one aspect of the 'rational order of reality', as
they saw things -- indeed, as the Apostle
Paul himself put it:
"Let every person be
subordinate to the higher authorities, for there is no authority except from
God, and those that exist have been established by God. Therefore, whoever
resists authority opposes whatever God has appointed, and those who oppose it
will bring judgement upon themselves." [Romans, 13:1-2. Quoted from
here.
Bold emphasis added.]
The rise and fall of different Modes of Production has had no
fundamental effect on these ruling forms-of-thought. For well over two
thousand years this over-arching ideology was
based on
dogmatically imposedconcepts and categories,
which were themselves built upon abstract and increasingly baroque foundations,
all of which amounted to little more than a series of linguistic tricks and
dodges, the results then peremptorily imposed
on reality. In fact, there was no need to impose them overtly on
reality; as we will see, theyconstituted reality. So, instead of
their
ideas reflecting the world, the world reflected their ideas. Traditional
Theorists dictated
to
reality what it must be like and what it must contain.
Despite the many changes in content these strands of ruling-class ideology has undergone as the various forms of
ruling-class power rose and fell, its form has remained remarkably constant throughout.
[Any who think this violates certain principles enshrined in HM should read
this and then perhaps think again.]
Indeed, it will take an
overthrow of ruling-class hegemony and the elimination of class rule before humanity
will finally rid
itself of this alien-class thought-form.
Unfortunately, the traditional approach to knowledge
has found its most fervent supporters and stoutest defenders among those
who should know better:
Dialectical Marxists. [An example
of this supine approach can be found
here (unfortunately, this link is now dead!); others
can be accessed
here and
here.]
Indeed, as we saw in
Essay Two, dialecticians are
only too
happy to concoct a priori theories of their own, imposing them on nature
just like
born-again traditionalists.
Because of that,
ruling-class ideas have extended their "rule", and have now come to dominate Dialectical
Marxism in its entirety.
Of course, allegations like these
require far more support than
the flowery rhetoric rehearsed above or they would be worth considerably less than the computer screen on which
you, dear reader, now view them.
Fortunately, the Essays posted at this site more than take up the slack.
Be this as it may, we
first of all need to: (a) Highlight what is perhaps the original and now major source of the abstract ideas found in
Traditional Thought and DM, (b) Reveal exactly what motivated their invention, and (c)
Expose the disastrous effect
this has had on Dialectical Marxism.
"Thought proceeding from the concrete to the abstract
-- provided
it is correct (NB)… -- does not get away from the truth but comes
closer to it. The abstraction of matter, the law of nature, the
abstraction of value, etc., in short all scientific (correct,
serious, not absurd) abstractions reflect nature more deeply, truly and
completely. From living perception to abstract thought, and from
this to practice, -- such is the dialectical path of cognition of truth,
of the cognition of objective reality." [Lenin (1961), p.171. Italic
emphases in the original.]
"Knowledge
is the reflection of nature by man. But this is not simple, not an immediate,
not a complete reflection, but the process of a series of abstractions, the
formation and development of concepts, laws, etc., and these concepts, laws,
etc., (thought, science = 'the logical Idea') embrace conditionally,
approximately, the universal, law-governed character of eternally moving and
developing nature." [Ibid.,
p.182. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at
this site.]
At first sight, these
passages don't appear to be consistent.
In the first of them Lenin tells his readers that "all truth is concrete, never abstract";
in the second and third he argues that humanity approaches truth viaincreasing
abstraction, and that "all
scientific...abstractions reflect nature more
deeply, truly and completely."
Admittedly, in the second
pair of passages Lenin referred to "practice" as a key component in the "cognition of objective
reality", but that doesn't explain how
"all scientific…abstractions" could possibly "reflect nature more…,
truly", when "truth is always concrete, never abstract" (emphases
added). How can practice reconcile or harmonise a "never" with an "always"?
How
could an abstraction like "All truth is concrete, never abstract"
(emphasis added, again) itself be true?
Of
course, the epistemological theory under-pinning Lenin's thought is a little more
sophisticated than these initial 'inconsistencies' might otherwise intimate. This
suggests
that the resolution of this 'difficulty' might require greater clarity
concerning the meaning of words like "abstract” and "concrete" --
particularly as they are used by dialecticians --, at the very least.
Indeed, it would be unfair to attribute to Lenin a fully-developed theory here
since the above comments appeared in notebooks.
This understanding of "abstract" is somewhat analogous to the traditional,
Rationalist use of the phrase "abstract universal"
(more on that presently) -- but, with
several major
differences.5
Even so, in DM circles this term is clearly linked to the apprehension (by 'Reason'
perhaps?) of general concepts that give expression to, or which capture and
"reflect" common elements connecting, underlying, or instantiated by concrete individuals, bodies or
processes.
But, these general concepts aren't accidentally or 'externally'-connected with these concrete
particulars. That is, there is held to be some sort
of logical or 'internal' connection linking individuals with the 'concept' they
supposedly instantiate, or, even the connections they enjoy with one another. [On this, and the
material posted under next three sub-headings, see also
Appendix B.]
This use of "abstract" emphasises the "one-sided" and "simple"
nature of abstractions, how they are "removed from reality", "cut off",
"separated or divorced from their interconnections", "unchanging", etc. In this case
perhaps, a
subtractive process (involving the mental disregard (abstraction) of
particular features of each item given in experience), or maybe even a
separating exercise
(carried out 'in the mind') also seems to underlie the creation of abstract (general) concepts
for some DM-theorists, given this understanding of the term.
This sense of "concrete" is clearly linked with
AB1
above and appears to involve objects and processes in their individuality (that
is, they are viewed as
individuals of a certain type), often as they are
given in experience, depending on which part of the 'dialectical process of
cognition' they make an appearance.
Again, this contrasts with its twin, AB2,
and emphasises the interconnectedness of objects and processes in
reality (reflected in our theories about them -- these two are often run-together
in DM-circle, as we will see) --, their all-round relationship with, and development alongside,
other objects and processes, as opposed to their separation in non-, or pre-,
dialectical, 'commonsense', 'metaphysical', or 'formal' thought.6
~~~~~~oOo~~~~~~
In the
first of the two passages quoted above, Lenin seems to be
using "abstract" in sense AB2, but in sense
AB1
in the second. This means he must be using "concrete" in sense CON2in the first. These distinctions might help resolve the apparent inconsistency noted
above. Anyway, a clearer picture of these terms as they appear in DM will,
hopefully, emerge as this Essay proceeds.
[Spoiler: no such luck!]
Unfortunately, Lenin only succeeded in
further confusing things when he added:
"Logical concepts are subjective so long as they
remain 'abstract,' in their abstract form, but at the same time they express the
Thing-in-themselves. Nature is both concrete and abstract, both
phenomenon and essence, both moment and relation. Human
concepts are subjective in their abstractness, separateness, but objective as a
whole, in the process, in the sum-total, in the tendency, in the source."
[Lenin
(1961) p.208. Bold emphasis
alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at
this site.]
In this passage, Lenin appears to be using both of these terms
in three of the four (or possibly even all four) ways at once.
Similarly, John Rees argued that:
"[A]ll science generalizes and abstracts from
'empirically verifiable facts.' Indeed, the very
concept of 'fact' is itself an
abstraction, because no one has ever eaten, tasted, smelt, seen or heard a
'fact,' which is a mental generalization that distinguishes actually existing
phenomena from imaginary conceptions. Similarly, all science 'deductively
anticipates' developments -- what else is an hypothesis tested by
experimentation? The dialectic is, among other things, a way of investigating
and understanding the relationship between abstractions and reality. And the 'danger of arbitrary construction' is far greater using an empirical method
which thinks that it is dealing with facts when it is actually dealing with
abstractions than it is with a method that properly distinguishes between the
two and then seeks to explain the relationship between them." [Rees (1998), p.131.
Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]
[One might well wonder how it is
possible to distinguish "abstractions" from "facts" if we are also told "facts"
are "abstractions", let alone how a "mental generalisation" can help
distinguish "actually existing phenomena from imaginary conceptions".]
At the beginning of this passage, Rees appears to be using
"abstract" in sense AB1,
while in the second half he seems to be employing it in sense AB2. In addition,
even though he says that "facts" are "abstraction", it looks like he
is using "fact" in sense CON2 -- when, for example, he claims that
that facts help us discriminate among our beliefs. They could hardly do that
if they were disconnected from other facts.
But,
who can say? None of these ideas have been worked out with satisfactory clarity, detail
or consistency by
DM-theorists, as the first two Parts of Essay Three will show.
[The above
passage from Rees (1998) will be analysed in more detail in Essay Twelve Part Four (when it is unpublished).]
Nevertheless, the loose and ill-defined way these terms are
employed in DM-circles mirrors Hegel's own obscure and inconsistent use.7
For
example, if abstractions are divorced from reality, cut-off and separated from
other things, how might they be employed to interconnect concrete objects
and processes in nature, as Lenin argued? And, if "concrete" objects and processes
are interconnected with everything, what makes them anything in
particular? What individuates, say, a photon? If all
photons are
identical (and on some accounts, they are unchanging, too), and interconnected (in
the abstract?), then what right have we to label them individuals or
even
particulars?8Depicted this way, photons (but not just photons) look pretty abstract.
Moreover, they appear to refute
Engels's, Trotsky's
and Hegel's a priori caveats about identity, as well as their ideas about change -- if,
that is, each photons is on an individual basis deemed "concrete".
Moreover,
according to Lenin,
objects and processes only become
"concrete" when they are interconnected with everything else in
existence (and then perhaps even beyond):
"The gist of his theoretical mistake in this
case is substitution of eclecticism for the dialectical interplay of politics
and economics (which we find in Marxism). His theoretical attitude is: 'on the
one hand, and on the other', 'the one and the other'. That is eclecticism.
Dialectics requires an all-round consideration of relationships in their
concrete development but not a patchwork of bits and pieces. I have shown
this to be so on the example of politics and economics....
"A tumbler is assuredly both a glass cylinder and
a drinking vessel. But there are more than these two properties, qualities or
facets to it; there are an infinite number of them, an infinite number of
'mediacies' and inter-relationships with the rest of the world.... Formal logic, which is as far as schools go (and
should go, with suitable abridgements for the lower forms), deals with formal
definitions, draws on what is most common, or glaring, and stops there. When two
or more different definitions are taken and combined at random (a glass cylinder
and a drinking vessel), the result is an eclectic definition which is indicative
of different facets of the object, and nothing more.
"Dialectical logic demands that we should
go further. Firstly, if we are to have a true knowledge of an object we must
look at and examine all its facets, its connections and 'mediacies'. That is
something we cannot ever hope to achieve completely, but the rule of
comprehensiveness is a safeguard against mistakes and rigidity. Secondly,
dialectical logic requires that an object should be taken in development,
in change, in 'self-movement' (as Hegel sometimes puts it). This is not
immediately obvious in respect of such an object as a tumbler, but it, too, is
in flux, and this holds especially true for its purpose, use and connection
with the surrounding world. Thirdly, a full 'definition' of an object must
include the whole of human experience, both as a criterion of truth and a
practical indicator of its connection with human wants. Fourthly, dialectical
logic holds that 'truth is always concrete, never abstract', as the late
Plekhanov liked to say after Hegel...." [Lenin
(1921), pp.90-93. Bold emphases alone added;
quotation marks altered to conform with conventions adopted at this site. Some
paragraphs merged.]
However,
if supposedly 'concrete' objects and processes are to count as "objective",
or even concrete, they must already be interconnected in reality
before any sentient being even attempted to so relate them. Or are we
to suppose that the status of each 'concrete' object has to wait on some human
being to designate them such before they are actually concrete? Does this mean
that the Sun, for example, wasn't 'concrete' until a human being capable of
cognising it in a dialectical sort of way decided it was 'concrete'? Perhaps
there are 'subjective concrete object and processes' just as there are
'objective concrete objects and processes'? If so, one might well wonder what
work the word "concrete" is actually doing. More to the point, what is
there in reality that could
possibly do all this relating and interconnecting, especially before sentient
life evolved?8a
Are there non-physical links of the same kind between objects that somehow
unerringly manage to locate, interconnect, and then collect together every
single member of a given group, category, set, or class in the entire universe,
like some sort of super-efficient bloodhound? A sort of universal 'metaphysical
net' that never misses, skips or omits a single one? And when an object of one
category
changes into another, are the inter-galactic links which that object enjoys with
other objects of that kind that are altered, or maybe severed, perhaps
instantaneously, which allow it to be inter-linked with all the other objects
of the new kindit has now developed into, everywhere across the
universe, instantaneously,
too? Or, is there some sort of delay as nature 'tries to catch up'?
If
none of these is the case, then by what right have we to classify such
objects and processes as 'concrete' if there is no 'objective' matters-of-fact here that
collect them into the correct group, category or class, in the first place? If they objectively
belong to such groups, categories or classes, they must have done so before a
single human being thought about them -- as indeed, Lenin opined:
"To be a materialist is to acknowledge objective truth, which is revealed
to us by our sense-organs. To acknowledge objective truth, i.e., truth not
dependent upon man and mankind, is, in one way or another, to recognise absolute
truth." [Lenin (1972),
p.148.]
So,
the question returns: Exactly what was it that collected such objects and
processes in the right sortal classes or groups before we evolved? No good
looking to DM-fans for an answer; they haven't even asked that
question, nor anything even remotely like it!
Apparently, posing such questions makes you 'pedantic'.
[I return to this topic in
Part Two.
I deal with Lenin's comments about Alizarin dye in Essay Thirteen
Part
One. Independently of that, although Lenin argues that the existence
of this dye is "objective" he nowhere asks the above questions about it
-- or even,
given his own strictures, how can this dye be
deemed "objective" before all its interconnections with the rest of the universe
had been established? His faithful echoes also fail to consider such annoying
'pedantries', too.]
Of course, human beings might not
at present know what all these interconnections are, or even be aware of
most of them; but,
as we have just seen, according to Lenin humanity will neverknow what they are. In that case, it seems that the objects they
inter-link will never become either concrete or objective for us.
If that is so, how can anyone conclude anything about a single one of them in
the here-and-now? Whatever is said about these alleged interconnections -- as
well as these supposed
'concrete' particulars -- will be infinitely far from the truth and must
therefore stand almost zero probability of being
correct.8b
It could be objected that these complaints are,
at best, academic, at worst, thoroughly misguided. The four senses
of "abstract" and "concrete"
outlined above (if there are
indeed four) shouldn't be thought of as separate or distinct, as seems to be the
assumption motivating this Essay. They must be understood "dialectically".
Or, so it might be
maintained.
But, as with other key DM-concepts, it is difficult to make
sense of what its theorists could possibly be saying here (that is, should they
offer the above
reply), nor is it easy to form a clear idea of what they might conceivably mean when they
use words like "concrete", "abstract" and "dialectical". This isn't to
suggest that DM-theorists have put little effort into writing about these terms
-- far from it --, but much of
what has been published by them on this issue is about as clear as the
Athanasian Creed.9
Hence, the employment here of yet another example of quasi-Hegelian jargon
(i.e., "dialectical") in no way helps. Indeed, the way it is used by
DM-supporters more than suggests this word works like a magic wand; wave
it about enough times and any old ideas, no matter how unclear or confused they
might happen to be,
can be miraculously transformed into ideas blessed with crystal clarity.
[I have quoted numerous DM-theorists heroically trying to explain their
ideas on this subject in
Appendix B, as well as
here and
here,
and in Part Two
(here
and
here).]
Anyway, one thing seems reasonably plain: the generalisations
dialecticians advance (in connection with the use of these terms)
aren't basedon any
sort of evidence. After all, to what might a single DM-fan point
or appeal? Hence, what is there here for a
consistent materialist
to
agree with? To be sure, for an Idealist, like Hegel, all this makes some sort of
crazy sense, but how might we make any sort of physical sense of it?
Since these notions (i.e., "abstract" and "concrete") can't be read from nature
(although Hegelians and some DM-theorists might claim otherwise), the
only conclusion is that they must have been foisted on it. In fact, not
only were these two categories invented by non-Marxists --
and non-working class theorists, at that -- but dialecticians have been only too eager to
appropriate them, selectivelyimposing
them on reality in like manner.
[It is
clearly impossible to derive either of these two notions from nature,
or from any amount of evidence -- as will be argued in Part Two of this
Essay (link above).]
Of course, dialecticians
notionally follow Hegel, here -- but they
then proceed to ignore the material flip that they say they have performed on his system
(in order to put it back on its feet, or the "right way up"). This can be
seen by the way that they not only view
abstractions in the same
rationalist light as Hegel, they employ many of the same
'arguments' he and other Idealists use.
Or to be a little more honest, they have
uncritically swallowed Hegel's sub-Aristotelian
logical blunders.
In the past, and even before the
evidence that we now possess even existed, Traditional Philosophers
made a conscious
decision to invent and then use abstract concepts in order to force
'knowledge' in certain favoured directions.9a
We now
know who made those choices, and they manifestly weren't
individuals known
for their lack of support for ruling-class priorities; indeed, they were
made by Idealists, ideologues, theologians and
Hermetic
Mystics.
Here, for example, is Hegel (a 'theorist' not known for his socialist
sympathies):
"To say 'This rose is red'
involves (in virtue of the copula 'is') the coincidence of subject and
predicate. The rose however is a concrete thing, and so is not red only: it has
also an odour, a specific form, and many other features not implied in the
predicate red. The predicate on its part is an abstract universal, and
does not apply to the rose alone. There are other flowers and other objects
which are red too. The subject and predicate in the immediate judgment touch, as
it were, only in a single point, but do not cover each other.... In pronouncing
an action to be good, we frame a notional judgment. Here, as we at once
perceive, there is a closer and a more intimate relation than in the immediate
judgment. The predicate in the latter is some abstract quality which may or
may not be applied to the subject. In the judgment of the notion the
predicate is, as it were, the soul of the subject, by which the subject, as the
body of this soul, is characterised through and through." [Hegel
(1975), p.237, §172. Bold emphases added.]
Naturally, this only
serves to underline the claim made above (and in
Essay Two) that
subsequent dialecticians haven't broken with this conservative philosophical
tradition. In fact, they
have been only too happy to appropriate, defend and disseminate this dogmatic approach
to knowledge, as well as trumpet
its ruling-class origin. Here is Lenin doing just that:
"The history of philosophy and the history of
social science show with perfect clarity that there is nothing resembling
'sectarianism' in Marxism, in the sense of its being a hidebound, petrified
doctrine, a doctrine which arose away from the high road of the
development of world civilisation. On the contrary, the genius of Marx consists
precisely in his having furnished answers to questions already raised by the
foremost minds of mankind. His doctrine emerged as the direct and immediate
continuation of the teachings of the greatest representatives of
philosophy, political economy and socialism. The Marxist doctrine is omnipotent because it is true. It is comprehensive
and harmonious, and provides men with an integral world outlook irreconcilable
with any form of superstition, reaction, or defence of bourgeois oppression. It
is the legitimate successor to the best that man produced in the nineteenth
century, as represented by German philosophy, English political economy and
French socialism." [Lenin,
Three Sources
and Component Parts of Marxism. Bold emphases alone
added; paragraphs merged.]
[TAR = The Algebra Of Revolution, i.e.,
Rees (1998).]
Worse still, both
of these terms (i.e., "abstract" and "concrete") appear to be abstract themselves.
Neither would pass, for example,
TAR's 'gastronomic test': "no one has ever
eaten, tasted, smelt, seen or heard" either of these 'concepts'. [Rees
(1998), p.131.] To be sure, when vocalised or committed to paper these
two words are
material objects in their own right, but that fact alone can't ground 'the
content' of either of them in
the material world,
nor can it legitimate their use. If it
could, we should all have to start believing in "God" just as
soon as that word had been spoken aloud or written down somewhere.
Far
worse than that: according to
Lenin it now seems that no one couldeven "eat (etc.)" a single concrete
object:
"But there are more than these two properties and
qualities or facets to [any material object]; there are an infinite number of
them, an infinite number of 'mediacies' and inter-relationships with the rest of
the world….
[I]f we are to have true knowledge of an object
we must look at and examine all its facets, its connections and 'mediacies'.
That is something we cannot ever hope to achieve completely…. [D]ialectical
logic requires that an object should be taken in development, in change, in
'self-movement' (as Hegel sometimes puts it). This is not immediately obvious in
respect of such an object as a tumbler, but it, too, is in flux, and this holds
especially true for its purpose, use and connection with the surrounding
world." [Lenin (1921),
pp.92-93. Italic emphases in the original;
paragraphs merged.]
If
not even an everyday tumbler is concrete unless it has
been set
against, and then interlinked with, an "infinite number of mediacies", who is there alive that could swear truthfully
that a tumbler is in fact concrete? Assuming these connections are
"infinite", then no matter how many interconnections we
set up for it, there will always be an infinite number still left to connect,
leaving any judgement we make about it stranded infinitely far from the truth with an
infinitely high probability of being false.
[The response that only 'relevant' connections should be
considered in this regard has been batted out of the park
in Essay Ten Part One,
here.]
Clearly, whatever applies to tumblers applies
equally well to things we
think we can eat; perhaps they aren't concrete, either? In that case, TAR's 'gastronomic,
touchy-feely test' fails to pick out even concrete
objects! If so, how it can be used to test whether something is 'abstract' or
'concrete', or distinguish the one from the other, is far from clear, to say the least.
Of course, it could be argued that whether we know it or
not, concrete objects are still concrete for all that. But are they? Who says?
And where is the infinite body of knowledge which would be needed to
substantiate a 'cosmically' bold (abstract) claim such as that?
Moreover,
if Lenin is right that "all truth is concrete,
never abstract", then the abstract claim that "whether we know it or not,
concrete objects are still concrete" can't itself be true.
Such are
the 'consolations' of 'dialectics'.
For
example: Is, say, the apple you might pluck from a tree or buy in a shop
now actually interconnected with everything in reality? Lest an
impatient dialectician is tempted to snap back a hasty "Yes, of course it is!"
in response to such an impertinent question, it is worth pointing out that that fact (if it
is one) could never itself be confirmed, but must either be imposed on the said
apple or accepted as an article of faith.
In that case, whatever it is that
dialecticians now claim they know about allegedly concrete objects (like
that apple) must, it seems,
be foisted on them, too, since no one at present would or
could ever be justified in calling anything
"concrete" unless they had pointed to the infinite number of
"mediacies" Lenin insisted were required to that end, or had actually gathered that amount of evidence in support of
such a hyper-bold contention:
"But there are more than these two properties and
qualities or facets to [any material object]; there are an infinite number of
them, an infinite number of 'mediacies' and inter-relationships with the rest of
the world…. [I]f we are to have true knowledge of an object we must look at and examine
all its facets, its connections and 'mediacies'. That is something we cannot
ever hope to achieve completely…." [Ibid., bold added.]
Do we havethis much information about apples?
Could
we cope with it even if we had?
Again, if Lenin were right that "all truth is concrete, never abstract", then the
abstract claim that the aforementioned apple is "actually interconnected with everything
in reality" can't itself be true -- whenever it is asserted this
side of the completion of the above infinitary task.
[This topic is discussed
in greater detail in Essays
Two, Ten
Part One, Eleven Parts
One and
Two,
and Thirteen
Part One.]
As has already been pointed out, both of these words (i.e.,
"abstract" and "concrete") are time-honoured, philosophical terms-of-art, invented by thinkers
intent on
'justifying' and rationalising the status quo, or the world-view upon
which their patrons' hegemony was predicated. However, it is plain that even though these two
words have
since become highly clichéd by their over-use, DM-theorists uncritically appropriated them
simply because they found them in Hegel's work (or the work of some other
Traditional Theorist), and, apparently,for no other reason.
In like manner,
Hegel employed them simply because of their status as entries in the
Idealist Philosophers' Phrase Book.
Even
worse
still,
and as far as can be ascertained, no attempt has ever been made by DM-theorists to
show precisely how a single abstract 'concept' can be derived
from, or even be seenin, concrete particulars -- or from anywhere else,
for that matter --
other than, of course, by importing that idea from
Hegel
and Traditional Thought.
Nor is this surprising; no one has been able to
demonstrate how this miraculous trick is humanly possible. To
be sure, theorists have dreamt-up countless abstract terms over the centuries,
and muttered various incantations over them as they were recruited into Traditional
Philosophical discourse, but
materialists should be no more impressed with verbal gymnastics like this than they are with
those that supposedly support belief in God.
[This topic
will be discussed in more
detail in Part Two of this Essay,
where it will be shown that the above controversial claims aren't just empty
rhetoric.]
And yet, for all that, it is possible to show that these
mythical beasts of lore, these 'abstractions', actually emerged out of rather more mundane, historically-specific,
social and political causes,
not the result of an 'inner, mental process of abstraction' --, causes that were in fact
motivated by the ideological priorities of our ancient class enemies.10
Anyway, and despite this, what we actually find in
DM-circles in place of evidence and supporting argument are
vague attempts at justification; these wafer thin DM-rationalisations will be examined
extensively in what follows, and in subsequent
Essays.
This means that the entire edifice of DM-epistemology has been built
on alarmingly insubstantial foundations --
in fact, as we are about to find out, these 'foundations' are all sand and no
concrete.11
In
the previous section, it was alleged that the origin and provenance of 'abstract
concepts' renders them more than highly suspect. This sub-section and the rest of this
Essay will
examine those seemingly rash allegations a little more closely.
Consider once again Lenin's attempt to specify what our knowledge
of a particular object consists in:
"[I]f we are to have true knowledge of an
object we must look at and examine all its facets, its connections and
'mediacies'. That is something we cannot ever hope to achieve completely, but
the rule of comprehensiveness is a safeguard against mistakes and rigidity…."
[Lenin (1921),
p.93.]
Hence, according to Lenin, a fuller and more complete understanding of any particular
must involve a consideration of its wider, perhaps law-governed connections with other
particulars, other processes. Unfortunately, this is a strategy we will soon find there is good
reason to question.
The first serious problem this passage faces is that
these ever-widening 'law-governed' connections must themselves involve the use of general
terms (or "abstractions" -- in sense
AB1)
right from the start. In that case, it seems that the dialectical
process of cognition can't even begin.
It could be replied that the above
objection is spurious, since, according to
TAR knowledge actually starts
with:
"…an abstraction from the inessential and
accidental features of reality to grasp more clearly its key features…. Constant
empirical work is therefore essential to renew both the concrete analyses and
the dialectical concepts that are generalized from these analyses." [Rees
(1998),
p.110.]
This suggests that law-governed generalisations are themselves integral
to dialectics. That is because human knowledge has:
"[Brought] to it a framework composed of our past
experiences; what we have learned of others' experience, both in the present and
in the past; and of our later reflections on and theories about this
experience…. Concepts and theories are necessary to interpret the world."
[Ibid., p.63.]
As dialecticians themselves tend to argue: a reference to (and use of) general terms ('concepts'?) in the pursuit of
knowledge is also required since neither science nor dialectics can rely solely on
"surface appearances" or "immediate experience". The idea seems to be that while the latter might relate to,
or temporarily shape,
our initial view of things, philosophical and scientific knowledge both seek to locate
and integrate nature's underlying law-governed "essences" by the use of further and more
refined abstractions (or generalisations), subsequently tested in practice.
These
ideas can be found in Marx's expressed opinions, too:
"[S]cience would be superfluous if the outward
appearance and the essence of things directly coincided." [Marx (1981),
p.956.]
"It would seem right to start with the real and concrete, with the actual
presupposition, e.g. in political economy to start with the population, which
forms the basis and the subject of the whole social act of production. Closer
consideration shows, however, that this is wrong. Population is an
abstraction if, for instance, one disregards the classes of which it is composed.
These classes in turn remain an empty phrase if one does not know the elements
on which they are based, e.g. wage labour, capital, etc. These presuppose
exchange, division of labour, prices, etc. For example, capital is nothing
without wage labour, without value, money, price, etc. If one were to start
with population, it would be a chaotic conception of the whole, and through
closer definition one would arrive analytically at increasingly simple concepts;
from the imagined concrete, one would move to more and more tenuous abstractions
until one arrived at the simplest determinations. From there it would be
necessary to make a return journey until one finally arrived once more at
population, which this time would be not a chaotic conception of a whole, but a
rich totality of many determinations and relations.
"The first course is the one taken by political economy historically at its
inception. The 17th-century economists, for example, always started with the
living whole, the population, the nation, the State, several States, etc.,
but analysis always led them in the end to the discovery of a few determining
abstract, general relations, such as division of labour, money, value, etc.
As soon as these individual moments were more or less clearly deduced and
abstracted, economic systems were evolved which from the simple [concepts], such
as labour, division of labour, need, exchange value, advanced to the State,
international exchange and world market.
"The
latter is obviously the correct scientific method. The concrete is
concrete because it is a synthesis of many determinations, thus a unity of the
diverse. In thinking, it therefore appears as a process of summing-up, as a
result, not as the starting point, although it is the real starting point, and
thus also the starting point of perception and conception. The first
procedure attenuates the comprehensive visualisation to abstract determinations,
the second leads from abstract determinations by way of thinking to the
reproduction of the concrete.
"Hegel accordingly arrived at the illusion that the real was the result of
thinking synthesising itself within itself, delving ever deeper into itself and
moving by its inner motivation; actually, the method of advancing from the
abstract to the concrete is simply the way in which thinking assimilates the
concrete and reproduces it as a mental concrete. This is, however, by no
means the process by which the concrete itself originates. For example, the
simplest economic category, e.g. exchange value, presupposes population,
population which produces under definite conditions, as well as a distinct type
of family, or community, or State, etc. Exchange value cannot exist except as an
abstract, one-sided relation of an already existing concrete living whole.
"But as a category exchange value leads an antediluvian existence. Hence to the
kind of consciousness -- and philosophical consciousness is precisely of this
kind -- which regards the comprehending mind as the real man, and only the
comprehended world as such as the real world -- to this consciousness,
therefore, the movement of categories appears as the real act of production --
which unfortunately receives an impulse from outside -- whose result is the
world; and this (which is however again a tautology) is true in so far as the
concrete totality regarded as a conceptual totality, as a mental concretum, is
IN FACT a product of thinking, of comprehension; yet it is by no means a product
of the self-evolving concept whose thinking proceeds outside and above
perception and conception, but of the assimilation and transformation of
perceptions and images into concepts. The totality as a conceptual totality
seen by the mind is a product of the thinking mind, which assimilates the world
in the only way open to it, a way which differs from the artistic-, religious-
and practical-intellectual assimilation of this world. The real subject remains
outside the mind and independent of it -- that is to say, so long as the mind
adopts a purely speculative, purely theoretical attitude. Hence the subject,
society, must always be envisaged as the premiss of conception even when the
theoretical method is employed.
"But have not these simple categories also an independent historical or natural
existence preceding that of the more concrete ones? Ça dépend. [That
depends -- RL.] Hegel, for example, correctly takes possession, the simplest
legal relation of the subject, as the point of departure of the philosophy of
law. No possession exists, however, before the family or the relations of lord
and servant are evolved, and these are much more concrete relations. It
would, on the other hand, be correct to say that families and entire tribes
exist which have as yet only possession and not property. The simpler category
appears thus as a relation of simpler family or tribal associations with regard
to property. In a society which has reached a higher stage the category appears
as the simpler relation of a developed organisation. The more concrete
substratum underlying the relation of possession is, however, always presupposed.
One can conceive an individual savage who has possessions; possession in this
case, however, is not a legal relation. It is incorrect that historically
possession develops into the family. On the contrary, possession always
presupposes this 'more concrete legal category'. Still, one may say that the
simple categories express relations in which the less developed concrete may
have realised itself without as yet having posited the more complex connection
or relation which is conceptually expressed in the more concrete category;
whereas the more developed concrete retains the same category as a subordinate
relation.
"Money can exist and has existed in history before capital, banks, wage labour,
etc., came into being. In this respect it can be said, therefore, that the
simpler category can express relations predominating in a less developed whole
or subordinate relations in a more developed whole, relations which already
existed historically before the whole had developed the aspect expressed in a
more concrete category. To that extent, the course of abstract thinking which
advances from the elementary to the combined corresponds to the actual
historical process." [Marx
(1986), pp.37-39. (This links to a PDF.) Bold emphases alone added.
capitals in the original. Quotation marks altered to conform with the
conventions adopted at this site. This passage will be examine in more detail in
Part Two.]12
"Beginnings are always difficult in all sciences. To understand the first
chapter, especially the section that contains the analysis of commodities, will,
therefore, present the greatest difficulty. That which concerns more especially
the analysis of the substance of value and the magnitude of value, I have, as
much as it was possible, popularised. The value-form, whose fully developed
shape is the money-form, is very elementary and simple. Nevertheless, the human
mind has for more than 2,000 years sought in vain to get to the bottom of it
all, whilst on the other hand, to the successful analysis of much more composite
and complex forms, there has been at least an approximation. Why? Because the
body, as an organic whole, is more easy of study than are the cells of that
body. In the analysis of economic forms, moreover, neither microscopes nor
chemical reagents are of use.
The force of abstraction must replace both.
But in bourgeois society, the commodity-form of the product of labour -- or
value-form of the commodity -- is the economic cell-form. To the superficial
observer, the analysis of these forms seems to turn upon minutiae. It does in
fact deal with minutiae, but they are of the same order as those dealt with in
microscopic anatomy." [Marx
(1996), pp.7-8. Bold emphasis added. I have modified the first
sentence to agree with the Penguin edition since it reads much better.]
This appears to mean that while scientists,
and/or dialecticians, might have to begin
with what look like concrete particulars given in experience (albeit understood indeterminately, at first), in order to
gain genuine knowledge, or even 'relative truth', they must apply certain, perhaps specific
abstract concepts to the phenomena (maybe deploying those that have been
inherited from the work of previous generations -- or those that have been 'critically
re-formulated' from whatever resources that are available) in order to interconnect, and
hence account for, phenomena with increasing accuracy in a more all-rounded,
determinate and "concrete" manner.
Or
perhaps even better: scientists and dialecticians should begin
with abstract concepts (or "frameworks)" and apply them to the phenomena in
order to interconnect, and hence account for, objects and processes with
increasing accuracy in a more all-rounded, determinate manner -- albeit, tested
in practice. As Marx put it,
the correct method would lead: "from abstract determinations by way of
thinking to the reproduction of the concrete." [Marx (1986),
p.38.]
Moreover,
except perhaps at the very beginning of human 'consciousness', this process
never actually starts from scratch (as it were); we use the gains of
previous generations to assist in the advancement of knowledge. But, even
this isn't sufficient; abstractions have continually to be referred back
to the material world so that they can be tested against additional experience in
order to be refined in
practice (etc.). Even though human beings inherit generalisations, concepts and categories
(abstractions) from the past, all of them are revisable
in the light of novel experience, knowledge and practical activity. This
process of revision constantly shapes and contours the never-ending search for
understanding, achieving a different expression in each
Mode of Production, but reaching its pinnacle, one presumes, in a fully
socialist society.
This appears to be the import of Lenin's words (quoted earlier):
"Thought proceeding from the concrete to the abstract
-- provided
it is correct (NB)… -- does not get away from the truth but comes
closer to it. The abstraction of matter, the law of nature, the
abstraction of value, etc., in short all scientific (correct,
serious, not absurd) abstractions reflect nature more deeply, truly and
completely. From living perception to abstract thought, and from
this to practice, -- such is the dialectical path of cognition of truth,
of the cognition of objective reality." [Lenin (1961), p.171. Italic
emphases in the original.]
"Knowledge
is the reflection of nature by man. But this is not simple, not an immediate,
not a complete reflection, but the process of a series of abstractions, the
formation and development of concepts, laws, etc., and these concepts, laws,
etc., (thought, science = 'the logical Idea') embrace conditionally,
approximately, the universal, law-governed character of eternally moving and
developing nature." [Ibid.,
p.182. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at
this site.]
Indeed, the above passage looks like an embellishment of Marx's
own thoughts quoted a few paragraphs further back.
Again, these
extra comments look as if they might help resolve the apparent inconsistency noted
earlier on. Hence, it is
now a little clearer what the dialectical search for knowledge (via the
interplay between abstraction and practice) consists in -- it seem it must include one or more of the
following
considerations:
(1) The search for knowledge must begin at some point with a
practical (or in some cases a theoretical)
interface with the world, interpreted by means of general concepts
(abstractions) inherited
from previous generations, or fashioned as the need arises.
(2) From there onwards further abstract
general ideas must be extracted from experience, or refined, borrowed, applied,
deduced, critically constructed or modified by thought (depending on which
'dialectical' theory of abstraction one adheres to!). Used correctly, abstractions help
reflect, represent and explain, with increasing accuracy, the essential features
that underlie the surface appearances of nature and
society --, but only if they are continually tested in practice. In order to do
this, general and perhaps poorly understood abstractions must be broken down into their
simpler parts, which, when they have been understood aright, must be re-combined,
or re-assembled, so
that the original abstraction is no longer a chaotic whole, but "a rich totality
of many determinations and relations."
(3) To that end, newer abstractions must be
introduced to
re-interpret or theoretical process any novel processes, structures, particulars or relations (maybe as each
new mode of production arises, or as the class war throws them up), which as a
result will mean that the latter will be more
fully understood because they will now be far richer in content since they are
much more widely interconnected,
and hence more concrete.
(4) Every stage must be checked
against reality, as part of revolutionary and/or scientific practice; all traces of ruling-class ideology must be exposed and
removed.
(5) Whatever emerges as a result must always be
regarded as tentative and subject to further revision.
(6) As a result, absolute truth is only ever a theoretical goal,
never an actual terminus.
Viewed in this way -- it we ignore much that has gone before in this Essay -- what Lenin said appears
to be correct (in its own terms): all truth is concrete, not abstract. That is because all
knowledge-claims must constantly interface with concrete reality, more and more
widely understood, against an increasingly well comprehended, law-governed background.
However, further truths (or, rather, newer,
more refined concepts
that
are closer to the truth, or even less 'relatively true', which in turn
will allow further concrete truths to be
discovered, developed or enriched) can only be shaped, discovered or grasped by means of wider abstractions that
refine and correct previous sets of concrete concepts (by removing/resolving any contradictions,
etc., that they might still contain or imply). This seemingly endless process helps reveal deeper and broader interconnections, making
such truths ever more concrete, which yields a more all-round picture of objective
reality (but, once again, only if the results are continually tested in practice).
In this light, it now looks as if Lenin was
right (in terms of his view of 'the materialist dialectic') to emphasise both the abstract and
concrete nature of scientific truth. The "dialectical interplay" between the abstract and the concrete -- here
only superficially outlined (much has been omitted; more details are
given in
Appendix B) -- constitutes the
central core of the DM-theory of knowledge, as Lenin and others see things.
Materialist dialectics stands -- or falls -- with it.
The above comments seem, therefore, to resolve
an apparent incongruity
noted earlier.
The problem is that, despite the fanfare,
the DM-juggernaut can't
actually get
rolling, since it soon turns out it has no engine, diesel or battery!
The
reason why the dialectical juggernaut can't even begin to roll is
connected with answers that might be given to the following rather surprising questions:
(a) What if it should turn out that
instead of beginning with abstract general terms in order to help refine experience
along the lines outlined
earlier,
dialecticians without exception actually start with a set of
abstract particulars -- or
they begin with terms that turn out to be the Proper Names of these abstract particulars?
(b)
What if dialecticians then attempt to advance from there by the use of
yet more abstract particulars and they only ever end up with abstract particulars?
(c)
What if general terms actually appear nowhere in the entire process?
(d) What if no concrete particular or process is ever actually the resultant?
As
should seem obvious, an unhelpful answer to these four questions would
only increase the suspicion that DM can't account for knowledge since generality will
have been abstracted away, even destroyed, as a result; and if
that is so, not only would DM-epistemology have run off the road and into a
ditch, scientific knowledge would be in there with it.
[In
this sub-section I first summarise the argument that attempts to show
how the aforementioned "destruction of generality" came about; much of the rest of this Essay
will fill in the details.]
Readers sympathetic to DM
might be forgiven for thinking that the above allegations are completely
misguided; dialecticians certainly donot do this. They
don't remain stuck in an abstract, 'particularist' rut, as the earlier comments insinuate.12a
Nevertheless, as will soon become apparent, the process of
abstraction, far from assisting in the discovery of knowledge concerning the 'essential'
features of reality that underpin 'appearances', actually prevents that
search from
even starting. It does this by transforming general words/concepts into singularterms -- that is, it turns them into the Proper Names of 'abstract' ideas,
categories or concepts.12b
If that is
indeed so, the claim that DM begins with the general in order to
interpret the particular is the opposite of the truth.
In fact, what really happens is that DM-theorists begin with the
Proper Names
of abstract particulars (which
terms they inherited from previous generations of
Traditional Theorists, like Plato, Aristotle,
Plotinus, Aquinas, Descartes, Leibniz, Kant and Hegel,
to name just a few); they then
make a ham-fisted attempt to link these with the Proper Names of
genuinely material
particulars (such as that
tumbler that
exercised Lenin), all the while failing to notice that generality went out the
non-dialectical window a couple of thousand years ago.
It is this
ancient muddle that stalls the DM-juggernaut on the
starting grid.
That
initial false step finds DM-theorists -- following
on Hegel's example -- re-interpreting sentences containing subject and predicate (general) terms
as disguised identity statements.
Because of this,
DM-apologists begin by eliminating the general terms they claimed were
necessary in order to refine or interpret particulars given in experience -- which
moves we were told were essential if anyone wants to loop the very first dialectical loop --, replacing them with the
Proper Names of
'abstract objects'. Naturally, this just leaves them
with a
handful of lifeless singular terms.
Again, they do this by
re-writing predicative sentences as propositions that express identity; it is
this move that transforms the general terms they contain into the aforementioned
Proper Names (or other singular terms).13
Hence, as we will soon see, "man", for instance, is turned into the
Proper Name, "Man"; "is
the same as" is transformed into the Proper Name, "Identity"; "is not the same as"
now becomes the Proper Name, "Difference";
everyone in a given society becomes the singular term, "The Population", and so on.
The
result of false steps like this doubles back, completely undermining DM-epistemology, so that instead of beginning
with the general to account for the particular, DM-theorists use the
Proper Names of abstract particulars (i.e., the Proper Names of abstract
classes, groups, universals, categories, 'essences' or 'concepts') to account
for what are supposed to be concrete particulars -- an impossible task even in its own terms.
Naturally, this explains
the need for all the increasingly baroque and labyrinthineattempts to explain the "process of cognition"
we find in books and articles on dialectics; they can't fail to be convoluted because of the intractable
pseudo-problem with which dialecticians began. [Why
it is a pseudo-problem will soon become apparent.]14
DM-theorists
weren't, of course, the first to have erred in this
respect; indeed, this fault runs right through Traditional Epistemology, from
Ancient Greece right down to today. Its ubiquity is easily explained since it
seems that these false moves and what caused them were impossibly difficult to spot.
Well..., not really:
they were in fact staring us in the face
-- and have been for over two thousand years!
But,
for all the attention Traditional
Theorists (and now dialecticians) have paid to it one would be forgiven for thinking these
moves were
well-hidden. In fact, DM-adepts continue to ignore them -- even after they have been
brought to their attention!
As
will be demonstrated presently, several familiar and everyday features of language
must
be wilfully ignored, distorted or reconfigured to make this traditional
con-trick work. What had been in full-view all along -- the everyday use of
general terms in ordinary language, invented by those who don't tend to make such crass
mistakes (i.e., working people) --
highly educated individuals manage to overlook, confuse or deliberately misconstrue.
And they have been doing this for over two thousand years. Indeed, the 'higher' the dialectician, the more likely
they are to follow Traditional Theorists down this linguistic cul-de-sac -- and the more
inured to their errors these hapless victims appear to be.
[Concerning
the different 'levels' in the dialectical pecking order, see
here.]
As noted above (and as will be demonstrated in Essay Twelve
(summary
here
and
here)) these moves were invented by Ancient Greek theorists. In that case, dialecticians
have found
themselves in bad company; and, as they should know, bad associations spoil
useful
epistemological habits.
It is ironic, therefore, that in order to account for concrete
particulars (by the use of general terms), this inept dialectical segue
has meant that
general terms feature nowhere at all in their theory!
Hence, in the search for scientific knowledge, all that dialecticians have
available to them
are two different types of particulars (or the Proper Names thereof): 'the
abstract' and 'the concrete'. Of course, the latter of the two, 'the
concrete', is now left without
the general background that had all along been touted for it; that is because
the newly fashioned context
has been transformed into a series of particulars, too.15
Hence, the DM-juggernaut not only lacks a starter motor (i.e., it
is devoid of general
terms), its fuel tank is empty and its way
has also been blocked by a huge slab of concrete.
The rest of this Essay is aimed at explaining, and
then substantiating, these
seemingly wild allegations.
In order to justify the above
controversial claims, it is important to see
how and why such a re-write of predicative sentences goes badly wrong, and why it can't work even after running repairs have
been attempted.
As we
will soon find out, the answer to these and other questions is connected
with:
Although DM-epistemology supposedly begins with the general in
order to qualify and refine each particular, the way that dialecticians frame
their theory in fact denies it the capacity to do either.
Before my entirely novel criticism of DM can begin we must once
again make a slight detour, and it is one that will introduce a method of analysis that will look
rather odd to those unfamiliar with
Analytic Philosophy
and Modern Logic. However, its
superiority over traditional methods of analysis will emerge soon enough; the reader's
indulgence is therefore requested, once more.
[Those not
particularly interested in the minutiae of my argument might prefer to skip the next sub-section and begin
again here. However,
several
points that will be made later on (as well as those in other Essays published at this site) might not be fully
appreciated by those who take
advantage of this
shortcut.]
~~~~~~oOo~~~~~~
First, a brief word of explanation
is required for the rather odd-looking expressions used in these Essays -- such as
"ξ
is a socialist", or "ξ
is a supporter of the Labour Party". Sentence schemas like these help illustrate
certain features of (fact-stating) language relevant to the aims of this site.
In fact, these aspects of language are familiar to all language users, as will
soon become apparent. That is because they shed light on our ability to form
true (as well as false)
indicative sentences, and then draw inferences
from them. We do this when we employ singular terms (e.g., Proper Names or
Definite Descriptions) to replace gap markers
like, "ξ" and "ζ"
(used in sentence schemas, such as, "ξ
loves ζ").
[Several examples of the use of these letters will be given presently, alongside
an explanation of that use.]
A gap marker like
ξ is essential
here, for by suitably defining it
in use, or more rigorously in a formal system,
legitimate substitution instances (this term will also be explained) can be
clearly specified. Why it is important to be precise here will also emerge as
this Essay unfolds. An actual gap -- such as this, " loves ", or even a series of dots, as in "...loves...", won't do,
since, of course, gaps can't be defined. So: " is a socialist" and
"...is a socialist" are no good. A gap wouldn't be any
use, of course, if we wanted to distinguish between
sentences like these: "Brutus killed Caesar" and "Brutus killed himself".
Plainly, both would become " killed " and
"...killed...", if we removed the Proper Names and simply used gaps or dots. By
employing suitably
defined gap markers we can distinguish those two sentence forms as follows: "ξ
killed ζ" and "ξ killed ξ",
respectively.
What counts as a "legitimate substitution instance" depends on
whether we are speaking about, (a) he interpretation of sentence schemas in a
formal language or a formal system, or whether we are, (b)
Trying to make sense of the sentential
patterns we use in everyday speech. As far as (a) is concerned, the formal pattern will
probably be expressed in the following way: "F(ξ,ζ)"
-- where "F( , )" stands for a two-place, first level (formal) linguistic function
or predicate
variable.
[Again, these technical terms are explained in Note 15a,
link above.]
An interpretation
in this sense amounts to the replacement of the above schematic
letters/sentences
-- i.e., predicate expressions,
linguistic functions (follow the link for
an explanation of that term), or gap markers, for
example -- with terms defined by the formal rules of the system itself (or implied
by the natural language concerned) in order to form an ordinary indicative sentence. So, for example, a formal system might allow for the substitution
of singular terms for the two Greek letters above, which when translated
into English might yield the following sentences, or "substitution instances":
[Yes, I am
aware Mount McKinley is now called Denali!]
Here substituting "Mount Everest" for "ξ",
"Mount McKinley" for "ζ", and "ξ
is higher than ζ" for "F(ξ,ζ)".
[Again, an explanation for the peculiar order of the letters in F(ξ,ζ)
is given in Note 15a, specifically,
here.]
Or:
Y2: "Romeo loves Juliette."
Substituting "Romeo" for "ξ",
"Juliette" for "ζ", and "ξ
loves ζ" for "F(ξ,ζ)".
Y3:
"The River Thames loves Paddington Bear."
Substituting "The
River Thames" for "ξ",
"Paddington Bear" for "ζ", and "ξ
loves ζ" for "F(ξ,ζ)".
As
will no doubt be appreciated, some substitution instances fail to yield
sentences that make sense to English speakers. In which case, as
far as Option (b)
from earlier is concerned, acceptable
substitution instances will depend on what is counted as a legitimate
ordinary language interpretation of the schematic letters involved. Such
restrictions might be waved to some extent, or even completely ignored, in a formal
language. However, since English isn't a formal language (to state the
obvious!), there are no formal rules to guide us with respect to the
vernacular, although
there are rules of thumb that can and do provide a rough guide. For example, in relation to
"ξ
loves ζ", acceptable substitutions would normally be limited to
sentences formed by the use of the names of, or the names for, a human
being. [On the distinction between a "name of" and a "name for", see
here.] Largely because of that, the vast majority of
English speakers (if not all of them) would recognise Y3 above as
non-sensical and
Y1 and Y2 as
legitimate indicative sentences (even if the latter relates to two fictional
characters).
[To be sure,
Y3 might make sense in poetry or fantasy fiction --
or maybe even as a coded message --
which is why I made the point that there are no hard-and-fast guidelines here,
just rough rules of thumb.]
Now, there is nothing in language or logic that forces
the above analysis on us, it just turns out to have rather useful 'spin-off
benefits',
as it were, which clearly recommend it (that is, in addition to the more formal
advantages it has, allowing
modern logicians to study inferences more precisely). [Again, there is more on this in Note 15a.]
So, from the semi-formal schematic expression, "ξ
is the capital of France", we can form the following sentences using three names
successively -- "Paris",
"London" and "Rome" -- to replace
ξ in each
case, respectively:
F1: Paris is the capital of France.
F2: London is the capital of France.
F3: Rome is the capital of France.
And
so on. As noted above, some of these will be true, some false, and some might
change from true to false, or vice versa, as
circumstances arise. Plainly, these propositions all share a common pattern which is expressed by
the semi-formal schema, "ξ is
the capital of France".15b
Now, consider an example of an object supposedly given in experience --
indeed, one to which Lenin himself
referred --, a simple glass tumbler. We might want to say the following about it:
E1: This tumbler is made of glass.
E1 appears to express a fact about a particular, this tumbler
(possibly picked out by a pointing gesture or a nod), but that object isn't concrete,
yet --
or not concrete in the right sort of DM-sense.
Hence, so key features of the dialectical process must
now be applied to it.
According to the above
dialectical circuit, we must interconnect this
aspiring particular
with other features of reality by employing (or maybe even by refining) an abstract general
concept (or concepts) in relation to it.
But, E1 already contains a use of
a general concept (or predicate expression) "ξ is made of glass",
which, of course, isn't the name of anything, general or particular. Moreover, the
sentence formed by combining the singular, demonstrative term, "This tumbler", with
the concept/predicate expression, or
linguistic function, "ξ is
made of glass" (i.e., thereby forming E1) isn't a name, either.16
In that case, in E1 we don't seem to have a particular (or even
an "individual") upon which we can begin
to inflict some dialectics.
It might be wondered why these seemingly irrelevant linguistic concerns have
been allowed to distract us when it is perfectly plain what is meant -- that if E1 were true, it would provide us with an
example of a particular (or an individual), namely, the said
tumbler, perhaps picked out by the
reference of the
indexical phrase: "This tumbler (here)."
E1a: This tumbler (here) is made of glass.
Unfortunately, whether or not that is so
can in no way help us make sense of the
'dialectical process' under consideration here. On its own, and without
an elaborate (implied) context (and historically-conditioned social background) the phrase "This tumbler"
would say nothing at all. Indeed, it only succeeds in picking out the said tumbler because of the complex social and
linguistic practices surrounding its normal use -- and, of course, the
significance of pointing gestures.17
On the other hand, if this
phrase is meant to, and even manages to, pick out this and onlythis
tumbler, and nothing else, it would be operating as a Proper Name, or some other singular designating
expression (at best), which point isn't being contested here (at least, not yet).
Of course, the phrase itself
may be used to say something when combined with a linguistic-functional
expression, such as "ξ is made of
glass", but that would clearly involve the use of general terms again.
However, even if
DM-epistemology were 100% correct, the dialectical process can't begin with bare
particulars (whatever they turn out to be!), as everyone, including DM-theorists, agrees.
It
requires the use of general terms. That is, the particulars DM-theorists envisage have
to be particulars of a certain type. So, a tumbler isn't just a
lump of glass, or a body of matter. It is an item of glassware intended for a
certain purpose. It is also why this Essay takes the line it does; it is aimed at demonstrating that no
matter how this 'process' is re-packaged and sold to us by DM-fans, no sense can be made of it,
as we are about to find out.
[This
topic will be dealt with presently and in Note 18 (link below).]
In that
case, perhaps the following example might succeed in picking out a particular:
E2: This tumbler is made of this lump of glass.
However, the phrase "lump of glass" still contains a
general term,
namely, "glass".18
In case anyone is tempted to
object that DM-theorists in fact begin with the
general in order to refine the particular -- and because of that the argument in this Essay is thoroughly misconceived --, it is worth recalling that the whole point of this
exercise is to show that while DM-theorists might say this is what they do,
it isn't what they actually do. What they in fact do is re-interpret
sentences like E1 as identitystatements. This involves the
re-configuration of expressions like the following:
A1: NN is F,
as:
A2: NN = F*.
[Where "NN" is a Proper Name and "F*" a
nominalised
or particularised predicate expression (like "Man", "Manhood",
or "runner").
Additionally, in A2, the "=" sign is interpreted as one or more of the
following: a symbol for (i) The identity relation, (ii) Class inclusion, or (iii)
A part/whole attribution -- or, indeed, all three at once! (I have employed an F*
here, as opposed to the more usual F to indicate that this use of
a predicate letter variable is non-standard.) A word is particularised
when it is changed from a general to a
particular
term; when, for instance, a
common noun is transformed into a
Proper Noun or
Definite Description -- for example, "man" into "Manhood", "beauty" into
"The Beautiful" -- or a general verb, such as "runs", is also converted into a
Proper Noun, in this case, "Runner". These moves will be explained at length
as Essay unfolds, alongside their philosophical, logical and ideological significance).
However, on this see also
Note 01 of Part Two.]
As we will see, it is
this
initial wrong-turn,
or distortion, that 'allows' DM-theorists to
derive several counter-intuitive conclusions from ordinary sentences that employ
perfectly innocent-looking predicate expressions.
Moreover,
it is this
linguistic move that saves DM-apologists the job ofactually having to abstract anything at all --, which is fortunate
since that task is impossible to perform, let alone describe, with
anything other than empty platitudes or vague and confused 'thought experiments'.
By
means of that 're-analysis' of ordinary predicate expressions dialecticians
imagine they can bypass the
'abstractive process', all the while claiming that it has been carried out!
This motivates the belief that they can access abstractions at will, when
all they have done is conjure the Proper Names of abstract particulars out of less than thin air -- such as "Man", "Consciousness", "Identity",
"Difference", "The Population", "abstract labour", or "Being".
The
Proper Names of these abstract particulars are then used to flank, on the
right-hand side, a transmogrified "is", which now works as an identity sign, directly facing the original singular
term, on the left -- as in A2:
A2: NN = F*.
This
re-configures the hackneyed DM-sentence "John
is a man" -- which we will meet
later -- into
"John is identical to Man", "John is identical with mankind", or even "John =
Man".
In
order for that to happen, the
"is" of predication has been transformed into an "is" of identity
--,
plainly in order to
hold this implausible theory together and provide some sort of
'rationale'
for what supposedly follows from it.
Maybe, then the following will work?
E3: This tumbler is composed of these n Silicon atoms.
Once more, E3 contains
yet more general terms (for instance, "atoms").
We needn't labour the point; indeed, it is one that
dialecticians themselves accept -- but, alas, only when it has been buried under
a heap of obscure Hegel-speak.
There is a fundamental
logical principle at stake here that can't be side-stepped, by-passed or ignored. Whatever is done to try to describe a particular,
or an individual in this way, it will always involve the use
of general terms.19
Against this, it could be argued that
it might be possible to refer to particulars or individuals by means of an identifying indexical
description, such as the following:
E4: This is a tumbler.
[Accompanied perhaps once more with a pointing gesture.]
But, the problem with E4 is that the word "tumbler" is now a
general term.
Even a pointing gesture
on its own, followed by the word:
E4a: "Tumbler",
would be of no
help. Unless Proper Names, and only
Proper Names, are used to pick out such aspirant 'concrete particulars' (but on that, see
below), there is no way around this obstacle. For example, no one supposes
that the word "Tumbler" is the name of only that piece of
glassware; i.e., that this is that particular tumbler's Proper Name!
This means
we face a logical (but not an epistemological, psychological or ontological) barrier before
we can even begin to loop the first dialectical loop -- a logical
condition in relation to which DM-theorists at least pay lip service.
As
noted above, one way to avoid this difficulty might be to be to try to represent
concrete particulars by the use of Proper Names. Unfortunately, Proper Names
only function as such in combination with other linguistic expressions that
don't operate in that way. That is because letters or sounds on their own
can't work as names without the right sort of linguistic and social context.
[Suppositions to the contrary not only fall foul of
Wittgenstein's
Private Language Argument, but also of several comments
Marx made about language.]
Some readers might find this point difficult to
appreciate because, as regular language users, they automatically recognise the
use of Proper Names in ordinary
homophonic
contexts, and hence they automatically recognise the occurrence of linguistic expressions
conventionally assigned to this grammatical
category -- even when they are
used in isolation. Many jokes trade on that fact.20
However, sounds
propagated in the air, inscriptions committed to paper or printed on a screen can't count as
Proper Names when they are totally divorced from the complex social and linguistic background
mentioned
above. Rule-governed, socially-sanctioned sentential contexts and practices are required to
turn such uninterpreted marks or noises into words with a specific
mode of
signification, and thus into
names.
["Inscription"
here applies to physical marks on a page/screen/wall/blackboard/whitescreen/cavewall
that aren't considered random, but are held to be the product of intentionality, part of a natural-, or even a formal-language -- or perhaps
even a work of
art, no matter how 'primitive'.]21
Indeed, uninterpreted objects or processes in nature are by themselves incapable of
determining the meanings of any marks or sounds we use to talk about whatever it
is we
talk about.
That is, of course, because uninterpreted objects
and processes lack
social organisation, practical skills or intellect.
Naturally, that is just a roundabout way of saying that uninterpreted objects
and processes can't determine a rule; only human beings
can do that (in practice), since language is a
rule-governed product of our social being, not a superficial aspect of discourse's own syntactical being.
Not even a
series of Proper Names can pick out anything true or false of 'concrete
particulars', or anything else for that matter. That is because such a series would, at best, constitute a list, not
a sentence (still less a proposition). Consider, for example, the following:
Lists like
this say nothing -- even if they have a use, as here, to make that
very point! We could, perhaps, imagine a sense for E5, but only by
articulating it with general terms or with words that function other than as
names.
[This
"imagined sense" might
involve the answer to a question like: "Which eight Proper Names and titles appear most
often in the novels of Woodruff Durfendorfer?" In such circumstances, E5 would
now become something like this "These eight
names and titles appear most often in the novels of Woodruff Durfendorfer: London, Lenin, Amazon, Venus, Morning Star,
Coronation Street, Tony Blair, Proxima Centauri."]
We
can perhaps see this if instead of E5 we were confronted by this list of
'inscriptions':
If
someone were to assert that these were Proper Names, much more than
their say-so would be required. We would need to know in which natural language any of
them are actually used, and in which viable sentences in that language.
This minimal requirement is perhaps easier to see when we are confronted with inscriptions that
we don't already recognise as plausible examples of Proper Names. A list of
words we already recognise as Proper Names (in, say, E5) perhaps obscured
that fact.
Moreover, even if a list of the Proper Names of objects or
individuals were replaced by another list formed out of the words we have for
concepts or abstract general terms, it would make no difference; it would
still say nothing, as the next two examples illustrate:
E6: Identity, Substance, Matter, Form, Flux, Space, Time,
Part, Whole, Mode, Particular, Absolute, General, Essence, Trope, Appearance,
Entity, Thing-in-Itself.
E6 and E7 have no
sense, and say nothing (in
that respect), since they are also lists. To repeat, in order to gain a sense
these terms would have to be articulated with expressions that don't function as names,
general or Proper.21a
At this point it could be argued that we might be able
to pick out a targeted or a specific particular by the use of a Proper Name, in the
following manner:
E8: Karl Marx.
Undoubtedly, this Proper Name designates the individual Karl
Marx, but that is only because of all the social and historical stage-setting
which already
surrounds its normal use, and the fact that it is both a
name
for
and a name of a man. That background involves the use of
countless sentences like the following:
E9: Karl Marx is the author of Das Kapital
and was born in Trier in 1811.
Without this context in general,
the word "Karl Marx" could be the name of the man at the delicatessen, or a new brand of Vodka, or even that of the winner of the
three-thirty at Newmarket. In fact, without such a background this inscription might not even be a compound
word, let
alone a name, general or Proper.22
The aforementioned detour ends at this point; back to the main
feature.
~~~~~~oOo~~~~~~
We are now in a position to see
how and why dialecticians (i) Turn all predicate
expressions into the Proper Names of
abstract particulars and why (ii) That
transforms sentences into
lists,
preventing them from saying anything at
all.
As Essay Twelve Part
Two will show,
Ancient Greek Philosophers faced a serious problem.
It
was abundantly clear to them that concepts (although they weren't called that
then!) -- or what were presumed to be the referents of general terms -- couldn't be picked out
in any straight-forward sense. That is, they weren't the sorts of things we experienced or encountered in the
everyday world in the same way that the referents of the
Proper Names of individuals or genuinely material objects are (again, that isn't
necessarily how they
would have put this point all those years ago!). For example, if you lived back
then, while you could look at, meet, shake hands with, or engage in argument
with Socrates, you couldn't do any of those things with justice, mortality, time
-- or even 'Manhood'. You couldn't even meet or point to all dogs, cats, tables,
chairs and wine bottles in existence at that point in time, let alone in the
past or the future.
But, it also
seemed clear to them that such general terms must represent something,
otherwise their use would
signify nothing at all; they would be "empty words" (Flatus vocis, as
Medieval
Nominalist,
Roscelin
maintained). When we say general things about objects in nature or society we
aren't simply producing aimless sounds.
Here, for example, is Parmenides (as reported by
Simplicius):
"What
can be said and be thought of must be; for it can be, and nothing cannot."
[Barnes (2001), p.81.]
"What
is there to be said and thought must needs be: for it is there for being, but
nothing is not." [Quoted in Kirk et al (1999), p.247.]
About
which the authors of Kirk et al had this to say:
"Parmenides' summary...says in effect that any object of thought must be a real
object, confirms despite its obscurity that his rejection of 'is not' is
motivated by a concern about what is a possible content for a genuine thought."
[Ibid. p.247.]
So, if someone says "Vladimir
Putin is a man",
while "Vladimir
Putin" (at the time of writing) certainly picks out an identifiable
individual in the physical universe, "man"
doesn't seem to designate anything obvious. What then does it
designate? It must refer to something. If so, what? According to
Parmenides, what it designates must exist. But where does it exist, and
in what form?22ab
[We
still do not know the answer to these questions, not because they are too
difficult for our finite minds, but because they are the result of linguistic
chicanery; hence they are no more legitimate than asking these questions about
chess: "Ok so who gave planning (i.e., zoning) permission to build that castle
over in the corner? And who actually performed the wedding ceremony for the King
and Queen? While we are at it exactly where was that Bishop consecrated, and are
those pawns in a union?"]
In
spite of the fact that the alleged referents of general terms don't appear to exist in
the everyday world for anyone to point to (or to identify in any other way),22aa some sense had to be
given to their mode of signification (i.e., the grammatical role they occupy
and how they contribute to what a sentence can be used to say, truly or falsely). It seemed
reasonable, or even natural, therefore, to model the denotation of general terms on something that
already worked: on the direct reference
achieved by the use of the Proper Names of 'concrete individuals', like Socrates
or Alcibiades. Those names managed
to pick out
identifiable particulars in reality, so it was tempting to think that the same
must be the
case with
general words. Hence, based on the
successful
'naming relation', and despite appearances to the contrary, general words
were believed to work
because they actually
named something.
If
such words were capable of representing
things to us, they
couldn't be the names of non-existents --
they would have to be the names of 'entities' which must exist
somewhere, even if whatever that was remained invisible or inscrutable to us.
Unfortunately, this
syntactical
segue (i.e., regarding the designating role
occupied by Proper Names as the model for all words) now initiated a
completely futile and fruitless 2400-year-long search to find these newly invented entities
-- the supposed referents of general terms
--, soon to be given such grandiose titles as: "abstractions" (aphairesis
-- Urmson (1990), p.20; Peters (1967), pp.20-21), "Concepts",
"Categories", "Ideas", "Forms",
and "Universals".
The following spurious
questions then forced themselves on Traditional Theorists: Do these
'abstractions', or 'Universals', exist in
the 'mind'? [Conceptualism.]
Or in 'heaven'? [Platonic
or Old-fashioned Realism.] Or in 'God's Mind'? [The
theological version of Platonic Realism.] Maybe in the objects themselves? [A
half-way house between Conceptualism and Realism, echoed in many forms of modern-day
Scientific Realism.] Or perhaps nowhere at all? [Nominalism.]
Or could they even exist in some other suitably
obscure region or aspect of 'Being Itself'? [All stations between
Scepticism and Platonic Realism.]
Every single one of these proposed 'solutions'
appealed to something invisible, intangible, non-physical, and ultimately
inscrutable as the supposed referent of such words. Just as Proper Names
referred to, or could be used to refer to, identifiable individuals/objects in
the world around us, so these other words did likewise with respect to these
ghostly, but not at all easily identifiable, 'abstractions', 'Concepts',
'Categories', 'Ideas', 'Forms',
and 'Universals'.
Fortunately
for Traditional Theorists,
each and every one of these abstractions was completely inaccessible to the
senses
(otherwise the jig would have been up on day one). Indeed, they were incapable of being accessed by any means other than
by pure thought
(just as Plato intimated),
having long ago been emptied of all contentbecause they had been abstracted far away from material reality by a
privileged, elite group of thinkers, all of
whom were
nearly as cut-off from everyday life as the abstractions they so effortlessly
conjured up -- just as
Marx himself had pointed out (on this, see
Note 3b).
[The political and ideological significance of these
remarks will
be explored in Essay Twelve.]
Hence, in
short,
because general words seemed incapable of picking out 'general
objects' in
nature
-- there being no such thing, of course, as a 'general dog' (what
would a general dog even look like?),
or whatever it was that all dogs supposedly held in common, which can't
exist in nature (why that is so will be explored in
Part Two)
-- the assumption that all words were names of some sort
naturally led to the conclusion that
general words must refer to, or name, otherworldly objects like this --
otherwise, of course, they would simply be vacuous.
And that
is
why highly influential Greek Philosophers, Logicians and Grammarians turned general words into the Proper
Names of
just such
otherworldly
'objects'. The theories they subsequently
concocted in order
to 'justify' such moves were
merely window-dressing.
Named objects clearly exist (if, that is, we ignore for now the
names of the
'gods',
mythical beasts and fictional characters, etc.) -- we see them around us
all the time. Because of this seemingly incontrovertible fact, the
nominalisation
and particularisation of general words appeared to give them some
sort of content, or substantiality ('ousia'),
allowing them to represent 'things' as they are 'in-themselves' behind
'appearances' (i.e., as they
are 'essentially'),
but which 'essences', unfortunately, were now no longer part of the material
world -- or, at least, not in any obvious way.22a0
Hence, it seemed to such theorists that some account could be given of the
meaning or the denotation
of general words that feature in
predicative
expressions. If they were interpreted as the Proper Names of the Forms,
of
certain Universals
--
or, in some cases, the Proper Names of Categories
(later, "Concepts" or "Ideas")
--,
propositions that contained them could be
employed to represent
or reflect the
'hidden world' that these theorists now claimed lay behind 'appearances',
and which gave them some sort of substantiality.
Philosophers then awarded themselves a licence to hunt down and then uncover
the "essential", underlying (later
a priori) structure of 'reality'
(or 'Being') by means of this newly invented 'process of abstraction',
which they also imagined could achieved by thought alone.
Of course,
if a given theorist
also
believed in the existence of a supremely rational 'God' (who,
so myth and fable had it,
created
the world by the word of 'His' 'mouth'), then the temptation became irresistible
to regard the Proper Names of the 'Forms' (etc.) as the names
of the corresponding 'Ideas' in 'His Mind'
-- or, at least as the names
of the 'Forms' that resided with 'Him' in 'Heaven' --
which 'He' had used as exemplars when creating the world. Just like 'Him', they
were mysterious, obscure and far removed not only from the physical
world, but they were totally immune from easy disconfirmation by those
disreputable, impertinent and
annoying materialists.
Subsequently, these unchanging Ideas (the referents of general words) 'came to life' in Hegel's work as he endeavoured to re-animate them
in order to compensate for the fact that earlier generations of philosophers had killed
them stone dead.
This accounts for
Hegel's ham-fisted attempt to criticise the LOI, why the 'rational' approach he
adopted was so important for him, and why this meant that
his entire
programmehad alreadyrun off the railslong beforehe began to work on
it. [More on thatlater.]
Traditional Philosophers (other than the
Neoplatonists and
Hermetic Mystics) had left him with lifeless
and changeless 'concepts', and the LOI was now seen as the main culprit -- when that 'law' in fact arrived relatively late on the
scene,
indeed, by many centuries. However, in his haste to rectify this
pseudo-problem,
Hegel only succeeded in injecting even more
formalin
into these moribund 'concepts', as we will soon discover.22a
[LOI = Law of Identity.]
Unfortunately, the above re-configuration of predicate expressions as the
Proper Names
of abstract particulars destroys the capacity ordinary language has for
expressing generality (why that is so will be explained below) --, or,
rather, it does so with respect to the jargonised
language Traditional Philosophers substituted for certain targeted words in the
vernacular.
We can
actually see this happening in the thought of
the Early Greek
Philosophers (the full details will be laid out in Essay Twelve (summary
here and
here)). These
theorists found that there were no words available
to them in the vernacular
Greek
of their day
that allowed them to speculate about the nature
of these newly invented abstractions.
Hence,
they
simply manufactured their own terminology
--,or they borrowed and then
transformed jargon from earlier
myths and
Theogonies.
Consequently, words like "Being", "Logos",
"Fate", "The
Unlimited", "Nous"
-- and "abstraction" (aphairesis)
-- were co-opted and then put to no good.
However,
in order to cope with the many and varied forms
of generality available in the vernacular,
these thinkers found they also had to
appropriate and then make use of words that were already in circulation in every
day life. These
they nominalised
and particularised into "Justice", "Knowledge", "Beauty", "The
Table", "Man", "Manhood", "The Equal",
and later, "Identity" and "Difference" -- turning ordinary
general words into the
Proper Names
of these newly minted abstract particulars.22a1
"As long as preserved
communication remained oral, the environment could be described or explained
only in the guise of stories which represent it as the work of agents: that is
gods.
Hesiod takes the step of trying to unify those stories into one great
story, which becomes a cosmic theogony. A great series of matings and births of
gods is narrated to symbolise the present experience of the sky, earth, seas,
mountains, storms, rivers, and stars. His poem is the first attempt we have in a
style in which the resources of documentation have begun to intrude upon the
manner of an acoustic composition. But his account is still a narrative of
events, of 'beginnings,' that is, 'births,' as his critics the
Presocratics were to put it. From the standpoint of a sophisticated
philosophical language, such as was available to Aristotle, what was lacking
was a set of commonplace but abstract terms which by their interrelations could
describe the physical world conceptually; terms such as space, void, matter,
body, element, motion, immobility, change, permanence, substratum, quantity,
quality, dimension, unit, and the like. Aside altogether from the coinage of
abstract nouns, the conceptual task also required the elimination of verbs of
doing and acting and happening, one may even say, of living and dying, in favour
of a syntax which states permanent relationships between conceptual terms
systematically. For this purpose the required linguistic mechanism was furnished
by the timeless present of the verb to be -- the copula of analytic
statement.
"The history of early
philosophy is usually written under the assumption that this kind of vocabulary
was already available to the first Greek thinkers. The evidence of their own
language is that it was not. They had to initiate the process of inventing it....
"Nevertheless, the
Presocratics could not invent such language by an act of novel creation. They
had to begin with what was available, namely, the vocabulary and syntax of
orally memorised speech, in particular the language of
Homer and
Hesiod. What they proceeded to do was to take the language of the mythos and
manipulate it, forcing its terms into fresh syntactical relationships which had
the constant effect of stretching and extending their application, giving them a
cosmic rather than a particular reference."
[Havelock (1983), pp.13-14, 21. Bold emphases added; quotation marks altered to
conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Spelling modified to agree with
UK English. Links added.]
Havelock then shows in detail that
this is precisely what the Presocratic Philosophers succeeded in doing:
inventing abstract nouns, eliminating verbs in place of these newly-coined nouns,
and transforming the verb "to be" in the required manner.
Thus was born the so-called 'problem' of
Universals (the
'problem' of the "One
and the Many"), a
family of
insoluble conundrumspredicated on the above distortion of ordinary language, and nothing more --
again, just as
Marx noted.
Nevertheless, these
seemingly insignificant linguistic moves
had profound implications for the
Philosophy of Language and the Philosophy Logic that the Ancient Greeks
bequeathed to
later generations of
ruling-class theorists. FL was now regarded as an abstract science --
perhaps even the
formal wing of psychology and ontology --, whose adepts in fact studied the 'laws of thought',
the language associated with which was itself a secret code that contained (and thus was capable of revealing) the
very secrets of 'Being'. Here is George Novack:
"Logic is the science of the
thought process. Logicians investigate the activities of the though process
which goes on in human heads and formulate laws, forms and interrelation of
those mental processes." [Novack (1971), p.17.]
[FL = Formal Logic.]
Novack was simply echoing a widely-held belief among traditionalists, as was
indeed Engels:
"In every epoch, and
therefore also in ours, theoretical thought is a historical product, which at
different times assumes very different forms and, therewith, very different
contents. The science of thought is therefore, like every other, a historical
science, the science of the historical development of human thought. And this is
of importance also for the practical application of thought in empirical fields.
Because in the first place the theory of the laws of thought is by no means an
'eternal truth' established once and for all, as philistine reasoning imagines
to be the case with the word 'logic'." [Engels
(1954), p.43. Quotation marks
altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Bold emphases
added.]
And so was Lenin:
"Logic is the science of
cognition. It is the theory of knowledge…. The laws of logic are the reflections
of the objective in the subjective consciousness of man.... [These] embrace
conditionally, approximately, the universal, law-governed character of eternally
moving and developing nature."
[Lenin (1961),
p.182.
Bold emphasis alone added..]
So, too, was Trotsky:
"Hegel himself viewed
dialectics precisely as logic, as the science of the forms of human
cognition.... What does logic express? The
law of the external world or the law of consciousness? The question is posed
dualistically [and] therefore not correctly [for] the laws of logic express the
laws (rules, methods) of consciousness in its active relationship to the
external world.... Thought operates by its own
laws, which we can call the laws of logic...." [Trotsky (1986), pp.75, 87, 106.
Trotsky is apparently referring to Hegel's Introduction to The Science
of Logic (i.e., Hegel (1999),
pp.43-64.
Bold emphases added; paragraphs merged.]
This
form of metaphysical,
pseudo-logic cast a
long shadow over much of 'western' thought (and that includes DM). The
original, Ancient Greek syntactical false step outlined above (and further analysed in this Essay) exercised a profound influence on all subsequent
strands in
Traditional Philosophy, setting the parameters of 'acceptable' debate
among 'serious thinkers', and forming the scaffolding around which the "ruling
ideas" that Marx spoke about could be built. This abstract (quasi-Platonic) approach to knowledge also had a
lasting effect on the way science and mathematics have been
interpreted ever since.22b
Fast forward
a couple of thousand years and we can see the effect this grammatical segue
has had on the philosophical 'logic' inherited by European theorists -- but more
specifically by
German Idealists,
forcing their thought
in the direction taken by
Leibniz,
Kant,
Fichte,
Schelling, and especially Hegel. The
bowdlerised
'logic'
they inherited from Medieval and Renaissance logicians
appeared to freeze-frame reality into fixed forms,
logical straight-jackets comprised of the Proper Names of these Abstract Particulars. And, as we
are about to see, that is what motivated
Hegel's criticism of the
LOI, as well as the view he took of the
supposed limitations he claimed to have discovered in Aristotelian Logic. Given
that general terms had been obliterated -- or rather frozen as the supposed
referents of a set of Proper Names -- because of this ancient syntactical
screw-up, no wonder Hegel saw in them no 'motion', no change. [On this, see
Kenny (2006), pp.11-13. Also see the references listed
here.]
However,
as things transpired, Hegel's
'analysis' turned out to be an unintended and unwitting reductio ad absurdum of the
entire 'abstractionist project' (indeed, as the young
Marx and Engels saw,
albeit imperfectly). Hegel thus performed a great
service for humanity, albeit inadvertently: his system is so obviously based on a series of logical blunders
that no one with an
ounce of materialist good sense would ever take it seriously. By
unintentionally pushing these errors to their limit, Hegel completely undermined
the credibility of the
entire genre.
Marxist
Dialecticians uncritically appropriated the syntactical mess Hegel dumped on
all who take him seriously
-- except, of course, they imagined that in their hands it could be
inverted and put back 'on its feet', revealing its inner, 'rational' core after the
'mystical shell' had been paired away. But, as should seem
obvious (to those with
the aforementioned ounce of materialist good sense), rotating a logical blunder
through any number of degrees has absolutely no impact on its
statusas a blunder. Without giving careful thought (or any
thought) to the syntactical origin of these sub-Aristotelian clangers, and without considering for one moment the
deleterious effect this catalogue of
errors might have on
HM
(outlined below), dialecticians have only succeeded in saddling Marxism with an
unworkable
'theory of knowledge'.
Unfortunately, late in life Aristotle began to move in this direction, too,
laying the foundations for the so-called
Term Logic
that dominated the Middle Ages, inflated into a
full-blown theory by Medieval and Renaissance Logicians. A core principle of this theory came to be known as the
Identity (or Essential) Theory of Predication.22c
It is this mis-begotten theory, along with its
'philosophical' implications, which lies at the heart
both of dialectics and much of Traditional Philosophy.
So,
when dialecticians make use of the analysis of subject-predicate sentences
developed in and by this ancient tradition they not only turn their own
propositions into lists -- we will soon see exactly how this happens --, they actually
prevent the names
they think they are using from
being general names, to begin with. That is because these moves destroy the capacity
language has for expressing generality, which, as we have just seen, is essential if
Proper Names are to function as names, in the first place.
Hence, given the
Identity Theory Of Predication,
in order to be able
to refer to 'concepts', or 'abstractions', theorists found they had to turn predicate expressions
themselves into
the Proper Names of those Abstract Particulars.22d
In that case, a simple sentence like the
following:
E10: Blair is a man,
must now become:
E11: Blair [some form of attribution inserted
between these two halves] Manhood.23
The effect
of this can be seen if we examine E11a a little more closely. If both "Blair" and
"Manhood" are singular terms, which they are, then despite appearances to the
contrary,no predication has actually taken place. That is because
individuals can't be predicated of individuals -- or, rather
Proper Names can't be predicated of individuals
also named by a
Proper Name (why that is so is explained in Note 24a0 and
Note 24ab).24a0
Given this view of things, nothing will have been said of or
about Blair. Of course, on the surface it seems
that something has been said of Blair, but that is where the Identity
Theory kicks in. [More on this presently.]
Now, an ordinary predication (like the one expressed in E10, which says something
of a
named individual), seemed to many to be all too insubstantial. As noted
above, ascriptions like this don't appear to pick out anything in the world that is actually attributable
to Blair
--
i.e., nothing that can be pointed to or identified in any obvious way which is true of him. So, while on
the one hand we have the material object named "Blair", on the other, what
is said of him seems to be something altogether intangible. Since we can't point
to anything in the world called "man", or "Manhood", it
looks like E10 isn't really saying anything true of Blair! Ordinary
language appears to be misleading us, and, therefore, seemsto be defective.
In that
case, sentences like E10 must be put in 'correct logical order' so that sense
can be made of them. Hence, we need a new 'theory' that replaces predication with something a little
more substantial. [Of course, there were other reasons for these moves; they will be
examined in Part Two.]
E10: Blair is a man.
However, it is important to
remind ourselves that this 'problem' arose
because of
the adoption of the primitive idea that all words only gain meaning if they are
names -- or, as here,
Proper Names.
[Why that idea was in fact adopted will be examined in Essay Twelve.]
So,
the traditional account went something like this: since "...man"
in E10 isn't a
name of anything that can be identified in the manner described above, it can't be attributing anything to Blair
-- unless, that is, it is in fact a disguised Proper Name.
Because of
this
seemingly innocuous syntactic segue,
there was a pressing need to try to identify the 'something' that could serve
as the referent of the predicate "...is a man"
(or, in traditional logic, simply, "a man", or even just "man").
In order to rectify this, the general term was particularised so that it could now refer to an
abstract idea, or
Universal -- with each of the words "Man"/"Manhood" becoming the
Proper Name of the Universal 'Man'/'Manhood'.
In this way, propositions like E10 were now held to containtwo
Proper Names,
with an attributing or linking term that supposedly connected them
-- i.e., these two
Proper Names
become the subject term ("Blair"), and the
'predicate name' ("a man" or "Manhood"). The copula, "is", was now recast as an
"is" of identity (e.g., in E11, and E11a), and was no longer simply an "is" of predication. As a result, this analysis came to be known as the
"Two-name theory
of predication". [More on this presently.]
E11: Blair [some form of attribution inserted
between the two halves] Manhood.
E11a: Blair is Manhood.
[Paradoxically, both of these terms were sometimes also viewed as predicates
as well as Proper Names! An example of
radical confusion of this order can be found
here.]
However, in order to account for
"the unity of
a proposition" (more on that knotty problem later) in sentences
that contain two Proper Names (so that it didn't simply collapse into a list), something a little more powerful
than the
copula "is"
of predication (used in E10) would be required, linking both halves. In addition, this new
linking term must allow propositions like E10 to say
something of Blair that we could
point to -- at least, internally (in 'the mind'), 'abstractly', but later
perhaps as an Idea, or Concept. This new
linking term must relate the subject (the Proper Name "Blair", or the man
himself -- as we will see, these were often conflated) to the object (now
designated by
another Proper Name), to which
the old predicate allegedly referred (i.e., "Man"). Failing that, this
linking term must at
least
represent this relation -- i.e., it must represent the link between what "Blair" stood for and
what "man" stood for, and it must do this in language,
or, at least, it must do this in harmony with the 'laws of thought', in 'the mind'.
[But, again, the two were often run together.]
In that case, E10
would
be true if and only if "Blair" referred to one and the same thing as "Man" (or "Manhood");
there had to be an 'internal', non-accidental connection between these two terms
that reflected a similar link between whatever it was in 'reality' they
supposedly designated. Nothing less could reflect the 'essential' nature of
Blair; anything else would merely reflect what was 'accidentally' true of him,
which 'accidental truths' were of no interest to philosophy, or science. If these ideas
were to count as a valid, 'acceptable' re-presentation of "the deity's" knowledge (the
only 'true knowledge' there is, by definition, or so it was once believed), then an 'accidental relationship'
would only ever be radically deficient, and certainly couldn't represent
genuine knowledge, philosophical knowledge, knowledge of 'essence'. The identity relation
solved this problem. As a spin-off, it indirectly identified our 'mortal minds'
with the eternal 'mind of god', since those who thought this way would be in
harmony with 'his' thoughts.
This notion found a clear echo in what subsequently
became the main problematic of German idealism, Subject/Object
Identity -- or the 'identity of thought and Being', a spurious relation that
also exercised Engels.23a
E10: Blair is a man.
E10a:
Blair Man.
E10b:
Blair (relating expression) Man.
Hence, as should seem obvious, this new linking term had to be a
relational expression of some sort; it had to relate one
Proper Name to another Proper Name, or, at least, what they represented (as in
E10b),
and it had to do so "essentially".24aa
That is because the "is" of predication in E10 is simply that -- it is just an
"is" of predication, a handy linguistic devise that facilitates attempts to describe or
attribute something of someone or something. But, in that case, if E10 is now held to contain two
Proper Names, not one, it would
seem to be asserting one individual of
another (or, rather, asserting a
Proper Name ("Man"/"Manhood")
of an individual (Blair) -- again, in Traditional Thought, these were often
run-together). That is, "a man" was
now being viewed as the disguised Proper Name of an abstract particular,
'Man' or 'Manhood'. So,
E10 would be 'asserting' that the object that was the referent of the old predicate
(again, 'Man', or 'Manhood')
was 'true' of the object that is the referent of the subject term, "Blair".
And yet, no object can be true of
another object.
[Once more, why that is so is explained in Note 24a0
and Note 24ab (link below).]
So, this apparent predication can't be a genuine predication, it must
express a disguised relation
between two objects ('Manhood' and Blair, now designated by two
Proper Names, not one).24ab
The
former predicate ("a man") would, under this 'analysis',
vanish right before our eyes; its
real, 'essential', or 'below-the-surface', nature, or logical role now having been exposed as a
Proper Name,
not a predicate, with the copula "is" becoming the required relational
expression -- the "is" of identity.
So, even
though your very own eyes or ears might tell you that "...is a man"
(or "man") is
a predicate expression (used to describe someone or attribute something to that
individual), your mind (suitably 're-educated') tells you it is a
disguised
Proper Name.
Such is the 'persuasive power' of Idealist 'Logic'!
However,
when there is in fact a relation of identity in ordinary language, between two
named objects (or between two singular terms, depending on how we read it), conjoined by an "is" (as we will see
is the case in E12,
below), we
uncontroversially have a
statement of identity, not of predication, to deal with. A false analogy
drawn between these two distinct uses of "is" suggested to Traditional
Logicians and Grammarians that the "is" of predication must really be an "is" of identity.
Out of twisted
logic and grammar like this there arose a new 'theory' --
one that was in fact driven by a much more ancient doctrine working in the background:
that
all
words are really names (Proper or general) by means of which we re-present, or mirror, the divine order to
ourselves, and we do this by
naming its contents,
just like Adam named all the animals -- recorded at
Genesis
2:19.
This in turn suggested to the aforementioned traditionalists that although we
can't actually touch, taste, smell or see the things that
these new 'predicate'
Proper Names
reflect, or represent to us, that doesn't in fact present a problem since these 'entities' (i.e., whatever the old predicate 'really'
referred to) are hidden 'beneath' or 'behind'
'appearances'. From there it was but a short step to the idea that all true knowledge
must relate to, or arise from, a relation set up between 'The Knower' and this secret, non-material world, anterior to experience
-- 'The True Known' --,
which is more real than the material world we
see around us.
The world of secret 'essences' was conjured into existence by such verbal tricks
-- and nothing more.
This hidden 'world', of course,
isn't the 'proper concern' of common
folk, whose 'defective' and materially-grounded language had supposedly
created 'philosophical
problems'
like this (i.e., the 'problem' of predication), in the first place. The
'unwashed' were allegedly trapped in the world of 'appearances',
lost in a fog of 'commonsense' and 'formal thinking'. In stark contrast, 'genuine philosophers'
were not only highly qualified, they were capable of seeing through all this
'confusion' right into the heart of 'Being', thanks
to this glitzy new 'theory'.24a
So,
following the lead given by Ancient, Medieval and Early Modern philosophers (such
as
John Scotus Eriugena -- but not Jean
Buridan,
whose theorywas rather more complex -- and, of course, more overtly by Hegel
himself), DM-theorists were persuaded to accept the
elitist
idea that the articulation of
names by the use of the connective "is" (in sentences like E11, and then E11a)
in fact expresses a relation between a
named individual and another named abstraction, now interpreted as an
abstract particular, 'Manhood'.25
E11: Blair [some form of attribution inserted
between the two halves] Manhood.
E11a: Blair is Manhood.
Now, since particulars
(i.e., named objects) can stand in some sort of relation to one another,
this appeared to solve the 'problem' created by the 'disappearing predicate'
puzzle, mentioned
earlier.
And that is why,
under Hegel's influence, the "is" of predication came to be the "is" of
identity in 'Materialist Dialectics'.
[As we
will see, the usual justification advanced for these ancient moves is little more than an elaborate smokescreen.]
In order to see how this trick works in more detail, consider the following:
The "is"
in E12 is plainly, and uncontroversially, one of identity; no problem
with that.
That
is, both of these seem to be instances of the relational expression "ξ
is identical with ζ".
[However, the extra "is" in E12a can't
itself be an "is" of
identity on pain of infinite regress, but must be one of prediction. More on
that below.]
Nevertheless, difficulties soon arise if this relational form
is used as an archetype upon which all apparently ('philosophical') subject-predicate
propositions are to be modelled.
When that
happens, E10 and E11 have to be re-written as follows:
E13: Blair is Manhood.
{The other two were:
E10: Blair is a man.
E11: Blair [some form of attribution inserted
between the two halves] Manhood.}
Given the traditional theory, E13 would then be interpreted as:
E14: Blair is identical with Manhood.
The
(alleged) identity relation between Blair and the abstract particular,
'Manhood', is now plain for all to see. The particular (Blair) is now said
to be identical with the 'Universal' ('Manhood') -- which means that just as
"Tully" is a Proper Name in E12, "Manhood" is the Proper Name (of an abstract particular),
in E14.
E12:
Cicero is Tully.
E12a: Cicero is identical with Tully.
E14: Blair is identical with Manhood.
In this way,
abstractions could be conjured into existence to order as the
other-worldly correlates of some of the common nouns used in ordinary
language --, or, and far more likely, the other-worldly correlates of the jargonised expressions that Philosophers have been inventing ever since
Anaximander
was knee-high to baby goat.
If
Proper Names designate material particulars, then certain common nouns must
really be
the Proper Names of abstract particulars --, which exist, well..., where?
[For Plato, they were located perhaps in 'heaven'; for
dialecticians..., um..., er..., better not
ask! If you do, you risk being accused of not "understanding" dialectics.]
This is the 'reasoning' that
underpinned, and then initiated, the aforementioned
futiletwo thousand five-hundred year search for these ethereal beings -- motivated,
as we will see, by ruling-class
priorities and interests.
However, to spoil the fun: defective reasoning like this can
only be expressed in
the
Indo-European
family of languages (but see the qualifications mentioned
here), where subjects,
copulas and predicates abound. Different language groups had to rely on other
linguistic tricks to give life to their own, home-grown strains of parasitic, regressive ruling-class ideology.
[More on this in Essay Fourteen Part One (summary
here).]
Unfortunately, as noted above, because
of this syntactic segue,
generality was totally eliminated. In E14, we no longer have the
general expression "ξis a man", but the
Proper Name of an abstract
particular, 'Manhood'.
Indeed, this can be seen from the fact that it would make no sense
at all to
interpret E10 as expressing an identity relation between Blair and a
predicate (or even between his name and a predicate expression).
E14: Blair is identical with Manhood.
E10: Blair is a man.
How could Blair
-- or his name (if we avoid the
'use/mention' bear trap,
here) -- be identical with a
rather minor grammatical feature of
the Indo-European family of languages -- or what it supposedly stood for? How could Blair/"Blair" be identical with a
predicate, or even with a Universal?
But, to many, it did seem to make some sort of crazy sense to see
E10 as
expressing an identity between Blair and an abstract concept, or an
abstract particular, something for which the predicate ("a man") was now taken to
be a Proper Name.26
Unfortunately,
our consideration of
the malign consequences of the idea that all words are names hasn't yet run its
full course.
If all words
are indeed names, then the "is" of
identity must name the identity relation, too. [We can see this move
actually happening
here.] That
was the point of the use of the word "attribution" in E11:
E11: Blair [some form of attribution inserted
between the two halves] Manhood.
But,
this can't be correct. It doesn't even look correct.
That can be seen if an attempt is made to treat this
controversial "is" as just such a
Proper Name
(of the identity relation); E12 would become:
E15: Cicero Identity Tully.
Or, perhaps:
E16: Cicero Identity Relation Tully.
[E12: Cicero is Tully.]
[In E15 and E16, the "is" in E12 has been replaced
in both cases by its supposed
Proper Name, and the phrase "some
form of attribution"
with what "is" supposedly attributes; in this case, the "Identity Relation".]
As is now plain, neither E15 nor E16 is capable of saying anything (true or false), for they are both lists.27
Admittedly, in many contexts the word "is" works quite happily as a relational
expression for identity, as we saw in E12. But, even then, the "is"
of identity names nothing, since it isn't a name, it is a verb. Treating all words as
names clearly turns sentences like this into lists, and
since lists say nothing, that move destroys the capacity we have in language for saying anything at
all.
To sum up: in E10, where a clear predicative use of
a general noun is being expressed, the misreading of the "is" of predication as an "is" of identity
reveals that an earlier
decision had already been taken to interpret predicate expressions
as the Proper Names of abstract particular.
Any subsequent 'grammatical adjustments', or arguments, that were advanced in
support (i.e., re-configuring
"is" as a relational expression of identity), were
invented so that they were now 'consistent' with that earlier metaphysical
move, itself
made for ideological reasons.
[What those reasons were will be revealed in Essay Twelve -- summary
here.]
E10: Blair is a man.
It is
this move -- not the attempt to process particulars by means of
'abstractions' given in thought, nor yet as part of an endeavour to access or use 'pure'
concepts or categories of 'reason', or even re-christening the diminutive verb "is" as the name of "Being", or of
"Identity" --, it is this syntactic segue which
kick-started this philosophical wild goose chase,
and then the sub-Aristotelian 'logic' Hegel cobbled together, unfortunately now echoed
in 'Materialist Dialectics'.28
So, the mythical 'process of abstraction' was motivated by
the syntactically inept re-write of general terms as the Proper
Names
of abstract particulars, detailed above. In turn this linguistic conjuring trick was itself based on an earlier move
that interpreted predicate
expressions as the Proper Names of the "Forms", or of "Universals", and later "Ideas", "Categories" and "Concepts".
Clearly this 'process' was based on an uncheckable, occult capacity which some claim
they possess -- i.e., the 'ability' to process concepts in the privacy of their heads at the flick of a
verb. These
phoney moves originally arose out of the
actual abstraction -- i.e., the removal, cutting-off, alienation, and thus
the distortion -- of concept expressions from their usual context in ordinary sentences
used in
everyday life. Again, as Marx noted:
"The philosophers would only
have to dissolve their language into the ordinary language, from which it is
abstracted, to recognise it as the distorted language of the actual world,
and
to realise that neither thoughts nor language in themselves form a realm of
their own, that they are only manifestations of actual life." [Marx
and Engels (1970), p.118. Bold emphasis alone added.]
"[P]hilosophy is nothing else but
religion rendered into thought and expounded by thought, i.e., another form
and manner of existence of the estrangement of the essence of man; hence equally
to be condemned...." [Marx
(1975b), p.381.]
This was
achieved by physically abstracting ordinary predicative expressions
(out of simple
propositions like E10), turning them into the Proper Names of abstract particulars,
thus distorting them, Traditional Philosophers (and later, DM-theorists) were
thus able to
magic into existence a whole new branch of
Super-Knowledge (Metaphysics and 'dialectics') out of less than thin air.
E10: Blair is a man.
Just as scientists study the material world,
so
it seemed Philosophers could study this hidden world of Super-Facts,
Super-Laws, 'Essences', 'abstractions', and 'necessities'.29
Of course,
Traditional Philosophers (and their latter-day,
conservative progeny
--
Marxist Dialecticians) paid no heed to the actual use of general words in
everyday language. They had excellent, class-motivated reasons for ignoring the
vernacular. [What these are will be explored in Essay Twelve (summaryhere).]Unfortunately,
DM-Traditionalists also had excellent (but this time entirely petty-bourgeois)
reasons for emulating this approach. [They have been exposed in Essay Nine
Part Two. This
ideologically-, and politically-motivated re-configuration of predicative
propositions was in fact something to which the early Marx and Engels themselves
drew attention (on that, see Note 30and
Part Two).]
Nevertheless, the alleged validity of
moves like this were (and still are)
'justified' by the
endless stream of
'philosophical knowledge' they seemed capable of generating. The fact that
Traditional Theorists in effect managed to do this on the cheap, so the speak -- without having to bother with all those expensive, time-wasting experiments, or,
indeed,
without having to bother with
prosaic facts that had been
'sullied' by their contact with vulgar "appearances", or, indeed,
without having to take account of the constraints
that social life places on language and communication -- was,
of course, an added bonus.
The profound
ramifications of this philosophical wrong-turn needn't concern us here, but it is possible to highlight
the effect it has had on DM by revealing how the misconstrual of the "is" of
predication as the "is" of identity expressed itself more locally, on the
dogmatic theory dialecticians, en masse,
then
imposed on the world.
In fact, as
will soon become clear: this linguistic dodge motivated, and still
motivates, practically every single
DM-theory.
Indeed, this move lies
at the heart of the metaphysical beast,
for here we have exposed the source of Dialectical Marxism's
Dilithium
Crystals.
First, the
Identity Theory of Predication
is central to Hegel's criticism of the LOI (details can be found
here and in Appendix E),
whereby he
deliberately conflated the
LOI ("stated negatively") with the
truth-functional implications that
hold between contradictory propositions (i.e., he intentionally confused it with the LOC). This egregious mix-up 'allowed'
him to 'derive'
a spurious
contradiction
from the 'negative form' of the LOI and that
in turn 'enabled' him to
galvanise and energise his Ideal Universe by means of the double negation of the results
of these
mix-ups. But, these moves were only possible because of the systematic
confusion of predicate expressions and predicates themselves with Proper Names, relations, objects, abstractions,
concepts and an
entire litany of other
Hegelian oddities.
[UO = Unity of Opposites; LOI = Law of
Identity; LOC = Law of Non-contradiction.]
As we
are about to see,
Hegel, like other Traditional Theorists, confused predicate expressions (which are artefacts of language) with
extra-linguistic objects, relations and concepts,
thereby conflating talk
about talk with talk about the world.
This then 'enabled' him to think that if he was able to think something -- i.e.,
'dialectically' develop certain 'concepts' via a series of 'negations' -- then
the universe itself must run on those lines, too. It was but a short step from
there for him to conclude that his thought processes were actually an expression
of the development of 'Reality'/'Being'/'God'. That would, of course, mean he
was as deluded as
those poor souls who think they are 'god'.
[And
we think it wise to take philosophical and logic advise from this confused individual?!]
If there is no
difference between a proposition, for instance, and its supposed object -- or, rather, if there is no difference between a proposition and the
Proper Name of an object -- it became 'natural'
to think that a contradiction alleged to exist between two propositions also expressed a
relation between two objects or processes so referenced. As a result of such false steps these objects/processes were now said to be in 'dialectical' union
or 'tension'
with one another.
This wrong turn is indeed the source of all those DM-'contradictions', which
were no longer seen as purely linguistic expressions, but as objects/processes/relation -- even opposing
forces -- in their own
right. Talk about talk again confused with talk about the world.
[Much of the above, and what follows, will only be fully understood by those who
have read
this and
this, parts of
which have been reproduced in
Appendix E.]
Moreover, when predication is conflated with the identity relation
-- or, when the
"is" of predication is reconfigured as an "is" of identity
--, it becomes
easy to claim that
an object is now only its 'essential' self when it is put into a
special sort of relation
with its unique Hegelian 'other' -- its
internally-linked 'opposite', which 'other' often turned out to be whatever was
given a Proper Name by the back end of a
suitably
doctored
proposition -- i.e., but only after it had been 'dialectically processed' by
Hegel.
This
move now fed into the belief that:
(i)
Reality itself is fundamentally contradictory,
(ii) Everything in existence is a
UO, comprised of a given object
or process and its dialectically-linked 'other',
which then morphed into the dogma that,
(iii) All 'true knowledge' is of the
'infinite', expressed by whatever these doctored predicates
were now
supposed to 'designate'.
As we will also see, this not only motivated the thesis that,
(iv) Everything is interconnected,
but also the dogma
that,
(v) Motion and change are inherent properties of matter,
as
well as the
idea that,
(vi) There are in fact no genuine falsehoods, just closer approximations to Absolute
Truth,
and
hence the doctrine that,
(vii) 'Truth is the Whole',
and then finally the belief that,
(viii) 'Freedom' is just the dialectical flip-side of
'necessity'.
From this
seemingly insignificant logical blunder, a whole web of DM-theses were
spun, which were then woven into a complex,
'mystical tapestry' by
generations of diligent dialectical digits.
Behind all this ran the
parallel idea that,
(ix) 'The process of abstraction' is what 'enables'
each adept to make a series of surprisingly easy discoveries concerning
fundamental aspects of reality --but generated from thought alone
-- without leaving the comfort of
their
non-dialectical armchairs.
So, the
'historic' discovery that the universe is populated with, and hence powered by,
'contradictions' wasn't based on experiment, observation, or any of the
sciences -- nor yet on the practice of a revolutionary party --, but on
this Hegelian logical blunder!
The confusion of predicate expressions with the Proper Names of abstract particulars, and the "is" of predication with the
"is" of identity, is the real source of the entire DM-menagerie.
As we have seen, the traditional approach to philosophical 'knowledge' was founded on the
following four guiding ideas:
(1)
Reality is populated with "essences", hidden 'beneath appearances',
which underpin every material object and process in existence.
Allied with this is the dogma that the universe has an underlying 'rational'
structure, and that 'reality' (logically and not accidentally) depends on this structure -- something that can be apprehended by
the application of thought alone.
(2) When viewed in the 'right way', general terms are in fact disguised
Proper Names, of which a select sub-group designate these "essences".
(3) Ordinary words are
totally unsuitable for expressing these deeper,
essential, 'philosophical truths' -- even if they dimly hint at them (when
they have been suitably doctored by the 'process of abstraction', a
psychological faculty allegedly possessed by, or exercised in, the 'mind', and helpfully identified for us without the use of a single experiment, set
of observations or even a consulting couch!). A more muscular
approach to theory is therefore required so that "speculative thought"
is capable of 'allowing'
Traditional Theorists to gain (easy) access to the 'hidden secrets' governing and
inter-linking these 'essences' -- the results of which
are (miraculously) valid for all of space and time.
Unfortunately, these Cosmic Verities can't be apprehended by
the senses, which means that this approach to knowledge lies ways beyond inspection
or confirmation,
and hence it is free from democratic control. Despite this, these 'essences' definitely exist -- or, so Traditional Philosophers
would have us believe -- which is a doctrine
that was 'substantiated', not by scientific evidence or research, but by
the use of incomprehensible jargon.
(4)
Although the existence of these 'cosmic
verities' can't be confirmed by any known physical
means, that just shows they are more fundamental
than anything accessible to the senses, and so their existence can only be 'verified' by indirect,
purely 'rational'
means. While we can't see them, or detect them in any way, shape or form, the logical
structure of our sentences tells us they are more real than any of the
material objects and processes in the world around us, or even those studied by the
sciences. We know this by a 'law of
cognition', or 'the light of reason'.
No problem there then...
Naturally, this means that these "essences", these 'abstractions', have
had to be
imposed on nature and society.30
Normally
(i.e., to a normal, materially-grounded human being -- like, say, a
worker) the occurrence of the word "is" in everyday sentences would
usually herald an incipient description, ascription, or predication –- i.e., it would suggest
to that ordinary individual that someone
was about to say something about someone or something, such as: "The boss
is a crook", "This strike is too passive", or "The
Morning Star
is out today".
Plainly, these sentences don't mean that The Morning Star is identical with
whatever it is that is out today, or that the boss is identical with a crook! (Which one?)
Or even that the boss is identical (or, indeed, is and is not identical) with the
'Essence of Crook'!
[For example,
"The
Morning Star
is out today"
is true under
different circumstances to
"The Morning Star is identical with whatever it is that is out today."
The Tory
Daily Telegraph is out on the same days as
the Morning Star, so it too will always be "out today". And yet the
Morning Star isn't identical with the Daily Telegraph. Hence, when "The
Morning Star
is out today" is true "The Morning Star is identical with whatever it is
that is out today" will be false. So, the second sentence isn't a paraphrase of
the first.]
Except under the influence of
a mind-altering drug,
or
quart bottle of vodka, why would
anyone conclude that the
second example above means that the said strike was identical with too passive?!
[Resist
the temptation to laugh at this point, but there is one deeply devoted dialectical disciple who does think this of the boss,
that he is identical with a crook --, for example, check
this
out! -- and he maintained that rather odd belief even after his error had been exposed
for all to see.
Worse still, three years later he still thinks this! (Read the sorry tale
here, along with my
reply.)]
Sentences like these wouldn't be interpreted as some sort of hint that
there was a profound philosophical truth hidden somewhere in the linguistic undergrowth
only capable of
being uncovered by a posse of suitably-trained philosophicalword-jugglers
and predicate-manglers.
Indeed, predication itself wouldn't normally be taken to be directed at
the unearthing of a
Pandora's Box of hidden "essences" that supposedly underlie appearances,
and which
may only be
winkled-out by the use of a super-duper "is" of identity. Of course, that is
plainly why no ordinary speaker would come up with such an implausible 'theory', but it
is why, in its modern and most sophisticated form, only an arch Idealist and
Hermetic Harebrain (Hegel)
would actually do that -- and be praised for it by those who claim to be
materialists!
In
stark contrast, and on the basis of
(1)-(4) above,
only those who
have a far less secure grip on material reality than ordinary humans -- i.e., ruling-class hacks, Traditional Philosophers, and, on
the 'left',
LCDs and
HCDs --
will conclude that they alone can
with ease spot such coded messages mysteriously buried in our everyday
sentences.
All they have to do is "reflect" on them, re-write them in their 'correct'
logical form, and the need to test the resulting 'propositions' with repeatable
experiments can conveniently be side-stepped.
[LCD = Low Church Dialectician; HCD =
High Church Dialectician; follow the above links for an explanation.]
Of course,
such
easy moves were originally performed (in the Ancient World) by those who enjoyed more leisure time than is good for any human being.
In this way then, it seemed plain to this
exclusive band of
intrepid abstractors that each diminutive "is" always hides
an identity that expressed a relation between an individual and an
invisible "essence", camouflaged behind an otherwise innocent-looking outer
façade -- the union of a letter "i" with a letter "s"
(or other diminutive letters in different languages) --, to form the truly
magical word, "is".
For ease of reference it
might be helpful to call this approach to discourse and its handy connection
with 'philosophical knowledge': "Language Implies Essence" -- or
LIMPE, for short.31
The disastrous impact on dialectics of this retreat from the
material-world into a LIMPE-esque, parallel universe
may best be appreciated by
considering the use dialecticians themselves have made of the following
overworked sentence (in this case, taken from
Lenin):
Given LIMPE, H1 isn't just saying something
about John, as only 'vulgar materialists' would rashly conclude. Far from it; it alerts
ThePhilosopher -- nay The Dialectician --,
to a hidden relation that exists between two named entities -- John and
the abstract universal, Man (Humanity, Mankind, or Manhood -- depending on
which strain of Traditional Myth-making a given theorist is trying to promote). But, since it isn't
possible to predicate one individual thing of another, the original
predication must be reconfigured in the
above manner, so that it now becomes an
ascription of one or more of the following:
(A) A class membership relation between an individual and a named
group, class, category, collection or set.
(B) An identity relation between a named individual and another
particular, individual or 'general' concept, class, category,
collection or set (picked out by a Proper Name or some other singular term).
(C) An identity relation between two classes, groups, concepts or
ideas.
(D) A partial or complete 'containment' relation between
subject and predicate terms, or sets and elements of the same.32
Ever since Plato and Aristotle's
set this band-wagon rolling, metaphysicians of
every stripe have seized on one or more of the above as the 'correct' analysis
of a superficially simple sentence like H1 -- a form of words, it is worth
noting, that wouldn't
even puzzle a working-class child.32a
Indeed, it takes an expensive education and years of training
--
or leisure -- to
misconstrue ordinary
language so comprehensibly.
[FL = Formal Logic; LOI = Law of
Identity.]
For DM-fans, one or more of the above
alternatives also motivates the allegation that FL is based on the
LOI.
(1) Predications are disguised identity statements.
[Some
might object that only certain predications -- so-called 'essential
predications' -- are identity statements. I have dealt with that objection
below,
here
and here,
as well as in
Appendix D. The example that Hegel himself
used, "The rose is red", is by no means an 'essential predication.]
(2) But, identity statements can't adequately reflect changing
reality since they attribute unchanging natures to objects, or at least
to the
relations that exist between them. In the
present case, this would involve the relation that supposedly exists between John and
'Manhood',
or, indeed, the Rose and 'Redness'. So, ordinary language, 'commonsense' and 'formal thinking'
plainly put objects and processes into unchanging categories.
(3) Ordinary discourse and FL are therefore
defective (at least at this level of dialectical analysis, even though they
are perfectly adequate in their own limited sphere, everyday life) That is because they are based on the idea that things don't
change; they attribute "this" or "that" unchanging property
to objects and processes, asserting, for example, that John is identical
to a universal, 'Manhood'.
[Quotations from the DM-classics and
'lesser' DM-clones that express the above ideas can be accessed
here.]
(5)
So, a correct 'dialectical' analysis of propositions
like H1 reveals the following, deeper truth: ordinary language vaguely alludes to an
identity between subject and predicate names (or the objects they supposedly designate;
as noted above, Hegel continually mixes the two up, and so do his latter-day
groupies,
DM-theorists). But, this can't be correct, because no
particular can be identical to a universal. This then leads "speculative reason"
'dialectically' to the opposite conclusion that the subject of such an ascription
of identity (i.e., "John"), or what its name designates (in this case, John) isn't and can't be identical with the said
predicate (now interpreted as a named abstract particular). So, in
reality John can't be identical with this predicate, or with what it 'names' (i.e.,
John isn't
identical with 'Man', or
'Manhood'). 'Thought' is thus led (by Spinoza's Principle) to the negation of this putative identity
(via H1a and H1b).
H1: John is a man.
H1a:
John is identical with Manhood.
H1b:
John is not identical with Manhood.
H1c:
John is not not identical with Manhood.
(6) But, this, too, can't be
the entire truth, since John is essentially a man -- in which sense he is
identified by his essence. This leads 'thought' back in the
opposite conclusion, once more, to the negation
of the former negation, yielding the final result that John is not
not identical with Manhood (i.e., H1c) -- which now means that all of the
concepts involved in this word-play are understood in a new
and more 'determinate' light. This astounding conclusion now expresses an
'essential' truth about John -- and, indeed, about everything else in the entire
universe, since a similar 'analysis' will reveal that every object and process is
essentially connected with its own unique Hegelian 'other', in a negative and then in a 'doubly
negative' sort of way, along similar lines. This 'liberating analysis' isn't available to those who are trapped either by
'formal thinking' or 'commonsense'. Or, of course, those who just don't 'understand'
dialectics.
(7) So, not only
is "thought" driven to opposite poles in its
bid to differentiate an object like John from all others (and this we are told necessarily involves,
in every single case, negativity -- that is because, clearly, John is not Peter, not Fred, not
Tarquin…, neither is he a mountain, a planet, a coffee mug, a toilet plunger, a meteorite...),
"thought" is then forced to conclude that no individual object could be
identical with a
universal. In that case, John is not mankind. But, as we saw, a further
consideration of his 'concept', his
'essence', tells us he is also not not-mankind, which means his original
identity needs revising -- or, made more 'determinate'.
(8) John is thus made 'determinate' by negation
-- as is everything
else. In which case, the whole determines the part and the part determines the whole, via
negativity.
(9) Hey presto,
it is now 'obvious' that everything in existence has negativity
(or 'difference') programmed into it, simply because dialectically-'enhanced' subject-predicate
propositions reveal this hidden truth to those with the eyes to see --and it is this
negativity which powers the entire universe.
The Big
Bang from the Big Re-write.
Which is why this approach to 'logic' was earlier
said to be the source of the
Dialectical Dilithium Crystals: by
these means DM-Superscience was 'powered by little other than Sloppy Syntax. No wonder
then that
HCDs
think
"negativity" has "power" -- indeed,
rather like Satan,
Shiva and
Ahriman of
Mystical Theology.
This is just one more (ancient) ruling-idea that still rules.
LIMPE thus encourages dialecticians to draw the
conclusion that not only do our words and concepts contain contradictions (John
is identical with, not identical with, and then not not-identical with, "Manhood"), concepts themselves
clearly change as a result of 'internal developments' like this -- but only
if "Reason"
is allowed to reprocesses them "dialectically", at a
higher level. This 'logical development' reflects parallel changes in Ideal
Reality. Or, even better: when this 'development' has been given a 'materialist flip',
it supposedly reflects changes that take place across the entire universe
independently of thought.
So, John is now not not-identical with "Manhood"; in fact John is
now a NON-person; the NON powers him along -- he is a 'self-developing' being.
[On
the serious, if not fatal, difficulties these ideas create for dialecticians, see Essay Eight
Part One.]
[NON = Negation of the Negation.]
This
means that 'concepts' and processes not only have 'negativity', and hence "movement", built into them, they
develop as "new content" emerges, courtesy of the irrepressible NON. This
in turn implies that things and
processes (now irrevocably confused with words) possess
"identity-in-difference" [IED], instead of plain and simple
material identity.
After having been suitably
processed (i.e., Dialectically Mangled), all our words have dialectics
built into them, or so the
DM-Cliff Notes tell us. And it is this that 'allows', nay encourages,
even requires dialecticians impose their doctrines on nature and society -- and then
pretend
they haven't done just that!
[In fact, as we will see, this is the exact
opposite of the truth.]
So,
when H1:
H1: John is a man,
is examined in more detail,
in a "speculative" sort of way, free from the usual constraints social
interaction places on the use of language -- hence, if 'Reason' is alienated from
social being, if language "goes on holiday" (to paraphrase Wittgenstein) --
and we re-write H1 as H1a, we may now 'rightly' conclude that John couldn't possibly be identical with
all men.
H1d:
John is identical with Man.
From
there it is but a short
hop and step to the 'derivation' of the
aforementioned dialectical contradiction -- for, according to H1b, John
both is and isn't identical with all men, the same and yet different from the
pack. But, because of the NON, he is also not not-identical with all men; he is
thus identical and not identical with his own 'other' (H1c), his Ideal alter-ego --,
which is an artificial abstraction that has no material correlate, conjured
into existence courtesy of the garbled 'logic' imported from the scribblings of a Hare-Brained Hermetic Mystic.
H1: John is a man.
H1a:
John is identical with Manhood.
H1b:
John is not identical with Manhood.
H1c:
John is not not identical with Manhood.
[UO = Unity of Opposites.]
This now traps the hapless John in the dialectical machinery,
a super-charged contraption that also powers the rest
of the universe, since he is now a UO, a unity of Identity and Difference. As a result of the logical
propertiesLIMPE
has imposed on him he must of
necessity undergo dialectical change, an inter-galactic process into which he
has now been
press-ganged.
This is the key to
understanding the self-movement of
everything in existence, according to Lenin:
"The identity of opposites…is the
recognition…of the contradictory, mutually exclusive, opposite tendencies
in all
phenomena and processes of nature…. The condition for the knowledge of all
processes of the world in their 'self-movement', in their spontaneous
development, in their real life, is the knowledge of them as a unity of
opposites. Development is the 'struggle' of opposites…. [This] alone
furnishes the key to the self-movement of everything existing…." [Lenin
(1961),
pp.357-58. Bold emphasis alone added.]
However --
and to spoil the metaphysical merriment --, the only
evidential support this creative word-juggling has ever enjoyed is this
ambitious re-write of ordinary language predicative sentences that use the verb
"to be", the inner 'logic' of which itself
depends on a crass misreading the surface grammar of
a rather unimportant sub-set of sentences found only in the Indo-European family of languages
-- and nothing more!
You just couldn't make this up.
Except, you needn't bother; Hegel and his groupies have already done that for
you.
Several other
myth-begotten creatures of DM-lore owe their existence to this syntactical
surgery -- for instance, the mysterious "Totality". A reading of the "is" of predication as an "is" of identity
motivates the idea that everything must be interconnected.
The 'reasoning'
goes something like this:
(1) If,
as in H1-H1c below, John is both identical and not identical with a universal, and
this universal has the infinite built into it (otherwise it wouldn't be
a universal), then John is only himself when he is viewed ininfinite
dialectical connection with everything else of the 'same' sort.
(2) If John is now put
in a similar relation with all the predicates applicable to him (including all the
negative examples expressed in propositions like "John is not Blair", or "John is not the
Pope", "John is not an interstellar dust cloud", required by the
SGP),
then he is in fact only an individual of the sort he is because of the seemingly
endless and
infinite (negative or positive) connections he
actually has with everything in existence (i.e., all those "mediacies"
that
Lenin spoke about), which
connections give him
his 'determinate'
nature -- if we but knew what the latter was in all its infinite glory. That is why
Engels said what he did about the "asymptotic"
path to knowledge. Moreover, all these properties and relations are "internally
related" to John -- not externally, or contingently, but 'logically' -- every last
one
guaranteed by the alleged import of a
re-configured participle of the diminutive
verb, "to be", namely "is".
H1: John is a man.
H1a:
John is identical with Manhood.
H1b:
John is not identical with Manhood.
H1c:
John is not not identical with Manhood.
(3)
By these means John assumes truly
cosmic significance; the whole of reality is linked to him and makes
him what he is, essentially. Not only that, but everything else is conditioned in like manner
by John in return. John is now at the centre of an intricate web of identities and
differences spanning right across all that exists, for all of time. This
unassuming individual is
now situated at the very heart the meaning universe -- and so is everyone and
so is everything else. All of reality defines John, all of reality is what
gives meaning to his existence and substance to his nature, and he returns the
favour to all that exists (the
part is determined by the whole and the whole by the part). To that extent, all of 'Being' depends on him, and he depends
on all of 'Being' in return. "As above, so below",
as
the old Hermetic saying put things. [On that, see below.]
And all this from a
single sentence written
in Indo-European grammar!
Who'd
have thunk it?
Even
so, one small step for John is a huge step for mankind. Innovative logic like
this can't be confined, corralled or restricted to just one individual; it has quite
expansive, if not imperialist aspirations as humanity itself now assumes universal significance. The
fate of our entire species now takes centre stage in John's meaning universe
(and not just his) -- the fate of every last atom of which is 'determined' by the semi-Divine
Logic built into 'reality' courtesy of
DL.
Hence, whatever happens to
John, or to humanity, is interconnected with everything in existence, and vice versa.
Indeed, each of us has our cosmic role assigned to us by such linguistic
flummery: as above, so below:
"This phrase comes from the beginning of
The Emerald Tablet
and
embraces the entire system of traditional and modern magic which was inscribed
upon the tablet in cryptic wording by
Hermes Trismegistus. The
significance of this phrase is that it is believed to hold the key to all
mysteries. All systems of magic are claimed to function by this formula. 'That
which is above is the same as that which is below'...Macrocosmos is the same as
microcosmos....
"To the magician the magical act, that of causing a
transformation in a thing or things without any physical contact, is
accomplished by an imaginative act accompanied by the will that the wanted
change will occur. [A quintessentially Maoist idea, too -- RL.] The magical act and imaginative act becomes one and the same.
The magician knows with certainty that for the change to occur he must will it
to happen and firmly believe it will happen. Here it may be noted that magic and
religion are akin: both require belief that a miracle will occur. [Or, indeed, a
'great
leap forward' -- RL.]
"To bring about such a change the magician uses the conception of 'dynamic
interconnectedness to describe the physical world as the sort of thing that
imagination and desire can effect. The magician's world is an independent
whole, a web of which no strand is autonomous. Mind and body, galaxy and atom,
sensation and stimulus, are intimately bound. Witchcraft strongly imbues the
view that all things are independent and interrelated.' These concepts pivot
on the belief that all things come from the One Thing, or First Cause, and 'Its
power is integrating, if it be turned into earth.'" [Quoted from
here.
Bold emphases added; quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions
adopted at this site. Links added.]
"Another parallel between Hermeticism and Hegel is the doctrine of internal
relations. For the Hermeticists, the cosmos is not a loosely connected, or to
use Hegelian language, externally related set of particulars. Rather, everything
in the cosmos is internally related, bound up with everything else.... This
principle is most clearly expressed in the so-called Emerald Tablet of
Hermes Trismegistus, which begins with the famous lines "As above, so below."
This maxim became the central tenet of Western occultism, for it laid the basis
for a doctrine of the unity of the cosmos through sympathies and correspondences
between its various levels. The most important implication of this doctrine is
the idea that man is the microcosm, in which the whole of the macrocosm is
reflected.... The universe is an internally related whole pervaded by cosmic energies."
[Magee (2008), p.13. Bold emphases added; paragraphs merged. More on this hereand
here.]
[DL = Dialectical Logic;
LIE = Linguistic Idealism; UO = Unity of Opposites.]
Not only is John related to the Whole, he is what he is
because of that dialectically-enhanced diminutive verb, "is", which implies he both is and is not identical (and then
not not-identical) with an infinite concept.33
Indeed, and in this way, every person, atom, and microscopic speck in the entire universe,
every process in nature and society, for all of time, has assigned to it its
rightful, 'mediated' place in the Infinite Whole. Every single object and process is identical
with, and not identical with, and then not not-identical
with its unique Hegelian 'other', guaranteed by a 'logic' that
smuggled identity into sentences in place of boring old predication.
H1: John is a man.
H1a:
John is identical with Manhood.
H1b:
John is not identical with Manhood.
H1c:
John is not not identical with Manhood.
As Lenin noted:
"'This harmony is precisely absolute Becoming
change, -- not becoming other, now this and then another. The essential thing is
that each different thing, each particular, is different from another, not
abstractly so from any other, but from its other. Each particular
only is, insofar as its other is implicitly contained in its Notion....' Quite
right and important: the 'other' as its other, development into its opposite."
[Lenin
(1961), p.260. Bold emphasis alone added;
quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Lenin is here commenting on
Hegel (1995a), pp.278-98; this
particular quotation coming from p.285. Lenin was clearly using a slightly
different translation.]
Indeed, as Hegel argued, this idea is integral to his doctrine of
reflection:
"Difference as such contains its two sides as moments;
in diversity they fall indifferently apart; in opposition as such,
they are sides of the difference, one being determined only by the other, and
therefore only moments; but they are no less determined within themselves,
mutually indifferent and mutually exclusive: the self-subsistent
determinations of reflection.
"One is the
positive, the other the negative, but the former as the intrinsically positive,
the latter as the intrinsically negative. Each has an indifferent
self-subsistence of its own through the fact that it has within itself the
relation to its other moment; it is thus the whole, self-contained opposition.
As this whole, each is mediated with itself by its other and contains
it. But further, it is mediated with itself by the non-being of its
other; thus it is a unity existing on its own and it excludes the
other from itself.
"The
self-subsistent determination of reflection that contains the opposite
determination, and is self-subsistent in virtue of this inclusion, at the same
time also excludes it; in its self-subsistence, therefore, it excludes from
itself its own self-subsistence. For this consists in containing within
itself its opposite determination -- through which alone it is not a relation to
something external -- but no less immediately in the fact that it is itself, and
also excludes from itself the determination that is negative to it. It is thus
contradiction.
"Difference as such is
already implicitly contradiction; for it is the unity of sides
which are, only in so far as they are not one -- and it is the separation
of sides which are, only as separated in the same relation.
But the positive and negative are the posited contradiction
because, as negative unities, they are themselves the positing of themselves,
and in this positing each is the sublating of itself and the positing of its
opposite. They constitute the determining reflection as exclusive; and
because the excluding of the sides is a single act of distinguishing and each of
the distinguished sides in excluding the other is itself the whole act of
exclusion, each side in its own self excludes itself.
"If we consider the two
determinations of reflection on their own, then the positive is positedness
as reflected into likeness to itself, positedness that is not a
relation to an other, a subsistence, therefore, in so far as positedness is
sublated and excluded. But with this, the positive makes itself into the
relation of a non-being -- into a positedness. It is thus
the contradiction that, in positing identity with itself by excluding
the negative, it makes itself into the negative of what it excludes
from itself, that is, makes itself into its opposite. This, as excluded, is
posited as free from that which excludes it, and therefore as reflected into
itself and as itself exclusive. The exclusive reflection is thus a positing of
the positive as excluding its opposite, so that this positing is immediately the
positing of its opposite which it excludes.
"This is the absolute
contradiction of the positive, but it is immediately the absolute contradiction
of the negative; the positing of each is a single reflection. The
negative, considered on its own over against the positive, is positedness as
reflected into unlikeness to itself, the negative as negative. But the
negative is itself the unlike, the non-being of an opposite; therefore its
reflection into its unlikeness is rather its relation to itself. Negation in
general is the negative as quality, or immediate determinateness;
but the negative as negative, is related to the negative of itself, to
its opposite. If this negative is only taken as identical with the first, then
it, too, like the first, is merely immediate; and so they are not taken as
mutual opposites and therefore not as negatives; the negative is not an
immediate at all. But now, since it is also just as much a fact that each is
the same as its opposite, this relation of the unlike is just as much their
identical relation.
"This is therefore the same
contradiction that the positive is, namely, positedness or negation as
self-relation. But the positive is only implicitly this contradiction,
whereas the negative is the contradiction posited; for the latter,
in virtue of its reflection-into-self which makes it a negative in and for
itself or a negative that is identical with itself, is accordingly determined as
a non-identical, as excluding identity. The negative is this, to be
identical with itself in opposition to identity, and consequently, through
its excluding reflection to exclude itself from itself.
"The negative is, therefore,
the whole opposition based, as opposition, on itself, absolute difference that
is not related to an other; as opposition, it excludes identity from
itself -- but in doing so excludes itself; for as self-relation it is
determined as the very identity that it excludes.
"...Contradiction
resolves itself. In the self-excluding reflection we have just considered,
positive and negative, each in its self-subsistence, sublates itself; each is
simply the transition or rather the self-transposition of itself into its
opposite. This ceaseless vanishing of the opposites into themselves is the
first unity resulting from contradiction...."
[Hegel (1999), pp.433,
§931-939. Bold emphases alone added. This continues in mind-numbing,
brain-cell-crunching fashion for another ten pages! Only masochists should read
any further.]
[This
topic is explored more extensively in Essays Seven
Part Three
and Eight
Part Three.]
This view of reality pictures the logical structure of sentences
mirroring the logical 'essence' of 'Being'; everything is simultaneously both at
the centre of an infinite web of relations and at its periphery; all are
at once insignificant and
all are at the same time cosmically important (a 'unity of opposites'). Part and Whole are interlinked,
inter-determining and inter-defining one another.34
Moreover, while John isn't all of mankind, he is somehow
dialectically united with every human being by their shared 'essence'. This fact allows necessity and contingency to
enter into the picture. Hence, John is
contingently a man
(in that he is this
particular person);
but he is also necessarily a man because an abstract universal so
identifies him as such and constitutes his essence. John is in fact a
UO -- he is both man and non-man (i.e.,
while he is plainly not all men, he shares an 'essence' with all men), revealing his
'essence' as identity-in-difference.
However, the essential nature of each particular (such as
John) isn't immediately apparent to any of our senses. Nevertheless, while the logical
properties fundamental to each individual might appear
to be expressed by an "is" of predication, those with a 'dialectical third eye'
can 'see' that predicative sentences are in fact
identity statements -- something that 'speculative reason' alone is capable of
revealing by the simple expedient of examining -- and then changing -- the
logical structure of a few
innocent-looking sentences. Of course, the rest of humanity -- those lost in a fog of 'formal
thinking' -- well, they just don't
"understand" dialectics.
This means that John is in reality other than he seems: John's material
properties only appear to be contingently interrelated to those of
other objects and processes around him. This misperception is either the result of a 'commonsense' failure to see things
'in the abstract'
-- i.e.,
essentially --, or because of a failure to connect the abstract with the
concrete in dialectical union/tension.34a
But, below the surface, where
neither human sight nor scientific equipment can penetrate, the necessary connections that exist between individuals and
universals may easily be ascertained -- only ifthey are viewed in the right manner
(i.e., 'essentially' and 'dialectically', but, manifestly, not materially).
Indeed, those connections are revealed to each
DM-adept, not by observation and
experiment, but by the 'careful' dialectical analysis of
a suitably
'doctored' sentence about John!
DM-wizards,
well-versed in these esoteric arts, are now uniquely placed to unmask cosmic-wide truths
lying 'below the surface'; verities unavailable to lesser souls who
stumble around, lost in a haze of 'static thought', whose ideas are
dominated by that truly awful intellectual bully, the "abstract understanding"
-- an aspect of the human psyche unknown to the psychological sciences, even to
this day.
By these means,
dialectical acolytes can now extrapolate from nouns to necessity,
and concepts to contingency, arguing that
both of these govern all of reality. That is because -- sure as eggs both are and
aren't eggs -- a covert reference to the now
de-personified Greek gods,
Moira and
Tyche
(Fate and Luck, Necessity and Contingency) had all along been buried in language,
had we but known it.
However, no one is quite sure who managed to hide
such super-facts in the vernacular, since
they have been
buried so
deep that only those who have
quaffed the dialectical Kool Aid are
capable of discovering them for the rest
of humanity. Who could have guessed they could be unearthed by inspecting
innocent-looking linguistic facts about 'John' and his 'Manhood', expressed in
a
soporifically banal sentence about 'him'? Who could have guessed that the 'logical
force' of negation, which has very helpfully been revealed to us by DM-fans,
controlled him and every last one of us -- as well as the most distant
galaxies in the universe?
However, it isn't too clear whether or not this 'hidden force' only began to
control us when some bright spark first came out with
tokens of the following
type-sentence: "(Insert your favourite name here) is a man" -- just as it isn't
too clear if the universe is controlled in this way only if a sexist sentence
that mentions John, but not Joan, is chosen -- and one of both are related to
"man", but not "woman".
The
conundrum that counterposes chance to necessity is, therefore, no sooner posed
than solved by innovative logic
like this, which is able to map-out everything in the entire universe,
employing the Hermetic jargon found in a book with no maps, and even less
genuine logic, written by that arch-mystic Hegel. John's local nature, and all
that happens to him (and every atom in his body) throughout his life is 'determined' by these universe-wide 'essences',
although he is at the
same time 'free' because of his subsumption under cosmic 'law' -- this 'contradiction'
paradoxically 'solved' by its merely being called a 'contradiction'!
Through all of this,
dialecticians imagine they are
actually examining
reality itself, and not just the supposed implications of a handful of doctored
sentences, or 'concepts', supposedly aboutseemingly insignificant parts of
it. As noted earlier -- and contrary to what one might have expected of those who
still
claim to have the word "materialist" somewhere in their job description
-- expert
'dialectical insight' like this isn't based on careful empirical work; it is the result of
the exercise of a rare gift, the ability to view an ordinary indicative sentence
in two distinct ways at the same time:
(a) Superficially, comprised of a subject and a predicate
--
mirroring the surface appearance of things, which is adequate enough for
materially-bound individuals, every day life, and those who take language at face value -- such
as, say,
workers -- but certainly not for 'philosophers', who know better.
And:
(b) More profoundly, as an identity
statement that reveals the underlying identity-in-difference at work in all
objects and processes,
and which reflects the abstract/concrete nature of reality --, 'knowledge' of which
is the special preserve of our very own, self-appointed, Dialectical Superscientists (i.e., those with the dialectical equivalent of
'Second
Sight').
Hence, a sort of intellectual gestalt-switch operates in
each dialectically-tuned mind, which allows those suitably blessed to hop back and forth
between two differing interpretations of the word "is", as it
features in this tiny sub-set
of sentences, found in just one family of languages.
Given the truth of
LIE, language thus contains a
secret code that conceals an even bigger cosmic secret -- the DM-equivalent of
the
Kabbalah, or even
The True Bible Code.35
The
linguistic
hocus pocus described in earlier sections of this Essay represents the real
dialectical "path of cognition" -- the 'philosophical pilgrimage' toward enlightenment along which
path all aspiring novices must pass at least once in their lives, the DM-equivalent of
The Hajj. It has nothing to do
with the mythical 'process of abstraction' touted by the official DM-brochure.
This isn't just my say-so; the above allegation is
easily confirmed by a consideration of the following passages from the DM-classics:
"The identity of thinking and being, to
use Hegelian language, everywhere coincides with your example of the circle and
the polygon. Or the two of them, the concept of a thing and its reality, run
side by side like two asymptotes, always approaching each other but never
meeting. This difference between the two is the very difference which prevents
the concept from being directly and immediately reality and reality from being
immediately its own concept. Because a concept has the essential nature of the
concept and does not therefore prima facie directly coincide with
reality, from which it had to be abstracted in the first place, it is
nevertheless more than a fiction, unless you declare that all the results of
thought are fictions because reality corresponds to them only very circuitously,
and even then approaching it only asymptotically…. In other words, the unity of
concept and phenomenon manifests itself as an essentially infinite process, and
that is what it is, in this case as in all others." [Engels to Schmidt
(12/03/1895), in Marx and Engels (1975b), pp.457-58, and Marx and Engels (2004),
pp.463-64.
Bold emphases added.]
"'Fundamentally, we can know only the infinite.' In
fact all real exhaustive knowledge consists solely in raising the individual
thing in thought from individuality into particularity and from this into
universality, in seeking and establishing the infinite in the finite, the
eternal in the transitory…. All true knowledge of nature is knowledge of the
eternal, the infinite, and essentially absolute…. The cognition of the
infinite…can only take place in an infinite asymptotic progress." [Engels
(1954),
pp.234-35.
Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site;
paragraphs merged.]
"Abstract
identity
(a=a; and negatively, a cannot be
simultaneously equal and unequal to a) is likewise inapplicable in
organic nature. The plant, the animal, every cell is at every moment of its life
identical with itself and yet becoming distinct from itself.... The fact that identity contains difference within itself is
expressed in every sentence, where the predicate is necessarily different from
the subject; the lily is a plant,
the rose is red,
where, either in the subject or in the predicate there is something that is not
covered by the predicate or the subject…. That from the outset identity with
itself requires difference from everything else as its complement, is
self-evident." [Ibid.,
pp.214-15.
Italic emphases in the original.]
Engels clearly saw no problem with his derivation of what
look
like
scientific conclusions -- which apply to everything in existence
-- from a re-configuration of the
'logical'structure ofa handful ofunrepresentative sentences:
"the lily is a plant, the rose is red."
He also failed to notice that this approach conflicted with his own sharp criticism of
Hegel's 'method':
"All
three [laws -- RL] are developed by Hegel in his idealist fashion as mere laws of thought:
the first, in the first part of his Logic, in the Doctrine of Being;
the second fills the whole of the second and by far the most important part of
his Logic, the Doctrine of Essence; finally the third figures
as the fundamental law for the construction of the whole system. The mistake
lies in the fact that these laws are foisted on nature and history as laws of
thought, and not deduced from them. This is the source of the whole forced and
often outrageous treatment; the universe, willy-nilly, is made out to be
arranged in accordance with a system of thought which itself is only the
product of a definite stage of evolution of human thought." [Engels
(1954),
p.62. Bold emphasis alone added.]
But this is precisely where Engels found this
example of sub-Aristotelian 'logic'. There is no way he could have deduced
these ideas from a scientific investigation of nature, only from an
artificial 'analysis' of a tiny sub-set of sentences (the
subject-copula-predicate form that takes an "is", found almost exclusively in the Indo-European
family of languages), the conclusion then airily imposed on
reality!
So, while
Engels might
have thought he was analysing nature in the raw, he was in fact reproducing
Hegel's misguided interpretation of the logical properties of a un-important sub-section of Indo-European
grammar. He even
reproduced, unchanged, Hegel's
own examples!
The fact that he was
deluding himself can be seen by his use of the phrase
"self-evident" in the last sentence of the second passage quoted above:
"Abstract
identity
(a=a; and negatively, a cannot be
simultaneously equal and unequal to a) is likewise inapplicable in
organic nature. The plant, the animal, every cell is at every moment of its life
identical with itself and yet becoming distinct from itself.... The fact that identity contains difference within itself is
expressed in every sentence, where the predicate is necessarily different from
the subject; the lily is a plant, the rose is red,
where, either in the subject or in the predicate there is something that is not
covered by the predicate or the subject…. That from the outset identity with
itself requires difference from everything else as its complement, is
self-evident." [Ibid.,
pp.214-15.
Bold emphasis alone added.]
Substantive truths about the world may be evident
following upon an investigation that manages to find relevant evidence, but
they can't be self-evident -- not unless they can attest for themselves.
In
that case, Engels's use of the phrase "self-evident" was either an
inappropriate hyperbole or it was an unconscious give-away. When something is
self-evident it provides evidence on its own behalf; naturally,
that would make it auto-interpretingand self-authenticating,
implying that it is an agent of some sort, and therefore
quasi-human. In fact, the phrase "self-evidence" is only rightly applicable
if a deduction has been made (by a human being) from the supposed meaning of certain words, which
is why no supporting evidence would be necessary. For example, no evidence is
required to establish the 'truth' of, say, "A regicide is king-killer", or "A
vixen is a female fox". Hence, this give-away tells us that Engels's
conclusions follow
from language and thought alone, not from evidence.
If
Engels were serious in his use of this
term -- and it must be
recalled that this passage comes from unpublished notebooks, so they might not
represent his more considered thoughts --, it would reveal just how deep his Idealism
had sunk into his thought, as George Novack and Maurice Cornforth pointed out:
"A consistent materialism cannot proceed from
principles which are validated by appeal to abstract reason, intuition,
self-evidence or some other subjective or purely theoretical source. Idealisms
may do this. But the materialist philosophy has to be based upon evidence taken
from objective material sources and verified by demonstration in practice...."
[Novack (1965), p.17. Bold emphasis added.]
"Our party philosophy, then, has a right to lay
claim to truth. For it is the only philosophy which is based on a standpoint
which demands that we should always seek to understand things just as they
are…without disguises and without fantasy…. Marxism, therefore, seeks to base our ideas
of things on nothing but the actual investigation of them, arising from and
tested by experience and practice. It doesnot invent a 'system' as previous
philosophers have done, and then try to make everything fit into it…."
[Cornforth (1976), pp.14-15. Bold emphasis added; paragraphs merged.]
However, in that earlier passage, Engels
appears to attribute intelligence to linguistic
expressions and not just to the humans who employ them:
"The fact that identity contains difference within itself is
expressed in every sentence, where the predicate is necessarily different from
the subject; the lily is a plant, the rose is red,
where, either in the subject or in the predicate there is something that is not
covered by the predicate or the subject…. That from the outset identity with
itself requires difference from everything else as its complement, is
self-evident." [Engels (1954),
pp.214-15.
Bold emphasis alone added.]
Self-evidence,
as noted above, emerges
(if or when it does) from a 'conceptual' or linguistic analysis of certain words,
phrases or propositions, for which extraneous evidence is irrelevant --
as our use of that term itself suggests ("self-evident"). Now this
rather strict epistemological condition -- self-evidence -- could only
be satisfied if the linguistic expression
itself were tautological, or where, perhaps, it might even strike its appraiser as a trivial, linguistic 'truth'.
So, if things were as Engels airily asserted, then nature could only contain self-evident truths if it
were a huge tautology,
if it had trivially-true sentences plastered all over it, or if it were itself
language-, or concept-like (as indeed
Ancient Theologians supposed it to be, well over two thousand years
ago).
However, nature isn't made of subjects and predicates, nor has it been
fly-posted with trivially-true indicative sentences by a mischievous agent
acting under orders from 'Being Itself'. Engels surely knew this. The only
conclusion possible, therefore, is that he, too, had been seduced by LIMPE -- as
also seems to have been the case with all subsequent dialecticians.
[LIMPE = Language Implies Essence -- explained
earlier.]
Be this as it may,
and as we will see
here, the "self-evidence" to which Engels
refers is in fact the exact opposite.
Another rather fitting 'dialectical inversion' for readers to ponder.
Lenin'sPhilosophical Notebooks contain similar passages that illustrate the 'power' of 'innovative' Hegelian 'logic'. A particularly good
example (and one which almost single-handedly commits all of the dialectical
sins outlined
earlier) is the following:
"To begin with what is the simplest, most ordinary, common,
etc., [sic] with anyproposition...: [like] John is a man…. Here
we already have dialectics (as Hegel's genius recognized): the individual
is the universal…. Consequently, the opposites (the individual is opposed
to the universal) are identical: the individual exists only in the connection
that leads to the universal. The universal exists only in the individual and
through the individual. Every individual is (in one way or another) a universal.
Every universal is (a fragment, or an aspect, or the essence of) an individual.
Every universal only approximately embraces all the individual objects. Every
individual enters incompletely into the universal, etc., etc. Every individual
is connected by thousands of transitions with other kinds of individuals
(things, phenomena, processes), etc. Here already we have the elements,
the germs of the concept of necessity, of objective connection in nature,
etc. Here already we have the contingent and the necessary, the phenomenon and
the essence; for when we say John is a man…we disregard a number of attributes
as contingent; we separate the essence from the appearance, and
counterpose the one to the other….
Thus in any proposition we can (and must) disclose as a
'nucleus' ('cell') the germs of all the elements of dialectics, and
thereby show that dialectics is a property of all human knowledge in general."
[Lenin (1961),
pp.359-60.
Bold and italic emphases in the original; paragraphs merged.]
Admittedly,
Lenin did go on to mention
the general support the sciences provided for this rather odd view of language,
but he failed to say how a finitely large body of evidence (even if he
had produced any, which he didn't) could
possibly confirm the truth of his sweeping generalisations. Nor did he
even so much as try to account
for the fact that his theory is based on a crass misreading of a
diminutive verb found almost exclusively in the Indo-European family of languages
-- which, of
course, means that what he says can't be a "property of all human knowledge in general".36
For example -- and linguistic juggling to one side
--, what confirmatory evidence could
there possibly be for the following?
"[O]pposites (the individual is opposed to the universal) are
identical: the individual exists only in the connection that leads to the
universal. The universal exists only in the individual and through the
individual. Every individual is (in one way or another) a universal.
Everyuniversal is (a fragment, or an aspect, or the essence of) an
individual. Everyuniversal only approximately embraces all the
individual objects. Everyindividual enters incompletely into the
universal, etc., etc…. Here already we have the contingent and the necessary,
the phenomenon and theessence…." [Ibid. Bold emphases added.]
We
needn't bother searching through the archives for the missing evidence since Lenin was quite open and honest about the real
source of this dialectical flummery, it follows from
Hegel's conclusions about what he says we say; it follows from language:
"Here we already have dialectics (as Hegel's genius recognized)….
[F]or when we say John is a man…we disregard a number of attributes as
contingent; we separate the essence from the appearance, and
counterpose the one to the other…. Thus in anyproposition we
can (and must) disclose as a 'nucleus' ('cell') the germs of all
the elements of dialectics." [Ibid. Bold emphases added.]
"Hegel brilliantly
divined the dialectics of things (phenomena, the world, nature)
in the dialectics of concepts…. This aphorism should be expressed more
popularly, without the word dialectics: approximately as follows: In the
alternation, reciprocal dependence of all
notions, in the identity of their opposites, in the transitions
of one notion into another, in the eternal change, movement of notions, Hegel
brilliantly divined precisely this relation of things to nature…. [W]hat
constitutes dialectics?…. [M]utual dependence of notions all without
exception…. Every notion occurs in a certain relation, in a certain
connection with all the others." [Ibid., pp.196-97.
Bold
emphases alone added.]
Lenin is quite clear here: dialectics follows from the logical
properties built into sentences, from what we say (or, rather from what Hegel
says we say) -- not from a "careful" or scientific study of the world.
But, as we can now see,
what Hegel and Lenin concluded doesn't even follow from a 'careful study' of
what we do in fact say!
[The
real source of all this Hegelian
Hocus Pocus has been exposed
here.]
Finally, this African America protester from the 1960s isn't pointing out that
he is 'identical to a man' (why that is so is explained
here):
It
could be objected that propositions are quite
uncontroversially used to
convey information; human cognition reflects reality accurately when
this information is drawn from nature and society, tested in practice. Hence, it could be
argued that Lenin was simply outlining the consequences of this uncontroversial
fact,
pointing out that the logical structure of language couldn't fail to
mirror the deep structure of reality if language is part of the world, and part of our relation to that world and
to one another. That
being the case, human beings may legitimately infer substantive truths about the
nature of reality from language, since nature's dialectical structure will already have
been 'programmed' into discourse as a result of the interplay between cognition
and practice, reflected in the use of language by countless generations of human beings.
Indeed, that
was the crux of an argument published recently by a Maoist:
"Lenin claims that the statement 'John is a man' is already
charged with contradiction. How? Here, the inclusion of mathematical symbols can
assist us in understanding the scandal. Could we say that 'John is a man'
translates to 'John=Man'? That would suggest that either the term 'John' or the
term 'Man' really is superfluous, that it would suffice to say 'John is John' or
'Man is Man.' However, we know we are conveying something non-trivial. We are
saying that John belongs to the category of man (we could use the logical symbol
ϵ). Does this resolve the problem, though? From a more philosophical point of
view, it is in fact correct to say that John is 'man,' for there is no 'man' in
the abstract, and our abstract notion of 'man' is really only cobbled together
from the common aspects of all individual men. Thus, it turns out that the
simple relationship 'John is a man,' which we all understand, conveys a really
complex notion: the identity of an identity (John=Man) and a non-identity
(John≠Man), coexisting in contradiction. Dialectics is the appreciation that
even the barest expression 'John is a man' is making an interesting argument!
"Marx says 'Capital is labour.' But, how can this be? Capital
is the opposite of labour! So there Marx goes, explaining that
capital is labour, via the commodity cycle. As it turns out, the mere expression
of a contradictory relationship carries the implication that there exists a
process whereby one can reach the other. This is how contradiction is deeply
tied to change.
"The word 'change' is apt because really there are very many ways
that one concept may turn into its opposite. Perspective determines whether we
are still or in motion. Space determines whether a gesture is rude or polite.
With time we see the living become the dying, and the dying give birth to the
living." [Day
(2019). Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions
adopted at this site.]
But,
if that were so, why all the pretence that DM-theses are only
acceptable if they have passed rigorous empirical examination, or have to be
tested in practice? If truths about
nature are so easily obtained -- that is, if they can be ascertained merely
by examining the structure of a few sentences --, why all the pointless rigmarole of
trying to deny that DM is a "master-key" that opens all doors to knowledge?
"Dialectics and
materialism comprise the basic elements of the Marxist cognition of the world.
But this by no means implies that they can be applied in any field of knowledge
like an ever-ready master-key. The dialectic cannot be imposed on facts, it must
be derived from the facts, from their nature and their development. Only
painstaking work on boundless material gave Marx the ability to erect the
dialectical system of economics on the concept of value as realized labour."
[Trotsky (1973),
p.233. Spelling modified to agree with UK English.]
"The dialectic is not a magic
master key for all questions. It does not replace concrete scientific analysis.
But it directs this analysis along the correct road, securing it against sterile
wanderings in the desert of subjectivism and scholasticism." [Trotsky (1971),
p.68.]
"[The laws of dialectics] are not, as
Marx and Engels were quick to insist, a substitute for the difficult empirical
task of tracing the development of real contradictions,not a suprahistorical
master key
whose only advantage is to turn up when no real historical knowledge is
available." [Rees (1998), p.9.]
"'[The dialectic is not a] magic
master key for all questions.' [Quoting Trotsky -- RL.] The dialectic is not a calculator into which
it is possible to punch the problem and allow it to compute the solution. This
would be an idealist method. A materialist dialectic must grow from a
patient, empirical examination of the facts and not be imposed on them…."
[Ibid., p.271. In all of the above, bold emphases alone added.]
Here
are several more DM-statements along the same lines:
"Finally, for me there could be no
question of superimposing the laws of dialectics on nature but of
discovering them in it and developing them from it." [Engels
(1976), p.13. Bold emphasis added.]
"We all agree that in every field of
science, in natural and historical science, one must proceed from the given
facts, in natural science therefore from the various material forms of
motion of matter; that therefore in theoretical natural science too the
interconnections are not to be built into the facts but to be discovered in
them, and when discovered to be verified as far as possible by experiment.
"Just as little can it be a question of
maintaining the dogmatic content of the Hegelian system as it was preached by
the Berlin Hegelians of the older and younger line." [Engels (1954),
p.47. Bold emphasis alone added.]
"In this way, however, the whole dogmatic content of the Hegelian system is
declared to be absolute truth, in contradiction to his dialectical method, which
dissolves all dogmatism...." [Engels
(1888), p.589. Bold emphasis added.]
"But [Marx's] way of
viewing things is not a doctrine but a method. It does not provide ready-made
dogmas, but criteria for further research and the method for this research." [Engels
to Werner Sombart, 11/03/1895; Marx and Engels (2004),
p.461. Bold emphasis added.]
"Idealism and metaphysics are the
easiest things in the world, because people can talk as much nonsense as they
like without basing it on objective reality or having it tested against reality.
Materialism and dialectics, on the other hand, need effort. They must be based
on and tested by objective reality. Unless one makes the effort, one is liable
to slip into idealism and metaphysics." [Mao, quoted from
here. Bold emphasis added.]
"A consistent materialism cannot
proceed from principles which are validated by appeal to abstract reason,
intuition, self-evidence or some other subjective or purely theoretical source.
Idealisms may do this. But the materialist philosophy has to be based upon
evidence taken from objective material sources and verified by demonstration in
practice...." [Novack (1965), p.17. Bold emphasis added.]
"Precisely because Marx's dialectic is a
materialist one, however, it does not start from intuition, preconceptions or
mystifying schemes, but from a full assimilation of scientific data. The
method of investigation must differ from the method of exposition. Empirical
facts have to be gathered first, the given state of knowledge has to be fully
grasped. Only when this is achieved can a dialectical reorganization of the
material be undertaken in order to understand the given totality. If this is
successful, the result is a 'reproduction' in man's thought of this material
totality: the capitalist mode of production." [Mandel
(1976), p19. Bold emphasis added. (This links to a PDF.)]
[Many
more statements like these have been quoted in Essay
Two.]
But, why
is it that only a sub-set of all the
indicative sentences that can be formed in just one family of
languages contains these 'hidden clues'? And even then, why does the grammar of these sentences have to
be altered (from the predicative-, to the relational-form) to make them say what
Idealists, and now DM-fans, want it to say. And why do it in a way that
actually
destroys the
capacity of language to say anything at all?
To be sure, if language does in fact contain
such hidden truths about reality (programmed into its structure,
say), then it could indeed serve as just such a 'master key', and there
would be no quibble. We could as a result openly admit our Idealism, loud and proud --
i.e., admit
that substantive truths are obtained from thought, or from language, alone. It would then
at least be clear that DM
is based, not on an inversion of Hegel, but on a wholesale reversion
to Hegel.
Nevertheless, this
picture of the relation between thought and language was in fact committed to
paper (or, indeed, parchment) long before the required evidence had
turned up; metaphysical chicanery like this dates back to
Anaximander, reaching classical form in the writings of Greek Philosophers like
Heraclitus,
Parmenides,
Plato,
Aristotle,
Plotinus,
Proclus,
Porphyry,
Pseudo-Dionysius and
Iamblichus -- the original progenitors of DM. In their work, empirical evidence didn't (and couldn't)
have featured, let alone have an impact. And that isn't just because there
wasn't much to speak of all those years ago. Nor could evidence justify the idea that reality is mirrored in
this way in or by discourse,
or reveal that there are
'essences' hidden behind 'appearances', and then inform us that every object and process in the
entire universe is interconnected --, or even that everything is
a UO, riddled with 'contradictions'.
In fact, only if language is distorted
in the way indicated above can it be
made to say such convenient things.36a
However, it is now
reasonably clear what
it is that 'justifies' such
dialectical dogmatism: a commitment to
LIMPE, motivated by the idea that reality has
its own
logical form, and a form that just happens to mirror Ancient Greek -- and more widely,
Indo-European --, grammar; and distorted grammar, at that. In which case, this whole sordid affair begins
to make a little more sense. The fact that there were clear political and
ideological reasons why thinkers who belonged to, or were patronised by, the
various ruling-elites the class war has inflicted on humanity -- who were
pre-disposed toward making such moves, and whom the dialectical-classicists
were only too happy to tail-end -- only serves to underline this point.37
Again, it could be argued that since human knowledge has grown
over many centuries, the input from practical activity can't fail to have been
reflected in language. If so, DM-theorists are only extracting from language
what had already been put there.
This response has the merit of
substantiating the
allegations advanced above (and in Essay Twelve
Part One):
in common with every other metaphysical system, DM is based on the fetishisation of language. That is, it
is predicated on the view
that language, far from being a means of communication, is 'really' a
secret code that has profound truths about nature and society encoded
within it. As will be shown in
Essay Twelve Part Four (when it is published), this approach to knowledge
is based on the RRT. [Further discussion of this topic will be postponed
until then; a summary of the argument can be accessed
here.]
[RRT = Reverse Reflection Theory -- this
is the theory that says the world reflects language, not the other way round --
basically it denies that language reflects the world.]
Nevertheless, the situation is far worse than the above
might suggest; that is because Lenin made
unqualified claims about all of reality for all of time (without
exception) based on an examination of a few simplistic and
unrepresentative sentences --, and even then, like Hegel, he had to doctor their
grammar to make these ideas 'work'.
Even if the labours of previous generations of heroic abstractors
had encoded into language all they knew, or thought they knew, about
anything and everything, that wouldn't be enough to substantiate this theory. Lenin's claims were meant to apply to all of
reality for all of time, way beyond the meagre knowledge or intellectual
powers of these plucky ancestral abstractors, even had there been any. Plainly, these
brave abstractors couldn't have programmed
into language anything of which they were ignorant. So, Lenin's bold,
universal
extrapolation of dialectics right across all of reality for all of time
actually projected this theory way beyond anything our ancestors could possibly have known,
which, naturally, means that his words were indeed imposed on
the facts.37a
But even worse still: How would it be possible to guarantee that
the information allegedly encoded in language is correct if there is no
conceivable way it could be checked? For all Lenin knew, this encoded linguistic
'data' could have been totally wrong. Indeed, given DM-epistemology, thereis
in fact no way to distinguish truth from
error. [More on that in Part Four of this Essay.]
An
appeal to practice would be no help, here; as we will see in Essay Ten
Part One, practice can't distinguish truth from error, either.
But, even if
practice could do all that is claimed for it, no amount of evidence would be sufficient to substantiate the sort of claims Lenin made above (or those
recorded in Essay Two);
the conclusions he drew about the nature of the entire universe -- from a single
sentence-type! -- were of an order that puts them way beyond any conceivable body
of evidence. As such, his theory
could only ever have been based on a thoroughly traditional, a priori view of
reality, subsequently reflected back onto nature, and with just this tiny 'linguistic fig-leaf'
of an excuse for cover.
Moreover, had Lenin gone about his daily agitational business
uttering the kind of sentences he considered philosophically significant (such as
"John is a man"), comrades would rightly have questioned his sanity. Just why such
agitationally-, and propagandistically-challenged sentences were deemed significant is, therefore,
something of a dialectical mystery.38
Despite this, there are other reasons beyond those aired above for rejecting this view
of language. Indeed, it is instructive to compare Lenin's conclusions about
"John" with the following sentences, which presumably DM-theorists will want to
reject:
H2: God is our father.
H2a:
God is a father.
That
repudiation might perhaps be prompted by the fact that H2 and/or H2a express an
ideologically-motivated belief for which there isn't one shred of
acceptable evidence (nor could there be). But, if that is so, and to be consistent, we should
also repudiate the following
sentences (from Lenin) for similar reasons -- i.e., for lack of evidence:
H3: The individual is different from the universal.
H4: The opposites are identical.
[H1: John is a man.]
There is no evidence for the truth of either these
sentences, or at least none that isn't itself based on an ancient, garbled analysis of grammar, and only that.
But, of course,
a search for 'evidence', even if one had ever been attempted, wouldn't make it
that
far, for the above are pseudo-grammatical, or
metaphysical
statements, the 'truth' of which supposedly follows from the meaning of the words
they contain. No wonder then that Hegel and Lenin imagined they could
extrapolate from the assumed truth of H3 and H4 (or from "S is P"-type propositions/'judgements'
-- where "S" stands for "Subject" and "P" for "Predicate") to
a set of theses that is supposedly true everywhere and everywhen. If, however, the above
combinations of
words possesses no
sense, then neither H3 nor H4 is
capable of being true or false
(or even 'dialectically' both). [Why this is so is discussed in detail in
Essay Twelve Part One,
summary
here.]
Moreover, at this point it is worth recalling that given certain definitions of
the word "God", H2/H2a are in fact a tautologies! We can be reasonably sure that
this imputed 'logical status' of those two sentences wouldn't be sufficient to guarantee
their acceptance
by a single atheist. No dialectician in her or his left mind would accept an argument that claimed that the whole
truth of theology is contained in such propositions. We surely wouldn't
agree with
the claim that just because
assorted priests and mystery-mongers -- who might be tempted to conclude that the past endeavours of intrepid
religious abstractors and grammarians had programmed into language profound truths about
the nature of the 'Godhead' --, that that fact alone
(not that it is one!) forces us to accept this example of Divine Logic
as Super-Empirically-true.38a
H2: God is our father.
H2a:
God is a father.
Well, the same should
surely be concluded about H1, H3 and H4. In fact,
DM-theorists should only feel confident about their derivation of such a priori
'truths' from such
sentences if they are prepared to acknowledge, say, the validity of
Anselm's infamous
"Ontological
Argument" for the existence of
'God',
since that argument manages
to wring similar Super-Cosmic Verities about 'divine reality' from equally tortured
prose.
H1: John is a man.
H3: The individual is different from the universal.
Nevertheless, there are several serious problems with
Lenin's reasoning, which require resolution before questions can
even be raised about the support his theory might or might not gain from what little 'evidence' there
is.
H1: John is a man.
Lenin clearly interpreted the "is" in H1 as an "is" of identity
(and later perhaps as an "is" of class inclusion). But, because it plainly
isn't one of identity in the vernacular, both Lenin and Hegel
imagined they could
'derive' several counter-intuitive conclusions from the incongruity they had artificially introduced into
such sentences in this way.39
However, instead of concluding perhaps that Hegel's "genius" had misled him --
or that this wasn't the only way
(or even the most obvious, natural, or sane way) to interpret such simple
sentences -- Lenin proceeded to weave several lengths of dialectical cloth from
these slender
threads of
woolly thought.
"To begin with what is the simplest, most ordinary, common,
etc., [sic] with anyproposition...: [like] John is a man…. Here
we already have dialectics (as Hegel's genius recognized): the individual
is the universal…. Consequently, the opposites (the individual is opposed
to the universal) are identical: the individual exists only in the connection
that leads to the universal. The universal exists only in the individual and
through the individual. Every individual is (in one way or another) a universal.
Every universal is (a fragment, or an aspect, or the essence of) an individual.
Every universal only approximately embraces all the individual objects. Every
individual enters incompletely into the universal, etc., etc. Every individual
is connected by thousands of transitions with other kinds of individuals
(things, phenomena, processes), etc. Here already we have the elements,
the germs of the concept of necessity, of objective connection in nature,
etc. Here already we have the contingent and the necessary, the phenomenon and
the essence; for when we say John is a man…we disregard a number of attributes
as contingent; we separate the essence from the appearance, and
counterpose the one to the other….
Thus in any proposition we can (and must) disclose as a
'nucleus' ('cell') the germs of all the elements of dialectics, and
thereby show that dialectics is a property of all human knowledge in general."
[Lenin (1961),
pp.359-60.
Bold and italic emphases in the original; paragraphs merged.]
The fact that the "is" of H1 isn't one of identity
can be seen from Lenin's own use of it. Consider one of his more
'abstract' sentences:
H5: "[T]he opposites (the individual is
opposed to the universal) are identical."
[H1: John is a man.]
From this we can perhaps extract two
embedded sentences:
H4: The opposites are identical.
H6: The individual is opposed to the universal.
[H4 plainly contains a cognate of "is" -- namely, "are".]
However, if "is" always indicates identity -- and could be
interpreted as an expression of the form "ξ
is identical with ζ" -- then we
should be able to re-write H4 and H6 in the following manner:
H7: The opposites are identical with identical.
H8: The individual is identical with opposed to
the universal.39a
[In H7, the verb "are" (from H6), and in H8 the verb "is" (from
H6), have been replaced by "are identical with" and "is
identical with", respectively, on 'sound' dialectical lines. (The reason why
these terms have been highlighted in bold will soon become
apparent.)]
It doesn't take any dialectical logic at all
(and no bourgeois prejudice whatsoever) to see what nonsense results from
this 'brilliant' Hegelian insight. Nor is it difficult to foresee the infinite
task Lenin's 'analysis' holds open to those who have swallowed this theory as he, or anyone else, tries to
say what the meaning is of each bold "is" (or the meaning of each
bold "are") that recurs
in "is identical
with" (or in "are identical with") in H7 and H8,
respectively, now made explicit in H9 and H10:
H9: The opposites are identical with identical
with identical.
H10: The individual is identical with identical with opposed
to the universal.
Here, the
bold "is" from H8 and the bold "are" from
H7 have been replaced with what we are told they really mean -- namely "is identical
with" and "are identical with", respectively (both highlighted in
bold
again) -- to yield the
nonsensical result we see in H9 and H10. In turn, two more similar replacements by their supposed
'dialectical' equivalents yields these gems:
H11: The opposites are identical
with identical with identical
with identical.
H12: The individual is identical with identical with identical with opposed
to the universal.
And so on to infinity...
Lest anyone thinks this
is unfair to Lenin, or even Hegel, they are
invited to try to say for themselves what the "is" in "is identical
with" itself
means (without thereby abandoning Hegel's theory!).
Neutral onlookers can only wish such brave souls plenty of luck, and hope
they are blessed with boundless patience, limitless supplies of paper and ink --
and, of course, plenty of Prozac.
It is
worth recalling, though, that the above collapse into incoherence has only
arisen because dialecticians insist that the "is" of predication is really
an "is" of identity -- i.e., that it is the same as "is identical with".
By assuming this (again,
with no proof), they themselves would be forced to use another "is" to reveal this
good news to the rest of us -- as in:
H13: The is of predication is an is of identity.
But the middle "is" in
bold in H13 cannot -- ex
hypothesicannot!
-- be one
of mere predication. It, too, according the Hegel has to be one of
identity (in that it tells us what is or identity 'essentially' are). In that case, we
would obtain the following from H13:
H14: The is of predication is identical with the
is of identity.
And then:
H15: The is of predication is identical with
identical with the is of identity.
As each alleged "is" of predication is suitably replaced by an
"is identical with" with which it is supposed to be identical.
If anyone wants to go down that route, they, too, will require an endless supply of
painkillers and anti-depressants.
But, more fool them; they have been warned!39b
On the other hand, those who hold that the "is" of predication is
in reality just that (i.e., an "is" of predication -- or
better, that "is" is part of the predicate expression to begin with!) aren't
faced with such an infinite and morale-sapping task. That is because they seek
neither to revise nor re-write ordinary language in such Idealist terms,
replacing an ordinary "is" with another sort of "is" -- a
dodge that 'allows' metaphysicians to think they can transform predicates into the
Proper Names of abstract
particulars as and when it suites them.
So, when genuine materialists say things like "Blair is a
warmonger", they aren't saying that Blair is identical with a warmonger (which
one?), they are merely saying that the description "warmonger" applies to the
individual named "Blair".
No "is" anywhere in sight.
You
can put the Prozac away now, comrades; that ancient philosophical pseudo-problem has been dissolved.40
[I have dealt with the objection that since
the above aren't "essential judgements" or "essential predications" this entire
argument is flawed from beginning to end,
here,
here, and
here.]
However, the morbid (if not prurient) interest in John's manhood isn't confined to Lenin. We find a similar
but less cautious version of it in comrade
Novack's widely circulated
book:
"This law of identity of opposites, which so perplexes and
horrifies addicts of formal logic, can be easily understood, not only when it is
applied to actual processes of development and interrelations of events, but
also when it is contrasted with the formal law of identity. It is logically true
that A equals A, that John is John…. But it is far more profoundly true that A
is also non-A. John is not simply John: John is a man. This correct proposition
is not an affirmation of abstract identity, butan identification of opposites.
The logical category or material class, mankind, with which John is one and the
same is far more and other than John, the individual. Mankind is at the same
time identical with, yet different from John." [Novack (1971), p.92.
Bold emphases added.]
Contrary to what Novack imagines will be the reaction of
any "addicts of formal logic" who might stumble across his book, they will find little in this passage
to worry them -- or, indeed, prompt them to kick the habit. However, they
will find much to amuse and bemuse them, just as they will find even more that will put
them off Marxism forever -- that is,if
they conclude that this is the best example of 'advanced logic' that Marxist dialecticians
can
come up with!
The
highly clichéd DM-version of the LOI (that Novack also employs -- i.e., "A
equals A") will be examined in detail in
Essay Six, but Novack's own brand of superior
logic immediately changes it into "John is John" (and not even "John equals
John"). Novack then reproduces his own version of Hegel's egregious confusion of
the "is" of predication with the "is" of identity -- a switch that Novack nowhere
even attempts to justify or defend. [On that specific confusion, see
below.]
It is
worth asking therefore whether Novack (or any other dialectician) would try to
pull the same syntactic trick in relation to
the following sentence:
N4: John is a centimetre taller than his brother
Jim.
By no stretch of the imagination could this be read as:
N5: John is identical to a centimetre taller
than his brother Jim.
Or even:
N6: John equals a centimetre taller than his
brother Jim.
[Concerning the obvious objection that N6 is really:
N6a: John equals someone who is a centimetre taller than his
brother Jim, the reader is re-directed
here for
my response.]
Nor would he (they) try it out on the following:
N7: John is angry with his boss.
If we were to apply 'Novackian logic' to N7, we would get these
misbegotten sentences:
N8: John is identical with angry with his boss.
N9: John equals angry with his boss.
Mischievous readers might like to suggest what dialecticians
would do with the following:
N10: John is taller than Sheila, shorter than Mike,
but just as heavy as Simon.
N11: John is planning to go on strike
this week and he has just printed the strike leaflets.
N12: John is not himself today; he ate a dodgy
curry last night.
N13: John is the equal of any comrade in the
party.
N14: John is unequal to the task set him by the
strike committee.
N15: John is convinced that dialectical logic is wrong
about the copula "is" being an "is" of identity.
It could be objected that both Hegel and Novack are
only interested in
analysing "essential predications", not ordinary predictions, since the former
do involve identity, while the latter don't. Again, that objection has been
defused
here,
here, and
here.
Be this as it may, Novack
then pulls an unrelated
schematic sentence out of thin air (i.e., "A is also non-A"), which, with respect
to John, he immediately mistranslates -- recall, this is Novack's own
example! Hence, instead of using "John is also non-John" --, which would have
been an obvious absurdity even though it is a correct translation
of his own schematic sentence (i.e., "A is also non-A") -- Novack
turns his attention to a non-equivalent paraphrase of it, namely "John is not
simply John" -- which, plainly, would have been a translation of "A is
not simply A". So, the schematically equivalent, non-negated version of that sentence (which is the necessary logical foil that Novack needed to set up
a spurious IO) should have been "A is simply A", which nowhere appears in the
above passage.
Even so, based on what Novack does say, "A is simply
A" -- or "John is simply John" -- must have
been the version of the LOI he had in mind, given that he then went on to use
"John is not simply John" to contradict it. But, who apart from John is going to
get excited about that version of the LOI? Isthere a formal logician this
side of the
Kuiper Belt
who would want to defend "A is simply A" as a legitimate,
even if simplistic, form of the LOI? It
manifestly isn't a classical example of the LOI. It isn'teven Novack's example!
[IO = Identity of
Opposites; LOI = Law of Identity.]
As we delve deeper into the murky depths of Novackian
'logic' we find the reasoning becomes even more perplexing. How, it might be
wondered, is the simple sentence "John is a man" the expression of an IO? Surely, "John is a woman" would have
been a better choice? Or maybe: "John is Peter"? Or perhaps even: "John is an
ape-like ancestor of the human race"?
But, given the fact that such
dialectically-interconnected 'entities' are supposed
to "struggle" with and then
turn into
their 'dialectical opposites' (witness Plekhanov's clanger,below),
and the fact that opposite tendencies
(in objects or processes) eventually become
apparent in the changes that emerge (because of the aforementioned "struggle"
that is on-going in everything, and between all things, if
Lenin is to be believed), doesn't this mean that John is about
to become every man -- as he too changes into his
'opposite'? If John is
in fact the opposite of all men, then surely he must one day become all
men --
and they must likewise become him -- that is, after struggling with each and
every single one of them -- if the DM-classics are telling
us the truth!
[Anyone who doubts that this universal punch-up
is a direct consequence of this crazy 'theory of change' should follow the first
of the three links in the previous paragraph, check out what the DM-classicists
themselves had to say about 'dialectical change', and then perhaps
think again.]
In this universal, futuristic John-like world-- and
world-like John --, where every man (or woman?) has become John and John has morphed into
them, all struggle would surely cease, for then it
would be true that John is everyone and everyone is John. In this universal Johnsville, the class struggle would surely come to an end, for then nothing
would be the opposite of John, and the earth would be one huge John-centred
tautological love-in.
Of course, if John is to turn into everythingthat he is not,
then the entire universe will one day become this unfortunate character;
Johntology of this peculiar sort seems to be the final denouement of the Big
Bang, given such 'logic'. Wags might even
call this the "Johntological
Argument". On the other hand, if John isn't supposed to turn into everything he
is not, then the Dialectical Gospels must be wrong, for they assure us that
everything in the entire
universe must "inevitably" turn into its own opposite, and vice versa.
[The
counter-claim that each object/process has its own 'unique dialectical
opposite', and hence won't turn into 'everything that they are not', was
neutralised in Essay Eight
Part Three, as
well as
here and
here.]
Alternatively, back in the real world, if John is to turn into
his opposite, he must become a man (as
indeed he must if he is the
opposite of "a man", as Novack asserts). In that case, what the
dickens is he now?
Is he a non-man, a sub-human, a rodent...? It seems he must be one or
more of these if he has to become his
opposite -- which opposite
DL assures us is "a man". So, despite appearances
to the contrary, "John is a
man" really means the following (i.e., as soon as we don our 'dialectical specs' and
reject the
prejudices of 'commonsense' and 'bourgeois formal thinking'): John is
(perhaps) an
untermensch, for only then
would it be possible for him to turn into his opposite -- "a man"!
On
the other hand,
and returning to an earlier point, if John and all men are opposites and subject to
inevitable struggle, then
it must be the case that
all men are opposing or struggling with John. Is he therefore a sort of inter-galactic
Donald Trump, whom
everyone despises and would gladly
slap insensible if they got
half a chance? Is the entire human race therefore ganging up on this hapless
character?
If not, then
what is the point of this Novackian 'analysis'? Even in DM-terms it makes no sense.
Of course, Novack does make some
sort of an attempt to
substantiate this prize specimen of Super-Duper-Dialectical 'logic' by an appeal to the
principle of class inclusion (or even of class identity!), in the following manner:
H1: John is a man.
N16a: John is a member of the class of men. [I.e., paraphrasing
Novack's: "The logical category or material class, mankind, with which John is
one and the same...."]
N16b: John is identical with the class of men. [Alternative
paraphrase of "The logical category or material class, mankind, with which John
is one and the same...."]
If,
as appears to be the case, Novack really did believe that H1 meant the same as
(or implied) N16b, then his understanding of English was seriously defective.
Novack never seems to have questioned the sense of asserting that an individual
is identical with a class; no ordinary speaker (not the worse for drink, drugs
or 'dialectics') would do this -- nor would anyone still in possession of their
sanity. Indeed, if someone were to claim that John (or anyone else) was
identical with a class that is as large as the class of men -- if we include women and children (!!), this class so far numbers
possibly
in excess of 107 billion individuals! --, that might prove
sufficient grounds to send this rather odd individual off to seek professional help.
Clearly, N16b could only ever be (sort of) true if John was the
only man left alive (compare this with
M5, below: "John is the strike committee now -- since
everyone else has been arrested"). But, even if H1 could be read as a
disguised class inclusion statement (i.e., as N16a above would have it), it
would still be impossible to extract from it all that Novack thought he could. Even Novack seems to half-recognise this since he had to substitute the
following for N16a:
N17: Mankind is at the same time identical with
yet different from John.
N16a: John is a member of the class of men. [I.e., paraphrasing
Novack's: "The logical category or material class, mankind, with which John is
one and the same...."]
But, the first half of this
(i.e., N17a) is false
-- in fact, it is so
bizarre, Novack should have been advised to resume taking his medication:
N17a: Mankind is identical with John.
H1: John is a man.
Quite
apart from the fact that N17a changes the subject of the sentence (from John to
Mankind), it plainly isn't true that mankind is identical with John (and H1
can only be made to say so on the basis of yet more 'innovative'
grammar; i.e., confusing the "is" of predication with the "is" of identity).
Even a
New Labour
spin doctor would have had problems twisting H1 into so grotesque
a shape. At the very best, Novack might have been able to argue that John
and the rest of 'mankind' share their common humanity, or at least a range of genetic, psychological,
and social
'properties' or characteristics,
and he might then have been able to infer from this that they are all equally
human. But, anyone who went down that route should rightly be
awarded a prize for "Stating The Bleeding Obvious" (to paraphrase
Monty
Python).
On the other hand, any normal person reading H17a would
surely take it to mean that John is perhaps the only survivor of a horrific worldwide
catastrophe of some sort, that John was all that was left of mankind
-- and that therefore John is mankind (or, humankind); i.e., he is their
sole
representative left alive --
The Omega
Man!
But then, how are we to make sense the second half?
N17b: Mankind is different from John.
Again, the (normal) way to interpret this would be to
regard it as suggesting that John mightnot actually be human, or
maybe not fully human. Perhaps he is half-animal, a clone, or maybe an
alien? But if so, what is all the fuss about? Indeed, would there be such a
fuss if the sentence had been "Joan is a man"?
But, shouldn't N17b be:
N17c: Mankind is identical with different
from John,
if the "is" of N17b is replaced by "is identical
with" that we are assured it should be?
Or even:
N17d: Mankind is identical with someone who
is different from John,
if we replace the "is" with "is identical with
someone who is", along the lines we will meet
below? And yet, both of these are susceptible of yet another
infinite regress, like the one we met
here.
Be this as it may, N17 would surely be
re-interpreted -- and far more honestly -- as one or more of the following:
N18: John is all that is left of humanity because
he is a clone -- making him different from other men -- who, because he was a
defective and resentful clone, proceeded to wipe out the
entire human male population.
N19: John is the sole survivor of a nuclear war, but
unfortunately the radiation neutered him, making him different from other men.
N20: John finally 'came out' and acknowledged he
was gay, while
the rest of the male population had sex-change operations (making John
different from all other men), every one of whom died as a result.
N21: John is the only man left on earth, but he
is very popular with the remaining women because of his unique sensitivity, a
trait which distinguishes him from all other men, who no longer exist having been wiped out by
their angry womenfolk
for their sexist disregard of their feelings.
[N17: Mankind is at the same time identical with
yet different from John.]
These (and possibly
several other alternatives) would be the only way to
interpret the odd
sentences Novack thought it wise to inflict on his readers.
In that case, the only "horrifying" thing about all this is that
Novack imagined such stilted English (compounded by the sort of reasoning
that all but the
seriously deranged would surely disown) was anything other than an insult to
ordinary workers -- none of whom would ever talk this way.
Finally -– and independently of the above -- Novack
failed to inform us precisely what justified him 'deriving' such profound,
scientific-looking truths from a few rather odd-looking sentences.
Exactly what could possibly sanction the bold theses Novack 'inferred' from this tortured
prose about John's identity/sexuality -- that is, over and above an
appeal to the assumed existential import of a few contingent featuresof
a minor sub-branch of Indo-European grammar (which he misconstrued anyway)?
After all,
Novack had argued as follows in another of his books:
"A consistent materialism cannot proceed from
principles which are validated by appeal to abstract reason, intuition,
self-evidence or some other subjective or purely theoretical source. Idealisms
may do this. But the materialist philosophy has to be based upon evidence taken
from objective material sources and verified by demonstration in practice...."
[Novack (1965), p.17. Bold emphasis added.]
Has
all the supporting evidence
Novack insisted upon been lost in the same anti-dialectical fire that seems to
have consumed
Engels, Plekhanov, Lenin, Mao, and Trotsky's
data?
So much for the use to which John's manhood is
subjected by an OT of
Novack's undoubted stature.
However, we find John cropping up all over the place; even STDs can't resist commenting on him and his
cosmically-significant
sexuality. Here is a passage from a dusty old (but classic)
Stalinist
text from the 1930s:
"The central fallacy involved in all metaphysical
reasoning is -- expressed in terms of logic -- the complete confusion of the
relations between the categories of Particular and General: of Unique and
'Universal.' Thus, for instance, if I affirm: 'John is a Man' I affirm that
'John' is a particular specimen of the general (or 'universal') category 'Man'.
I understand what 'John' is by subsuming him under (or
'identifying him with') the wider category 'Man'. Metaphysical reasoning
proceeds on the tacit or explicit assumption that the general category 'Man' and
the particular category 'John' exist independently of each other: that over and
above all the Particular 'Johns' in creation (and 'Toms,' and 'Dicks' and
'Harrys' and so on) over and above all particular men, there exists somewhere --
and would exist if all particular men ceased to be, or had never been -- the
general category 'Man.'...
"The dialectical method traverses this rigid metaphysic
completely. The category 'Man' includes, certainly, all possible 'men.' But
'Man' and 'men', though distinct, separate, and separable logical categories,
are only so as logical discriminations, as ways of looking at one
and the same set of facts. 'Man' -- is -- all men, conceived from
the standpoint of their generality -- that in which all men are
alike. 'Men' is a conception of the same fact -- 'all men' -- but in respect
of their multiplicity, the fact that no two of them are exactly alike. For
dialectics, the particular and the general, the unique and the universal -- for
all their logical opposition -- exist, in fact, in and by means of
each other. The 'Johniness' of John does not exist, cannot possibly be
conceived as existing, apart from his 'manniness'. We know 'Man' only as the
common characteristic of all particular men; and each particular man is
identifiable, as a particular, by means of his variation from all other
men -- from that generality 'Man' by means of which we classify 'all men' in one
group.
"It is the recognition of this 'identity of all (logical
pairs of) opposites,' and in the further recognition that all categories
form, logically, a series from the Absolutely Universal to the Absolutely Unique
-- (in each of which opposites its other is implicit) -- that the virtue of
Hegel's logic consists…. Let us now translate this into concrete terms. John is
-- a man.
Man is a category in which all men (John, and all the not-Johns)
are conjoined. I begin to distinguish John from the not-Johns by
observing those things in which he is not --what the other men are.
At the same time the fact that I have to begin upon the process of
distinguishing implies…that, apart from his special distinguishing
characteristics, John is identical with all the not-Johns who comprise
the rest of the human race. Thus logically expressed, John is understood
when he is most fully conceived as the 'identity' of John-in-special and not-John
(i.e. all man (sic)) in general.
"…When I affirm that 'John is a man' I postulate the oppositional
contrast between John and not-John and their coexistence (the negation of
their mutual negation) all at once. Certainly as the logical process is
worked in my mind I distinguish first one pole, then the other of the
separation and then their conjunction. But all three relations -- or
better still, the whole three-fold relation -- exists from the
beginning and its existence is presupposed in the logical act…." [Jackson
(1936), pp.103-06. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted
at this site. Italic emphases in the original. Several paragraphs merged.]
Anyone who
has struggled through to the end of this passage might emerge from that ordeal a
little puzzled as to how John is actually capable of being a "particular
specimen" of the general (or 'universal') category "Man" -- that worry not
helped by the author's liberal
and sloppy use of quotation marks.
[The single ones given in the above passage
were in fact double quotes in the original; they were changed to single quotes
because of the
conventions governing their use adopted at this site. (See
W1, below, where the originals have been restored.)] That is because, once encased in such quotes, "John" becomes a word not a man.
And "Man" itself is another word, not a category, class or concept.
I have to confess,
try as hard as I might, I couldn't quite see the first word ("John")
physically contained in the second term ("Man"), as it seems it should,
according to comrade Jackson.
W1: If I affirm: "John is a man" I affirm
that "John" is a particular specimen of the general (or "universal") category
"Man". I understand what "John" is by subsuming him under (or
"identifying him with") the wider category "Man".
Perhaps I just don't 'understand' dialectics...
Even so, my concern
has in no way been allayed by the author's casual reference to the "category
'Man'" to which "John" supposedly belongs (he being a "particular specimen" of it),
since it is even more difficult to see how a word like "Man" can be both a category
and a word all in one go. On the other hand, if the word "John" is in
fact an example of the category named by "Man", the latter must include both men and words
as exemplars -- which might help explain John's continual oscillation between the
two.
And, it won't do to complain that comrade Jackson was merely
summarising the traditional "metaphysical" analysis of this tediously overworked
sentence, since not only do
his own criticisms depend on these confusions, his subsequent 'dialectical
analysis' does, too. Nor will it do to suggest that Jackson is using a different
convention, which means that his use of quotation marks doesn't imply that
"John" is word, but a category, as he claims. Readers can check for themselves
(if they have access to Jackson's tome): there are no stated conventions
anywhere in the book.
Jackson's careless use of language and quotation marks (alongside his serial
confusion of
use with
mention) isn't of course
unrelated to the innovative and rather self-important 'reasoning' the
above passage
exhibits, the most
startling example of which is the turn toward the "concrete" near the end:
"Let us now translate this into concrete terms.
John is -- a man.
Man is a category in which all men (John, and all the not-Johns)
are conjoined. I begin to distinguish John from the not-Johns by
observing those things in which he is not --what the other men are.
At the same time the fact that I have to begin upon the process of
distinguishing implies…that, apart from his special distinguishing
characteristics, John is identical with all the not-Johns who comprise
the rest of the human race. Thus logically expressed, John is understood
when he is most fully conceived as the 'identity' of John-in-special and not-John
(i.e. all man) in general." [Ibid., p.105.]
[We might note in passing the
bourgeois
individualism obvious in this quotation; comrade Jackson seems to
think he learnt all this, and did all that 'distinguishing', by himself, in the comfort of his own
head! And worse, he thinks we all do likewise. Of course, as expected, he neglected to
supply, quote or even reference the evidence that might substantiate such
innovative psychology.]
Indeed, it might well be wondered how all men
could
have been successfully conjoined in, or recruited to, the one category Man? That category is
surely abstract -- it doesn't walk the earth, breathe, talk, or even work for a
living. And yet all men do most of these things at some point in their lives. In
what sense then are all men embroiled in this peculiar abstraction?
Again, as the late Fraser Cowley pointed out:
"The open sentence 'x is a spider' determines a class only
because 'spider' signifies a kind of thing. It is by being one of that
kind...that a value of x is a member of the class. To identify something as a
spider, one must know what a spider is, that is, what kind of thing 'spider'
signifies. Kinds of things can come to be or cease to be. The chemical elements,
kinds of substances, are believed to have evolved. The motorbike -- the kind of
vehicle known as a motorbike -- was invented about 1880. The dodo is extinct.
There is no obvious way of producing sentences equivalent to these in terms of
classes. The class of dodos and the class of dead dodos are not identical:
though all dodos are dead, a dead dodo is not a dodo....
"Since a kind is to be found wherever there are particular
things of the kind, it can have various geographical locations. The lion is
found in East Africa. Lions are found in East Africa. It makes no difference
whether we say 'the lion' or whether we say 'lions': what is meant is the kind
of animal. To say that it can be seen in captivity far from its remaining
natural habitats does not contradict the statement that it is found in East
Africa. A kind is not a class: the class of lions is nowhere to be found...."
[Cowley (1991), p.87. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions
adopted at this site.]
In like manner, we might wonder what has become of John if he
belongs to a class that is nowhere to be found anywhere on the planet.
Other
questions soon force themselves on us: Is a category a sort of
'ethereal club' that all males sign up to, or into which they are inducted, at birth?
Alternatively, are they all
metaphysically conscripted, as it were, at the moment of conception -- their
membership card perhaps taking the form of certain sets of chromosomes? Or, are they only honorary
members, waiting patiently in line for recruitment until some bright spark (like comrade Jackson)
helpfully remembers to abstract
them into it?
If so, what were they in the meantime? 'Limbo men'? Or, just
plain, unvarnished ordinary men -- i.e., males, but now without quotation marks
holding them in a vice-like grip --, and
hence as naked as the day before they were unceremoniously 'abstracted' without their consent?
As seems clear,
comrade Jackson was relying on his own
understanding of what look for all the world like ordinary words in order to derive several
counter-intuitive conclusions following on from Hegel and Lenin's lead. But, if he was being sincere in what he wrote, then,
like Novack, his comprehension of English looks about as reliable as his
'logic'. Are we really supposed
to believe (could anyone believe -- did this comrade actually believe!?)
that we may only begin to distinguish characters like John from all the
"not-Johns" by observing "those things in which he is not -- what the other men
are"? Imagine, then, this author meeting, say, the real John for the first
time. Would he have to wait until he had considered all the "not-Johns"
(who "comprise the rest of the human race") before he could distinguish John
from anyone else? If so, how on earth could he even begin?
[We
might well wonder exactly who comrade Jackson thought he was the first
time he looked in the mirror. Perhaps this: "At least I'm not-John"?]
Until this comrade had met every other member of the human race, given this
view, he wouldn't be able to tell any of these uncategorised, shapeless
entities apart. But, the very same rigmarole must surely apply to all these
"not-Johns", too. With respect to every single one of them, therefore,
this comrade wouldn't
be able to distinguish such formless shadows
from the rest until they had also been distinguished them from all the "not-not-Johns".
In turn, he couldn't do that until he had examined all of these
amorphous spectres and distinguished them from…, well what? Even
worse, he wouldn't be able to call either of these ghostly classes "the not-John group", or
"the not-not-John category" until he knew who John himself was! But, ex hypothesi,
he couldn't do that until all the
rest had been identified..., and so on and so forth.
Neither side of this dialectically bent coin is identifiable without the other
already having been; indeed, they both fall flat together. In which case, the
dialectical spin
into which John is now allegedly locked can't be
rendered 'determinate' at any point -- despite the fact that comrade Jackson assures us that these relations
are somehow objectively there beforewe even begin to think about them!
Lest the reader concludes that this comrade is right, and that we do
indeed need to be able to distinguish John-like characters from what they are
not, before we can know who or what John is, it might prove helpful
to consider a slightly less
pragmatically-challenged sentence about him, such as this:
W2: John is the first comrade to win a
lottery jackpot.
Do any of us have to meet a single lottery jackpot winner
in order to know what this is telling us? Do we really need to be
introduced to every comrade who hasn't won a jackpot in order to do that? What about every
non-comrade who has won one? Or, indeed, every non-comrade who hasn't?
Perhaps this example isn't of the
'right type' in that it doesn't use a genuine universal term. Consider then the following:
W3: John isn't an insect.
Lest again it be thought that we would have to meet every single
insect before we knew who or what John is, we only need recall that according to
David Attenborough's recent TV programme on these
wee beasties,
there are
200,000,000 of them for each one of us.
Good luck to
any brave dialecticians who think they are up to that
challenge!
Again it might be thought that
W3 isn't a positive
affirmative universal proposition. Well, putting to one side the hopelessly
confused notion, "positive affirmative proposition", beloved of obsolete logic
texts, consider this:
W4: John is not a non-mammal.
This isn't a negative proposition (or if it is, its two negatives
'cancel', to use that obsolete jargon for the moment), but it is universal. Now, just try
and work out the introductory
protocols one would have to observe to be able to distinguish John from all those
non-mammals, if comrade Jackson is to be believed. Dialectical sleuths would have to visit the
outer fringes of the universe and introduce themselves to every single proton (surely these are
non-mammals?), in order to be able to figure out who John is. And that would only
represent the beginning of such an
Herculean, of not
Sisyphean, task.
[I return to consider
'affirmative' and 'negative' propositions,
below.]
Is John really worth
all this trouble?
And what about this recalcitrant example?
W5: John is everything that Tony Blair is not.
Is
this proposition positive, negative, affirmative, universal, singular...? While
we wait for a reply to that unanswerable question, bored readers might like to
figure out who they would have to bump into in order to understand it. And then,
how they would go about that unwelcome quest if they don't yet
understand the sentence that prompted that aimless exercise in the first place!
[Which
sentence, of course, they wouldn't yet understand since they could only grasp it at the
end of that tedious time-taking task! And if they don't understand it
yet, how would they know what to do in order to confirm it?]
Nevertheless, an earlier paragraph in the above passage claimed
that the ability to distinguish John from other men must be understood in the
following way:
"We know'Man' only as the common
characteristic of all particular men; and each particular man is identifiable, as a particular,
by means of his variation from all other men -- from that generality 'Man' by
means of which we classify 'all men' in one group." [Ibid., p.104. Bold emphasis
alone added.]
Or:
W6: We know "Man" only as the common
characteristic of all particular men; and each particular man is
identifiable, as a particular, by means of his variation from all other
men -- from that generality "Man" by means of which we classify "all men" in one
group. [Original quotation marks restored, again.]
Once more, the careless use of quotation marks
in W6 (apparent in Jackson's use
of the word "Man" to express the "common characteristic of all particular men")
only succeeds in prompting the following question: Do all men actually share in
common the letters "M", "a" and "n", as the emphasised clause suggests? [That is
because the clause in question concerns the word "man", which
is, plainly, comprised of those three letters.] Are we now to conclude
that every man has a sort of metaphysical tattoo etched on them at
birth -- or, maybe, at conception?
Is
this what the following comment implies?
"But all three relations -- or better still, the whole
three-fold relation -- exists from the beginning and its existence is
presupposed in the logical act…." [Ibid., p.106. Bold emphases alone added.]
Does
the above mean that:
W7: In the beginning was the word "Man"?
Is this,
therefore, the Logical Adam that gave life to us all?
This example of 'path-breaking logic', courtesy of comrade Jackson, appears to
suggest that we can infer substantive truths about reality from the
logical relation (or, maybe, from that which is "presupposed in the logical act"), which
appears to
hold between concepts, or perhaps even between words themselves (or is it
between letters?).
If so, this might help explain why
this comrade thought it unnecessary to mention any of the evidence that must exist
(somewhere?) that substantiates this latest example of
LIE. Where, then, are
the autopsy reports that confirm that all of humanity (including women) are
branded with the mystic letters "M", "a", and "n"? Where, too, is the data from
astronomy that verifies the fact that alongside the primeval goop that
comprised the material of the Big Bang (if it contained any, and if there was
one) there was indeed this Dialectical Trinity, a "whole three-fold relation" that
"exist[ed] from the beginning"?
Perhaps this is
all unfair
parody and sarcasm at comrade Jackson's expense when he is no longer here to
defend himself? Maybe the word "Man" is really meant to refer to
a characteristic that all men share? But, that means "Man" must be the
Proper Name of that characteristic -- so it can't bea characteristic itself. Anyway, do
women
possess this trait?
Or, are we to suppose that the latter have "Woman" in common? What about
transsexuals? Are these individuals born with some sort of spelling mistake?
Indeed, if someone had a sex change operation, would this mean that the surgeons
involved had to erase and then insert a few new marks into this patient's 'metaphysical bar code'?
Of course, the real reason this author had to employ such
stilted and wooden English (peppered with all those incautious quotation marks) -- and which
is easily lampooned as a result -- is that if
he had tried to use ordinary language (as Marx
suggested he should) he wouldn't
have been able to serve his readers this
bowl of dialectical goulash. That is why, as soon as he translated what
he fancied he thought he meant into the specialised terminology he unwisely lifted from
Hegel (festooned with all those quotation marks), his reasoning became
incoherent.
No wonder DM has never actually seized the masses if this is
the gobbledygook dialectical militants used to -- and still do -- dish up!
We encountered the
following example of Dialectical
Legerdemain in
Essay Two, but it is worth repeating it here if only because it
spares us yet more prurient gossip about John and his much ballyhooed 'Manhood':
"This law of the permeation of opposites will
probably be new to you, something to which you have probably not given thought.
Upon closer examination you will discover that you cannot utter a single
meaningful sentence which does not comprehend this proposition.... Let us take a
rather common sentence: 'The lion is a beast of prey.' A thing, A, the lion is
equated with a thing B. At the same time a distinction is made between A and B.
So far as the lion is a beast of prey, it is equated with all beasts of that
kind. At the same time, in the same sentence, it is distinguished from the kind.
It is impossible to utter a sentence which will not contain the formula, A
equals B. All meaningful sentences have a form which is conditioned by the
permeation of opposites. This contradiction [is] contained in every meaningful
sentence, the equation and at the same time differentiation between subject and
predicate...." [Thalheimer (1936),
pp.168-69.
Bold emphases added.]
Thalheimer has clearly allowed
DL to corrupt his memory since it
made him forget about the countless sentences that aren't of the form that he
assures us we can't avoid using (i.e., "A equals B"). Fortunately, Thalheimer refuted this peculiar
idea of his at the very beginning of the above paragraph: "This
law of the permeation of opposites will probably be new to you, something to
which you have probably not given thought." That sentence and countless others
in his book manifestly aren't of the form "A equals B". This is
surely logic for simpletons, not socialists.
Independently
of the above, it might be interesting to consider how comrade
Thalheimer would have interpreted this sentence:
T1: President Trump is one cent short of a dollar.
Is he really identical with "one cent short of a dollar"?
And, what of the following?
T2: Trump isn't the racist to whom I was
referring.
Good luck to anyone who wants to translate that into
dialectical gobbledygook.
Of course, the source of this comedy of
errors is
Hegel's Logic. Here is a passage we met earlier:
"The
Judgmentis the notion in its particularity, as a
connection which is also a distinguishing of its functions, which are put as
independent and yet as identical with themselves not with one another.
"One's first impression about the Judgment is the
independence of the two extremes, the subject and the predicate. The former we
take to be a thing or term per se, and the predicate a general term
outside the said subject and somewhere in our heads. The next point is for us to
bring the latter into combination with the former, and in this way frame a
Judgment. The copula 'is', however, enunciates the predicate of the
subject, and so that external subjective subsumption is again put in abeyance,
and the Judgment taken as a determination of the object itself. The etymological
meaning of the Judgment (Urtheil) in German goes deeper, as it were
declaring the unity of the notion to be primary, and its distinction to be the
original partition. And that is what the Judgment really is.
"In its abstract terms a Judgment is expressible
in the proposition: 'The individual is the universal.' These are the terms under
which the subject and the predicate first confront each other, when the
functions of the notion are taken in their immediate character or first
abstraction. (Propositions such as, 'The particular is the universal', and 'The
individual is the particular', belong to the further specialisation of the
judgment.) It shows a strange want of observation in the logic-books, that in
none of them is the fact stated, that in every judgment there is still a
statement made, as, the individual is the universal, or still more definitely,
The subject is the predicate (e.g. God is absolute spirit). No doubt there is
also a distinction between terms like individual and universal, subject and
predicate: but it is none the less the universal fact, that every judgment
states them to be identical.
"The copula 'is' springs from the nature of the
notion, to be self-identical even in parting with its own. The individual and
universal are its constituents, and therefore characters which cannot be
isolated. The earlier categories (of reflection) in their correlations also
refer to one another: but their interconnection is only 'having' and not 'being', i.e. it is not the identity which is realised as identity or
universality. In the judgment, therefore, for the first time there is seen the
genuine particularity of the notion: for it is the speciality or distinguishing
of the latter, without thereby losing universality....
"The Judgment is usually taken in a subjective
sense as an operation and a form, occurring merely in self-conscious thought.
This distinction, however, has no existence on purely logical principles, by which the judgment is
taken in the quite universal signification that all things are a judgment. That
is to say, they are individuals which are a universality or inner nature in
themselves -- a universal which is individualised. Their universality and
individuality are distinguished, but the one is at the same time identical with
the other.
"The interpretation of the judgment, according to
which it is assumed to be merely subjective, as if we ascribed a predicate to a
subject is contradicted by the decidedly objective expression of the judgment.
The rose is red; Gold is a metal. It is not by us that something is first
ascribed to them. A judgment is however distinguished from a proposition. The
latter contains a statement about the subject, which does not stand to it in any
universal relationship, but expresses some single action, or some state, or the
like. Thus, 'Caesar was born at Rome in such and such a year waged war in Gaul
for ten years, crossed the Rubicon, etc.', are propositions, but not judgments.
Again it is absurd to say that such statements as 'I slept well last night' or
'Present arms!' may be turned into the form of a judgment. 'A carriage is passing
by' should be a judgment, and a subjective one at best, only if it were
doubtful, whether the passing object was a carriage, or whether it and not
rather the point of observation was in motion: in short, only if it were desired
to specify a conception which was still short of appropriate specification....
"The abstract terms of the judgement, 'The
individual is the universal', present the subject (as negatively self-relating)
as what is immediately concrete, while the predicate is what is
abstract, indeterminate, in short the universal. But the two elements are
connected together by an 'is': and thus the predicate (in its universality) must
contain the speciality of the subject, must, in short, have particularity: and
so is realised the identity between subject and predicate; which being thus
unaffected by this difference in form, is the content." [Hegel (1975),
pp.230-34,
§§166-169. Italic emphases in the original.
Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions
adopted at this site.]
[This passage in fact continues
in the same vein for
several more pages, and readers keen to develop a throbbing headache are welcome
to follow the above link and read it for themselves.
There is a considerably more involved and convoluted passage like this in Hegel's
Science of Logic (i.e., Hegel (1999)) which has been reproduced in
Appendix A
for the benefit of those suffering from insomnia.]
As the reader will no doubt have noticed,
Hegel's comments are
considerably more complex than those found in the poor relation
that goes by the name "materialist dialectics" -- even if it is no
less incomprehensible.
At least Hegel was a competent mystic who could knit-together
impenetrable jargon to compete with the best. In fact, he could have confused for
his country.
Nevertheless, in the above passage Hegel appears to limit positive judgements to what
others have called "universal affirmative propositions", and then
restrict propositionsthemselves to what others have called "singular affirmative propositions".
That isn't a happy distinction. [Of course, this isn't to suggest Hegel
considered only positive forms of either. On that, see Inwood (1992), pp.151-53.]
Although Hegel
adapted mediaeval and Kantian ideas in this area, he superimposed his own idiosyncratic
constraints
on the distinction between a mere "satz" (sentence/proposition) and an "urteil"
(a judgement) -- which will be examined in more detail in Essay Twelve Part Five
(when it is published).
However, because
Hegel based his theories on
these highly dubious, ancient and seriously limited logical distinctions, much of
what he had to say is of little value. As we
will see in Essay Twelve, these categories are of little use to scientists
or mathematicians -- least of all philosophers and genuine logicians --,
since they are far too crude and restrictive.
For example, how would the following be classified?
H1: Every sailor loves a girl who reminds him of
anyone other than his mother.
H2: Anyone who knows Marx's work will conclude that
he is second to none in his analysis of the economic forces and processes operating in
Capitalism as well as most of those constitutive of other Modes of Production.
H3: Any prime factor of an even number between
two and one hundred is less than a composite number not equal to but greater
than fifty.
H4: Most of those who admire some who do not
despise themselves often avoid sitting opposite any who criticise individuals who
claim membership of the minority break-away faction of the Socrates
Appreciation Society.
H5: Today, Blair met several activists who think his
policy on Iraq is a betrayal of his few remaining socialist principles.
Are these universal, particular, negative, or
positive? Are they judgements or propositions? But, these sort of propositions (and worse!)
feature in mathematics and the sciences all the time (to say nothing of everyday
speech, excepting perhaps H4). Indeed, the serious limitations of the
restrictive old logic, with its incapacity to handle complex sentences in
mathematics, and those involving multiple generality, relations and complex
forms of negation, inspired
Frege to recast the entire discipline in its modern form
over a hundred and thirty years ago -- breaking news of which has yet to
filter through to most
dialectically-addled brains.
[On that, see
Essay Four.]
Of course, the banal "judgements" that Hegel
himself examined only serve further to confirm that conclusion. But, which scientist (for
goodness sake!) is going to get excited over "The
rose is red"? And although "Gold is a metal"
might appear in Chemistry textbooks, only an eight year-old will learn much from it.
To be
sure, some of the counter-examples considered in this Essay don't
apply directly (or, at least, in any straight-forward sense) to issues of concern
to Hegel, or even DM-fans, since they aren't "judgements", but propositions. And yet,
what is "The rose is red"? It certainly looks like a proposition not a
"judgement". However, Hegel also appears to have believed that the
same set of words -- "The rose is red", for instance -- can oscillate between
to apparently unstable states: being a judgement and being a proposition (see, for example, John McCumber's
comment, quoted below). Nevertheless, as we
will also see in Essay Twelve, the distinction Hegel drew between propositions
and judgements is unsustainable, anyway. [Until that is published, the reader is
directed to Rosenthal (1998), pp.111-36.]
"By virtue of this negativity which, as an
extreme of the judgment, is at the same time self-related, the predicate is an abstract individual.
For example, in the proposition: the rose is fragrant, the
predicate enunciates only one of the many properties of the rose; it singles out
this particular one which, in the subject, is a concrescence with the others;
just as in the dissolution of the thing, the manifold properties which inhere in
it, in acquiring self-subsistence as matters, become individualised.
From this side, then, the proposition of the judgment runs thus: the
universal is individual.
"In
bringing together this reciprocal determination of subject and
predicate in the judgment, we get a twofold result. First that
immediately the subject is, indeed, something that simply is, an
individual, while the predicate is the universal. But because the judgment is
the relation of the two, and the subject is determined by the predicate
as a universal, the subject is the universal. Secondly, the predicate
is determined in the subject; for it is not a determination in general,
but of the subject; in the proposition: the rose is fragrant,
this fragrance is not any indeterminate fragrance, but that of the rose; the
predicate is therefore an individual. Now since subject and predicate
stand in the relationship of the judgment, they have to remain mutually opposed
as determinations of the Notion; just as in the reciprocity of
causality, before it attains its truth, the two sides have to retain their
self-subsistence and mutual opposition in face of the sameness of their
determination. When, therefore, the subject is determined as a universal, we
must not take the predicate also in its determination of universality -- else we
should not have a judgment -- but only in its determination of individuality;
similarly, when the subject is determined as an individual, the predicate is to
be taken as a universal....
"We have already referred above to the prevalent
idea that it depends merely on the content of the judgment whether it be true or
not, since logical truth concerns only the form and demands only that the said
content shall not contradict itself. The form of the judgment is taken to be
nothing more than the relation of two notions. But we have seen that these two
notions do not have merely the relationless character of a sum, but are
related to one another as individual and universal. These
determinations constitute the truly logical content, and, be it noted,
constitute in this abstraction the content of the positive judgment; all
other content that appears in a judgment (the sun is round, Cicero was
a great orator in Rome, it is day now, etc.) does not concern the
judgment as such; the judgment merely enunciates that the subject is
predicate, or, more definitely, since these are only names, that the
individual is universal and vice versa. By virtue of this purely
logical content, the positive judgment is not true, but has its
truth in the negative judgment. All that is demanded of the content is
that it shall not contradict itself in the judgment; but as has been shown it
does contradict itself in the above judgment....
"Since the negation affects the relation of the
judgment, and we are dealing with the negative judgment still as such,
it is in the first place still a judgment; consequently we have here
the relationship of subject and predicate, or of individuality and universality,
and their relation, the form of the judgment. The subject as the
immediate which forms the basis remains unaffected by the negation; it therefore
retains its determination of having a predicate, or its relation to the
universality. What is negated, therefore, is not the universality as such in
the predicate, but the abstraction or determinateness of the latter which
appeared as content in contrast to that universality. Thus the negative
judgment is not total negation; the universal sphere which contains the
predicate still subsists, and therefore the relation of the subject to the
predicate is essentially still positive; the still remaining
determination of the predicate is just as much a relation. If, for
example, it is said that the rose is not red, it is only the determinateness
of the predicate that is negated and separated from the universality which
likewise belongs to it; the universal sphere, colour, is preserved; in
saying that the rose is not red, it is assumed that it has a colour,
but a different one. In respect of this universal sphere the judgment is still
positive." [Hegel (1999),
pp.633-40,
§§1364-76. I have used the online version here. Bold emphases alone added.]
"The
rose is fragrant" and "The rose is not red" don't look like
'essential' propositions, nor yet "judgements" -- although, as has
have already been noted, Hegel ran these two logical categories together,
depending on how the "subject" was to be understood or conceived
(again, on that, see below) --, as we can see
from the next paragraph:
"in which the sides of the judgment would have fallen completely asunder
and only their self-relation would be expressed, while their relation to one
another would be dissolved and the judgment consequently sublated."
[Ibid.,
p.634, §1366.]
Here
two propositions are also two judgements. It isn't easy to make
much sense of that passage.
Nevertheless, John
McCumber did make some
attempt to extricate Hegel-fans from this dialectical briar patch:
"The second of them [McCumber is here
responding to two objections to Hegel's ideas about belief -- RL] can be
habilitated
via Hegel's
famous distinction between a 'judgement' (Urteil) and a 'proposition' or
'sentence' (two possible meanings of Satz; I will translate it as
'assertion' to capture both). While an 'assertion' simply unites any subject and
predicate, a 'judgement' claims to present the same object twice: once under the
form of an individual, and again as a universal. We may rephrase this by saying
that a judgement, unlike mere assertion, claims to give a complete
account of what an individual thing is. The subject presents the thing as a mere
denotatum; the
predicate presents its complete nature.
"This completeness claim seems to make judgements
bizarre creatures indeed; but Hegel explains that the completeness of the
account of an individual thing offered by a 'judgement' is in fact relative to
purposes at hand. Such judgements do not only occur in ordinary speech, but play
a distinctive role in the fixation of belief: 'that is a wagon,' for example, is
a judgement only if the nature of the thing has previously been put into doubt.
That it is in fact a wagon is then a complete account of its nature for the
purposes at hand: the judgement assures us that the wagonhood of the object is
all we need to know about it; acceptance of it ends our present enquiry into its
nature." [McCumber (1993), pp.37-38. Italic emphases in the original;
bold added.
Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.
Links added.]
McCumber in fact admits that it will take the rest of his book
to untangle this mess (p.39) -- my paraphrase, not his! Despite this, exactly how a
judgement differs from an emphatic assertion still seems unclear.
The fact that Hegel considers propositions
like "The rose is fragrant" and judgements like "The sun is round"
(isn't it in fact spherical?) to make his
point might mean that the objections to the criticisms of Hegel
noted above are themselves
misguided. [Again, see Inwood (1992), pp.151-53, on this.]
In response, it is
worth asking: Exactly how does "The rose
is red" manage to "give a complete
account of what an individual thing is?" In which case, McCumber's assertion that "The subject presents the thing as a mere
denotatum; the predicate presents its complete nature" is far from the truth, to
say the least.
In
the above passage, McCumber introduces another consideration that at first sight
appears to clear things up:
"Hegel explains that the completeness of the account of an individual thing
offered by a 'judgement' is in fact relative to purposes at hand. Such
judgements do not only occur in ordinary speech, but play a distinctive role in
the fixation of belief: 'that is a wagon,' for example, is
a judgement only if the nature of the thing has previously been put into doubt.
That it is in fact a wagon is then a complete account of its nature for the
purposes at hand: the judgement assures us that the wagonhood of the object is
all we need to know about it; acceptance of it ends our present enquiry into
its nature." [Ibid; bold emphases added.]
Hence, it is relative to the "purposes at hand" that a sentence like
"That is a wagon" becomes a judgement, but "only
if the nature of the thing has previously been put in doubt."
Consequently:
"That it is in fact a wagon is then a complete account of its nature for the
purposes at hand: the judgement assures us that the wagonhood of the object is
all we need to know about it; acceptance of it ends our present enquiry into
its nature." [Ibid. Bold emphasis added.]
And yet, one
might well wonder how such a doubt might be expressed. Perhaps like this:
"Is that a wagon? I'm not convinced." Or maybe, "I'm not too sure what counts as a wagon, can you
help me out?" Or possibly even, "I can't tell whether that object in the distance
is a wagon or a coach. What do you think?" In which case, "That is a wagon"
would merely be an assertion, which would, hopefully, remove all
reasonable doubt.
While
the truth of a given proposition, p, might be challenged by asserting its
negation, or merely by simply denying it is true, who expresses a doubt (as opposed to
posing a challenge or raising a query, like the foregoing) in the form of an assertion?
The point of
that
question will become a little clearer if we consider what else McCumber had to
say:
"While an 'assertion' simply unites any subject and
predicate, a 'judgement' claims to present the same object twice: once under the
form of an individual, and again as a universal. We may rephrase this by saying
that a judgement, unlike mere assertion, claims to give a complete
account of what an individual thing is. The subject presents the thing as a mere
denotatum; the
predicate presents its complete nature." [Ibid. Bold emphasis alone added.]
In
which case,
it seems that propositions and judgements are both assertions, but propositions only
become judgements if they settle a doubt, or which maybe neutralise/assuage one. But, once again: How
can an assertion also be an expression of doubt? How
can what has already been admitted to be such and such by means of an assertion (namely,
in this case, the proposition
"That is a wagon" -- recall, that that set of words only becomes a judgement when
those very same words settle some doubt or other, according to McCumber) -- how can it also
constitute an expression of doubt?
If
someone asserted the following:
V1: "That is a wagon."
Who
in charge of their senses would then assert
(in response to V1):
V2:"That is a wagon. I am
glad I have cleared that up for you."?
Anyone replying with V2 in answer to V1 would be regarded as distinctly odd, at best, somewhat
deranged, at worst.
Again, perhaps someone could express a doubt by asserting something like, "That
isn't a wagon". But how would any of the above settle things if the object in question isn't
actually a wagon, and the assertion, "That is a wagon", is what created the
doubt in the first place? And what if a doubt -- such as, "Is that a wagon over
there in the distance?" -- had been cleared up by the following assertion, "No,
it's not a wagon, just a very good painting of a wagon", when it turns out that
it wasn't a wagon after all?
But, let us suppose for the purposes of argument that "That isn't a wagon" is
what created the said doubt. How does "That is a wagon" now remove
the doubt? They are both assertions, and it is always open to the
individual who said "That isn't a wagon" to respond, "I'm sorry, you are
mistaken; it isn't a wagon, it is in fact a mock up of one made for the
next scene in the film". To which the other responds "A mock up of a wagon
is still a wagon!" Which one of these is the judgement and which the
proposition? Neither has settled the question whether it is indeed a wagon. Do
mock-up wagons count as wagons? Does a model of a wagon count as one? What about
this
Magritte
painting? Is it correct that it isn't a pipe?
Figure Two: Pipe Or Not A
Pipe?
It
could be replied that what matters here is which one of these sentences cleared
things up in the end. In other words, a judgement is simply an assertion that
turns out to be true.
But,
isn't that also the case with propositions?
Anyway, we have still failed to consider this seemingly fatal objection: How is
an assertion like "That isn't a wagon" an expression of doubt as
opposed to it possibly being the expression of a difference of opinion? What we
lack here is a genuine assertion that is also an expression of doubt. In fact,
as already noted, doubts are expressed in the manner outlined above, not by
means of assertions:
And yet, one
might well wonder how such a doubt might be expressed. Perhaps like this:
"Is that a wagon? I'm not convinced." Or maybe "I'm not too sure what counts as a wagon, can you
help me out?" Or possibly even, "I can't tell whether that object in the distance
is a wagon or a coach. What do you think?" In which case, "That is a wagon"
would merely be an assertion, which would, hopefully, remove all
reasonable doubt.
Who
in their left mind would assert something and express doubt at the same
time by means of the very same words? McCumber conspicuously failed to cite
even
one example where an assertion can be used to express a doubt. In fact, an
assertion is the exact opposite of expressing a doubt! "That is a wagon, but I doubt it"
makes no sense -- nor does "That isn't a wagon, but I doubt it isn't, and so
should you."40a1
Couldn't someone assert the following "I doubt that that is a wagon!" But
that is the expression of doubt not the assertion of a doubt. Who has
ever said, "I assert that I doubt x, y, or z!"? Of course,
someone might be quite emphatic about their doubt "No, I really do doubt
that that is x, y, or z!" And yet that is just an
emphatic expression of a doubt, not an assertion of one. Admittedly, someone
else could assert something like this: "Look, NN doubts x, y,
or z!" But that is an assertion about NN's doubt not an assertion
of a doubt itself.
Furthermore, any indicative sentence can be turned into an 'essential'
judgement/proposition by such means if it clears up a given doubt ("in
the present circumstances", which addendum is itself so vague it looks like
yet another
'get-out-of-jail-free' card), and if McCumber is to be believed.
For example:
Q1:
"I'm not sure it's raining."
Q2:
"It is raining."
If Q2
clears up this doubt, then it must be an 'essential' proposition/judgement, in
which case the "is" here must be one of identity, and Q2 should become:
Q3:
"It is identical with raining."
Is
anyone prepared to defend that as a legitimate way to represent what Q2
is attempting to say?
Hence,
in the light of the above,
McCumber's attempt to explain what Hegel was banging on about is no help at all.
So,
as
we have just seen, Hegel calls some sentences both propositions and
judgements, while some sentences (such as "The rose is fragrant") seem to
oscillate between the two! Perhaps some sense can be made of this, but I'm not
holding my breath, especially given the unsatisfactory attempt made by McCumber to clear
things up.
Lawler
(1982) is easily the best article
I have so far encountered in my attempt to find out if there are any DM-theorists
who know
what a 'dialectical contradiction' actually is. His essay also makes
some attempt to defend the reading of the "is" of predication as an "is" of
identity -- for example, when that participle is used in sentences like "Socrates is mortal" and
"Socrates is the man who drank the hemlock".
It will soon become apparent that
Lawler has
himself conflatedHegel's comments
about "judgements" with those about "propositions" -- but since Hegel was
himself thoroughly confused in
this area,
as we have just seen, this is hardly Lawler's fault.
Although, having said that, just like
McCumber, Lawler does precious little to clear
up the mess.
However,
becausethis Essay is about "Materialist Dialectics", and not the Über-Mystical
version of 'dialectics' promulgated by Hegel, I will confine my comments here to what Lawler had
to say, not
the linguistic spaghetti Hegel cooked up. [Nevertheless, aspects of Hegel's work
that are relevant to the aims of this Essay will also be considered (and
then in more detail in Essay Twelve
Parts Five and Six
--
summaries
here
and
here).]
Referring to
Bertrand Russell's criticism of Hegel (which
criticism
is vaguely similar to the line adopted in these Essays), Lawler claims that:
"Russell accuses Hegel of confusing these two
different uses of 'is'. It is not necessary to deny the distinction made by
Russell in order to see that his argument misses the point. In the example of an
identity statement, in Russell's terms, there is still the 'difference'
indicated by Hegel. We do not interpret identity as requiring us to say
'Socrates is...Socrates.' To say that Socrates is 'the man who drank the
hemlock' is to assert something different in the predicate from what was
asserted in the subject. In the process of knowledge, assuming that the sentence
is informative, we are told that 'Socrates,' some individual vaguely or
incompletely known, is indeed 'the man who drank the hemlock.' Socrates'
'identity' is established by our being told something 'different,' and knowledge
develops through a process of moving from vague, 'undifferentiated' knowledge,
to more specific knowledge. In this respect there is no difference between this
proposition and the other, presumably also informative, assertion that 'Socrates
is mortal' -- not a Greek god, but a human being." [Lawler (1982), p.25.
Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]
Now, this 'argument' only works if it is accepted that the word
"Socrates" asserts something, which Lawler simply takes for
granted. If, however, the word
"Socrates" asserts nothing, or can't be used on its own to assert
anything, then his entire argument falls flat.
It is worth reminding ourselves that predicates
are used to assert things of
individuals named, or picked out, by subject terms
(these typically being Proper Names or Definite Descriptions). So
the Proper Name
"Socrates" would be used to assert something only if it too were a predicate
expression, which,
I take it, everyone (other than perhaps
Quine
-- but even he had to re-write names as obviouspredicates,
which only served to underline this syntactic distinction), everyone is
agreed that such names aren't predicates when they are used as subject terms.
The fact that the word "Socrates" can't be used to assert
anything in such sentences can be seen from the additional fact that we have to attach predicate
expressions
to it in order to assert something of the individual so named.
Hence, if someone just said "Socrates", they wouldn't
be asserting anything (in the sense that they would be making no assertion) -- unless it was in answer to a question such as "Who was
Plato's teacher?" Then it would, of course, be a contextual paraphrase
for "Socrates was Plato's
teacher."
Someone might object, and point out that it is possible to assert
Socrates, for example, by means of the following:
S1: A man is Socrates.
Of course,
even with respect to that bizarre example (and I have to say that,
except in books and articles on the philosophy of logic (etc.), I have yet to
read, see or hear anyone use a sentence like this), "Socrates" is
no longer functioning simply as a Proper Name, it now forms part of the expression, "ξ
is Socrates", and in that case, "Socrates" wouldn't be asserting
"something different in the predicate from what was asserted in the subject",
since the new subject (viz., "A man") isn't now asserting anything. That
role has been devolved to the new predicate
expression,"ξ
is Socrates". Hence, if the "A man" isn't actually asserting anything
in S1, then "ξ
is Socrates" can't assert something different from it. So, Lawler's claims
fail, even in this case.
In
addition,
Lawler completely
skewed his argument by considering an example of a predicate expression that also works as
an identifying (definite) description (i.e., "Socrates is the man who drank the
hemlock"). It won't work with sentences such as
"Socrates is running after the man who gave him the hemlock", since the
predicate "ξ is running after the man who gave him the hemlock" in no way
identifies Socrates
(indeed, if anything, it identifies his quarry);
it merely says something about him.
And if,
for some reason, it is still thought that
"Socrates is running after the man who gave him the hemlock"
does succeed in identifying Socrates, it is worth pointing out that identity and
being identifiable are not at all the same. Here is what I have written
about this in Essay Eight
Part Three:
It is worth adding that this 'problem' has been compounded by the fact that Hegel and Lawler slide between two,
dare I say it, different uses of the word "identity" and "identify" -- that is,
between (a)
"identity" when it is used to provide an empty (or perhaps even significant)
identity statement for any given object,
and (b)
"identify" when it is used to speak about the capacity the vast majority of us possess of being able to discriminate, pick out, or
recognise a person,
property, location, smell, taste, sound, tune, process or
object from moment to moment.
For example,
if
squaddie NN is asked whether or not he can identify Osama bin Laden in a line-up,
and he replies,
"Yes, Sarge! Osama is identical to
Osama, Sarge!", he would risk
being put on a charge. On the other hand, if he points to one of the suspects
and says, "That's
him, Sarge!", he wouldn't.
[This was, of course, written before the
US military executed Osama bin Laden extra-judicially.] So, identification isn't the same as
identity (no pun intended).
Naturally,
identification (i.e., use (b), above)
could in some circumstances involve a capacity to differentiate among
objects, but that isn't necessarily so in all cases (as was argued
here).
Would, for
example, the rather dim squaddie above be able to identify Osama bin Laden
only if he had first learnt to distinguish the latter from everything that Osama wasn't?
Upon meeting someone for the first time, and being introduced to them, which one
of us even so much as thinks "Hang on! Let me first distinguish this character
from a bucket of fish, a corkscrew, a
Rabbit Jelly Mould, a tidal estuary, a flock of geese, your recently
deceased
grandmother, a rusty old car, the
Andromeda Galaxy, a
self-adjoint operator, a
pi-Meson, a
Pulsar...,
before you tell me who she is, otherwise I won't know who you are talking about!"
By
running these two words together, Hegel revealed once again that he was even more confused than
this rather dim squaddie. Lawler might be advised, therefore, to
abandon his role as Hegel's Dialectical Defence Counsel.
Notwithstanding this, Lawler has an additional argument:
"Moreover, it seems that a 'predicative'
relation, such as 'Socrates is mortal' can be readily turned into an 'identity'
statement: 'Socrates is that particular mortal man'." [Ibid., p.25.]
[Interestingly, this is a dodge that
Jean Buridan
also tried out on his readers; on that, see
here.]
However, even if that paraphrase were acceptable (which it isn't since the two
sentences don't mean the same, and they are true/false under
different circumstances; for example "Socrates is that particular mortal man"
might be false if "that particular man" is, say,
Alcibiades; whereas "Socrates is mortal" would
still be true in such circumstances), one would want to know precisely what this identity is meant to
be. Surely Lawler isn't suggesting that Socrates is identical to "that
particular mortal man". If he is then the following argument would be sound:
L1: Plato is mortal.
L2: Socrates is mortal.
L3: Therefore, Plato is Socrates.
If L1 and L2 both pick out "that particular mortal man" then
Plato and Socrates must be one and the same.
Of course, it could be objected that the phrase "that particular
mortal man" refers to someone different in each case, so L3 doesn't follow from
L1 and L2.
Well, that is quite easy to fix:
L4: Plato is mortal = Plato is that particular
mortal man1.
L5: Socrates is mortal = Socrates is that
particular mortal man2.
The
problem is that "mortal
man1"
now becomes a rigid designator for Plato, no different from his name, and "mortal
man2"
becomes a surrogate for "Socrates". In that case, L4 and L5 would become:
L4a:
Plato is mortal = Plato is Plato. (!)
L5b:
Socrates is mortal = Socrates is Socrates. (!)
It
could be objected that "mortal
man1"
isn't a surrogate for the name "Plato", and "mortal
man2"
isn't a surrogate for "Socrates", so the above objection is misguided.
But,
the problem is that if that response were correct,
"that particular mortal man1"
might in fact pick out Alcibiades. How can that
be ruled out without using Plato's name to identify
"that particular mortal man1"?
Which would make the whole exercise circular. [That was in fact the point of the
above counter-objection that led to L4a and L5a, and the point made
here.]
But
Lawler's argument fails for other reasons; that is because it is still controversial whether or not L2
is an identity statement, so that alleged fact can't be used in its own support --, whereas is isn't
controversial that L5/L5a are identity statements:
L2: Socrates is mortal.
L5: Socrates is mortal = Socrates is that
particular mortal man2.
L5a:
Socrates is mortal = Socrates is Socrates.
Lawler merely asserts that "Socrates
is mortal" and "Socrates is that particular mortal man"
are saying same (since L2 is an identity
statement), or that one can be read from the other:
"...it seems that a 'predicative'
relation, such as 'Socrates is mortal' can be readily turned into an 'identity'
statement: 'Socrates is that particular mortal man'." [Ibid., p.25.]
Lawler's "it seems" here gives the game away, one feels; there is no logical route that will
take us from L2 to L5/L5a -- if there were, Lawler would surely have included it
in his argument. In other words, Lawler assumes L2 is an identity statement in
his 'proof' that it is one -- or, at least, that it can be turned into one in some
as yet unspecified way.
Which, of course, implies that it L2 isn't an identity statement, after all;
otherwise an appeal to L5 would be superfluous.
But,
even
if the above rebuttals are
rejected for some reason, Lawler's sentence presents a number of problems of its own (rather
like those we have already met several
times):
A1: "Socrates
is
that
particular mortal man."
If the "is"
here (highlighted in green) is one of identity, and stands for "is identical
with", then we would be faced with yet another incipient
infinite regress. Replacing
the highlighted "is" in A1 with what we are told it means yields the following:
A2: "Socrates
is
identical with that particular mortal man."
But, the same surely applies to the new "is" (highlighted in
red) in A2. If we now replace it
with what we are told it means (i.e., "is identical with"), we obtain this
meaningless sentence:
A3: "Socrates
is
identical with identical with that particular mortal man."
And, if we do the same again, we obtain:
A4: "Socrates is identical with identical with
identical with that particular mortal man."
And so on...
A 'sentential explosion' like this can only be
halted by those who deny that
"is" is always an "is" of identity in such contexts.
[Objections to this particular line-of-argument -- on the grounds that Hegel was
only interested in "essential" predication" -- have been neutralised
here.]
Of
course, it could be objected that A3 is an ill-formed sentence, so it has
nothing to do with Hegel's argument. Any suggestion to the contrary is
ridiculous. But, any theorist who happily countenances sentences like the
following (taken directly from
Lenin) has lost all right to appeal:
H5: "[T]he opposites (the individual is
opposed to the universal) are identical."
"We do not interpret identity as requiring us to
say 'Socrates is...Socrates.' To say that Socrates is 'the man who drank the
hemlock' is to assert something different in the predicate from what was
asserted in the subject. In the process of knowledge, assuming that the sentence
is informative, we are told that 'Socrates,' some individual vaguely or
incompletely known, is indeed 'the man who drank the hemlock.' Socrates'
'identity' is established by our being told something 'different,' and knowledge
develops through a process of moving from vague, 'undifferentiated' knowledge,
to more specific knowledge." [Ibid., p.25.]
No one doubts that predicate expressions are often physically
different from Proper Names, but that difference is logically irrelevant. Nor
does that alleged predicate have to say anything different.
Both can be seen if we consider this sentence:
L10: Socrates is Socrates.
Here the
alleged predicate**,
"...Socrates", isn't different from
the subject in any relevant way. Naturally, it could be objected that L10 isn't informative.
But,
it could be. Sentences like L10 are used all the time; they tell us that
the named individual is rather unique, that he or she behaves in a quirky,
idiosyncratic or characteristic sort of way. This form can also be used to argue
that whatever happens can't be changed, for better
or worse -- for example, "Boys will be boys", "Whatever will be, will be"
(which was also a
Doris Day
hit song in the 1950s; "Que
sera, sera"). Other uses of this sentential form include,
"A rose is a rose" (which was, incidentally, also the title of an
episode in the US cop drama,
Major Crimes (Season 4, Episode 1), as well as forming part of the title of a poem by
Gertrude
Stein: "A
rose is a rose is a rose is a rose") -- indeed, we also have
a use of this locution from fifty odd years ago: "A rose is a rose", which
was
the title of the Donna Reed Show (Season 4, Episode 2), 21/09/1961 --,
and "Business is business",
which is reputed to be a Mafia cliché (often used in gangster films), as well as
being the
title of a play by
Octave
Mirbeau:
Les affaires sont les affaires.
Moreover, someone could say "Best is best" (meaning that the late
George Best is the best footballer), just as they could assert "Sharp is sharp"
(meaning that someone called "Sharp" was quick-witted), "Blunt is
blunt" (meaning that someone called "Blunt" is somewhat forthright), "Down is down" (meaning
that the price of duck feathers had fallen), and "Dopey is dopey" (meaning that the famous dwarf
from the film,
Snow White, is slow-witted).
Or, as an
equine trainer said (in the run up to the 2012
London Olympics and in relation to how horses behave): "Horses are horses".
[Admittedly, the second word in each case, here, isn't a
Proper Name (while it is in "Socrates is Socrates"), but these examples have only been quoted
to illustrate the fact that the alleged predicate can be informative even if it
doesn't look or sound different from the
subject, and often 'says the same thing'. Moreover, "are" is, of course, just the plural form of "is". In
Note 40a I have listed scores of additional examples of the locutions, "NN is
NN" and "F is F" (where "NN" stands for a Proper
Name, and "F" for a noun or verb phrase).]40a
Moreover, dialecticians had better hope that no one is ever
given, say, the name, "Arthur Man" (i.e., "A Man") --
oops, too late! --, otherwise the following
thoroughly reactionary and
impertinently anti-dialectical sentence could truthfully be uttered:
A1: A Man is
a man.
Lest anyone think that the capital letters make much of a
difference, A1 could be a spoken sentence, or its letters could be typed or written wholly in
capitals, thus:
**In the
comment
above about "alleged predicate",
that phrase was chosen deliberately.
As noted earlier,
Lawler pointedly omits the
copula "is" when quoting predicate
expressions -- notice his reference to "the man who drank the hemlock",
instead of "...is the man who drank the hemlock", for
instance. The
serious misuse to which
truncations like this can be (and are often) put was also highlighted
earlier. That is why when predicative expressions
are mentioned or quoted in this Essay (and this site) they are expressed in the following way: "ξ
is mortal" or "ξ
is the man who drank the hemlock" -- unless, of course, Lawler's own, or
someone's else's, misuse is being quoted, etc. There is no way functional expressions like these
-- i.e, "ξ
is the man who drank the hemlock" --
can be misconstrued as Proper Names.
There were good reasons
why Traditional Theorists truncated predicate expressions; these were connected
with the idea that these expressions mirrored or reflected 'concepts' in the mind of the one
using them -- or, perhaps, they mirrored them in some other, 'heavenly' realm, or
maybe a hidden world, anterior to experience. The clause "is mortal" doesn't even
look like a name, general or Proper; but "mortal" does, so
the truncated form was more appealing to
those who wanted to promote traditional ideas about the alleged reference of
general terms. This idea could in turn be recruited in support of the
theory that concepts are 'mental constructs', or 'processes' of some sort in the 'mind'
or the brain. This
view of 'concepts' will be put under considerable pressure in
Essay Thirteen Part Three, where it
will be shown that, if true, it would render communication impossible. It is
also worth pointing out that the alternative approach adopted here
implies that concepts are more accurately to be characterised as linguistic rules
-- or, rather, their use is an expression of such a rule --, which would indicate that the individual
concerned had mastered a certain skill -- the ability to form or to generate coherent
sentences of a certain sort -- by their use of such expressions.
This view of concepts places them in the public domain, as opposed to burying them
in a private, uncheckable part of the brain/'mind' -- the latter approach being
different from
bourgeois
individualism and Cartesianism in name alone. [How that works out was outlined
here, and in Note 16.]
It
could be objected that the above sentences (i.e., "Socrates is Socrates", etc.)
weren't (originally) predicative, and so don't
count. But, dialecticians like Lawler turn predicative expressions into identity
statements all the time, so they are hardly in a position to complain. Anyway, it
isn't true that the above aren't predicative; "Best is best" is, and so are: "A Man is a man", "Business is business", "Rape
is rape", and "A negro is a negro" (Marx), as, indeed, are most of the
examples quoted in
Note 40a.
Someone else might object that in spite of the above, "ξ
is Socrates", in sentences like "Socrates is Socrates", is still predicating
"Socrates" of Socrates, which contradicts something said
earlier. In fact, it was merely asserted that
in sentences like "Socrates is mortal" the word "Socrates" can't assert
anything; that role is devolved to the predicate expression, "ξ
is mortal". We can certainly regard "ξ
is Socrates" as a predicate expression if we so wish, but it is perhaps better
to regard it as a relational expression when it appears in sentences like
"Socrates is Socrates" -- or even better: view that sentence as a
substitution instance of the two-place, first level linguistic function, "F(ξ,ξ)".
[For an explanation of those rather odd symbols, see
here and Note 15a.]
Alternatively, it could be argued that in the above examples something
different from the subject is being asserted from that
which is being asserted in the predicate,
which is all Lawler needs. But, that isn't true with
respect to
"Socrates is Socrates". Anyway, and more
importantly,
since nothing is being asserted by the word "Socrates" (in "Socrates is
mortal", as we have seen) -- because it is a Proper Name, not a predicate expression
that is being used to say something about some individual
--, no comparison with respect to sameness or difference between what has or
hasn't been asserted by "Socrates" and any predicate expression applicable to
him can be sustained. Only predicates (relational expressions and assorted descriptions, etc.) can be used
to assert things of named individuals or of objects, hence the above
response also fails. I have also covered the objection that these are
self-predications in Part Two,
here.
In that case, the only distinction Lawler could
conceivably be alluding to here is a physical or spatio-temporal difference between subjects and
predicates, the first one of which we have just seen isn't logically significant, anyway.
Well, what about
an alleged spatio-temporal difference? That is, one where the predicate and subject terms are located
in slightly different places on the page/screen, or where the predicate
expression has
to be uttered after, or at least at a slightly different time to, the subject expression?
Again, these are logically irrelevant. It would surely be confusing, but
not logically impossible to reconfigure L2 to read as follows:
L2: Socrates is mortal.
L2a:
Sioscmorartteals.
Where the inserted letters (coloured differently
-- "Socrates"
is in red, "is" is in green, and "mortal"
is in blue) in L2a say the same as L2. These
inserted letters represent the copula and the predicate
expression all in one go, and they can all be read at the same time as the subject term. It is also possible for someone to record themselves saying "is mortal" and then replay
it at the same time as saying "Socrates".
It could be objected that that isn't a
serious reply since the above jumble doesn't in fact say anything; but that
would be a mistake. It is only an accident of history that our written words
aren't concatenated as follows:
L2b: Socrates/is/mortal.
L2a:
Sioscmorartteals.
L2c: Socratesismortal.
Spoken languages
regularly run words together, as do certain secret codes. In fact,
Semitic languages, such as
Arabic, use the device
employed in L2a all the time. After noting that Arabic uses a root
formed of three consonants to say something, linguist Guy Deutscher makes the following
point:
"But how can a vowel-less group of three consonants ever
mean anything if it cannot even stand up on its own three legs and be pronounced
unaided? The answer is that such roots do not have to be spoken by themselves,
because the root is an abstract notion, which comes to life only when it is
superimposed on some templates: patters of (mostly) vowels, which have
three empty dots for the three consonants of the root. To take one example, the
Arabic template ΟaΟiΟa forms the past tense (in the third
person 'he'), so if you want to say 'he was at peace', you must insert the root
s-l-m ('be at peace') into that template to get:
Root: s-l-m
↓ ↓↓
Template: ΟaΟiΟa
s a l i m a ('he was at peace')
[I have posted a photograph of Deutscher's actual
diagrams in
Appendix C since
the above graphic isn't too clear! --
RL.]
"And if you want to form the past tense of another verb,
say, 'wear', you take the root l-b-s, and insert it into the same template, to
get labisa ('he wore')." [Deutscher (2006), p.37.
Italic emphases in the original.]
So, the suggestion advanced in L2a isn't all that fanciful;
indeed, Semitic speakers have been talking this way for centuries.
Furthermore, the same message could be communicated in
several other ways;
it would just take a little practice to decipher them with ease. So, we could have a code
that used the following rule:
L2d: Socrates.
L2e: Rule: Any name that has been struck through means
that the named individual is mortal.
[That adapts a suggestion Wittgenstein advanced
in the
Tractatus.]
Sure, the contingent features of the
subject-predicate form make it easier for us to read or hear what is said
(although that is probably a by-product of familiarity), but that fact is logically irrelevant,
even if it is psychologically important (at least, for Indo-European speakers).
In that case, the same information could
be conveyed in a number of different ways, many of which wouldn't fall foul of
Hegel's logically irrelevant criterion (that is, if this was his
criterion -- but, who can say?).
Now, if we examine a wider set of examples (i.e.,
one that is more
inclusive than the radically impoverished set dialecticians
usually consider -- which are limited to such banalities as "The rose is red" and
"John is a man", etc.), the above points will become even less controversial.
So, imagine someone pointing
at L11 while saying:
L11:
"L11 is an example that Lawler shouldn't have ignored."
In
this case, the above subject/predicate sentence, employing the verb "is", is
being used to say of itself what it says of itself, which
isn't different from what it says of itself. Even worse: it occupies the same spatio-temporal
region as it
itself occupies.
Less
contentious examples
than the above might seem to be, which address
an earlier point,
include, perhaps,
the following:
L17: Socrates said the same about himself last
week.
L18: And so did Plato.
Here,
what is being said is plainly not different from what each is about. [In fact,
as has been pointed out several times already, the sub-Aristotelian 'logic'
DM-fans inherited from Hegel can't cater for such sentences. Small wonder then
that Hegel and his ilk failed to consider them -- and that includes the other examples
given below.]
As
Wittgenstein noted:
"A main cause of
philosophical disease -- a one-sided diet: one nourishes one's thinking with
only one kind of example." [Wittgenstein (1958), §593, p.155e.]
The
seemingly perverse examples listed above (which are themselves but a tiny
fraction of the many that could have been chosen) -- as well as those given below
--, show that Wittgenstein's comment
wasn't all that wide of the mark.
So, it is what we do
with our words that distinguishes predication from naming. Physical shape and
spatio-temporal considerations are only of psychological, or perhaps rhetorical, importance.
However,
Lawler's abbreviation
(i.e., where he refers to "mortal" as the predicate instead of "...is mortal",
or
"the man who drank the hemlock", instead of "...is the man who drank the
hemlock")
'allows' him to
nominalise
(or particularise)
expressions as the whim takes him. In so doing he is following the same well-worn tradition examined
earlier in this Essay -- indeed, the very one that Hegel turned into a test
for all self-respecting idealists.
This can be seen by the way he talks about the "predicative relation",
above.
Objects,
ink marks on the page and the alleged 'referents' of nominalised expressions
can certainly be put into a 'relation of sorts',
but not predicates and subjects -- unless, of course, we wish to turn predicates into
objects (or the names thereof),
destroying not only
the unity of the proposition
but generality, into the bargain.
A predicate can be used to say things truly or falsely of whoever or whatever it
is that is designated by a subject term
(or, perhaps better, predicate expressions can be used to form true
or false sentences when completed with Proper Names
or other singular terms). If predicate expressions are nominalised (or particularised) they
can't do this (since, once again, that would turn the relevant sentence into a list, as we saw
earlier).
Certainly we can speak about the relation between certain inscriptions (i.e., marks on
the page and pixels on a screen), or sound patterns in the air (i.e., spoken words), but to conflate these with an
alleged relation between a Proper Name and a predicate
expression would be to confuse the medium with the message.
[Even
so, we will see below where Lawler tries to do just this,
and then again later when he attempts to clarify Hegel's obscure phrase,
"dialectical contradiction" -- see also, Essay Eight
Part Three,
where I deal at length with that specific topic alongside the rest of Lawler's article.]
We are perhaps now in a position to see the point of all the
'seemingly
pedantic' detail
given toward the beginning of this Essay (i.e.,
concerning
sentences and lists (etc., etc.)), which was intended to reveal the origin of this ancient
syntactic segue.
Naturally, only those
still mesmerised by Hegel, or, indeed, by the sloppy 'logic' upon which his ideas
are predicated (no pun intended), might perhaps fail to appreciate the above
comments.
Lawler continues:
"However, this is not the meaning of 'identity'
which Hegel attempted to formulate. It is not the dialectical identity which
Hegel wished to contrast with 'abstract' identity. In his interpretation of
Hegel, Russell mistakenly understands 'identity' only within the framework of
abstract identity. If it seems reasonable to distinguish the kind
of 'identity' statement which Russell described from other 'predicative' uses of
the connective 'is', one would still like to understand what in fact is asserted
when one predicates some general attribute or quality, such as mortality or
humanity, of some individual. There seems to be some sense in calling this one
of 'identity,' for Socrates' mortality is intrinsic to Socrates' being Socrates.
This problem is not one resolved by asserting that Socrates is one member of the
class of mortal things. But, if we interpret mortality realistically we are
still faced with the ontological problem of the relation of an individual to its
properties." [Lawler (1982), pp.25-26. Paragraphs merged; bold emphasis
added.]
Unfortunately, in the above passage we encounter one of the most common mistakes
committed by Traditional Philosophers; in this instance, it concerns the spurious 'problem' of the 'relation'
between a subject and its properties. If properties don't populate the world as objects (i.e., if they aren't
objects, and can only be turned into
'objects' by particularising them in ways highlighted earlier), they can't stand
in a relation to anything. That is, they aren't the sort of things that could
stand in relation to anything, any more than a Proper Name can be a verb.
Some might object to the assertion that a Proper Name can't be a verb and point
to the following as a counter-example to it (taken from one of the Essays
published at this site): "Nixoning".
Here the Proper Name of the 37th President of the USA, "Richard Nixon", has been
turned into a verb! Ironically, grammatical switches like this even have their
own Proper Name:
Anthimeria, a
sub-category of which is itself called "Verbification".
However, in this instance, the word "Nixoning" is no longer operating as a
Proper Name (there is no one on earth called "Nixoning" -- if anyone knows
differently, please
let me know); it is now a verb. The assertion was that a Proper Names
can't be a verb, not that they can't be turned into one.
So, this is just another classic example of a bogus
'ontological problem' conjured into existence by a clumsy distortion of
language -- in this case, inflicted on predicate expressions.
Furthermore, if Socrates does indeed belong to the class
of mortal beings --
and that is it, if that is all there is to him --, then comrades
like Lawler will just have to get used to it. Lawler certainly can't appeal to Hegel's mutant 'logic' to bully
nature or society into acceding to the demands that that Hermetic Harebrain,
Hegel, tried to foist on it.
Moreover,
as Hegel saw things,
Socrates's
mortality was considered part of his essencefor theological reasons, in that it was an aspect of the latter's finitude, set
over and against the 'Infinite'/the 'Absolute':
"The being of
something is determinate; something has a quality and in it is not only
determined but limited; its quality is its limit and, burdened with this, it
remains in the first place an affirmative, stable being. But the development of
this negation, so that the opposition between its determinate being and the
negation as its immanent limit, is itself the being-within-self of the
something, which is thus in its own self only a becoming, constitutes the
finitude of something.
"When we say of
things that they are finite, we understand thereby that they not only
have a determinateness, that their quality is not only a reality and an
intrinsic determination, that finite things are not merely limited -- as such
they still have determinate being outside their limit -- but that, on the
contrary, non-being constitutes their nature and being. Finite things
are, but their relation to themselves is that they are negatively
self-related and in this they are negatively self-related and in this
very self-relation send themselves away beyond themselves, beyond their being.They are, but the truth of this being is their
end.
"The finite not
only alters, like something in general, but it ceases to be; and its
ceasing to be is not merely a possibility, so that it could be without ceasing
to be, but the being as such of finite things is to have the germ of decease as
their being-within-self: the hour of their birth is the hour of their death."
[Hegel (1999),
p.129, §§248-49. Italic emphases in the original; bold emphases
added. I have used the on-line version here.]
These
are surely
no good reasons in the above material to persuade materialists to tail-end such a confused
and bumbling mystic -- something which one would have thought should be crystal
clear to any self-respecting radical,
especially since 'the nature' of any human being is surely an empirical, not a
logical issue.
Well, it is for us anti-Idealists.
[Naturally, we might incorporate
certain facts into our use of
language, along the lines discussed
here,
but that is a separate issue. Of course, how we employ words and how we draw inferences
from the use of certain sentences is a logical issue, but that, too, is a separate
matter.]
And, there is no way that this view of "finitude" can be
eradicated, eliminated, or swept under the carpet by the simple expedient of putting Hegel "back on his feet".
Furthermore, since "essences" like these are integral to DM, this is one aspect
of the 'mystical shell' that dialectician have imported into Marxism from
Traditional Thought. [On that, see Rosenthal (1998).]
At this point, some readers might object to the way that
propositions have been analysed in this Essay. If so, we
can put that analysis to one side.
Even then, the question would still remain: How is it possible for any
analysis of propositions to justify the imposition of its supposed results onto
the fundamental (and hidden) 'essence' of nature
and society? To be sure, that could only be justified if 'language implied essence'
(LIMPE), and the
'nature of reality' was in
some sense linguistic (LIE) -- and its deep structure 'fortuitously'
matched contingent features of a minor sub-category of just one strand of
Indo-European Grammar!
[LIE = Linguistic Idealism. This
term was explained
above, and
will be again in more detail In Essay Twelve (summary
here).]
For Lawler's theory
to work it not only has to rely on a radical reconfiguration of a simple
verb
(i.e., "to be"), it requires the nominalisation
(particularisation) of predicates, into the bargain, thereby destroying
generality. Hence, even if the neo-Fregean
reading of predicate expressions employed at this site
were to be rejected, Lawler's account would still be unacceptable to materialists.
Frege or no Frege, predicates aren't
Proper Names -- and even if they were, that
alleged fact would
have empirical consequences only for Idealists:
"A consistent materialism cannot proceed from
principles which are validated by appeal to abstract reason, intuition,
self-evidence or some other subjective or purely theoretical source. Idealisms
may do this...."
[Novack (1965), p.17. Bold emphasis added.]
Fortunately, the neo-Fregean approach
adopted at this site blocks this slide into Idealism. That consideration alone should recommend it
to consistent materialists.
Finally, immediately after the passage quoted above, Lawler
proceeded to argue
as follows:
"There is no 'pure' individual which is not some
kind of thing. There is only an individual with certain specific
properties and powers, common to those of other individuals.... Russell's
various attempts to solve the problem of universals and his admitted failures
suggest that the real solution involves more than making a simple distinction
between the 'is' of identity and the 'is' of predication." [Ibid., p.26.
Emphasis in the original. Lawler also references Fisk (1979) in support. Fisk's
arguments will be discussed in Essay Twelve (summary
here).]
Whatever one thinks of the claim that there are no "pure individuals", one thing
is clear, the 'dialectical analysis' of predicative propositions destroys our
capacity to speak in general about anything whatsoever (in what were predicative
sentences), let alone about these "pure individuals"
-- for, as we have seen, it reconfigures
general terms as the Proper Names of abstract particulars. In that case, howsoever badly Russell
did or didn't fail in his attempt to solve the spurious 'problem' of "Universals",
DL
fares a whole lot worse -- since it
destroys fact-stating language.
Of
course, if we cast our linguistic net a little wider and consider examples drawn
from everyday speech (which dialecticians seldom consider because that
is what
Traditional Philosophers have always done:
downplay, ignore or depreciate the vernacular, which naturally means that dialecticians are merely aping a
well-entrenched,
conservative thought-form,
as Marx himself
noted), Lawler's 'analysis'
becomes all the more bizarre. Consider, therefore, the following example:
L19: What is Socrates doing?
Using superfine DL we might re-write this as:
L20: What is identical with Socrates doing?
Whereas:
L21: Why is Socrates drinking the hemlock?
would have to become:
L22: Why is identical with Socrates drinking the
hemlock?
Finally:
L23: Is Socrates going to drink the hemlock?
would become:
L24: Is identical with Socrates going to drink
the hemlock?
Diabolical Logic like this needs preserving for
posterity as a warning to future generations.
Should anyone object, and claim, for
instance, that L20 should be:
L20a: What
is identical with whatever Socrates is
doing?
they
would then have to explain the role of this new is
in L20a, without generating the infinite regress we have met several times
already (most
recently, for example,
here).
Naturally,
it could be argued that the last few examples are completely irrelevant since they are questions, not
propositions,
and still less are they Hegelian "essential judgements".
Even so, they
were specifically chosen to expose the narrow range of examples considered by dialecticians.
But, these questions are logically linked to the type of proposition that could
sensibly be offered in answer to them -- for example:
L23: Is Socrates going to drink the hemlock?
L23a: Socrates is going to drink the hemlock.
L23a is one answer that could be given
to L23, in which case when it is given the Hegel-treatment, it would become:
L23b: Socrates is identical with going to drink the hemlock,
as the is in L23a is
replaced with what we are told it really means, is identical with,
in L23b.
Someone might object that L23a isn't an
'essential' proposition, but Lawler himself uses a 'non-essential' proposition
to make his point:
"To say that Socrates is 'the man who
drank the hemlock' is to assert something different in the predicate from what
was asserted in the subject. In the process of knowledge, assuming that the
sentence is informative, we are told that 'Socrates,' some individual vaguely or
incompletely known, is indeed 'the man who drank the hemlock.' Socrates'
'identity' is established by our being told something 'different,' and knowledge
develops through a process of moving from vague, 'undifferentiated' knowledge,
to more specific knowledge. In this respect there is no difference between this
proposition and the other, presumably also informative, assertion that 'Socrates
is mortal' -- not a Greek god, but a human being." [Lawler (1982), p.25.
Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.
Bold emphasis added.]
There is no way that "Socrates is the
man who drank the hemlock" is an 'essential' proposition (or judgement).
[However, on such propositions/judgements, see
Note 24a
and
here.]
So,
it
is quite plain what
Hegel was attempting to do here -- that is, he was
trying to distinguish what
one might call "contingent propositions" from those that are deemed to be
'essential' -- or perhaps even 'necessary' --, when faced with the fact that
discourse (or, at least, examples taken from the Indo-European family of
languages) appears to
use the verb "is" somewhat indiscriminately. Hegel
clearly wanted to distinguish the employment of this verb when it is used in the
latter sense from its role in the former. Unfortunately, he imposed a bogus metaphysic on this
linguistic distinction, which only succeeded in destroying a key feature of language,
and one that he himself relied
upon: its capacity to express generality.
Incidentally, this reconfiguration also destroys
'essential' predication, and for the same reason.
We will
examine this serious error again in Essay Twelve, where we will explore the
deleterious
effect it had on Hegel's thought, and hence on DM in general. [Of course, much of
this will merely be a continuation and elaboration of the points made
earlier in this Essay, as well as
those outlined
here and
here.]
Unfortunately, Hegel also buried this legitimate concern under a cascade of
incomprehensible terminology, and that, too, was forced on him because of the
woefully inadequate resources available to him courtesy of the bowdlerised logic he
inherited from previous generations of third-rate logicians and philosophical
hacks, a serious drawback compounded by the ruling-class tradition within which his work had been
created. As
a matter of course this
tradition ignored,
undervalued or otherwise disparaged the rich conceptual resources
ordinary language offers those who adopt a different approach (again, as Marx
urged). [On
this, see Kenny (2006), pp.11-13, and the references listed here. There is more on this in Essay Twelve, summary
here. See also,
here.]
And yet,
as we have seen,
Hegel himself uses examples like "The rose is fragrant" to make his point
(which is in no way 'essential'), so
the veracity of the comments expressed in the last few paragraphs is by no
means certain. The confusion is, I think, all of Hegel's own making.
However, it wouldn't be difficult to find other examples that Lawler's theory
can't
handle:
L25: Socrates gives at least as good as he gets in Plato's
dialogues.
L26: Socrates never loses an argument.
L27: Socrates is made of flesh and bone.
L28: Socrates is no more.
L29: Socrates is a creation of Plato's fertile
imagination.
L30: Socrates is in fact someone else.
L31: Socrates isn't a man to be trifled with.
L32: Socrates sits next to
Alcibiades whenever he
can.
L33: Socrates is in a hurry.
L34: Socrates is incensed with himself.
L35: Socrates is asserting nothing he hasn't
asserted before.
L36: Socrates is the like of no one else.
L37: No one who wants to emulate Socrates is
likely to
accept the opinions of anyone who agrees with
Protagoras.
And so on...
If we now use an even wider range of examples drawn from the
vernacular (but restricted to the use of "is"), the woeful inadequacy of
Hegel's theory will become even more obvious:
L38: This strike is too passive.
L39: No answer is also an answer.
L40: Everything in the sale is half-price.
L41: Hegel's Logic is difficult to understand.
L42: The emancipation of the working class is an
act of the workers themselves.
L43: The average cat is twice as fast as the
average mouse.
L44: Scabbing is nothing to be proud of.
L45: An unknown assailant is being sought by the
police.
L46: Sugar is fattening.
L47: If the weather forecast says it will rain
then it is wrong.
L48: This isn't what management promised.
L49: If this meeting is about anything, it
is about
the right of the majority of workers to decide who legitimately represents their
interests.
L50: Anything is better than this.
L51: Something in the bank is better than
nothing.
This list of course could easily be
extended until it contained thousands of sentences -- with which we are all
familiar -- from which it would also be clear that none of the above can be re-written with an "is" of identity,
à laLawler, while remaining comprehensible. For example:
L43a: The average cat is identical with twice as
fast as the average mouse.
L48a: If the weather forecast says it will rain
then it is identical with wrong.
L51a: Something in the bank is identical with
better than nothing.
Once more, it could be argued that these examples
could be re-written in the following way:
L46a: Sugar
is
identical with something that is
fattening.
L46: Sugar is fattening.
We saw
Lawler try to pull that dodge earlier. But, even
if L46 and L46a meant the same (which they don't; for example, L46a implies that
sugar could be identical with potatoes or junk food, whereas L46 doesn't), awkward questions would once
again arise over the nature of this new is. That
can't be an
"is" of identity (we saw what supposing otherwise led
to earlier), and once that is conceded,
the rationale for replacing the "is" of predication in this way simply vanishes.
An exposé of the origin of this
strain of "bad old logic" can be found in Peter Geach's article 'History Of The
Corruptions Of Logic', in Geach (1972a), pp.44-61. See also, Geach (1968),
pp.22-46. On this topic in general, see Kneale
and Kneale (1962).
Benson Mates (in Mates (1979)) claims
that the two main senses of "is" (i.e., predication and identity) are really one
and the same. I will examine relevant aspects of his argument in a later re-write of this
Essay.
[See also
here,
where it seems the bad old logic might be trying to make a come-back.
However, I suspect that that is because Traditional Logic makes it slightly easier to defend certain
forms of Christian Mysticism. In this case, it might help Roman Catholic theologians 'defend' the doctrine of
transubstantiation -- which is ironic in view of
these
comments.]
Day (2019)
presents the following reply to arguments like the above (although there is no
sign the author has read my work, and every indication he hasn't) -- I have
re-posted a large part of his on-line article so that no one can claim he is
being quoted 'out of context':
"Lenin claims that the statement 'John is a man' is already
charged with contradiction. How? Here, the inclusion of mathematical symbols can
assist us in understanding the scandal. Could we say that 'John is a man'
translates to 'John=Man'? That would suggest that either the term 'John' or the
term 'Man' really is superfluous, that it would suffice to say 'John is John' or
'Man is Man.' However, we know we are conveying something non-trivial. We are
saying that John belongs to the category of man (we could use the logical symbol
ϵ). Does this resolve the problem, though? From a more philosophical point of
view, it is in fact correct to say that John is 'man,' for there is no 'man' in
the abstract, and our abstract notion of 'man' is really only cobbled together
from the common aspects of all individual men. Thus, it turns out that the
simple relationship 'John is a man,' which we all understand, conveys a really
complex notion: the identity of an identity (John=Man) and a non-identity
(John≠Man), coexisting in contradiction. Dialectics is the appreciation that
even the barest expression 'John is a man' is making an interesting argument!
"Marx says 'Capital is labour.' But, how can this be? Capital
is the opposite of labour! So there Marx goes, explaining that
capital is labour, via the commodity cycle. As it turns out, the mere expression
of a contradictory relationship carries the implication that there exists a
process whereby one can reach the other. This is how contradiction is deeply
tied to change.
"The word 'change' is apt because really there are very many ways
that one concept may turn into its opposite. Perspective determines whether we
are still or in motion. Space determines whether a gesture is rude or polite.
With time we see the living become the dying, and the dying give birth to the
living." [Day
(2019). Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions
adopted at this site.]
"Let us take a step back, and think for a moment about where in
our lives we might hear expressions that do not take this contradictory form. I
can think of a few:
'Orders are orders.'
'God is God.'
'It is what it is.'
'Family is family.'
'I am what I am.'
'Freedom is freedom.'
'Men are men, women are women.'
'War is war'.
"These are all argument-enders. What all of these phrases have in
common is that they have an 'atomic' quality, where by atomic we mean tight and
self-contained. Tautologies. They're disconnected from the world in a very
important sense. This is to say, they are not describing the world, they
are asserting the world, demanding that you accept a finality. There's no
argument to be had, we have simply a premise -- fixed, unchanging, universal
across time and space -- being insisted upon....
"Another big enemy of dialectics is the reactionary British
writer George Orwell, who in 1984 famously
mocks the idea of embracing contradiction as a rhetorical tool for psychological
manipulation:
War is Peace
Freedom is Slavery
Ignorance is Strength
"The protagonist of the novel, innocent Englishman Winston Smith,
is tormented by this establishment propaganda. This establishment is represented
by O'Brien, an evil and vengeful Irishman who has usurped his way into power.
The world is upside-down!
"Aristocrats and conservatives despise dialectics because they
feel their privileges threatened by the very notion of change. They covet a
static world, which makes them heavily inclined in favor of undialectical
relationships. A Roman might say 'Masters are masters, slaves are slaves' in the
same way modern propaganda will suppress questioning the veracity of a claim by
insisting 'Evil is evil.' This is an injunction for one to accept what they are
being given.
"Rome immediately invites one to think of Christianity, which is
long-lived enough that it not only offers examples of dialectical and
non-dialectical thinking in its doctrine, but itself embodies the
notion of a concept turning into its opposite. Roman society was ruthlessly
hierarchical, with rigid hereditary castes, and their religion of eternal and
whimsical gods was fit for their purposes, legitimizing a society where men did
as they wished with their slaves. Though today Christianity is largely a
hegemonic and reactionary force, once upon a time it was considered deeply
revolutionary, and the Romans aggressively attempted to stamp it down. This is
because once upon a time Christianity's creed was considered explosively
dangerous on account of its dialectical proclamations ('The meek shall inherit
the Earth!' 'God is Man!'). Today, however, Christianity is in power, and thus
its rhetoric aims to preserve the status quo, with an emphasis on absolute
obedience and non-questioning ('God is God!' 'Marriage is marriage!'). In the
past Christianity was an agent of change, today it is an enemy of change....
"The aforementioned examples were chosen to illustrate the stark
antagonism between the expressions of the likes of Marx and the likes of
Nietzsche, but we must be aware that anti-dialectical thinking in everyday life
can take subtler forms.
"In his essay on dialectics Lenin defends the theory of
'development as a unity of opposites' against those who concede change, but
theorize it as mere part of 'a cycle of increase and decrease.' After all,
change is observable, and it is rare for someone to be so obtuse so as to deny
it outright. However, anti-dialecticians have another trick up their sleeve: a
jaded and cynical attitude towards history as a 'cyclical slaughterhouse.' They
concede that, yes, things change, but they change according to the whims of
fate, karma, accidents, willpower, or God; in the end, in their view, everything
is a wash; things never really change.
"This is the reason why Lenin argues that it is essential to
grasp the source of change: the struggle of mutually exclusive
opposites. If we do not, we end up among the ranks of those who are
clueless about how to effect change. Lenin polemicises not only against
powerful aristocrats and reactionaries, but also against all sorts of
sentimental idealists (anarchists, social democrats, left-communists) who desire
a better society but don't particularly care for or aren’t careful about the
details or the process of how to achieve it....
"In short, he rails against those who prove incapable of carrying
out 'a concrete analysis of a concrete situation.' Similarly, Marx and Engels'
polemics not only target bourgeois economists, but also those within the ranks
of 'the left': anarchists like
Proudhon and
Bakunin and right-opportunists like
Dühring.
"The virtue of concrete analysis is expressed in strategic
creativity that at once stands out from both resignation and utopianism. In Marx
and Engels the championing of the proletariat above the peasantry or
lumpenproletariat; in Lenin the Party as vanguard, the system of soviets, and
the
NEP; in Stalin tactical diplomacy that draws gleefully spectating Western
powers begrudgingly into the war; in Mao the concept of primary and secondary contradictions
on the basis of the reality of imperialism justifying a pan-Chinese alliance
against Japanese occupation (led by a Peasant Army but including capitalists in
its ranks); in
Deng irrevocable integration with the
incipiently hegemonic capitalist order coupled with a fierce defense of the
autonomy of the political executive; etc. The point of listing these
achievements is to make it clear that it is not a question of better poetry,
this is an approach that produces creative strategy that seizes victory from the
jaws of defeat again and again.
"In short, it is absolutely essential to grasp not only that relationships
will develop, but also that they develop because of the struggle of
mutually contradictory opposites -- that the contradiction at the core of their
self-identity is inescapable. This implies victories are never final: 'When a
contradiction is resolved, new contradictions emerge, and competition takes
place again. In this way, society constantly progresses.' This leads to a kind
of pessimistic optimism: opportunities will necessarily continue to
arise, and therefore we need to be organized and prepared to consistently seize
these opportunities in order to effect our desired outcomes. This is the
difference between rebellion and revolution." [Day
(2019). Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions
adopted at this site. Italic emphases in the original. Spelling modified
in line with UK English. Minor typo corrected. Links added, but I have omitted
the article's own footnoted links.]
As has
already been pointed out, the logical core of
the above passage depends on the validity of the
Identity Theory of Predication, which (just like Hegel.
Engels and Lenin) comrade Day nowhere even attempts to justify or defend.
In fact, in the present Essay we have seen that this Medieval theory falls apart
upon close examination, which in turn means that Day's entire argument simply
disintegrates.
However, Day
also
claims that sentences like "Socrates is Socrates", "Rome is Rome" and "rape is
rape" have:
"an 'atomic' quality, where by atomic we mean tight
and self-contained. Tautologies. They're disconnected from the world in a very
important sense. This is to say, they are not describing the world, they
are asserting the world, demanding that you accept a finality. There's no
argument to be had, we have simply a premise -- fixed, unchanging, universal
across time and space -- being insisted upon...." [Ibid.]
Is that the
case? Does "Socrates is Socrates" imply Socrates won't change?
Anyone who
understands how we use Proper Names to refer to individuals, objects, events and
processes and who thought that a sentence like "Socrates is Socrates" implies he
won't change would automatically call into question not just their comprehension of English
(or whatever language had been used to express this thought) but their basic
knowledge of the world. The use of sentences like "Socrates is Socrates" implies
that the individual concerned behaves in a characteristic sort of way -- and,
plainly, the word "behave" connotes change. Anything that "behaves" has to
change in order to do just that --, it plainly doesn't mean they are frozen in time. So,
this 'tautology' (if it is one; that has also been questioned in Essay
Eight
Part Three) isn't saying "Socrates is
identical with Socrates", it is saying "Socrates behaves in a way that is
characteristic of the man", which is no tautology.
And even if
"Socrates is Socrates" were "atomic" (but there are reasons to doubt that, too),
what is so iniquitous about "atomic" sentences? If we fail to understand their
logic -- or if we misrepresent them -- our ability to comprehend non-atomic
sentences stands no chance. And as for these comments:
"This is to say, they are not describing the world,
they are asserting the world, demanding that you accept a finality...", and "The source of
change [is] the struggle of mutually
exclusive opposites" we have already seen are dogmatic
and that in no way "describe the world". If, per impossible,
they were descriptive, they would in fact
imply change is
impossible.
The article
then tries to argue that critics of dialectics have an answer:
"In his essay on dialectics Lenin defends the theory of
'development as a unity of opposites' against those who concede change, but
theorize it as mere part of 'a cycle of increase and decrease.' After all,
change is observable, and it is rare for someone to be so obtuse so as to deny
it outright. However, anti-dialecticians have another trick up their sleeve: a
jaded and cynical attitude towards history as a 'cyclical slaughterhouse.' They
concede that, yes, things change, but they change according to the whims of
fate, karma, accidents, willpower, or God; in the end, in their view, everything
is a wash; things never really change. This is the reason why Lenin
argues that it is essential to grasp the source of change: the
struggle of mutually exclusive opposites." [Ibid.
Paragraphs merged. Italic emphases in the original.]
Several
Essays at this site have been devoted to showing that this theory of Lenin's
collapses on close examination, and, further, that it actually implies that
change can't happen (as has just been pointed out) -- on that, see Essays Seven
Part Three,
and Eight Parts
One,
Two and
Three.
Hence, even if Marxists needed a philosophical theory of change (which we
don't!), dialectics wouldn't make the bottom of the list of viable candidates.
Furthermore,
nowhere at this site has it been claimed that
things change "according to the whims of fate,
karma, accidents, willpower, or God; in the end...things never really change",
so that unsupported rebuttal can't be used against anything argued in
these Essays.
Finally, it
is worth pointing out that comrade Day employs the theory of change through
'internal contradiction' to rationalise what seem to be pairs of contradictory
strategies and tactics (for example, the
CCP's
alliance with the
Guomindang,
and Deng Xiaoping's "irrevocable
integration with the incipiently hegemonic capitalist order coupled with a
fierce defense of the autonomy of the political executive").
In Essay Nine
Part Two, I expose this as one of the main reasons why
opportunists and substitutionists of every stripe (within Dialectical Marxism)
cling to this contradictory theory: it allows them to promote and then 'justify'
whatever is politically expedient and its opposite, at the same time.
Hence, the integration of a 'socialist economy' into the capitalist world
market allied with the continued exploitation of the Chinese working class makes
eminently sound, contradictory sense --, if you accept DM!
It could be objected that this
Essay completely misses
the point. It is misguided to claim that DM-theorists argue that knowledge begins with the
"isolation of particulars in thought"; in the search for knowledge human beings
never simply start from scratch, as the earlier sections of this Essay seem to suggest. On the contrary, as
TAR notes:
"[I]t is impossible simply to stare at the world
as it immediately presents itself to our eyes and hope to understand it. To make
sense of the world, we must bring to it a framework composed of elements of our
past experience; what we have learned of others' experience, both in the present
and in the past; and of our later reflections on and theories about this
experience." [Rees (1998), p.63.]41
"[A]ll science generalizes and abstracts from 'empirically
verifiable facts.' Indeed, the very concept of 'fact' is itself an abstraction,
because no one has ever eaten, tasted, smelt, seen or heard a 'fact,' which is a
mental generalization that distinguishes actually existing phenomena from
imaginary conceptions. Similarly, all science 'deductively anticipates'
developments -- what else is an hypothesis tested by experimentation? The
dialectic is, among other things, a way of investigating and understanding the
relationship between abstractions and reality. And the 'danger of arbitrary
construction' is far greater using an empirical method which thinks that it is
dealing with facts when it is actually dealing with abstractions than it is with
a method that properly distinguishes between the two and then seeks to explain
the relationship between them." [Ibid., p.131. Quotation marks altered to
conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]41a
These passages show that the criticisms of the
dialectical process advanced in this Essay are flawed from beginning to end.42
No dialectician of any intelligence would imagine
that in the search for knowledge human beings just look at objects and
processes divorced from historical, political, social or linguistic contexts, and blurt
a few ideas out. As Engels himself noted:
"The identity of thought and being, to express myself in
Hegelian fashion, everywhere coincides with your example of the circle and the
polygon. Or the two of them, the concept of a thing and its reality, run side by
side like
two asymptotes, always approaching each other but never meeting. This difference
between the two is the very difference which prevents the concept from being
directly and immediately reality and reality from being immediately its own
concept. Because a concept has the essential nature of the concept and does not
therefore prima facie directly coincide with reality, from which it had
to be abstracted in the first place, it is nevertheless more than a fiction,
unless you declare that all the results of thought are fictions because reality
corresponds to them only very circuitously, and even then approaching it only
asymptotically." [Engels to Conrad Schmidt (12/03/1895), in Marx and Engels
(1975b), p.457.]
This means
that the dialectical circuit can't simply be joined at any point; cut into as if this were some sort of dance. Hence, it could
be claimed that this is largely where the above analysis goes off the rails: it assumes that the DM-circuit begins
at a specific place, and because it manifestly can't do that, the incorrect conclusion is
then drawn that DM-epistemology is fundamentally flawed.
As a matter of fact --
as this objection might continue -- knowledge arises out of, and as a result
of, a historical
process. Human beings don't just go about the place "identifying particulars"
(etc). They use whatever historical, social, linguistic and epistemological
resources they have available to them under specific social conditions, and this
they do in order to advance knowledge and
refine technique. Moreover, they do this even though the entire process is
continually distorted by class division and ruling-class ideology, etc., etc.
To paraphrase Marx: human beings
develop their own concepts, but
they don't do this under social or logical
circumstances of their own choosing. DM-theorists highlight this fact;
they don't ignore it or sweep it under a rug.
Or, so this response might go...
Unfortunately, that reply isn't strictly relevant since it
confuses a logical point with what is
in fact an epistemological fairytale.
The
above legend arises out of the mythical nature of the 'process of abstraction',
unfortunately omitted from the volunteered objection outlined in the last few
paragraphs. The process of abstraction not only can't take place,
its alleged results destroy generality,
as we have seen. If that is so, the 'results'
of that mythical process can't be passed on from one generation to the next
without also transmitting that fatal defect, nor can they be
built upon by later dialecticians (and for the same reason).
To
put the same point differently: all that former generations of
Idealists can pass on to their equally Idealist descendants is distorted grammar, impenetrably obscure jargon
and unfathomable confusion.
The myth of the 'original abstraction' (on which this
entire fable depends)
-- like Adam's legendary fall from grace -– fails to provide DM-theorists with
the explanation of the nature and source of knowledge they require, since (once again to paraphrase Marx): it itself requires
explanation.
Hence, the logical points made above can't be neutralised, avoided or by-passed by a
vague extrapolation back into the mists of time.
To paraphrase once more
(but this time
Lessing):
The accidental truths of history can't provide a secure foundation for anyone who
wants to ignore
the rules of
discursive logic.43
Worse still, even if they could,
the chronicles of humanity's
heroic abstractionsstill won't pass muster.
That is because this myth, like
other metaphysical yarns, is devoid of sense -- as we will discover in the next
Part
of this Essay.
Here is Hegel's longer
'argument', which seeks to establish
some of
the points criticised in this Essay, and elsewhere at this site.
The Judgement
§1358
...To restore this
identity of the Notion, or rather to posit it, is the goal of the
movement of the judgment. What is already present in the
judgment is, on the one hand, the self-subsistence of subject and predicate, but
also their mutually opposed determinateness, and on the other hand their none
the less abstract relation. What the judgment enunciates to
start with is that the subject is the predicate; but since the
predicate is supposed not to be what the subject is, we are faced with a
contradiction which must resolve itself, pass over into a
result. Or rather, since subject and predicate
are in and for themselves the totality of the Notion, and the judgment
is the reality of the Notion, its forward movement is only a development;
there is already present in it what comes forth from it, so that proof
is merely an exposition, a reflection as a positing of
that which is already present in the extremes of the judgment; but even
this positing itself is already present; it is the relation of the
extremes....
(a) The Positive Judgment
§1362
1.The subject and predicate as we have remarked,
are in the first instance names, which only receive their actual
determination through the course of the judgment. However, as sides of the
judgment, which is the posited determinate Notion, they have the
determination of moments of the Notion, but by virtue of their
immediacy, the determination is still quite simple: for it is not
enriched by mediation, and also, in accordance with the abstract opposition, it
is determined as abstract individuality and universality. The
predicate, to speak of this first, is the abstract universal; since
this abstract is conditioned by the mediation in which the individual or
particular is sublated, this mediation is so far only presupposition.
In the sphere of the Notion there can be no other immediacy than one in
which mediation is essentially and explicitly a moment and which has
come to be only through the sublating of that mediation, that is, the immediacy
of the universal. Thus even qualitative being, too, is in
its Notion a universal; but as being, the immediacy is not yet so
posited; it is only as universality that it is the Notion
determination in which is posited the fact that negativity essentially
belongs to it. This relation is given in the judgment in which it is the
predicate of a subject. Similarly, the subject is an abstract
individual, or the immediate that is supposed to be as such,
and therefore the individual as a something in general. Thus the
subject constitutes the abstract side of the judgment according to which the
Notion has in it passed over into externality. As the two Notion
determinations are determined, so also is their relation, the is or copula;
it too can only have the significance of an immediate, abstract being.
On account of the relation which as yet contains no mediation or negation,
this judgment is called the positive.
§1363
2.The immediate pure enunciation of the positive
judgment is, therefore, the proposition:
the individual is universal.
This
enunciation must not be put in the form: A is B; for A and B
are entirely formless and consequently meaningless names; the judgment as such,
however, and therefore even the judgment of existence, has Notion determinations
for its extremes. A is B can represent any mere proposition
just as well as a judgment. But in every judgment, even in those with a
more richly determined form, there is asserted the proposition having this
specific content: the individual is universal; inasmuch, namely, as
every judgment is also in general an abstract judgment. With the negative
judgment, how far it likewise comes under this expression, we shall deal
presently. If no heed is given to the fact that in every judgment -- at least,
to begin with, every positive judgment, the assertion is made that the
individual is a universal, this is partly because the determinate form
whereby subject and predicate are distinguished is overlooked -- the judgment
being supposed to be nothing but the relation of two notions -- and partly,
probably, because the rest of the content of the judgment, Gaius is
learned, or the rose is red, floats before the mind which is busy
with the representation of Gaius, etc., and does not reflect on the
form although such content at least as the logical Gaius (sic) who has
usually to be dragged in as an example, is a much less interesting content and,
indeed, is expressly chosen as uninteresting in order not to divert attention
from the form to itself.
§1364
In its
objective signification, the proposition that the individual is universalconnotes, as we previously had occasion to remark, on the one hand the
perishableness of individual things, and on the other hand their positive
subsistence in the Notion as such. The Notion itself is imperishable, but that
which comes forth from it in its partition is subject to alteration and to
return into its universal nature. But conversely, the universal gives
itself a determinate being. Just as essence issues into a reflected
being [Schein] in its determinations, ground into the
manifestation of Existence, and substance into the revelation of itself,
into its accidents, so the universal resolves itself into the
individual; and the judgment is this explication of the universal, the
development of the negativity which it already is in itself. The latter
fact is enunciated by the converse proposition, the universal is individual,
which is equally enunciated in the positive judgment. The subject, which in the
first instance is the immediate individual, is related in the judgment
itself to its other, namely, the universal; consequently it is posited
as the concrete; in the sphere of being as a something of many
qualities, or as the concrete of reflection, a thing of manifold
properties, an actuality of manifold possibilities, a substance of such and
such accidents. Since these manifold determinations here belong to the
subject, the something or the thing, etc., is reflected into itself in its
qualities, properties or accidents; or it continues itself through
them, maintaining itself in them and equally them in itself. The positedness or
determinateness belongs to the being-in-and-for-self. The subject is, therefore,
in its own self the universal. The predicate, on the other hand, as
this universality which is not real or concrete but abstract,
is, in contrast to the subject, the determinateness and contains only
one moment of the subject's totality to the exclusion of the others. By
virtue of this negativity which, as an extreme of the judgment, is at the same
time self-related, the predicate is an abstract individual.
For example, in the proposition: the rose is fragrant, the
predicate enunciates only one of the many properties of the rose; it singles out
this particular one which, in the subject, is a concrescence with the others;
just as in the dissolution of the thing, the manifold properties which inhere in
it, in acquiring self-subsistence as matters, become individualised.
From this side, then, the proposition of the judgment runs thus: the
universal is individual.
§1365
In
bringing together this reciprocal determination of subject and
predicate in the judgment, we get a twofold result. First that
immediately the subject is, indeed, something that simply is, an
individual, while the predicate is the universal. But because the judgment is
the relation of the two, and the subject is determined by the predicate
as a universal, the subject is the universal. Secondly, the predicate
is determined in the subject; for it is not a determination in general,
but of the subject; in the proposition: the rose is fragrant,
this fragrance is not any indeterminate fragrance, but that of the rose; the
predicate is therefore an individual. Now since subject and predicate
stand in the relationship of the judgment, they have to remain mutually opposed
as determinations of the Notion; just as in the reciprocity of
causality, before it attains its truth, the two sides have to retain their
self-subsistence and mutual opposition in face of the sameness of their
determination. When, therefore, the subject is determined as a universal, we
must not take the predicate also in its determination of universality -- else we
should not have a judgment -- but only in its determination of individuality;
similarly, when the subject is determined as an individual, the predicate is to
be taken as a universal.
§1366
Reflection
on the above mere identity yields the two identical propositions:
The individual is individual,
The universal is universal,
in which
the sides of the judgment would have fallen completely asunder and only their
self-relation would be expressed, while their relation to one another would be
dissolved and the judgment consequently sublated. Of the two original
propositions, one, the universal is individual, enunciates the judgment
in respect of its content, which in the predicate is a singled out
determination, while in the subject it is the totality of them; the other,
the individual is universal, enunciates the form which is stated
immediately by the proposition itself. In the immediate positive judgment the
extremes are still simple: form and content are, therefore, still united. In
other words, it does not consist of two propositions; the twofold relation which
we found in it directly constitutes the one positive judgment. For its extremes
appear as (a) self-subsistent, abstract sides of the judgment, and (b) each side
is determined by the other, by virtue of the copula connecting them. But for
that very reason, the difference of form and content is implicit in it,
as we have seen; to wit, what is implied in the first proposition: the
individual is universal, pertains to the form, because it expresses the
immediate determinateness of the judgment. On the other hand, the
relationship expressed by the other proposition: the universal is
individual, that is to say, that the subject is determined as universal,
but the predicate as particular or individual concerns the content; for
the sides of the judgment arise only through the reflection-into-self whereby
the immediate determinatenesses are sublated, with the result that the form
converts itself into an identity that has withdrawn into itself and persists in
opposition to the distinction of form: that is, it converts itself into content.
§1367
3. Now if the two propositions, the one of form and
the other of content:
Subject
--
Predicate
The individual is universal
The universal is individual,
were,
because they are contained in the one positive judgment, to be united, so that
both subject and predicate alike were determined as unity of individuality and
universality, then both subject and predicate would be the particular;
and this must be recognised as implicitly their inner determination.
Only, on the one hand, this combination would only have been effected by an
external reflection, and, on the other hand, the resultant proposition, the
particular is the particular, would no longer be a judgment, but an empty
identical proposition like those already derived from the positive judgment,
namely, the individual is individual, and the universal is universal.
Individuality and universality cannot yet be united into particularity, because
in the positive judgment they are still posited as immediate. In other
words, the judgment must still be distinguished in respect of its form and
content, just because subject and predicate are still distinguished as immediacy
and something mediated, or because the judgment, according to its relation, is
both self-subsistence of the related sides and also their reciprocal
determination or mediation.
§1368
First,
then, the judgment considered in respect of its form asserts that
the individual is universal. But the truth is that such an immediate
individual is not universal; its predicate is of wider scope and therefore does
not correspond to it. The subject is an immediate being-for-self and
therefore the opposite of that abstraction, of that universality
posited through mediation, which was supposed to be predicated of it.
§1369
Secondly, when the judgment is considered in respect of its content,
or as the proposition, the universal is individual, the subject is
a universal of qualities, a concrete that is infinitely determined; and since
its determinatenesses are as yet only qualities, properties or accidents, its
totality is the spuriously infinite plurality of them. Such a subject
therefore is, on the contrary, not a single property such as its
predicate enunciates. Both propositions, therefore, must be denied
and the positive judgment must be posited rather as negative.
(b) The Negative Judgment
§1370
1. We have already referred above to the prevalent
idea that it depends merely on the content of the judgment whether it be true or
not, since logical truth concerns only the form and demands only that the said
content shall not contradict itself. The form of the judgment is taken to be
nothing more than the relation of two notions. But we have seen that these two
notions do not have merely the relationless character of a sum, but are
related to one another as individual and universal. These
determinations constitute the truly logical content, and, be it noted,
constitute in this abstraction the content of the positive judgment; all
other content that appears in a judgment (the sun is round, Cicero was
a great orator in Rome, it is day now, etc.) does not concern the
judgment as such; the judgment merely enunciates that the subject is
predicate, or, more definitely, since these are only names, that the
individual is universal and vice versa. By virtue of this purely
logical content, the positive judgment is not true, but has its
truth in the negative judgment. All that is demanded of the content is
that it shall not contradict itself in the judgment; but as has been shown it
does contradict itself in the above judgment. It is, however, a matter of
complete indifference if the above logical content is also called form, and by
content is understood merely the remaining empirical filling; in that case, the
form does not imply merely an empty identity, the determinate content lying
outside it. The positive judgment has, then, through its form as
positive judgment no truth; whoever gives the name of truth to the
correctness of an intuition or perception, or to the agreement of
the picture-thought with the object, at any rate has no expression left
for that which is the subject matter and aim of philosophy. We should at least
have to call the latter the truth of reason; and it will surely be granted that
judgments such as: Cicero was a great orator, and: it is day now, and so on, are
not truths of reason. But they are not such not because they have, as it were
contingently, an empirical content, but because they are merely positive
judgments that can have and are supposed to have no other content than an
immediate individual and an abstract determination.
§1371
The
positive judgment has its proximate truth in the negative: the individual is
not abstractly universal -- but on the contrary, the predicate of the
individual, because it is such a predicate or taking it by itself apart from its
relation to the subject -- because it is an abstract universal, is
itself determinate; the individual is, therefore, in the
first instance a particular. Further, in accordance with the other
proposition contained in the positive judgment, the negative judgment asserts
that the universal is not abstractly individual, but on the
contrary, this predicate, just because it is a predicate, or because it
stands in relation to a universal subject, is something wider than a mere
individuality, and the universal is therefore likewise in the first
instance a particular. Since this universal, as subject, is itself in the
judgment determination of individuality, the two propositions reduce to one:
the individual is a particular.
§1372
We may
remark (a) that here the predicate proves to be in the determination of
particularity of which we have already made mention; but here it is not
posited by external reflection, but has arisen by means of the negative relation
exhibited by the judgment. (b) This determination here results only for the
predicate. In the immediate judgment, the judgment of existence, the
subject is the underlying basis; the determination seems therefore
to run its course at first in the predicate. But as a matter of
fact this first negation cannot as yet be a determination, or strictly speaking
a positing of the individual, for the individual is the second
negation, the negative of the negative.
§1373
The
individual is a particular, is the positive expression of the
negative judgment. This expression is not itself a positive judgment, for the
latter, by reason of its immediacy, has only abstractions for its extremes,
while the particular, precisely through the positing of the relation of the
judgment presents itself as the first mediated determination. But this
determination is not to be taken only as moment of the extreme, but also -- as
it really is in the first instance -- as determination of the
relation; in other words, the judgment is to be regarded also as negative.
§1374
This
transition is based on the relationship of the extremes and their connection
generally in the judgment. The positive judgment is the relation of the
immediately individual and universal, therefore the relation of things, one
of which at the same time is not what the other is; the relation is, therefore,
no less essentially separation or negative; that is why the positive
judgment had to be posited as negative. It was, therefore, unnecessary for
logicians to make such a fuss over the not of the negative judgment being
attached to the copula. In the judgment, what is determination of
the extreme is no less a determinate relation. The judgment's
determination, or the extreme, is not the purely qualitative determination of
immediate being which is supposed to confront only an other outside
it. Nor is it determination of reflection, which, in accordance with its
general form, has a positive and negative bearing, each being posited as
exclusive, and only implicitly identical with the other. The judgment's
determination, as determination of the Notion, is in its own self a universal,
posited as continuing itself into its other determinations. Conversely,
the relation of the judgment is the same determination as that
possessed by the extremes; for it is just this universality and continuation of
them into one another; in so far as these are distinguished, the relation
also has negativity in it.
§1375
The
above-stated transition from the form of the relation to the form of
the determination has for its immediate consequence that the
not of the copula must no less be attached to the predicate
and the predicate determined as the not-universal. But by an
equally immediate consequence the not-universal is the particular.
If we stick to the negative in the completely abstract
determination of immediate not-being, then the predicate is only the
completely indeterminate not-universal. This determination is commonly
treated in logic in connection with contradictory notions and it is
inculcated as a matter of importance that in the negative of a notion
one is to stick to the negative only and it is to be regarded as the merely
indeterminate extent of the other of the positive notion. Thus
the mere not-white would be just as much red, yellow, blue, etc., as
black. But white as such is a notionless determination of
intuition; the not of white is then equally notionless not-being,
an abstraction that has been considered at the very beginning of the logic,
where we learned that its proximate truth is becoming. To employ as
examples, when treating of the terms of the judgment, such notionless contents
drawn from intuition and pictorial thinking, and to take determinations of
being and reflection for terms of the judgment, is the same
uncritical procedure as the Kantian application of the notions of the
understanding to the infinite Idea of reason or the so-called
thing-in-itself; the Notion, which also includes the judgment that
proceeds from it, is the veritable thing-in-itself or the rational;
those other determinations, however, are proper to being or essence
and have not yet been developed into forms which exhibit them as they are
in their truth, in the Notion. If we stop at white and red as
sensuous images, we are giving, as is commonly done, the name of Notion to
what is only a determination of pictorial thinking; in that case the not-white
and not-red are of course not positive predicates, just as also the
not-triangular is something completely indeterminate, for a determination based
on number and quantum is essentially indifferent and notionless. But
this kind of sensuous content, like not-being itself, must be
conceptually grasped and must lose that indifference and abstract immediacy
which it has in blind, static, pictorial thinking. Already in determinate being,
the meaningless nothing becomes the limit, through which
something does, after all, relate to an other outside it.
But in reflection, it is the negative that essentially relates
to a positive and hence is determinate; a negative is
already no longer that indeterminate not-being; it is posited as
existing only in so far as the positive is its counterpart, the third member of
the triad being their ground; the negative is thus confined within an
enclosed sphere in which, what the one is not, is something
determinate. But more than this, in the absolutely fluid continuity of the
Notion and its determinations the not is immediately a positive, and the
negation is not merely a determinateness but is taken up into the
universality and posited as identical with it. The not-universal is therefore
immediately the particular.
§1376
2.Since the negation affects the relation of the
judgment, and we are dealing with the negative judgment still as such,
it is in the first place still a judgment; consequently we have here
the relationship of subject and predicate, or of individuality and universality,
and their relation, the form of the judgment. The subject as the
immediate which forms the basis remains unaffected by the negation; it therefore
retains its determination of having a predicate, or its relation to the
universality. What is negated, therefore, is not the universality as such in
the predicate, but the abstraction or determinateness of the latter which
appeared as content in contrast to that universality. Thus the negative
judgment is not total negation; the universal sphere which contains the
predicate still subsists, and therefore the relation of the subject to the
predicate is essentially still positive; the still remaining
determination of the predicate is just as much a relation. If, for
example, it is said that the rose is not red, it is only the determinateness
of the predicate that is negated and separated from the universality which
likewise belongs to it; the universal sphere, colour, is preserved; in
saying that the rose is not red, it is assumed that it has a colour,
but a different one. In respect of this universal sphere the judgment is still
positive.
§1377
The
individual is a particular -- this positive form of the negative
judgment enunciates immediately that the particular contains universality. But
in addition it also expresses that the predicate is not merely a universal but
also a determinate universal. The negative form implies the same; for though for
example the rose is not red, it must not merely retain the universal sphere of
colour for predicate but must also have some other specific colour;
thus it is only the single determinateness of red that is negated; and
not only is the universal sphere left but determinateness, too, is preserved,
though converted into an indeterminate or general determinateness, that
is, into particularity.
§1378
3. The particularity which we have found to
be the positive determination of the negative judgment is the mediating term
between individuality and universality; thus the negative judgment is now, in
general, the mediating term leading to the third step, to the reflection of
the judgment of existence into itself. It is, in its objective
significance, merely the moment of alteration of the accidents -- or, in the sphere
of existence, of the isolated properties of the concrete. Through this
alteration the complete determinateness of the predicate, or the concrete,
emerges as posited.
§1379
The
individual is particular, according to the positive enunciation of the
negative judgment. But the individual is also not a particular, for
particularity is of wider extent than individuality; it is therefore a predicate
that does not correspond to the subject, and in which, therefore, it does not
yet possess its truth. The individual is only an individual, the
negativity that relates not to an other whether positive or negative,
but only to itself. The rose is not a thing of some colour or
other, but has only the specific colour that is rose-colour. The individual
is not an undetermined determinate, but the determined determinate.
§1380
Starting from this positive form of the negative judgment, this negation of it
appears again as only a first negation. But it is not so. On the contrary, the
negative judgment is already in and for itself the second negation or the
negation of the negation, and what it is in and for itself must be posited.
That is to say, it negates the determinateness of the predicate of the
positive judgment, the predicate's abstract universality, or, regarded
as content, the single quality which the predicate contains of the subject. But
the negation of the determinateness is already the second negation, and
therefore the infinite return of individuality into itself. With this,
therefore, the restoration of the concrete totality has been achieved,
or rather, the subject is now for the first time posited as an
individual, for through negation and the sublating of the negation it is
mediated with itself. The predicate, too, on its side, has herewith passed over
from the first universality to absolute determinateness and has equated itself
with the subject. Thus the judgment runs: the individual is individual. From the
other side, inasmuch as the subject was equally to be taken as universal,
and as the predicate (which in contrast to that determination of the subject is
the individual) widened itself in the negative judgment into
particularity, and as now, further, the negation of this
determinateness is no less the purification of the universality
contained in the predicate, this judgment also runs: the universal is the
universal.
§1381
In these
two judgments, which we had previously reached by external reflection, the
predicate is already expressed in its positivity. But first, the negation of the
negative judgment must itself appear in the form of a negative judgment. We saw
that in it there still remained a positive relation of the subject to
the predicate, and the universal sphere of the latter. From this side,
therefore, the negative contained a universality more purged of limitation than
the positive judgment, and for that reason must be all the more negated of the
subject as an individual. In this manner, the whole extent of the
predicate is negated and there is no longer any positive relation between it and
the subject. This is the infinite judgment.
(c) The Infinite Judgment
§1382
The
negative judgment is as little a true judgment as the positive. But the infinite
judgment which is supposed to be its truth is, according to its negative
expression, negatively infinite, a judgment in which even the form of
judgment is set aside. But this is a nonsensical judgment. It is
supposed to be a judgment, and consequently to contain a relation of
subject and predicate; yet at the same time such a relation is supposed
not to be in it. Though the name of the infinite judgment usually appears in the
ordinary logics, it is not altogether clear what its nature really is. Examples
of negatively infinite judgments are easily obtained: determinations are
negatively connected as subject and predicate, one of which not only does not
include the determinateness of the other but does not even contain its universal
sphere; thus for example spirit is not red, yellow, etc., is not acid, not
alkaline, etc., the rose is not an elephant, the understanding is not a table,
and the like. These judgments are correct or true, as the expression
goes, but in spite of such truth they are nonsensical and absurd. Or rather,
they are not judgments at all. A more realistic example of the infinite
judgment is the evil action. In civil litigation, something is negated
only as the property of the other party, it being conceded that it should be
theirs if they had the right to it; and it is only the title of right that is in
dispute; the universal sphere of right is therefore recognised and maintained in
that negative judgment. But crime is the infinite judgment
which negates not merely the particular right, but the universal sphere as well,
negates right as right. This infinite judgment does indeed possess
correctness, since it is an actual deed, but it is nonsensical because it
is related purely negatively to morality which constitutes its universal sphere.
§1383
The
positive moment of the infinite judgment, of the negation of the negation,
is the reflection of individuality into itself, whereby it is posited
for the first time as a determinate determinateness.
According to that reflection, the expression of the judgment was: the
individual is individual In the judgment of existence, the subject appears
as an immediate individual and consequently rather as a mere
something in general. It is through the mediation of the negative and
infinite judgments that it is for the first time posited as an
individual.
§1384
The
individual is hereby posited as continuing itself into its
predicate, which is identical with it; consequently, too, the universality
no longer appears as immediate but as a comprehension of
distinct terms. The positively infinite judgment equally runs: the universal
is universal, and as such is equally posited as the return into itself.
§1385
Now
through this reflection of the terms of the judgment into themselves the
judgment has sublated itself; in the negatively infinite judgment the difference
is, so to speak, too great for it to remain a judgment; the subject and
predicate have no positive relation whatever to each other; in the positively
infinite judgment, on the contrary, only identity is present and owing to the
complete lack of difference it is no longer a judgment.
§1386
More
precisely, it is the judgment of existence that has sublated itself;
hereby there is posited what the copula of the judgment
contains, namely, that the qualitative extremes are sublated in this their
identity. Since however this unity is the Notion, it is immediately sundered
again into its extremes and appears as a judgment, whose terms however are no
longer immediate but reflected into themselves. The judgment of existence
has passed over into the judgment of reflection. [Hegel (1999),
pp.631-43. I have used the online version here. Bold emphases alone added.]
Good luck to
anyone who thinks they can make sense of that!
[The above
Hegelian ramble continues on for another thirty pages and should be read only by
those suffering from incurable insomnia.]
In this
Appendix, in addition to
the passages already quoted in the main body of this Essay -- e.g.,
here and
here, and
in Part Two,
here
and
here --, I will be posting material taken from several (hopefully representative) DM-theorists
who attempt to explain what they mean by the
'process of abstraction' and its supposed 'results'.
[Several of the
points I make below also apply to
the first few chapters of Ilyenkov (1982).
However, as noted earlier, Ilyenkov clearly failed to notice the fatal
implications they had for this entire way of 'doing philosophy'.]
The following
was
taken from Spirkin's textbook on DM:
"One of the instruments of thought is language, and also other sign systems,
such as the abstract symbols of mathematics, or the concrete images of the
'language of art'. The elements of these systems support such basic operations
of thought as abstraction, generalisation and mediation. Abstraction enables us
to ignore an object's inessential properties and relations and concentrate on
those that are relevant to the intellectual task in question. Generalisation
enables us to classify large numbers of phenomena according to certain essential
attributes. For example, one can classify certain symptoms as symptoms of a
certain illness. [p.220.]
"Scientific concepts reveal the profound properties, what is general,
essential and law-governed in an object. Just as the whole is not merely the sum
of its parts, so the concept is not merely the sum-total of certain general
features. We move on from the sensuous stage of knowledge to logical thought
when we proceed from perception and representation to reflection in the form of
concepts and, on this basis, to judgements and inferences. Abstract thinking
implies operating with concepts. It is thanks to concepts that thought becomes
theoretical as well as practical, because the essence of things is perceived
only in concepts. Concepts arise from the summing up of human experience, they
are compressed travelogues, digests, of the road that has been travelled towards
knowledge. A concept is both the sum and the means of cognitive activity. [pp.229-30.]
"Abstraction is the mental identification, singling out of some object from
its connections with other objects, the separation of some attribute of an
object from its other attributes, of some relation between certain objects
from the objects themselves. Abstraction is a method of mental
simplification, by which we consider some one aspect of the process we are
studying. The scientist looks at the colourful picture which any object
presents in real life through a single-colour filter and this enables him to
see that object in only one, fundamentally important aspect. The picture
loses many of its shades but gains in clarity. Abstraction has its limit.
One cannot abstract the flame from what is burning. The sharp edge of
abstraction, like the edge of a razor can be used to whittle things down
until nothing is left. Abstraction can never be absolute. The existence of
content shows intrinsically in every abstraction. The question of what to
abstract and what to abstract from is ultimately decided by the nature of
the objects under examination and the tasks confronting the investigator.
Kepler, for example, was not interested in the colour of Mars or the
temperature of the Sun when he sought to establish the laws of the
revolution of the planets.
"What we get as a result of the process of
abstracting is various concepts about certain objects, such as 'plant',
'animal', 'human being', ideas about the separate properties of objects and
the relations between them ('whiteness', 'volume', 'length', 'heat
capacity', etc.).
"Idealisation as a specific form of abstraction is an important technique
in scientific cognition. Abstract objects do not exist and cannot be made to
exist in reality, but they have their prototypes in the real world. Pure
mathematics operates with numbers, vectors and other mathematical objects
that are the result of abstraction and idealisation. Geometry, for example,
is concerned with exact circles, but physical object is never exactly
circular; perfect roundness is an abstraction. It cannot be found in nature.
But it is an image of the real: it was brought into existence by
generalisation from experience. Idealisation is a process of forming
concepts, whose real prototypes can be indicated only to a certain degree of
approximation. As a result of idealisation there comes into being a
theoretical model in which the characteristics and aspects of the objects
under investigation are not only abstracted from their actual empirical multiformity
but also, by means of mental construction, are made to stand
out in a sharper and more fully expressed form than in reality itself. As
examples of concepts resulting from idealisation we may take such things as
the 'point' (an object which has neither length, nor height, nor breadth);
or 'the straight line', the 'circle', and so on. [pp.232-33.]
"The mental transition from the more general to the less general is a process
of limitation. Without generalisation there can be no theory. Theory, on the
other hand, is created so that it can be applied in practice to solve
certain specific problems. For example, when measuring objects or building
certain technical structures, we must always proceed from the more general
to the less general and the individual, there must always be a process of
limitation. The grotesque fantastic images of mythology with its gods and
monsters are closer to ordinary reality than the reality of the microworld
conceived in the form of mathematical symbols. One can see that the turn
towards the abstract is a very obvious trend of our time. Recourse to the
abstract may also be observed in art, in abstract pictures and sculptures.
"The abstract and the concrete. The concept of
'the concrete' is used
in two senses. First, in the sense of something directly given, a sensuously
perceived and represented whole. In this sense the concrete is the starting
point of cognition. But as soon as we treat it theoretically the concrete
becomes a concept, a system of scientific definitions revealing the
essential connections and relations of things and events, their unity in
diversity. So the concrete appears to us first in the form of a sensuously
observable image of the whole object not yet broken down and not understood
in its law-governed connections and mediations, but at the level of
theoretical thought it is still a whole, but internally differentiated,
understood in its various intrinsic contradictions. The sensuously concrete
is a poor reflection of phenomena, but the concrete in thought is a richer,
more essential cognition. In contrast to the abstract the concrete is only
one moment in the process of cognition, we understand it by comparing it
with the abstract. Abstraction usually suggests to us some thing 'mental',
'conceptual', in contrast to the sensuously observable. The abstract is also
thought of as something one-sided, poor, incomplete, separated, or as a
property, a relation, a form, etc. withdrawn from its connection with the
whole. And in this sense not only a concept but even an observable image,
for example, a diagram, a drawing, an abstract painting, stylisation, a
symbol may be abstract. The category of abstraction is contradictory. It is
dead, one-sided, separated from the living phenomenon, but it is also an
essential step towards the knowledge of a concrete fact brimming with life.
We call knowledge abstract also in the sense that it reflects a fragment of
reality, as it were, stripped down, refined and thereby impoverished.
"Abstractions are
'bits' of whole objects, and our thinking works with
such 'bits'. From separate abstractions thought constantly returns to the
restoration of concreteness, but each time on a new, higher basis. This is
the concreteness of concepts, categories, and theories reflecting unity in
diversity.
"What
do we mean by cognition as a process of ascent from the abstract to the
concrete? '...[C]ognition rolls onwards from content to
content. First of all, this advance is determined as beginning from simple
determinatenesses the succeeding ones becoming ever richer and more
concrete. For the result contains its beginning and its course has
enriched it by a fresh determinateness. The universal constitutes the
foundation; the advance is therefore not to be taken as a flowing
from one other to the next other. In the absolute method the
Notion maintains itself in its otherness. the universal in its
particularisation, in judgment and reality; at each stage of its further
determination it raises the entire mass of its preceding content, and by its
dialectical advance it not only does not lose anything or leave anything
behind, but carries along with it all it has gained, and inwardly enriches
and consolidates itself." [Georg Wilhelm Friedrich
Hegel's Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe. Fünfter Band. Wissenschaft der
Logic. Berlin, 1834, Verlag von Duncker und Humblot, S.348-49. (This is in
fact
Hegel (1999), p.840. §1809.)] Seen in this light, the process of abstraction is a
realisation of the principle: one must step back in order to get a better
view. The dialectics of the cognition of reality lies in the fact that by
'flying away' from this sensuously given reality on the 'wings' of
abstraction, one may from the heights of concrete theoretical thought better
'survey' the essence of the object under investigation. Such is the history
and logic of scientific cognition. Here we have the essence of the Marxist
method of ascent from the abstract to the concrete. According to Marx, this
method is the means by which thought assimilates the concrete, reproduces it
by linking up concepts into an integrated scientific theory, which
reproduces the objective separateness of the objects and the unity of its
essential properties and relations. The concrete is concrete because it is a
synthesis of many definitions, and, consequently, a unity of the diversity.
The principle of concreteness means that we must approach facts of natural
and social life not with general formulas and diagrams but by taking into
exact account all the real conditions in which the target of our research is
located and distinguish the most important, essential properties,
connections, and tendencies that determine its other aspects." [Spirkin
(1983),
pp.233-35.
Bold emphases alone added; quotation marks altered to conform with the
conventions adopted at this site. I have used the translation found in Hegel
(1999), not Spirkin's version.]
From
the above it is
plain that Spirkin's account itself lies somewhere between the Empiricist and the
Rationalist versions of this mythical 'process' (more about that in
Part Two):
"Abstraction enables us
to ignore an object's inessential properties and relations and concentrate on
those that are relevant to the intellectual task in question....
"We move on from the sensuous stage of knowledge to logical thought
when we proceed from perception and representation to reflection in the form of
concepts and, on this basis, to judgements and inferences. Abstract thinking
implies operating with concepts. It is thanks to concepts that thought becomes
theoretical as well as practical, because the essence of things is perceived
only in concepts. Concepts arise from the summing up of human experience, they
are compressed travelogues, digests, of the road that has been travelled towards
knowledge. A concept is both the sum and the means of cognitive activity....
"Abstraction is the mental identification, singling out of some object from
its connections with other objects, the separation of some attribute of an
object from its other attributes, of some relation between certain objects
from the objects themselves. Abstraction is a method of mental
simplification, by which we consider some one aspect of the process we are
studying.
"Idealisation as a specific form of abstraction is an important technique
in scientific cognition. Abstract objects do not exist and cannot be made to
exist in reality, but they have their prototypes in the real world. Pure
mathematics operates with numbers, vectors and other mathematical objects
that are the result of abstraction and idealisation. Geometry, for example,
is concerned with exact circles, but physical object is never exactly
circular; perfect roundness is an abstraction. It cannot be found in nature.
But it is an image of the real: it was brought into existence by
generalisation from experience. Idealisation is a process of forming
concepts, whose real prototypes can be indicated only to a certain degree of
approximation. As a result of idealisation there comes into being a
theoretical model in which the characteristics and aspects of the objects
under investigation are not only abstracted from their actual empirical multiformity but also, by means of mental construction, are made to stand
out in a sharper and more fully expressed form than in reality itself....
"The concept of
'the concrete' is used
in two senses. First, in the sense of something directly given, a sensuously
perceived and represented whole. In this sense the concrete is the starting
point of cognition. But as soon as we treat it theoretically the concrete
becomes a concept, a system of scientific definitions revealing the
essential connections and relations of things and events, their unity in
diversity. So the concrete appears to us first in the form of a sensuously
observable image of the whole object not yet broken down and not understood
in its law-governed connections and mediations, but at the level of
theoretical thought it is still a whole, but internally differentiated,
understood in its various intrinsic contradictions. The sensuously concrete
is a poor reflection of phenomena, but the concrete in thought is a richer,
more essential cognition. In contrast to the abstract the concrete is only
one moment in the process of cognition, we understand it by comparing it
with the abstract...." [Ibid.]
In line with the Empiricists and the Rationalists, Spirkin
clearly sees
'abstraction' as a 'mental process' that takes place in 'the mind' of each individual.
In other words, as is the case with other DM-fans, he is a
bourgeois
individualist:
"We move on from the sensuous stage of knowledge to logical thought
when we proceed from perception and representation to reflection in the form of
concepts and, on this basis, to judgements and inferences. Abstract thinking
implies operating with concepts. It is thanks to concepts that thought becomes
theoretical as well as practical, because the essence of things is perceived
only in concepts. Concepts arise from the summing up of human experience, they
are compressed travelogues, digests, of the road that has been travelled towards
knowledge. A concept is both the sum and the means of cognitive activity....
"Abstraction is the mental identification, singling out of some object from
its connections with other objects, the separation of some attribute of an
object from its other attributes, of some relation between certain objects
from the objects themselves. Abstraction is a method of mental
simplification, by which we consider some one aspect of the process we are
studying....
"Geometry, for example, is concerned with exact circles, but physical object is
never exactly circular; perfect roundness is an abstraction. It cannot be found in nature.
But it is an image of the real: it was brought into existence by
generalisation from experience. Idealisation is a process of forming
concepts, whose real prototypes can be indicated only to a certain degree of
approximation. As a result of idealisation there comes into being a
theoretical model in which the characteristics and aspects of the objects
under investigation are not only abstracted from their actual empirical multiformity but also, by means of mental construction, are made to stand
out in a sharper and more fully expressed form than in reality itself.
"The mental transition from the more general to the less general is a process
of limitation. Without generalisation there can be no theory....
"The concept of
'the concrete' is used
in two senses. First, in the sense of something directly given, a sensuously
perceived and represented whole. In this sense the concrete is the starting
point of cognition. But as soon as we treat it theoretically the concrete
becomes a concept, a system of scientific definitions revealing the
essential connections and relations of things and events, their unity in
diversity. So the concrete appears to us first in the form of a sensuously
observable image of the whole object not yet broken down and not understood
in its law-governed connections and mediations, but at the level of
theoretical thought it is still a whole, but internally differentiated,
understood in its various intrinsic contradictions. The sensuously concrete
is a poor reflection of phenomena, but the concrete in thought is a richer,
more essential cognition. In contrast to the abstract the concrete is only
one moment in the process of cognition, we understand it by comparing it
with the abstract....
"Abstractions are
'bits' of whole objects, and our thinking works with
such 'bits'...." [Ibid.]
Spirkin clearly failed to notice that this approach to knowledge (or even
'cognition') completely undermines the emphasis he elsewhere placed on the
social nature of knowledge and language.
Moreover, Spirkin nowhere attempts to
prove, or even substantiate, any of his rather bold claims; he merely
asserts them as if they were established fact. He neither cites nor quotes any
scientific/psychological evidence in support of what he repeatedly claims. Nor does
he so much as mention the many problems this theory faces (for example, those
that have been raised in this Essay,
or those advanced by earlier anti-abstractionists, such as..., er..., Marx and Engels!),
let alone attempt to address them.
[In Spirkin's case, this isn't surprising.
Any
admission, or concession, no matter how mild or nuanced, that DM faces
serious problems would probably have landed him in jail, a psychiatric
'hospital', or, at the very
least, he would have suffered the Russian equivalent of 'being
sent to Coventry'. The same excuse can't, however, exculpate
DM-theorists writing and publishing in more 'liberal' countries.]
The following
point requires special comment, though:
"Idealisation as a specific form of abstraction is an important technique
in scientific cognition. Abstract objects do not exist and cannot be made to
exist in reality, but they have their prototypes in the real world. Pure
mathematics operates with numbers, vectors and other mathematical objects
that are the result of abstraction and idealisation. Geometry, for example,
is concerned with exact circles, but physical object is never exactly
circular; perfect roundness is an abstraction. It cannot be found in nature. But it is an image of the real: it was brought into existence by
generalisation from experience. Idealisation is a process of forming
concepts, whose real prototypes can be indicated only to a certain degree of
approximation. As a result of idealisation there comes into being a
theoretical model in which the characteristics and aspects of the objects
under investigation are not only abstracted from their actual empirical multiformity but also, by means of mental construction, are made to stand
out in a sharper and more fully expressed form than in reality itself. As
examples of concepts resulting from idealisation we may take such things as
the 'point' (an object which has neither length, nor height, nor breadth);
or 'the straight line', the 'circle', and so on." [Ibid.]
And yet, if there are no "exact" circles
anywhere in the world, and if our 'thought'
exists in this same world, then there can be no "exact" circles 'in thought',
either! It is no use appealing to some sort of "approximation" here, since
an approximation only makes sense in relation to that with which it is
an approximation. But, there is nothing with which these approximations can be
compared (even in theory) so that we might see, or be able to say, judge or
conclude they are
approximations to begin with, rather than figments of the imagination -- since
"Abstract objects don't exist and can't be made to exist in
reality...".
Of course, that doesn't mean we can't
ascertain how accurately a given circle has been drawn, since, we don't compare
such drawings with the 'perfect circle', we determine how well the rules we have
for drawing circles have been observed.
So, from where do we obtain the idea of an "exact" circle? Certainly not from
'abstraction'.
[I say more about this topic in several
other Essays, for example:
here and here. See also
here.]
"First and foremost, and stripped of all
qualifications added by this or that dialectician, the subject of dialectics is
change, all change, and interaction, all kinds and degrees of interaction. This
is not to say that dialectical thinkers recognize the existence of change and
interaction, while non-dialectical thinkers do not. That would be foolish.
Everyone recognizes that everything in the world changes, somehow and to some
degree, and that the same holds true for interaction. The problem is how to
think adequately about them, how to capture them in thought. How, in other
words, can we think about change and interaction so as not to miss or distort
the real changes and interactions that we know, in a general way at least, are
there (with all the implications this has for how to study them and to
communicate what we find to others)? This is the key problem addressed by
dialectics, this is what all dialectics is about, and it is in helping to
resolve this problem that Marx turns to the process of abstraction." [Ollman
(2003),
pp.59-60. Bold emphasis added.]
"In his most explicit statement on the subject, Marx claims that his method
starts from the 'real concrete' (the world as it presents itself to us) and
proceeds through 'abstraction' (the intellectual activity of breaking this whole
down into the mental units with which we think about it) to the 'thought
concrete' (the reconstituted and now understood whole present in the mind) (Marx
(1904), pp.293-94; this is a reference to
A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy
-- RL). The real
concrete is simply the world in which we live, in all its complexity. The
thought concrete is Marx's reconstruction of that world in the theories of what
has come to be called 'Marxism.' The royal road to understanding is said to pass
from the one to the other through the process of abstraction." [Ibid.,
p.60. Bold emphasis added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this
site, as they have been in the rest of the passages quoted from this source.
Referencing conventions modified to agree with those implemented at this site, too.]
"In one sense, the role Marx gives to abstraction is simple recognition of the
fact that all thinking about reality begins by breaking it down into manageable
parts. Reality may be in one piece when lived, but to be thought about and
communicated it must be parceled (sic) out. Our minds can no more swallow the
world whole at one sitting than can our stomachs. Everyone then, and not just
Marx and Marxists, begins the task of trying to make sense of his or her
surroundings by distinguishing certain features and focusing on and organizing
them in ways deemed appropriate. 'Abstract' comes from the Latin, 'abstrahere',
which means 'to pull from.' In effect, a piece has been pulled from or taken out
of the whole and is temporarily perceived as standing apart.
"We 'see' only some of what lies in front of us, 'hear' only part of the noises
in our vicinity, 'feel' only a small part of what our body is in contact with,
and so on through the rest of our senses. In each case, a focus is established
and a kind of boundary set within our perceptions distinguishing what is
relevant from what is not. It should be clear that 'What did you see?' (What
caught your eye?) is a different question from 'What did you actually
see?' (What came into your line of vision?). Likewise, in thinking about any
subject, we focus on only some of its qualities and relations. Much that could
be included -- that may in fact be included in another person's view or thought,
and may on another occasion be included in our own -- is left out. The mental
activity involved in establishing such boundaries, whether conscious or
unconscious -- though it is usually an amalgam of both -- is the process of
abstraction.
"Responding to a mixture of influences that
include the material world and our experiences in it as well as to personal
wishes, group interests, and other social constraints, it is the process
of abstraction that establishes the specificity of the objects with which we
interact. In setting boundaries, in ruling this far and no further, it is what
makes something one (or two, or more) of a kind, and lets us know where that
kind begins and ends. With this decision as to units, we also become committed
to a particular set of relations between them -- relations made possible and
even necessary by the qualities that we have included in each -- a register for
classifying them, and a mode for explaining them.
"In listening to a concert, for example, we often
concentrate on a single instrument or recurring theme and then redirect our
attention elsewhere. Each time this occurs, the whole music alters, new patterns
emerge, each sound takes on a different value, etc. How we understand the music
is largely determined by how we abstract it. The same applies to what we focus
on when watching a play, whether on a person, or a combination of persons, or a
section of the stage. The meaning of the play and what more is required to
explore or test that meaning alters, often dramatically, with each new
abstraction. In this way, too, how we abstract literature, where we draw the
boundaries, determines what works and what parts of each work will be studied,
with what methods, in relation to what other subjects, in what order, and even
by whom. Abstracting literature to include its audience, for example, leads to a
sociology of literature, while an abstraction of literature that excludes
everything but its forms calls forth various structural approaches, and so on."
[Ibid.,
pp.60-61. Bold emphases added.]
"Before concluding our discussion of the place of change in Marx's abstractions,
it is worth noting that thinking in terms of processes is not altogether alien
to common sense. It occurs in abstractions of actions, such as eating, walking,
fighting, etc., indeed whenever the gerund form of the verb is used. Likewise,
event words, such as 'war' and 'strike', indicate that to some degree at least
the processes involved have been abstracted as such. On the other hand, it is
also possible to think of war and strike as a state or condition, more like a
photo than a motion picture, or if the latter, then a single scene that gets
shown again and again, which removes or seriously underplays whatever changes
are taking place. And unfortunately, the same is true of most action verbs. They
become action 'things.' In such cases, the real processes that go on do not get
reflected -- certainly not to any adequate degree -- in our thinking about them.
It is my impression that in the absence of any commitment to bring change itself
into focus, in the manner of Marx, this is the more typical outcome." [Ibid.,
p.67. Bold emphasis added.]
As can be seen
from the above, Ollman has adopted a simplified form of the Empiricist
Theory of Abstraction.
Ollman has much
more to say about this topic; I have posted the relevant passages in Part Two (here),
subjecting them to sustained criticism. Even so, from the sections I quoted above, it is clear that Ollman also conceives of abstraction as a 'mental
process', making him a
bourgeois
individualist, too. In addition, he seems to think this 'process' results in the
formation of the Proper Names of
activities like walking, eating, and fighting. It is hard, therefore, to see how he
might preserve the
unity of the proposition because of his
repetition of this ancient syntactical blunder.
In common
with every other dialectician, Sayer also thinks that 'abstraction' is a
'mental' phenomenon or skill we are all supposed to possess, instantiate or
perform; but, like them, too, he becomes rather
vague when it comes to specifics:
"To be
practically-adequate, knowledge must grasp the differentiations of the world: we
need a way of individuating objects, and of characterising their attributes and
relationships. To be adequate for a specific purpose it must 'abstract' from
particular conditions, excluding those which have no significant effect in order
to focus on those which do. Even where we are interested in wholes we must
select and abstract their constituents.
"In
many accounts of science abstraction is assumed to be so obviously necessary
that little is said about how it should be done. It is a powerful tool and
hence and also a dangerous one if carelessly used. Once we have become
accustomed to a particular 'mode of abstraction' it is often hard to dislodge,
even where it generates problems in research and applications. In contrast to
some accounts, I therefore want to emphasize the importance of trying to keep in
mind what we abstract from....
"In
popular usage, the adjective 'abstract' often means 'vague' or 'removed from
reality'. The sense
in which the term is used here is different; an
abstract concept, or an abstraction, isolates in thought a one-sided or partial
aspect of an object. [In a footnote, Sayer adds 'My use of "abstract" and
"concrete" is, I think, equivalent to Marx's' (p.277, note 3).] What
we abstract from are the many other aspects which together constitute
concrete objects, such as people, economics [I'm sure Sayer means
economies here -- RL], nations, institutions, activities and so on. In this
sense an abstract concept can be precise rather than vague; there is nothing
vague about abstractions such as 'temperature', 'valency', 'gender', 'income
elasticity of demand', or 'the circuit of money capital'. And the things to
which these abstractions refer need be no less real than those referred to by
concrete concepts. Hence the abstract and the concrete should not be aligned
with the distinction between thought and reality.
"The
concept of 'concrete objects' does not merely concern 'whatever exists' but
draws attention to the fact that objects are usually constituted by a
combination of diverse elements or forces. As a concrete entity, a particular
person, institution or whatever combines influences and properties from a wide
range of sources, each of which (e.g. physique, personality, intelligence,
attitudes, etc.) might be isolated in thought by means of abstraction, as
a first step towards conceptualizing their combined effect.
"In
other words, the understanding of concrete events or objects involves a double
movement: concrete → abstract, abstract → concrete. At the
outset our concepts of concrete objects are likely to be superficial or chaotic.
In order to understand their diverse determinations we must first abstract them
systematically. When each of the abstracted aspects has been examined it is
possible to combine the abstractions so as to form concepts which grasp the
concreteness of their objects.
"Before
proceeding it should be noted that not all concrete objects are empirically
observable, nor are all abstract aspects of objects unobservable.
Concept-dependent phenomena apart, they exist regardless of whether anyone
happens to be able to observe or otherwise know them. Abstractions need not be
seen as 'idealizations', nor are they merely
heuristic
devices for ordering observations. As concepts, abstractions are obviously
different from material objects to which they may refer, but this applies to
empirical observations and concrete concepts no less than to abstractions: all
of them can refer to real objects...". [Sayer (1992),
pp.86-88. Bold emphases alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this
site. Link added. The page numbering is completely different in the Second
Corrected Edition, i.e., Sayer (2010), pp.58-60.]
As part of a discussion of what he calls "contentless abstractions", he had
this to say:
"There
are also cases where abstractions become virtually contentless not because there
is nothing they could refer to but because their sense-relations are too weakly
articulated to allow unambiguous reference. An abstract concept might be
denoted by the symbol p, which in turn might refer to an object P.
The danger of taking abstractions to the extreme form of mere notation is that
we are easily led to forget P, and what kind of thing it is, so that our
manipulations of logical or mathematical formulae 'take on a life of their own'
and we lose our grip on our knowledge of those material and causal (as opposed
to logical) properties of P which determine what it can and cannot do....
As Marx said of Hegel, it involves the fallacy of taking 'the things of logic
[or mathematics -- this is Sayer's interpolation, not mine -- RL] for the logic of
things'." [Ibid., p.99. Bold emphases alone added. Sayer (2010), p.67.]
From this it
is clear that Sayer, too, thinks abstractions, or the words used to express
them, or by means of which we supposedly refer to them (he, too, is unclear about this distinction --
i.e., between words about abstractions and those abstractions themselves,
he just runs the two together; we can see that by the way he talks about the "logical
properties of P", which he has just told us in an "object") are Proper
Names, or other singular referring expressions. Hence, as
was the case with Ollman, it is isn't easy to
see how he, too, might hope to preserve the
unity of the proposition.
In an earlier
article Sayer added these comments:
"By
'concrete' we mean something real, but not something which is reducible to the
empirical: we mean far more than just 'factual'. The concrete object is concrete
not simply because it exists, but because it is a combination of many diverse
forces or processes. In contrast, an abstract concept presents a one-sided or
partial aspect of an object. For example, if we conceptualise an object such as
a factory simply in terms of its outward appearance, the concept will be
abstract in the sense of one-sided even though it refers to something which can
be empirically observed. To make this a concrete concept we would have to
specify all the relationships in which the factory is involved: with its
workforce; its suppliers and buyers; its creditors and competitors, etc.
These diverse determinations are not simply listed and 'added up', but are
synthesised; that is, their combination qualitatively modifies each constituent
element. However, in order to understand this combination, we normally have
to isolate each element in thought first, even though they do not and sometimes
could not exist in isolation in reality. It's important to note that whether
the concrete is observable (and hence an empirical object for us) is contingent
(i.e., neither necessary nor impossible). The concepts 'concrete' and
'empirical' are not equivalent." [Sayer (1981), p.123. Bold emphases
alone added.]
And
yet, as we have seen, and as
Lenin admitted, specifying "all the relationships" that anything
possesses is in fact impossible.
That would imply that nothing would or could ever be declared 'concrete'.
The
following was taken from
RIRE [i.e., Woods and Grant (1995/2007); the page references are to the First
Edition]:
"The need to understand the world was closely linked to the need to survive.
Those early hominids who discovered the use of stone scrapers in butchering dead
animals with thick hides obtained a considerable advantage over those who were
denied access to this rich supply of fats and proteins. Those who perfected
their stone implements and worked out where to find the best materials stood a
better chance of survival than those who did not. With the development of
technique came the expansion of the mind, and the need to explain the phenomena
of nature which governed their lives. Over millions of years, through trial and
error, our ancestors began to establish certain relations between things. They
began to make abstractions, that is, to generalise from experience and practice.
"For centuries, the central question of philosophy has been the relation of
thinking to being. Most people live their lives quite happily without even
considering this problem. They think and act, talk and work, with not the
slightest difficulty. Moreover, it would not occur to them to regard as
incompatible the two most basic human activities, which are in practice
inseparably linked. Even the most elementary action, if we exclude simple
biologically determined reactions, demands some thought. To a degree, this is
true not only of humans but also of animals, such as a cat lying in wait for a
mouse. In man, however, the kind of thought and planning has a qualitatively
higher character than any of the mental activities of even the most advanced of
the apes.
"This fact is inseparably linked to the capacity for abstract thought, which
enables humans to go far beyond the immediate situation given to us by our
senses. We can envisage situations, not just in the past (animals also have
memory, as a dog which cowers at the sight of a stick) but also the future. We
can anticipate complex situations, plan and thereby determine the outcome, and
to some extent determine our own destinies. Although we do not normally think
about it, this represents a colossal conquest which sets humankind apart from
the rest of nature. 'What is distinctive of human reasoning,' says Professor
Gordon Childe, 'is that it can go immensely farther from the actual present
situation than any other animal's reasoning ever seems to get it.' From this
capacity springs all the manifold creations of civilisation, culture, art,
music, literature, science, philosophy, religion. We also take for granted that
all this does not drop from the skies, but is the product of millions of years
of development." [p.36.]
"Abstraction is absolutely necessary. Without it, thought in general would be
impossible. The question is: what sort of abstraction? When I abstract from
reality, I concentrate on some aspects of a given phenomenon, and leave the
others out of account. A good mapmaker, for instance, is not someone who
reproduces every detail of every house and paving-stone, and every parked car.
Such an amount of detail would destroy the very purpose of the map, which is to
make available a convenient scheme of a town or other geographical area.
Similarly, the brain early on learns to ignore certain sounds and concentrate on
others. If we were not able to do this, the amount of information reaching our
ears from all sides would overwhelm the mind completely. Language itself
presupposes a high level of abstraction.
"The ability to make correct abstractions, which adequately reflect the
reality we wish to understand and describe, is the essential prerequisite for
scientific thought. The abstractions of formal logic are adequate to express the
real world only within quite narrow limits. But they are one-sided and static,
and are hopelessly inadequate to deal with complex processes, particularly
movement, change and contradictions. The concreteness of an object consists of
the sum-total of its aspects and interrelationships, determined by its
underlying laws. It is the task of science to uncover these laws, and to get as
close as possible to this concrete reality. The whole purpose of cognition is to
reflect the objective world and its underlying lawfulness and necessary
relationships as faithfully as possible. As Hegel point [sic] out, 'the truth is
always concrete.'
"But
here we have a contradiction. It is not possible to arrive at an understanding
of the concrete world of nature without first resorting to abstraction. The word
abstract comes from the Latin 'to take from.' By
a process of abstraction, we take from the object under consideration certain
aspects which we consider important, leaving others to one side. Abstract
knowledge is necessarily one-sided because it expresses only one particular side
of the phenomenon under consideration, isolated from that which determines the
specific nature of the whole. Thus, mathematics deals exclusively with
quantitative relations. Since quantity is an extremely important aspect of
nature, the abstractions of mathematics have provided us with a powerful
instrument for probing her secrets. For this reason, it is tempting to forget
their real nature and limitations. Yet they remain one-sided, like all
abstractions. We forget this at our peril.
"Nature
knows quality as well as quantity. To determine the precise relation between the
two, and to show how, at a critical point, one turns into the other is
absolutely necessary if we wish to understand one of the most fundamental
processes in nature. This is one of the most basic concepts of dialectical as
opposed to merely formal thought, and one of its most important contributions to
science. The deep insights provided by this method, which was long decried as 'mysticism,'
are only now beginning to be understood and appreciated. One-sided abstract
thought, as manifested in formal logic did a colossal disservice to science by
excommunicating dialectics. But the actual results of science show that, in the
last analysis, dialectical thinking is far closer to the real processes of
nature than the linear abstractions of formal logic....
"Without abstraction it is impossible to penetrate the object in
'depth,' to
understand its essential nature and laws of motion. Through the mental work of
abstraction, we are able to get beyond the immediate information provided by our
senses (sense-perception), and probe deeper. We can break the object down into
its constituent parts, isolate them, and study them in detail. We can arrive at
an idealised, general conception of the object as a 'pure' form, stripped of all
secondary features. This is the work of abstraction, an absolutely necessary
stage of the process of cognition." [pp.85-87.]
"The initial process thus goes from the concrete to the abstract. The object
is dismembered, analysed, in order to obtain a detailed knowledge of its parts.
But there are dangers in this. The parts cannot be correctly understood apart
from their relationship with the whole. It is necessary to return to the object
as an integral system, and to grasp the underlying dynamics that condition it as
a whole. In this way, the process of cognition moves from the abstract back to
the concrete. This is the essence of the dialectical method, which combines
analysis with synthesis, induction and deduction.
"The whole swindle of idealism is derived from an incorrect understanding of
the nature of abstraction. Lenin pointed out that the possibility of idealism is
inherent in any abstraction. The abstract concept of a thing is counterposed
artificially to the thing itself. It is supposed not only to have an existence
of its own, but is said to be superior to crude material reality. The concrete
is portrayed as somehow defective, imperfect and impure, as opposed to the Idea
which is perfect, absolute and pure. Thus reality is stood on its head.
"The ability to think in abstractions marks a colossal conquest of the human
intellect. Not only 'pure' science, but also engineering would be impossible
without abstract thought, which lifts us above the immediate, finite reality of
the concrete example, and gives thought a universal character. The unthinking
rejection of abstract thought and theory indicates the kind of narrow,
Philistine mentality, which imagines itself to be 'practical,' but, in reality,
is impotent. Ultimately, great advances in theory lead to great advances in
practice. Nevertheless, all ideas are derived one way or another from the
physical world, and, ultimately, must be applied back to it. The validity of any
theory must be demonstrated, sooner or later, in practice." [pp.88-89.
Bold emphases alone added; quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions
adopted at this site.]
As seems
plain
from the above, Woods and Grant have also adopted a naive version of the
Empiricist Theory Of Abstraction:
"Over millions of years, through trial and
error, our ancestors began to establish certain relations between things. They
began to make abstractions, that is, to generalise from experience and practice....
"When I
abstract from reality, I concentrate on some aspects of a given phenomenon, and
leave the others out of account....
"Through
the mental work of abstraction, we are able to get beyond the immediate
information provided by our senses (sense-perception), and probe deeper. We can break the object down into
its constituent parts, isolate them, and study them in detail. We can arrive at
an idealised, general conception of the object as a 'pure' form, stripped of all
secondary features. This is the work of abstraction, an absolutely necessary
stage of the process of cognition....
"The initial process thus goes from the concrete to the abstract. The object
is dismembered, analysed, in order to obtain a detailed knowledge of its parts...."
[ibid.]
Moreover, just like the Empiricists (and, indeed, like many Rationalists,
too), they imagine
this to be an individual, 'mental' or neurological(?) skill we are all supposed to
possess (naturally?):
"This fact is inseparably linked to the capacity for abstract thought, which
enables humans to go far beyond the immediate situation given to us by our
senses....
"When I
abstract from reality, I concentrate on some aspects of a given phenomenon, and
leave the others out of account.... Similarly, the brain early on learns to
ignore certain sounds and concentrate on others. If we were not able to do this,
the amount of information reaching our ears from all sides would overwhelm the
mind completely....
"Through
the mental work of abstraction, we are able to get beyond the immediate
information provided by our senses (sense-perception), and probe deeper.... This is the work of abstraction, an absolutely necessary
stage of the process of cognition....
"The initial process thus goes from the concrete to the abstract. The object
is dismembered, analysed, in order to obtain a detailed knowledge of its parts."
[Ibid.]
Just like the
other theorists considered
above, Woods and Grant nowhere try
to prove, or even superficially substantiate, anything they dogmatically assert or
conclude; they seem to think that what they have to
say is incontrovertible. Nor do they even so much as attempt to address the many
objections
raised in this Essay (or those advanced by earlier anti-abstractionists --
again, such
as Marx and Engels!). Indeed, their description of the alleged 'process
of abstraction' is sketchy in the extreme, to say the least. But, that is
just par for the course in this area of Traditional Myth-making.
Marcuse, no stranger to dogmatic assertion himself, presents the reader with yet more of
the same, in One Dimensional Man:
"Philosophy shares this abstractness with
all genuine thought,for nobody really thinks who does not abstract from
that which is given, who does not relate the facts to the factors which have
made them, who does not -- in his mind -- undo the facts. Abstractness
is the very life of thought, the token of its authenticity." [Marcuse
(1968), p.112. Bold emphases added.]
Surprising as this might seem to many who lionise the thoughts of
The Frankfurt School, it is plain from the
above that Marcuse is also a
Bourgeois Individualist, for he seems to think
we all abstract in our 'minds', making this an isolated, individualised skill.
Moreover, far
from it being "the very life of thought", we have seen that abstraction
works
more like a dose of
Cyanide.
And we are still waiting for the
original data sheets of the survey I am sure Marcuse conducted, or commissioned,
into the abstractive skills of everyone who has ever lived, or will ever live,
on this planet -- or, failing that, a representative sample of such --, that support
this rather bold assertion:
"for nobody really thinks who does not abstract from
that which is given...".
A few
years ago, I came across
a more sophisticated defence of certain aspects of Hegel's work relevant to the purposes
of this Essay: Dulckeit
(1989). As is the case with Lawler's attempted defence of Hegel that
we met earlier much of Dulckeit's apologetic revolves around Bertrand Russell's notorious
criticisms of Hegel's transformation of the "is" of predication into an "is" of
identity. In addition, Dulckeit also focuses on the weaknesses, or 'perceived'
weaknesses, in the Russell's
Logical Atomism and his
Theory of
Descriptions. [This links to a PDF, and unfortunately assumes the reader is
familiar with Modern Logic. A somewhat similar argument to Dulckeit's, but which
doesn't specifically target Russell, can be found in
Pippin (1978).]
Now,
I have no wish to defend either of Russell's theories, so I will
concentrate on Dulckeit's valiant attempt to make Hegel comprehensible. Having said
that, I can't find anywhere in her article where she distinguishes -- as Hegel attempted to do
--
between propositions and judgements (although she mentions both), and it isn't hard to
see why. As has been pointed out
elsewhere in this Essay,
Hegel made a complete mess of this distinction, appealing
to examples of propositions to make several 'logical' points about what he took
to be true only of judgements (and that includes running together asserted
propositions and asserted judgements). Unfortunately, this makes much of what Dulckeit
has to say somewhat irrelevant. In fact, Dulckeit runs these two terms together,
for example, here:
"In its most abstract terms a judgement,
according to Hegel, is expressible in the proposition 'The individual is
the universal' (a is F), or, more definitely, 'The subject is the
predicate' (s is P). There are two terms in a
judgement, then, and they are connected by the copula 'is'." [Dulckeit
(1989), p.112. Italic
emphases in the original, bold emphases added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions
adopted at this site.]
One
minute, we have a proposition, the next a judgement!
Putting this fatal flaw to one side, in the same passage, Dulckeit drops
a logical clanger:
"In its most abstract terms a
judgement, according to Hegel, is expressible in the proposition 'The individual
is the universal' (a is F), or, more definitely, 'The subject is
the predicate' (s is P)." [Ibid.]
This
might seem a minor issue, but "The individual is the universal" and "The subject
is the predicate" should be "The a is the F" and "The
s is the P" respectively,
and not "a is F" or "s is P",
as Dulckeit renders
both. This isn't a
trifling point since it illustrates yet again the sloppy approach to matters
logical adopted by fans of that mystical bumbler, Hegel. The logical form of
definite descriptions (such as "the a", "the s", "the F", or "the P") is radically different from
that of "a", "s", "F", and "P" -- i.e., subject terms and predicables,
respectively.
"As used in this work, the terms 'subject' and 'predicate' will always be
linguistic terms. I shall never call a man a logical subject, but only the name
of a man; the name 'Peter', not the Apostle, is the subject of 'Peter was an
Apostle'; and not the property of being an Apostle but its verbal expression is
a predicate. I shall say, however, that what the predicate in 'Peter was an
Apostle' is predicated of is Peter, not his name; for it is Peter, not his name,
that is being said to have been an Apostle. In saying that something is
predicated of Peter, I do not mean that this predicate is true of or applies to
Peter, but only that in some significant sentence, true or false, it is
predicated of Peter. I shall say that a predicate is attachedto a
subject, is predicated of what the subject stands for, and applies to
or is true of this if the statement so formed is true.
"The stipulations in the last paragraph are of course arbitrary; but it is
convenient to make some such stipulations and adhere to them. For lack of this,
logicians as distinguished as Aristotle and Russell have fallen into almost
inextricable confusions, so that you just cannot tell whether a predicate is
something within language or something represented by means of language." [Geach
(1968), pp.22-23 (this links in fact to the 3rd
(1980) edition and so has different page numbers:
pp.49-50. Italic emphases in the
original.]
As we
will see, Dulckeit also appears to be confused over
whether a predicate is "something within
language or something represented by means of language". In fact, it is
reasonably clear that
she has fallen into just such confusion since, like so many other Hegel-fans, she is
clearly intent to excuse this logical incompetent for these very muddles.
Putting this second opening 'false step' also to one side, Dulckeit continues:
"In its most abstract terms a judgement,
according to Hegel, is expressible in the proposition 'The individual is the
universal' (a is F), or, more definitely, 'The subject is the
predicate' (s is P). There are two terms in a
judgement, then, and they are connected by the copula 'is'. It follows that an
adequate theory of judgement must at least account for the nature of the
relationship between subject and predicate. The relation between s
and P is expressed by the copula. Just what does it mean to say 'the
subject "is" the predicate'? On the one hand the subject or individual seems
utterly different from, even opposed to, the predicate, yet on the other hand
the copula appears to assert precisely that they are one and the same. Says
Hegel:
'No doubt there is...a distinction
between terms like individual and universal, subject and predicate: but it
is none the less the universal fact, that every judgement states them to be
identical....' [Dulckeit is here quoting
Hegel (1975), p.231,
§166.
I have corrected her quotation to conform with the published, 3rd
edition. I have also reproduced this passage in full
below.
Italic emphases here are Dulckeit's, not Hegel's -- RL.]
"The suggestion seems to be
that, somehow, s and P are both (1) distinct from each
other, and also (2) identical. Formally, that is, the judgement
announces the identity of s and P, but since in fact P does
not exhaust s, there is a tension between what the form of the judgement
posits and what the content delivers. In fact, (1) and (2) appear to be mutually
exclusive alternatives. In Hegel's words:
'What the judgment enunciates
to start with is that the subject is the predicate; but since the
predicate is supposed not to be what the subject is, we are faced with a
contradiction which must resolve itself...'. [Dulckeit is here
quoting
Hegel (1999), p.630, §1358.
I have used the on-line version (and have corrected a minor typo when the latter
is compared with the published text).
I have reproduced this passage in full
in
Appendix A
-- RL.]
"Let us use an example. In
the judgement 'The rose is red,' subject and predicate appear to be entirely
independent from one another. For the subject as an object exists whether or not
it possesses this particular predicate, and the universal determination exists in
other subjects even if it does not belong to this one." [Dulckeit (1989),
pp.112-13. Most of the
italic
emphases are in the original; quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions
adopted at this site. Some paragraphs merged.]
First of all, as noted above,
Hegel and Dulckeit run
together talk about talk (i.e., language about language) with talk about 'the world',
confusing the subject of a sentence with (in this case) the individual concerned, just as
the latter also seems to think predicates aren't what is said
about that individual (or whatever), but what a predicate expression
supposedly stands
for -- it is"the universal determination [that] exists in other
subjects". So, "red" (to use for the moment the traditional way of alluding to
predicables) presumably is this "universal determination [that] exists in other
subjects" and stands for "redness", one presumes. We also see
this in the next few words of the same article:
"From this subjective vantage point, says
Hegel, the act of judging merely involves the reflection of whether a given
predicate located 'in someone's head' ought to be attached to an object existing
'outside' that person, an object which is what it is, regardless of whether or
not the judgement is made. The independence of the two extremes suggest that
s and P are distinct and opposed to each other, and consequently, are
related merely externally." [Ibid.,
p.113.
Italic
emphases in the original; quotation marks altered to conform with the
conventions adopted at this site.]
Here, it is clear that a predicate isn't just
a linguistic expression, it is also something that exists somewhere --
"in the head", or in the "outside" world --, and hence that predicate
expressions must refer to such things.
Admittedly, Dulckeit criticises this view on
Hegel's behalf (in that it implies an 'external relation' between subject and
predicate), but it is also clear that without the above characterisation,
Hegel and Dulckeit would have nothing to criticise. Their
mischaracterisation of predicate expressions (as referring terms) is the
point of departure for these dialectical fairy tales. If predicate expressions
aren't what these two say they are, then Hegel's fantasies can gain no grip --
so it is important for these two to so mischaracterise them.
It is worth examining this point a little
further, since it is abundantly clear that Dulckeit does do this --, for
example, when she says things like the following:
"On the one hand the
subject or individual seems utterly different from, even opposed to, the
predicate...." [Ibid.]
"In the judgement 'The rose
is red,' subject and predicate appear to be entirely independent from one
another. For the subject as an object exists whether or not it possesses this
particular predicate, and the universal determination exists in other
subjects even if it does not belong to this one." [Ibid. Bold
italicised emphases alone added;
quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]
The emphasised words clearly indicate
that Dulckeit has confused what we might say about someone or something with
what or whom we are talking about -- as well as conflating their names with the individuals (or the
objects) concerned --, saying "the subject as an object exists whether or not
it possesses this particular predicate" --, which indicates that, for her,
subject and predicate aren't always linguistic expressions.
Subjects don't "possess"
predicates any more than cats possess adverbs, or cell phones prepositions. So, if the subject of
a sentence is crossed out -- in, say, "Donald Trump is a
racist" -- that doesn't mean that the individual, Donald Trump, has been crossed
out, which it would do if the subject of a sentence were the individual
concerned, not an expression employed in order to refer to him or her. One might
wish
that bigots and racists were quite so easily disposed of, so that striking their names out would
automatically consign them to the dustbin of history, but, as the saying goes,
"If wishes were horses, beggars would ride". Other than in magic, what we do
with subject terms no more affects the
individual to whom that term refers than sticking pins in a doll harms whoever that doll is
supposed to represent. Running the two together is, plainly, what magical thinking is
based upon. So, the subject of a sentence isn't an "object"; it is a
linguistic expression.
It might be countered that all linguistic
expression are objects of one sort or another; but, in that case, if the word
"subject" is also an "object" -- indicated when Dulckeit says "For the subject as an object exists whether or not it
possesses this
particular predicate" (bold added) -- she is asserting of the word "subject" (not what it supposedly designates,
but the word itself) that it possesses a predicate. Are we really supposed to
believe that the word "subject" possesses the predicate "red" (to use for the moment
(again) the
traditional way of alluding to predicables), so that we could truthfully assert
"'Subject' is red"? That is, that the word "subject" is coloured red?
It could further be objected that it is perfectly
normal to speak about, say, Socrates (the man) being the subject spoken about in
or by sentences such as "Socrates is mortal", as well as being the subject of the
sentence itself.
Indeed, and it is this equivocation that is part of the problem,
as Geach pointed out earlier:
"As used in this work, the terms 'subject' and 'predicate' will always be
linguistic terms. I shall never call a man a logical subject, but only the name
of a man; the name 'Peter', not the Apostle, is the subject of 'Peter was an
Apostle'; and not the property of being an Apostle but its verbal expression is
a predicate. I shall say, however, that what the predicate in 'Peter was an
Apostle' is predicated of is Peter, not his name; for it is Peter, not his name,
that is being said to have been an Apostle.... For lack of this, logicians as
distinguished as Aristotle and Russell have fallen into almost inextricable
confusions, so that you just cannot tell whether a predicate is something within
language or something represented by means of language." [Geach
(1968), pp.22-23. Paragraphs merged.]
One minute, dialecticians like
Dulckeit are talking
about logical or grammatical parts of sentences, the next about
whatever they are supposed to designate 'in the world', failing to distinguish
between the two even while sliding effortlessly from one to the other, as if each
such move creates no
logical problems of its own. As noted above, they "run together talk about talk with talk about 'the world'".
This is, of course, precisely
where, in Ancient Greece, Traditional Theorists began to go wrong, as we have seen
throughout this Essay.
The only defence advanced in favour of this
slide that I can find in Dulckeit's article is the following:
"With respect to the
formulations of a judgement just given, please keep in mind that, from a
Hegelian point of view, it is not only unnecessary, but impossible to
distinguish strictly between these metaphysical and linguistic notions because
they are, for Hegel, two expressions for the same relation." [Ibid., p.127.]
In other words, if we blindly follow Hegel
into this fog of mysticism, we will see 'the truth' for ourselves and it will
make us free -- free from the constraints the social nature of communication and language place
on all who use it. Dulckeit
offers her readers no other reason why we should allow Hegel (or her) to get
away with such linguistic licence. Neither does Hegel! But much of
his (and her) argument depends on this slide.
[To be sure, Dulckeit is trying to interpret
Hegel, but there is nothing in her article to suggest she disagrees with him
about any of this; quite the reverse in fact (no pun intended). Presently, we
will see that Dulckeit (and Hegel, if she has interpreted him aright -- but, who can say?) becomes even more
confused, and that is partly a result of this initial muddle.]
Second, Dulckeit simply takes Hegel at his
word when he blithely assumes what is to be proved: that when we predicate something of an
individual by attaching a predicate expression to a subject term, this is true:
"the
copula appears to assert precisely that they are one and the same."
[Ibid.]
So, Dulckeit simply asserts that the copula appears
to be, or to do, whatever Hegel says it appears to be, or to do -- albeit with a cursory attempt
to justify these moves a page or so later. [Her apologia will be examined presently.]
This is quite apart from the fact that a copula can't assert anything, and so
can't even "appear" to do it, either. Human beings assert things, and they do so
using indicative sentences. At a pinch, we can assert things of an
individual by attaching a predicate expression to a subject term.
A few lines later we are met with this prize
example of dialectical confusion (also examined above):
"From this subjective vantage
point, says Hegel, the act of judging merely involves the reflection of whether
a given predicate located 'in someone's head' ought to be attached to an object
existing 'outside' that person, an object which is what it is, regardless of
whether or not the judgement is made. The independence of the two extremes
suggest (sic) that s and P are distinct and opposed to each other, and
consequently, are related to each other externally.... Just as from a
grammatical point of view, the copula is a device by which two separate words
are connected. Insofar as the copula asserts the nature of their relation,
therefore, it at once expresses their differences." [Ibid., p.113. Italic
emphases in the original.]
We saw
earlier that the traditional analysis of
predicate expressions encouraged theorists to conceive of them as objects, or
even as 'mental' entities of some sort (alternatively as expressions, or as
singular terms, referring to one or both
-- this is just another consequence of the syntactic slide mentioned above), at the same
time as regarding them as designating universals that exist
independently of us, 'somewhere'/'who-knows-where'(?). And we can surely see the
result of this slide for ourselves in the above passage. Hegel
stumbled into this bear trap like a falling down drunk, and Dulckeit seems happy not only to highlight
this logical blunder, but follow him into its jaws. So, on this view, predicates aren't simply linguistic
expressions, they
are somehow 'mental entities', as well as 'objects' exiting somewhere in 'extra-mental'
reality. [Or, it is what such terms supposedly designate that so exist?] Curious readers will look long and hard
for any justification for these flights-of-fancy (that is,
"justification" over and above the fact that it is
traditional to conceive of predicates this way, but only when they have been subjected to the syntactic segue
analysed more fully
elsewhere in this Essay.
They will also wonder how a
minor feature of a sub-branch of the Indo-European family of languages
(namely, the subject-predicate form that takes the copula "is")
single-handedly manages to achieve all three things at once.
But, here we see these errors compounded, for
it is now plain that not only are predicates not linguistic
expressions (or they are and they aren't!), they enjoy a life of their own
milling about in someone's head, helpfully identified or us by Hegel without the
benefit of a single brain probe or
CT scan, while whatever they "attach" to (is
this "the subject"?) floats about outside that head in glorious freedom.
Language and what language allegedly represents are run together shamelessly
here -- indeed, as
predicted.
Dulckeit also uncritically accepts what I
have elsewhere called the
SGP (i.e., 'Spinoza's Greedy Principle') -- "Every determination is
also a
negation" --, referring to it several times (but, without once even
so much as attempting to justify it, an intellectually cavalier and negligent
approachto logic she clearly
inherited from Spinoza and Hegel) -- for example, here:
"In his [Hegel's] analysis of
sense-certainty in the
Phenomenology, he had already established that
saying what a thing is must also involve saying what this particular thing is
not." [Ibid., p.114. Italic emphases in the original.]
I outlined the fatal defects of this
intellectual virus -- the
SGP -- earlier
in this Essay.
Readers are directed there for more details. I have also analysed it more fully from a
different angle,
below.
[However, readers will also search long
and hard in the Phenomenology for anything resembling a proof of what
Dulckeit alleges, or
anywhere where it is "established that saying what a thing is must also involve
saying what this particular thing is
not". What they will find in its place is page after page of
incomprehensible gobbledygook. Of course, readers are invited to check this for
themselves and not just take my word for it. If anyone thinks Hegel's words
aren't gobbledygook, please
contact me with a clear translation into
ordinary English.]
However, it is worth pointing out
that without the SGP, the entire edifice of Hegelian 'dialectics' collapses
faster than a cheap deckchair.
In which case, it is more than a little puzzling that this principle has never been defended -- or,
rather, it has never been seriously defended -- by those whose brains have been
compromised by this mystical twaddle. Rather like the countless
gnomic
pronouncements that litter Traditional Thought, the SGP is perhaps
to be viewed as 'self-evident'.
Well that
settles things and no mistake...
Dulckeit now aggravates these self-inflicted
wounds by once again taking Hegel at his word:
"Suppose that (1)
is correct and the individual is in fact distinct from the universal, and hence
s from P. On this assumption, any attempt to say what a
thing is appears to lead us directly into the following contradiction: While we
may correctly assert that with respect to the rose that 'The individual is the
universal', or 's is P,' we would be just as correct in asserting, on the basis
of (1), that 'The individual is not the universal' or 's is not
P'. According to our previous example, we would then get (a) 'The rose is
red' and (b) 'The rose is not red', since other things are red and are not this
rose.... [U]nless it is the case that both (a) and (b) are correct, nothing
informative could ever be said about what a thing is, such that alternative
(2) would always yield some empty version of
's is s' or (c) 'The rose is a rose.'... Apparently, then, Hegel can avoid the
empty (c) only by embracing the seemingly contradictory (a) and (b)." [Ibid.,
p.114. Italic emphases in the original. Quotations marks altered to
conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]
It is here that we see the syntactic and
semantic sins of yesteryear (which Hegel uncritically appropriated from the
Ancient Greeks, Medieval and Renaissance Logicians) deliver their inevitable payload: total
confusion.
[Apologies for that mixed metaphor!]
Again, we have already noted that Traditional
Theorists chose to reconfigure predicate expressions as the logical equivalent
of singular terms -- the Proper Names of
Abstract Particulars -- and
here we witness Dulckeit inadvertently exposing Hegel's false steps in all
their glory in that respect. This is perhaps most clearly seen as part of his (and her)
translation of "The rose is red" into the schema "The subject/individual is the
universal", but earlier as "The
subject is the predicate", where what used to be a predicate
expression, "...is red" (or, more traditionally just "red"), has now become
a singular term, "the predicate". Now, it might make some sort of crazy,
half-baked, Idealist sense to suppose there could be a relation of sorts between
"red", so doctored, and "The rose", so processed --, that is, between "The predicate" and
"The subject", but only if they have been surgically 'enhanced' in this way
-- and, in a manner that destroys the judgement itself, turning it into a list!
But, that is just about all that can be said on its behalf.
Hegel's diabolical 'logic' now stalls on the starting
grid as a result of the above linguistic
legerdemain, since there can be no identity between the linguistic
expressions, "The rose", and, "...is red", nor yet between what they supposedly
refer to. That is because "...is red" isn't a referring expression, to begin with.
In that case, there can be no such identity if predicates don't designate anything
that could be put into any sort of relation with anything else, let alone form
part of an identity relation; indeed, they don't designate, period. If
predicates were referring expressions, "The rose is red"
would
become a list (i.e, "The rose/identity/red") --, and, as we saw earlier, lists say nothing.
Much also appears to revolve around the
rather odd and seemingly irrelevant claim that "somehow, s and P
are both distinct from each other", the 'justification' for which appears to be
the following:
"While we may correctly
assert that with respect to the rose that 'The individual is the universal', or
's is P,' we would be just as correct in asserting, on the basis of (1), that
'The individual is not the universal' or 's is not P'.
According to our previous example, we would then get (a) 'The rose is red' and
(b) 'The rose is not red', since other things are red and are not this rose...."
[Ibid.]
The 'justification' for concluding that "The
rose is red" and "The rose is not red" -- i.e., that "other things are red and
are not this rose" -- looks like a
non
sequitur of historic proportions.
But, don't be fooled, it is a non
sequitur of historic proportions!
Exactly how does the fact that roses
aren't the only red flowers (or even the only red objects, simpliciter) imply that "The rose is not
red"? Dulckeit doesn't say, and as far as can be determined, neither does Hegel.
If you had a red rose in your hands and someone were to assert that that flower
wasn't in fact red because post boxes or Manchester United football (soccer)
shirts are also red, I think you'd be right to question their sanity. One
thing you wouldn't do is conclude that that individual was a "genius" and
had somehow unearthed the deepest secrets of "Being" as a result of
the observation that there are other red objects. To be sure, had the original proposition been "Only the rose is red" -- or even "The
rose is exclusively red" -- there might have been some mystical mileage, here;
but it wasn't, so there isn't.
It could be objected that Dulckeit's point is
that there is no internal connection between a rose and its colour, which
can be seen by the fact that roses can be other colours, and there are many
other objects that are red. As she noted, this connection is external.
Quite apart from the additional fact that these traditional terms-of-art (i.e.,
"external" and "internal") are themselves as clear as mud, this objection trades
on the even more obscure idea that there are such things as 'essences'. So, this
response relies on the claim that the colour of a rose isn't part of that
plant's 'essence', whereas the fact that the rose is a plant is part of
its 'essence'.
And yet, there are plants that aren't roses,
just as there are objects that aren't red. If that is enough to deny that
being red is part of the 'essence' of a rose, then the fact that there are other
plants which aren't roses should be enough to deny that being a plant is part of
the 'essence' of a rose, too. Of course, if there are no 'essences' to begin
with (or if it makes no sense to assert that there are any -- as will be
demonstrated in Essay Thirteen Part Two), then this whole line of argument goes
out of the window. [Until that is published, readers are directed to my remarks
on this topic in Essay Eight Part Two,
here. I also return to this topic
below.]
The only other possible justification for
concluding that there is a
difference
between subject terms and predicate expressions (or what they supposedly
designate) is that a proposition like "The rose is red" supposedly suggests to us an identity
between subject and predicate, which -- so the argument goes -- plainly isn't the case
(as Hegel himself acknowledged, even if only temporarily). Hence, the conclusion
is that they are
obviously different. As we will see, this
small and seemingly innocent step catapults us right into the middle of
this Hegelian Madhouse, for these considerations re-introduce the SGP --
since, as we will also see, this somehow means that 'identity implies difference' (or
it implies 'non-identity'') -- 'every determination is also a negation', or so we have been assured.
We will return to cut a path through this
logical thicket
below, but Dulckeit's
(and Hegel's) claim that sentences like "The rose is a rose" are 'uninformative
and empty tautologies' is no less misguided. First of all, it is doubtful
whether such sentences are tautologies to begin with; since I have
covered that point
elsewhere, the reader is directed there for more details. Secondly, we have
already seen that not only are such
sentences not 'empty', they can be informative, too.
In the next section of her article, Dulckeit
attempts to justify the above moves with a series of replies addressed to
several hypothetical critics of this way of re-casting the copula "is" as one of
identity. It is to this section that I now turn.
"[It] must be remembered that
[Hegel's] analysis of the forms of judgment in the Logic is motivated by
his interest in essential judgement. There are two conditions for such
judgements. To begin with, a judgement is an essential judgement only if P
tells us precisely and exclusively what s is; no less and no more. But
merely predicating universals of particulars is insufficient for this, unless
the term in the predicate position at once expresses the essential nature of the
subject. This, in turn, argues Hegel, is possible only if the 'is' expresses
some identity between s and P. For if essential determination were possible
exclusively via predication, the subject and the predicate would remain separate
and the relation between them expressed by the copula would remain external.
As a consequence, s would refer to one thing, namely an individual, while
P would designate something distinct from s, namely a universal.
But the truth of
sense-certainty in the
Phenomenology has already been shown that qua individual,
an
individual is grasped only through the mediation of universals. It follows
that divorced from these, it would then have to be an individual without a
universal nature, i.e., a bare individual.... Thus, if s and P are
utterly distinct they must be mutually exclusive, which means that s will
necessarily be bare, and P necessarily abstract.... Clearly then, where
judgements of essence are concerned, the 'is' of predication will not do because
it entails the distinction between s and P which would commit us
to a metaphysical thesis already overcome in the Phenomenology."
[Ibid., pp.115-16.
Italic emphases in the original. Quotation marks altered to conform with the
conventions adopted at this site. Links added.]
So,
from the above, a 'judgement' is
'essential' on two conditions: (a) "Only if P tells us precisely and
exclusively what s is; no less and no more", and (b) A predicate
expression must express "the essential nature of the subject", and that is
possible only if the copula is an "is" of identity.
When these are coupled with what we have
already learnt about Hegel's 'logic' from Dulckeit in the previous paragraphs,
we can see that this argument is clearly circular: a 'judgement' is 'essential' only if it
expresses the 'essential nature' of the subject, and it can only do that if the
copula "is" is one of identity. But -- and here we loop the first loop -- it is one
identity only if it captures that 'essence'! But, and again, what if there are no
'essences'? Hegel just assumes there are with no attempt to justify that
crucial move, content merely to import the idea from the Ancient Greeks (along
with the term, "universal", and a host of other obscure, jargonised expressions).
Plainly, if there
are no 'essences' there can be no 'essential judgements', either.
So, the argument appears to be: (i) There are only 'essential judgements'
if the copula is one of identity and it captures that 'essence', (ii) 'Essences' are expressed by 'essential judgements', (iii) There are
'essential judgements' only if the copula is one of identity, (iv) The copula
captures that 'essence', and (v) 'Essences' are expressed by
'essential judgements'..., and so on...
But, what is so 'essential' about the alleged
'judgement "The rose is red"? This most certainly doesn't tell us "precisely and
exclusively" what a rose is. Or, rather, it doesn't do so unless we impose on that
sentence the idea that the "is" here is one of identity -- which,
plainly, would make the
rose one with redness (such that nothing else could be red!), and that in turn would tell us, one supposes,
"precisely and exclusively" what a rose is. This means, once more, that only if
we accept everything Hegel says as Gospel Truth, only if we accept the
doctrine that
there are such things as 'essential judgements', and that the copula in
these 'essential judgements' is one of identity, will we be able to conclude
that are there 'essential judgements' captured by identity in the first place!
Welcome to the
Hegelian merry-go-round! Strap yourself in...
Nevertheless, according to Dulckeit, Hegel
has an argument of sorts in support of all this 'circular logic':
"[I]f essential determination
were possible exclusively via predication, the subject and the predicate would
remain separate and the relation between them expressed by the copula would
remain external. As a consequence, s would refer to one thing,
namely an individual, while P would designate something distinct from
s, namely a universal." [Ibid.]
In other words, ordinary predication can't
capture the 'internal' nature of 'essential judgements'! Again, we are being
asked to accept the supposed conclusion here solely on Hegel's say-so, which conclusion
is then re-used as a key component in its own proof!
So many circles!
The reader should be dizzy by now!
The
background argument appears to be
something like this: an 'external' link between a predicate and a subject would
imply that they can be separated (at least in thought), and if that were
generally so we would be faced with a "bare individual" and an "abstract
predicate":
"It follows that divorced from these, it
would then have to be an individual without a universal nature, i.e., a bare
individual.... Thus, if s and P are
utterly distinct they must be mutually exclusive, which means that s will
necessarily be bare, and P necessarily abstract...." [Ibid.]
We can perhaps now see from where the muddle has
arisen for we are told that predicates "designate...a universal", that
is, that predicates are the Proper Names of abstract particulars, and such particulars can enter
relations with whatever it is that a subject term designates --, for example, the
relations of identity and/or difference. However, only if predicates are
transmogrified in this way will this Hegelian dog run. If predicates do not do
this, if they don't function like Proper Names, then the idea that they can be
so characterised can't arise. And if that is so, the belief that
this has anything to do with 'external' links between subject and predicate
gains no purchase.
It might be objected that we can surely
question whether a given rose is red, or any other colour. Indeed, but that
would typically be achieved by asserting "The rose isn't red", or perhaps
even, "The
rose is blue/pink/white...". No one is going to assert "The rose has no colour
at all", which, if it were to be asserted, would be the consequence of
accepting the odd idea that predicates can be separated from subjects.
That in turn would imply -- so we have been told -- there are, or can be, "bare
individuals". But that isn't what we would conclude about "The rose isn't red";
we would infer it was another colour not that it was colourless, nor yet
that it was a "bare individual" (devoid of any properties!). Of course,
philosophers entertain such weird ideas (that a given property is separable from
any subject concerned, and hence all properties are separable, yielding a
"bare individual"). However, to counter such flights-of-fancy by an appeal to
Hegel's 'logic' isn't like using a sledgehammer to crack a nut, it is more like
using a nut to crack a sledgehammer. The sledgehammer here is how we use
ordinary language and what that will do to such 'off-the-wall' theories,
especially when we
take Marx's
advice --, and the nut is Hegel.
So, yes, we can certainly imagine a rose with
a different colour, but not one with no colour. Ordinary language
prevents us from making sense of any suggestion to the contrary.
What about this, though?
"But the truth of
sense-certainty in the
Phenomenology has already been shown that qua individual, an
individual is grasped only through the mediation of universals. It follows that
divorced from these, it would then have to be an individual without a universal
nature, i.e., a bare individual.... Thus, if s and P are utterly
distinct they must be mutually exclusive, which means that s will
necessarily be
bare, and P necessarily abstract....
Clearly then, where judgements of essence are concerned, the 'is' of predication
will not do because it entails the distinction between s and P
which would commit us to a metaphysical thesis already overcome in the
Phenomenology." [Ibid.]
For the hundredth time, we have already seen that while Hegelians might
insist that "an individual is grasped only through the mediation of
universals", what actually happens is that their theory transforms
these 'universals' into the Proper Names of Abstract Particulars.
All that this leaves Hegel-fans with are 'individuals' and 'abstract particulars',
thrown together in a list, destroying
their capacity to say anything at all!
Dulckeit now returns to an earlier point,
hoping to drive it home this time:
"[A]ccording to Hegel, an
essential judgement must also be informative. The 'is' of identity as
Russell conceives it, however, would result in a mere tautology, since the
identity it would express between the two terms of the judgement would be a
merely abstract or formal identity. Hegel's whole point, then, is to show that
neither the 'is' of predication nor the 'is' of identity are capable on their
own to yield [sic] an informative judgement about what something is
essentially. Again Hegel's own example serves to illustrate this nicely: 'The
rose is red' may be informative, but fails to tell us about what it is
that is red. And, according to Hegel's view, s must already be a
particular before we can predicate of it a property, such as 'red'. And while
'The rose is a rose' exhibits the form of an identity statement, it
hardly provides information about the essential character or nature of whatever
is asserted to be identical with itself. Unless we want to deny that judgements
about essences (which must express identity) can also be informative, argues
Hegel, what we need is neither the 'is' of predication nor the 'is' of identity,
but a dialectical unity of the two which we might call the 'is' of
'identity-in-difference.' According to Hegel, Russell's example for [sic] the
'is' of identity is really an example for [sic] the notion of
identity-in-difference as Hegel conceives of it, although it does not yet
constitute a perfect instance of it. The same applies to Hegel's own example. In
the judgement 'The rose is red,' the difference between s and P is
still very great and the 'is' only minimally mediates between the two
terms. Because they depend in part on the content, the degrees of mediation
cannot be spelled out explicitly. But in Hegel's view, judgements progress from
this still largely 'immediate' or 'qualitative' judgement in which the 'is'
closely parallels Russell's 'is' of predication, through a long series of
progressively more adequate judgements in which s and P become
increasingly more congruous until they are finally 'identical.' But even here,
the identity retains an inner distinction and, consequently, is unlike Russell's
own conception of formal identity (i.e., identity which does not consider
content). It is clear, then, that for Hegel any absolute distinction between the
'is' of predication and identity ultimately vanishes. But surely, this is
not to say that Hegel cannot tell the difference between them where it does
exist, particularly since his entire treatment of judgement clearly consists of
a careful working out of this very difference, culminating in
'identity-in-difference.' Since difference is preserved in even the most perfect
case of identity, Hegel can hardly be accused of denying the distinction
between s and P. Quite clearly, he insists on it. Insofar,
however, as the distinction is internal, what is distinguished at once
remains a unity or 'identity.' Or, to put it even more strongly, the identity
is an identity only by virtue of the (internal) distinction. Surely,
discovering the inadequacy of two philosophical notions in isolation (i.e., in
abstraction) is not the same as overlooking their difference." [Ibid.,
pp.116-17. Italic emphases in the original; quotation marks altered to
conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]
Much of the above depends on the reader
already accepting (or, rather, swallowing) the probative nature of the
circular argument exposed earlier. Dulckeit never questions whether there are
such things as 'essential judgements', but takes it as read that there are.
However, if there aren't any, then much of the above is just philosophical hot
air. Her caveat "Unless we want to deny that judgements about essences (which
must express identity) can also be informative..." half acknowledges this. What
she should have said is: "Unless we want to deny there are any judgements
about essences...", which the reader will surely have a mind to do unless and until either she
or Hegel provides a cogent argument in support of the ancient dogma that these mythical beasts of yore
actually exist.
The following, then, appears to be (at least
part of) the central core of her argument:
"Again Hegel's own example
serves to illustrate this nicely: 'The rose is red' may be informative,
but fails to tell us about what it is that is red. And, according to
Hegel's view, s must already be a particular before we can predicate of
it a property, such as 'red'. And while 'The rose is a rose' exhibits the form
of an identity statement, it hardly provides information about the
essential character or nature of whatever is asserted to be identical with
itself." [Ibid.]
In fact, "The rose is red" does tell us what
it is that is "red" -- namely the rose! It may omit all mention of 'particularity'
(and even 'essence'),
but that itself is an a priori requirement Dulckeit has cavalierly
imposed on this innocent looking sentence for no good reason. Moreover, if the following were the case: "s must
already be a particular before we can predicate of it a property, such as
'red'" (emphasis added), we must surely have before us a bare particular, something
we were told Hegel had banished from
His
Ideal Kingdom for all eternity.
Have they been 'dialectically' smuggled
back in through a side door?
It could be argued that for Hegel individuals
become particulars when they are conceived of as individuals of a certain
sort -- that is,
"an
individual is grasped only through the mediation of universals." In that
case, even for Hegel, there can be no such thing as particulars
before we have predicated of them anything (an idea already prominent in
Kant, and, in embryo form in Plato and Aristotle). To be a particular is
eo ipso to be a particular of a certain
sort, otherwise it can't even be a particular.
That being so, the
validity of the spurious terms, 'difference' and 'identity-in-difference'
evaporates about as fast as a drop of ether on a hot plate -- since, even for
Hegel, there can be no dichotomy between a particular and its alleged
'essential properties'. This
means that all talk about 'mediation' and 'progression' -- indeed, the rest of
the above quotation -- turns out to be yet more wasted ink and effort.
Dulckeit next tackles a question that has
been rumbling away in the background all along: Why should all (or any) judgements have to be
'essential'? After pointing out that Hegel doesn't deny that predication is
important in ordinary language, and that he doesn't demand that all judgements be
'essential', Dulckeit adds:
"[Hegel] is simply pointing
out that if one wants to know the essential nature or identity of the subject,
qualitative judgements will not suffice, since even the longest list of
properties will not enlighten us in that regard unless the term in the
predicated place expresses the essential character of the subject. And this, he
argues, is possible only if s and P are identical in their
difference." [Ibid., pp.117-18. Italic emphases in the original.]
But, this just prompts us into asking once
again the nagging
question: what evidence is there that there are any
such 'essences' for 'judgements' to beabout to begin with -- that is, over and above the
fact that it is traditional to suppose there are any?
So, this is just more wasted
effort to add to the last batch.
Some might argue that in sentences like "John
is a man", John can't fail to be man, since he is an individual of that type.
It is essential to John that he is a man; change that and John would cease to
be John. Hence, this is an essential property.
Or so a counter-claim might go...
But, is this merely a verbal 'necessity'? Are
these 'essences' simply an artefact of the way we use language? Or are they
something more? Since I have covered this topic in Essay Eight Part Two (here),
readers are once again directed there for more details.
However, in her next comment, Dulckeit at
last homes in on the heart of the 'problem'; after pointing out that some might
conclude that after all is said and done Russell and Hegel aren't really all that far apart, she argues:
"To think this way, however,
would be seriously to misunderstand Hegel's central point. For identifying a
thing's essence necessarily involves difference. Without difference there
would only be one term, and the assertion of identity would be impossible. This
means that Russell could never get an 'is' of identity from which to distinguish
that of predication in the first place, unless he admits their interdependence.
But this is just what he wants to deny when he asserts their radical
difference." [Ibid., p.118. Italic emphasis in the original; quotation
marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]
Would it be out of place, if not
somewhat impertinent, to ask at this point: If Hegel and Dulckeit are right that in the end
(after they have been 'dialectically processed') these two forms of "is" are in
fact identical, they
must also be radically different? After all, as Dulckeit notes, identity
implies difference. Hence, if these two forms of "is" are identical they must also be radically
different, surely? Of course, this isn't my view, but that awkward realisation
now undermines Dulckeit's criticism of Russell; for on the basis of her argument,
Russell was right to underline their radical difference!
To be sure, the 'dialectical' reply to this annoying quibble is that according to Hegel we must accept both;
that these two versions of "is" are identical and radically different. In this
way, Hegel can 'have his cake and eat it', having found an easy way with any objection
-- absorbing one and all into the
body of confusion that is 'the dialectic', along with its opposite! Is
there any arguing with such scorched-earth 'logic'?
But, and once again, dialectical chicanery
like this only works if we accept the idea that Hegel's jargon makes any sense
-- along with the
yet-to-be-established existence of all these 'essences', as well as Hegel's lame-brained
criticism of the LOI. [I have dealt with Hegel and the LOI in Essay Eight Part
Three,
here.]
This is quite apart from the fact that
we have already seen that the alleged
difference between subject terms and predicates is logically irrelevant.
[LOI = Law of Identity.]
Dulckeit now
resurrects
the
SGP
-- a 'principle' that provides Hegel with his only substantive support
(or so it might seem):
"From this it also follows
that Russell is mistaken when he thinks that 'Socrates is the philosopher who
drank the hemlock' is an example of an identity statement which excludes all
difference. In sense-certainty, Hegel had shown that saying what something is is
possible only by saying what it is not. His point he takes to have been
established both in the Phenomenology and in the Logic where he
criticises the law of identity. Now he merely applies this insight to his
analysis of judgements. The inadequacy of the 'is' of identity by itself
stems precisely from its exclusion of difference. If all difference is
eliminated the judgement will no longer be informative but tautologious, for it
is the 'identity-in-difference' alone which allows identity judgements to be
informative. Russell's own example of an identity statement, however, is clearly
an informative judgement. Consequently, it is actually an instance of Hegel's
'identity-in-difference'." [Ibid., p.118. Italic emphases in the original; quotation
marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]
Hegelians are fond of saying things like
this, but when it comes to proof they all appear to have been struck dumb. They never
even attempt to spell-out the details underpinning this dogma, content
merely to parrot it uncritically -- which, when, you think about it, is
consistent with their serially sloppy approach to logic in general (Dulckeit included). This is doublypuzzling when we
consider the additional fact that they never tire of
telling us that DL is vastly superior to FL!
[DL = Dialectical Logic;
FL = Formal Logic.]
When it comes to making stuff up,
and muddling things,
maybe it is!
Ok, so let us try to
fill in the details these Dialectical Dupes conveniently omit. Consider a
very simple identity statement/proposition:
D1: A(1) is P(1).
D1a: A(1) is identical
to P(1).
[Where "A(1)" goes proxy for a
Proper Name or some other singular term. Here, and in what follows, "P(k)"
goes proxy for any predicable (expressing the 'essence' of
whatever it expresses, or doesn't express). The significance of the numbers will
soon become apparent.]
But, according to 'sense-certainty' and
the
SGP, D1a must be modified -- since
we are told that "Hegel had shown that saying what something is is possible
only by saying what it is not...", perhaps along the following lines:
D2: A(1) is identical to P(1)
and A(1) isn't B(1), B(2), B(3),..., B(n).
[Where "B(k)" stands for a Proper
Name, some other
singular term or predicate expression (we can afford to be indiscriminate and profligate here,
since,
as we have seen, Hegelians are already World
Champions in this Event), and n is indefinitely large -- and which will remain so until
Hegelians tell us just
how big their
"Totality" is. No sign of them doing that any day soon,
either!]
But, we don't yet know what B(1) is. So, if
we want to know what B(1) is we can "only" do so by "saying what it is
and is not". In
that case, we must now modify/'develop' D2:
D3: B(1) is identical to P(2) and
B(1) isn't C(1), C(2), C(3),..., C(n).
[Where, once more, "C(k)" stands for a Proper Name, some other
singular term or predicate expression, and n is indefinitely large.
(There will also have to be D3-type sentences for each of B(2), B(3),...,
B(n). Readers so minded can while away the hours working out the
details for each
remaining B(k). However, in order to save on repetition, and needless
complexity, I will omit this specific detail for subsequent letters.)]
But, we don't yet know what C(1) is. So, if
we want to know what C(1) is we can "only" do so by "saying what it is
and is not". In
that case, we must now modify/'develop' D3, as follows:
D4: C(1) is identical to P(3) and
C(1) isn't E(1), E(2), E(3),..., E(n).
[Where, once again, "E(k)" stands for a Proper Name, some other
singular term or predicate expression, and n is indefinitely large. (I
haven't used "D(1)" etc., here, to prevent confusion with lines D1
onwards.)]
But, we don't yet know what E(1) is. So, if
we want to know what E(1) is we can "only" do so by "saying what it is
and is not". In
that case, we must now modify/'develop' D4:
D5: E(1) is identical to P(4) and
E(1) isn't F(1), F(2), F(3),..., F(n).
[Where, as before, "F(k)" stands for a Proper Name, some other
singular term or predicate expression, and n is indefinitely large.]
It takes very little non-dialectical logic
(or even a tiny smattering of common sense)
to see that with this off-the-wall approach to 'logic' we wouldn't know
anything at all. Nothing would be 'informative'.
And yet, this is all so unnecessary. If we
interpret the LOI, not as a comic truth (or even a cosmically (abstract) truth, according to the
'abstract understanding'), but as a badly-stated rule of language
concerning the use of words we have for sameness and difference (as Wittgenstein
intimated), if we do that, these pseudo-problems simply vanish.
[LOI = Law of Identity.]
[An opaque drop of
metaphysical gobbledygook condensed out of a cloud of garbled grammar (to
paraphrase Wittgenstein). I have countered the Hegelian objection that we can't
just introduce negations "arbitrarily" -- which the above argument supposedly
does -- here
and here.]
In the third and penultimate section of her article,
Dulckeit 'examines' (or, rather, simply regurgitates) Hegel's criticism
of the LOI as part of her response to several objections Hegel's 'theory' might face (more
specifically those on which Russell himself focused):
"The Law of Identity, which
Hegel takes up in the 'Doctrine of Essence,' says that 'everything is identical
with itself.'" [Ibid., p.119. Quotation marks altered to conform with the
conventions adopted at this site.]
While this might be a garbled
version of
the LOI that Hegel further screwed around with, Dulckeit can't be happy with
this as a contemporary definition of identity -- that is, not without
embarrassment, or, worse, not without revealing her ignorance. And, it is little use complaining that she is
trying to defend Hegel's understanding of this 'law' since she is also
attempting to analyse (albeit superficially) Gotlob Frege and Bertrand Russell's views on identity, the LEM, and
Russell's theory of definite
descriptions (which itself incorporates a use of identity). However, and once again, this is
only to be expected of those who look to that Hermetic Harebrain, Hegel, for
guidance in matters logical.
[I have covered this topic at greater length in Essays
Six and Eight
Part Three. The reader is
directed there for more details.]
[LEM = Law of Excluded
Middle.]
Dulckeit continues:
"But if we wish to express
the fact that something is self-identical we must put it in the form
A = A, a
proposition which clearly uses two terms, not one. So while the object
o [sic] is one, to understand and state that fact [sic] requires two
terms 'o = o'." [Ibid., p.119.
Italic emphases in
the original, bold added.]
We had occasion to note earlier that those
who look to Hegel for inspiration are invariablyrecklessly cavalier
over their use
of what look like logical symbols -- but which they plainly aren't.
They can't be symbols since (a) we
are never told what they are, and have to try to work out for ourselves from the context what
they could possibly stand for, and (b) dialecticians use them inconsistently; one
minute they appear to stand for Proper Names, or other singular terms, the next
they designate predicate expressions (or what the latter supposedly stand for in
'extra-mental reality'), and then perhaps sentences or propositions, and, indeed, a host
of other imponderables. Mercurial inscriptions -- those that change at the
whim of the theorist involved, often within the same paragraph or sentence -- aren't
logical symbols,
whatever else they are.
Lo and behold! That is exactly what we find Dulckeit
herself doing.
She must know enough logic to realise that these moves are intellectually
indefensible, which, of course, means it is difficult to absolve her of
charlatanry here, too. Alas, the same can be said about every other Hegel-fan. We have already noted that
both Dulckeit and
Hegel confuse talk about talk with
talk about 'the world', and here we witness another instance of the same
confusion. We aren't told what the above letter "A" stands for (but it later
becomes apparent that it can, and does, stand for all the things mentioned in
the previous paragraph), except we are given a hint that it (or, rather, A = A)
somehow represents what is supposedly expressed by the phrase "something is
self-identical". So, A seems to stand for "something"
--
a quantifier!
Sloppy Hegelian 'logic'?!
Whatever was I thinking!
Dulckeit then changes tack and introduces a
new letter, "o", which is apparently an abbreviation for "object" --
but, note: this letter is an object, itdoesn't stand for an object
-- it is an object. That that is the case can be seen when Dulckeit
adds the following remark:
"So while the object o is one..." This letter doesn't, therefore,
stand for a non-descript 'object', it is this object!
Be this as it may, just after we have been apprised of
this 'fact', we are then confronted with the following gem: "to understand and state that
fact requires two terms 'o = o'." This mercurial
letter/object/abbreviation/whatever has now been transmogrified into a "term", capable of
occupying a logical role in that other ill-defined 'formula' "o = o"!
But, is this
o an
object on either side of an "=" sign, or a singular term? Or, what? Why is it necessary for
readers to have to rely on an ability to distance-read 'dialectical minds' in order
to understand what Hegel-groupies are trying to tell us? Is it any wonder that Bertrand Russell
asserted the following?
"This illustrates an important truth, namely,
that the worse your logic, the more interesting the consequences to which it
gives rise." [Russell (1961), p.715.]
Putting this sub-sophomoric logical gaffe to
one side for now, what is the significance of the fact that
we have to use two symbols (in fact, there are three -- two letter
"o"s
and an "=" sign -- unless we are to suppose that two occurrences of "o"
counts as one symbol -- once again we are left to guess!) in order to express self-identity?
Wonder no more:
"According to Hegel, this is
consistent with Leibniz's Law of the
Identity of Indiscernibles. Implicit in the
Law of Identity, then, is something which simply eludes the logic of the
understanding: the idea that identity makes sense only as self-identity which,
in turn, implies self-relation and, therefore, contains essentially the
idea of difference." [Dulckeit (1989. Italic emphasis in the original.
Link added.]
Dulckeit then refers her readers to this
passage from Hegel's Shorter Logic:
"Essence is mere Identity and reflection in
itself only as it is self-relating negativity, and in that way self-repulsion.
It contains therefore essentially the characteristic of
Difference. Other-being is here no
longer qualitative, taking the shape of the character or limit. It is now in
essence, in self-relating essence, and therefore the negation is at the same
time a relation -- is, in short, Distinction, Relativity, Mediation.
"To ask 'How Identity comes
to Difference', assumes that Identity as mere abstract Identity is something of
itself, and Difference also something else equally independent. This supposition
renders an answer to the question impossible. If Identity is viewed as diverse
from Difference, all that we have in this way is but Difference; and hence we
cannot demonstrate the advance to difference, because the person who asks for
the How of the progress thereby implies that for him the starting-point is
non-existent. The question then when put to the test has obviously no meaning,
and its proposer may be met with the question what he means by Identity;
whereupon we should soon see that he attaches no idea to it at all, and that
Identity is for him an empty name. As we have seen, besides, Identity is
undoubtedly a negative -- not however an abstract empty Nought, but the negation
of Being and its characteristics. Being so, Identity is at the same time
self-relation, and, what is more, negative self-relation; in other words, it
draws a distinction between it and itself." [Hegel
(1975), pp.168-69; §116. Link and bold emphasis in the original;
minor typo corrected. Some paragraphs merged.]
Dulckeit continues:
"Difference is the necessary
condition for grasping (as well as expressing) the notion of identity. What is
more, as is the case for all opposites for Hegel, identity and difference are
interdependent, or mediated, such that either one makes sense only in terms of
the other." [Dulckeit (1989), p.119.]
But, what sort of 'difference' is this, then?
'Difference' is supposed to be central to the 'inner logic' of this 'theory' (if
such it might be called by the excessively charitable among us); in that case,
one would have thought we would be given a clear idea --
or some idea -- what it implies. Again,it seems we are just supposed to guess, once more! Readers will search long and hard
(and to no avail) for
any clear idea what Hegel meant by this 'crucially important' notion. Dulckeit doesn't tell us, neither does, for example, Inwood
-- i.e., Inwood (1992),
pp.131-33. Incidentally, I have yet to find anything more comprehensive on
the use of 'difference' in Hegel's work than Inwood's attempt to render
comprehensible this example of Hegel-speak. Is it a reference to physical difference, or
something more 'logical'? Since I have dealt with this topic
earlier in this Essay, readers are directed
there for more details.
The Marxist Internet Archive Glossary
tells us the following about 'Difference':
"Difference is part of the very first stage of Essence in
the genesis of a Notion in the grade of Reflection. Difference is the negation
of Identity. The identity of something is defined by what is deemed to be
not-equal to it, different. But Difference soon cancels itself through the
discovery that 'everything is different', which is the 'maxim
of Diversity' (inessential difference). Difference is
only meaningful where the objects considered are also in some sense identical,
and thus passes over into
Opposition (essential difference) and
Contradiction, the unity of identity and difference."
[Quoted from
here; accessed 27/03/2016. Links in the original. Quotation marks altered to
conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]
So, still no clearer, then!
[In fact, this passage confuses equality with identity
-- or, "not-equal" with "difference" --
just as Trotsky
did! If readers bother to check, the above is more-or-less
the same standard-issue, high grade gobbledygook one encounters in books and articles on Hegelian Philosophy,
as their authors attempt to tell us what, for example, 'difference' is, alongside a host of
other Hegelian verbal monstrosities. Indeed, much of Modern French
'Philosophy' inexplicably revolves around the use of this word, which remains unexplained there, too (except,
of course, where it is 'explained' in
terms ofyet more gobbledygook). "Understanding dialectics" appears
to be the equivalent of accepting any old terminological rubbish thrown at the page or
the screen, especially if the one doing the throwing has done so in the French
language.]
However, from what little we are able to glean
from Dulckeit's highly compressed argument, it looks like 'difference' has something to do
with (i) The fact that there have to be two terms (or two As), not one, when we try to
express self-identity, and (ii) The SGP.
Well,
we have already seen that the
SGP would imply an infinite explosion, undermining the very possibility
of knowledge. In which case, I think (ii) can safely be ignored.
So, taking (i), next: What sort of 'difference' is this,
then?
Is it merely (a) numerical 'difference', or some sort of (b) physical 'difference'
that enables us to discriminate these As, one from the other? It
surely can't be physical difference, here, unless Hegel had secretly become an
empiricist. [Anyway, as noted above, I have dealt with this sort of 'difference' (and Trotsky's
half-baked ideas about it) in
Essay Six.
Readers are directed there for more details.]
The only alternative, then, is (a)
numerical difference -- our capacity to count two instances of the same
letter, as opposed to there being only one. The problem is, of course, that numerical difference
isn't a straight-forward concept, either. Consider just one of the difficulties
faced by anyone who holds a naive view of it: if asked to count, say, the number
of words in this Appendix, one would have to decide what was meant by that
specific request. Does it mean (i) typographically different words, or (ii)
words that a printer (or even Word) would count -- i.e., total
words, typographically identical inscriptions included as separate entries? So, for
example, this string of words, "The the the the the", would count as one word according to (i),
but
five words according to (ii).
The question is, which alternative do Hegel and Dulckeit
mean: (i) or (ii)? If they intend (i), then there is only one letter in A
= A; if they mean (ii), then there are two. From what she says, it looks like
Dulckeit thinks Hegel meant (ii). But, we can only distinguish (i) from (ii) by
the location of the relevant inscriptions in space and time being detectable
because their physical
differences. Unfortunately, that collapses (a)
above into (b),
which would make
Hegel an empiricist (never mind the other serious difficulties I have
highlighted in
Essay Six, or earlier in this Essay).
It could be objected that there is a logical
sense to "difference", which means that neither (a) nor (b) are what was
intended by the use of that word. Maybe there is, but after over 200 years of
Hegelians not
trying too hard they have failed to tell us what this 'logical' sense is. Perhaps
we are being too impatient and haven't waited long
enough?
Until more details are forthcoming,
or these Hegel-groupies express themselves for the first time in two centuries with a modicum of clarity, little
more can be made of the odd things they tend to say about the
LOI and 'difference'
-- or, indeed, much else they sadistically inflict on their readers.
Finally, in the above passage, Dulckeit mentions
something Hegel calls "the understanding" -- which is an aspect/'module' of the
human psyche that has, up to now, eluded detection by psychologists and neurologists. As far as can be ascertained from
the little that Hegel-fans tell us about this feature of Hegel's a priori 'psychology', it
appears to refer to the thinking habits of ordinary people (and workers) before
a fast-talking Hegel Honcho sells them a
lorry load of gobbledygook..., er..., sorry..., dialectics.
The next handful of paragraphs in Dulckeit's
article are devoted to answering several rather tame (and lame) objections to
Hegel's 'theory'. Since they aren't relevant to any of the issues raised in this
Essay, or at this site, they will (mercifully) be ignored.
[LEM = Law of Excluded
Middle.]
Dulckeit now focuses on the LEM:
"Hegel's onto-logic
also motivates his criticism of the Law of Excluded Middle, a law which, as
Hegel puts it, 'would feign avoid contradiction, but in doing so falls into it'
[Hegel
(1975), p.172, §119]. As formulated in the two
Logics, the law states 'Something is either A or not-A, there is no third' [Hegel
(1999), p.438, §952] and 'A is B or A is not B'
[Hegel
(1975), p.172, §119; in fact Hegel had this to
say: 'A must be either +A or -A' ; Dulckeit quotes this passage accurately on
p.129 -- RL].
"The crucial point in saying
that there cannot be anything that is not either A or not A, is the claim that
there can be no third possibility which is indifferent to the opposition because
the difference between the opposites is absolute. Thus the Law of the Excluded
Middle ordinarily is taken to mean something like the following: 'Of all
predicates, either this particular predicate or its "non-being" (i.e., the lack
of the predicate) belongs to a thing.' More specifically, explains Hegel:
'The opposite means here
merely the lack (of a predicate), or rather indeterminateness; and the
proposition is so trivial that it is not worth the trouble of saying it. When
the determinations sweet, green, square are taken...and then it is said that
spirit is either sweet or not sweet, green or not green, and so on, this is a
triviality leading nowhere
[Hegel
(1999), p.438, §952].'
"In abstract logic P
and not-P simply cancel each other out. According to Hegel, however, true
opposition should not lead from one determination to its non-being or
indeterminateness, which is clear from the principle of determinate negation.
After all, Hegel continues:
'The determinateness, the
predicate, is referred to something; the proposition asserts that
something is determined... [Hegel
(1999), p.438, §952].'
"For Hegel, therefore, 'A is
B or A is not-B' can be an important proposition, if and only if it is taken to
express that everything must be determined either positively or negatively. Thus
P and not-P do not constitute an absolute or essential
difference but are opposite determinations of something; the latter being
the third that the law seeks to exclude. One is invariably reminded of the
Greeks here for whom the idea of change was hard to grasp until they hit upon
the idea of an unchanging substratum which remained identical through the change.
Hegel argues that opposite determinations presuppose aground which is
neither yet both of them, and hence contains identity as well as difference....
This ground, or essence, is the (dialectical, not abstract) unity of
identity and difference.... Thus, he concludes:
'Instead of speaking by the
maxim of
Excluded Middle (which is the maxim of abstract understanding) we
should rather say: Everything is opposite. Neither in heaven nor in
Earth, neither in the world of mind nor of nature, is there anywhere such an
abstract "either-or" as the understanding maintains. Whatever exists is
concrete, with difference and opposition in itself. The finitude of things will
then lie in the want of correspondence between their immediate being, and what
they essentially are. Thus, in inorganic nature, the acid is implicitly at the
same time the base: in other words, its only being consists in its relation to
its other. Hence also the acid is not something that persists quietly in the
contrast: it is always in effort to realise what it potentially is. [Hegel
(1975), p.174,
§119.]'"
[Dulckeit (1989), pp.121-22. Quotation marks and
referencing conventions altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this
site. Italic emphases in the original. Minor typo corrected.]
We saw earlier that for Hegel (and Dulckeit),
the As in A = A probably stand
for Proper Names (or other singular terms), but here they seem to stand for predicate
expressions, noun-, or verb-phrases, or even propositions: "Something is either
A or not-A..."; and later
for all four at once: "A must be either +A or -A". I am assuming the "+" and the
"-" signs here stand for assertion(?) and negation(?), even though assertion and
negation aren't opposites -- for instance, it is easy to assert a negated sentence, as in "NN
asserted, 'Hegel isn't to be trusted when it comes to Logic'". However, as
usual, I am again forced to guess here, which isn't surprising. After all, a
crystal clear mystic would lose his or her licence to confuse.
Unfortunately, in the face of such syntactic
and semantic confusion, nothing determinate can follow (in the non-Hegelian/ordinary
sense of
"determinate"). However, Dulckeit did make some attempt to defend Hegel,
pointing out the following:
"Note that Hegel uses the
same symbols for subject and predicate because he is considering essential
opposition." [Ibid., p.129, Footnote 24. Italic emphasis in the original.]
In fact, if the same inscription (for
example, A or B) stands for a subject and a predicate, it isa different symbol in each of these two cases. That is because a symbol is an
inscription with a specific meaning or use (it isn't just a mark on the page
or screen), but here this pair has at least two
meanings: subject and predicate. [In fact, as noted earlier, these hyper-plastic
'symbols' have many more than just these two meanings!]
Nevertheless, given the strictures Hegel imposes
on the LOI, one wonders what Dulckeit can possibly mean by the phrase "the same
symbol". If she were consistent (a problematic policy for any dialectician to
have to adopt, to be sure) she can only mean by "the same symbol", "the same but
different symbol". This more accurate, 'dialectical' revision of Dulckeit's
words would reduce her attempted clarification to absurdity, along the following
lines:
"Note that Hegel uses the
same but different inscriptions for subject and predicate because he is
considering essential opposition." [Corrected version of ibid., p.129,
Footnote 24, replacing "the same symbol" with "the same but different symbol",
which we are told is what Hegel really meant. Italic emphasis in the original.]
But, that attempt to represent Hegel would be to
misrepresent him, too, since he uses the same (not different) inscriptions!
Of course, this only serves to remind us (as
we have witnessed repeatedly at this site -- for example,
here,
here,
here and
again, below), it is in
fact impossible to state (or even try to 'clarify') Hegel's 'theory' without descending from
woolly confusion intototal incoherence.
Be this as it may, it is worth pointing out
once more that Hegel's quirky syntax and semantics (and Dulckeit's attempt to justify
one or both) depend on the validity of the claim that there is such a thing as 'essential
opposition'. As we have seen many times, Dulckeit seems content merely to accept
Hegel's word as sufficient proof, which makes her rather like someone back in
2003 who affirmed there really were WMD in Iraq because George W Bush
said there were.
Dulckeit now falls into a familiar trap:
"In abstract logic P
and not-P simply cancel each other out." [Ibid.]
Which echoes what Hegel also asserted:
"The only thing correct in
that statement [that contradiction is unthinkable -- this is Dulckeit's gloss,
not mine -- RL] is that contradiction is not the end of the matter, but cancels
itself."
[Hegel
(1975), p.174,
§119, quoted in Dulckeit
(1989), p.122.]
However, contradictions don't 'cancel'
anything. Here is what I have written in Essay Eight
Part Three
about this -- as part of my criticism of Lawler (1982):
At last we
are nearing the dialectical denouement:
"For
our purposes, this illustration is sufficient to show that while the term
'contradiction' as used here does not have the seemingly 'full' sense of logical
contradiction, nevertheless it is not reducible to some 'clash' of externally
related 'positives.' Nor is it equivalent to some 'tranquil' association of
mutually exclusive logical contraries, such as odd and even numbers, male and
female persons, or north and south poles of a magnet -- unless these are in fact
understood dialectically…. It is necessary to understand the mutual relation and
opposition that constitutes the inner dynamic of the terms in opposition. This
opposition may contain the possibility of developing into 'full' contradiction,
i.e., into real destruction. However, the real potentiality for the development
of dialectical contradiction is not to be seen in this possibility of
destruction, but in a potentiality for transformation where only the 'immediate
forms' of opposing phenomena are suppressed -- while other, often more developed
forms are realised through essential 'internal' interconnections." [Lawler
(1982),
pp.37-38.]
Obscure jargon like this is standard fare in
HCD
texts, but that doesn't imply it makes any sense. Indeed,
it is a sure sign of the opposite.
[Irony intended.]
More
importantly, in what way does it help to interpret, say, the relation between
males and females, 'dialectically'? Do they struggle with and then change into one another,
as the DM-classics assure us they must? If so, that will be news to most of
us.
But, why
has "full contradiction"
been equated with "real destruction", here? The
LOC was (and still is) connected with
all manner of ideas that surfaced in the bad old logic (Lawler himself seems to think it has
something to do with "cancelling out" -- although he doesn't use those exact words, as far as I can
ascertain (but
Hegel certainly does -- he copied
this way of talking from
Kant), and yet he
does speak of negatives in mathematics cancelling; see below --, or as
"self-nullifying", as he puts it on p.16). As we will see in Essay Twelve
(and here),
card-carrying
HCDs also think likewise.
However, neither the contradictions of
FL nor those of ordinary language have
anything to do with "cancelling out", or "nullifying". If a proposition,
"p", is true, its contradictory, "not p", is simply false, not
"cancelled
out".
Look, it is still there on the page/screen, unharmed!
This odd idea is
connected with the equally bizarre notion that 'negative' propositions are all
false (or are 'defective' or 'non-existent', in some unspecified way). But, 'negative' propositions can be,
and often are, true. For example, "Blair isn't a socialist" is true, as is
"Anyone who reads the
Daily Mail
and doesn't reject much of what it says is no Marxist."
Furthermore, not even the content
of "not p" is "cancelled", for whatever it is that "not p"
says is still up for consideration; "not p" is just false
if
"p" is true -- true if
"p"
is false. Nor is it "nullified", for (and once more) "not p" could one day become true and
"p" itself false,
or vice versa. For example, "Blair hasn't resigned" is the contradictory of "Blair has resigned"; the first is false,
but, hopefully, it will become true one day -- it could hardly do that if it had been
"cancelled", or "nullified". [Needless to say, this was written before Blair
finally went!]
Moreover, every proposition is
paired/pairable with its negation; does that mean that they have all been
"cancelled"/"nullified"?
Anyway, what would count
as the "nullification" of, say, "Blair has resigned"? One could try to nullify
Blair's actual resignation (or its effects), but what could one do to nullify
"Blair has resigned"? Prevent this message getting out? Silence whoever might
want to utter it? [If that sentence is false, then what it says hasn't
even happened, so nothing can nullify it, surely?] Even so, that proposition is still there,
on your screen, annoyingly mocking any attempt to "nullify" it.
Those who talk this way
have clearly confused FL-contradictions with contradictory orders or
instructions, like "Open the door!"/"Close the door!", which, if acted
upon, undo each other, etc. But, the propositions of FL and ordinary
language are neither instructions
nor orders.
It has been noted several times that when it comes to
matters logical, fans of the dialectic (both the Hegelian and the 'Marxist' denominations)
are consistently slap-dash, all the while proclaiming the superiority of
DL over FL. Well, we
can now add to the list of charges against them that even where some sense can
be made of their off-the-wall claims about FL, they can't even get the basics right.
As far as Hegel's ill-advised comments about
the LEM are concerned, this is what I have written in Essay Nine
Part One:
Unfortunately,
these terms ("either" and "or") have been lifted from ordinary language, and, as
we have seen several times already, it is unwise for anyone (least of all
Hegel-groupies) to criticise such words, since that tactic invariably backfires
on any foolish
enough to try. Admittedly, Hegel wasn't attacking the use of "either-or" in
that specific area, simply the restrictive dichotomy he claimed these
words introduced into thought --, one imagines by that philistine (but nonetheless
mysterious), disembodied, inner alter ego, the "abstract understanding" --
very helpfully and 'scientifically' identified for us by Hegel without the use of
a laboratory, any evidence whatsoever, or even so much as a consulting couch! Freud would have
been most impressed:
"Instead of speaking by the
maxim of Excluded Middle (which is the maxim of abstract understanding) we
should rather say: Everything is opposite.Neither in heaven nor in
Earth, neither in the world of mind nor of nature, is there anywhere such an
abstract 'either-or' as the understanding maintains. Whatever exists is
concrete, with difference and opposition in itself. The finitude of things will
then lie in the want of correspondence between their immediate being, and what
they essentially are. Thus, in inorganic nature, the acid is implicitly at the
same time the base: in other words, its only being consists in its relation to
its other. Hence also the acid is not something that persists quietly in the
contrast: it is always in effort to realise what it potentially is." [Hegel
(1975), p.174;
Essence as Ground of Existence,
§119.
Bold emphasis added.]
Nevertheless, it is difficult to
see what Hegel was trying to say here. That is because any attempt to
interpret him requires the implicit or explicit use of the very terms he claims are misleading. The
construal of his work requires decisions be taken about whether he meant either this
or that by what he actually said. If an author always
means both -- or maybe even neither -- then interpretation is rendered impossible and any attempt to unravel
their meaning becomes self-defeating (as we are about to see).
So, if Hegel were right, if absolutely
"everything is opposite", and there is no "either-or"
anywhere in the universe, it would be impossible
to disentangle what he meant from what he didn't, since we would be
unable to decide whether he believed of, say, any two sentences P and Q one or more of
the following:
H1: (i) Both P and Q;
(ii) either
P or Q; (iii) neither P nor Q; or (iv) either P or Q, but not both.
But, if,
say, P and Q were
inconsistent (that is, if,
for instance, Q implies not P, or vice versa -- for
clarity's sake an example will be given below), and we interpreted his words one way
-- perhaps
that he believed both P and Q,since to do otherwise
would involve the implicit or explicit use of the dread 'either-or' --,
then, plainly, we would have to conclude that he accepted
both as part of the "unfolding of truth" (as he might have put it), which would
mean by his own lights, of course, that we would be unfolding error in
place of truth!
Hence, in order to reject one or other of the above options, we would be
forced to appeal to the forbidden "either-or" -- that is, we would have to conclude that
Hegel accepted P or he accepted Q, but not both.
On the other hand, if we were to remain true to Hegel's dictum --
that"neither in heaven nor in
Earth, neither in the world of mind nor of nature, is there anywhere such an
abstract 'either-or' as the understanding maintains" --, then we would have to
conclude he accepted both.
So, any attempt made
now to specify exactly what Hegel meant would undermine what he actually
said about the use of the "either-or of understanding", for we would have to
accept that Hegel asserted one thing (P), or he asserted something else (Q), but not both. Without that
assumption it would become impossible either comprehend or defend him. If Hegel genuinely
cast doubt on the "either-or of understanding" (and he wasn't being
deliberately enigmatic, disingenuous, mendacious, or merely playful) -- and assuming he was correct to do so
--, then any attempt to
interpret him as asserting Por asserting Q would have to
conclude that he asserted both. [Again, I give a clear example of this, below.]
In that case, any
determinate interpretation of
Hegel would have to ignore his own advice, and reluctantly accept
the deliverances of the "either-or" of ordinary language (or
'commonsense', along with its
corollaries), and acknowledge that, concerning either P or Q, he believed only one, not
both, and that he was a fully paid-up member of The Friends Of The Either-Or
Of Abstract Understanding.
Here, truth would advance --
by means of yet another
dialectical
inversion and by forcing us to disregard Hegel!
In order to make this more concrete, let us
suppose that:
"P" is: "Neither
in heaven nor in Earth, neither in the world of mind nor of nature, is there
anywhere such an abstract 'either-or' as the understanding maintains",
and,
"Q" is: "There is in fact an abstract
'either-or' somewhere in the world of mind and of nature (etc.)."
Now, either Hegel accepted Por he accepted
Q -- which would, of course, imply that there is at least one 'either-or' "in heaven or
in earth (etc.)" -- i.e., here, right in front of us, right here, right now!
On the other hand, if
Hegel (or anyone) took his advice and accepted
bothPandQ, thereby rejecting this annoying "either-or", then not much sense could be made of what he was
trying to say.
Incidentally, the above criticism
isn't
affected by Hegel's own interpretation of these controversial words, nor any
technical meaning his epigones might want to attribute to them, since they, too,
would have to conclude that he meant this or he meant that, not both, but solely concerns
how we are to understand him now, in this world, by our
consideration of
those very material words (in print, or on a screen), quoted earlier.
Hence, it is beside the point whether
the rationale for his own dialectical, then speculative criticism of the use of
such words by the "abstract understanding" is legitimate or not (irony intended). Hegel's writings
appear before us now as phenomenal objects, hence, given the additional
fact that they aren't
self-interpreting (especially when we recall that Hegel is no longer with us to explain himself --
but, even then we would have to accept he meant either PorQ, not both), they face the ordinary cannons we employ elsewhere to
understand anyone's words. In order to read and perhaps interpret Hegel as
believing this or that, but not both, we are forced to
ignore his advice and employ the dread "either-or".
Naturally, this is just one more
annoying reason why
ordinary language can't be by-passed, or undermined, no matter which 'genius'
cons some of us into thinking otherwise.
Once again, it is little use complaining that
this is not how Hegel wanted his use of the "either-or" of "understanding"
to be interpreted (i.e., ironically, -- that is, that we view it this way but not that),
since he
himself holed that complaint well below the water line when he
asserted:
"Instead of speaking by the
maxim of Excluded Middle (which is the maxim of abstract understanding) we
should rather say: Everything is opposite.Neither in heaven nor in
Earth, neither in the world of mind nor of nature, is there anywhere such an
abstract 'either-or' as the understanding maintains. Whatever exists is
concrete, with difference and opposition in itself. The finitude of things will
then lie in the want of correspondence between their immediate being, and what
they essentially are. Thus, in inorganic nature, the acid is implicitly at the
same time the base: in other words, its only being consists in its relation to
its other. Hence also the acid is not something that persists quietly in the
contrast: it is always in effort to realise what it potentially is." [Ibid.]
Hence,
if "everything is opposite",
and Hegel's works were written somewhere on this planet, and copies of them still take
on a physical form in this universe(!), then anything he committed to paper must be its own opposite,
too -- or, he was wrong.
[Irony intended again.]
In
either case, it would be
foolish to believe Hegel was serious (or, and what is far more likely, that he had thought things through with
due care) when he wrote the above words, while also accepting what he said about
the LEM -- the
dread "either-or".
So, and following Hegel's
own advice,
the above passage should in fact be re-written more consistently along the following 'Hegelian',
deny there is an 'either-or', lines:
"Instead of both speaking and
not speaking by the maxim both of Excluded Middle and not Excluded Middle and
(which is and is not the maxim of abstract understanding) we should and we
shouldn't rather say: Everything is, and some things are not, opposite. Neither
in heaven nor in Earth, and both in heaven and in earth, neither in the world of
mind nor of nature, and both in the world of mind and of nature, is there
anywhere such an abstract 'either-or' as the understanding maintains, but there
is, and it is everywhere, too, while it is nowhere
as well. Whatever
exists is concrete, and it isn't, with difference and opposition, and
also without difference or opposition, in itself, and not in itself, too. The finitude of things will and will not
then lie in the want of correspondence, but also with actual correspondence, between their immediate being, and what
they essentially are, or are not, and, indeed, both. Thus, in inorganic nature, and
outside it, the acid is and is not implicitly at the same time, and at other
times, the base, but it isn't the base, either: in other words, but also in the same words,
its only being, and its many other beings, consist, and do not consist, in its relation,
and absence of any relation, to its
other, and whatever isn't its other. Hence also the acid is not something, and
it is something, that persists quietly, and not quietly, in the contrast, or the
accord: it is
always, and is it is never, in effort to realise what it potentially is, and what it
actually is not."
Everyday,
boring old non-abstract understanding
will, I think, readily see what arrant nonsense results from Hegel's 'genius'
when we apply his ideas to his own words -- providing we remain in this universe.
Any who object to the above re-write can, of
course, neutralise its implications by demonstrating that Hegel's work wasn't actually written
in this universe, or on real paper, but was written on Ideal paper, neither in heaven nor on earth
-- and that they themselves don't exist anywhere, either (or both, or neither), in order to do that (or not).
[On the
'acid and base'
fiasco, even if we were to take Hegel seriously, see
here.]
In a recent book [Stewart
(1996)], a number of misinterpretations and misrepresentations of Hegel's work
were corrected by a handful of Hegel scholars. However, there would seem to be
little point to this exercise if Hegel's ideas about "either-or" are
to be believed. If he were right -- that in the entire universe there is no
"either-or" -- there would be some truth even in the wildest allegations about
him or his work.
For instance, these: that
(i) Hegel fully
accepted without question the unlimited applicability of the LOI in every
conceivable circumstance without any qualifications whatsoever (and this includes
its use in dialectical
and speculative thought as well as in relation to change, conceptual or material), and he did not; that
(ii) he flatly denied that reality or thought is contradictory
in any sense at all, and he did not; that (iii) he doubted the
truth of every single one of his own ideas all the time, and he did not; that
(iv) he wrote nothing at all in German in his entire life,
and
he did not; that (v) everything he wrote was actually written
by
Schelling
-- in fact it was published
only yesterday, and it
wasn't --; that (vi) he was a Shape-shifting Martian, and he wasn't...
[Anyone attempting to reject one or more of the above alternatives on the
grounds that Hegel must have accepted one of them, or one of them must be true, but not both -- or, indeed,
that such objectors must do likewise -- will, alas, have to employ the dread LEM in
order to do so, vitiating Hegel's challenge, as well astheir own
objections to the above argument.]
It could be objected that this
completely misunderstands the nature of
DL as Hegel
himself conceived it. Unfortunately, even that response is framed in ordinary language-- and, it was foolishly written in this universe! --, so,
since a decision has to be taken over whether or not it is valid, a quick
reference to DL will indicate it is both.
[DL = Dialectical Logic.]
This means that until DL-fans commit
themselves to one or other view (but not both), it is impossible even to begin to
evaluate anything they say -- and neither can they!
Unfortunately, just as soon as they actually manage to specify what they mean
(i.e., that they genuinely intend this but not that), we must cease to take
them seriously -- since they would then have employed the dread LEM,
thereby undermining their own criticisms of it!
Either way,
such defenders of Hegel may
be ignored even before they decide whether they agree with the above criticisms,
or not (or both).
It
could be objected that the above conclusions are ridiculous and do not follow
from a consistent application of the dialectical method; hence Hegel can't be saddled with any of them.
Once
more, these 'ridiculous conclusions' either do or they do not follow from what Hegel wrote. If the above
rebuttal is right, and they don't follow, then there is at least one either-or at work here, namely
this one -- since, in that case, both options wouldn't be correct -- only one option
would be the right one, namely that they don't follow. And, if that
is so, these
'ridiculous conclusions' do indeed follow, after all, since Hegel would, in that case, be
wrong to assert there is no either-or anywhere in existence when one such
has just been used to reject one option in favour of the other!
So, taking each 'ridiculous conclusion',
one at a time, if we maintain it doesn't follow, then we will have applied the
LEM once more -- in that we would thereby have denied that that particular 'ridiculous
conclusion' both does and does not follow, and thus that one of these either-or
options must obtain. Hence, we arrive at the same result.
On the other hand, if they do follow,
then they do, anyway.
The problem with sweeping claims like
these (which litter Traditional Philosophy, and not just Hegel's ill-considered
work) -- in this case, concerning the supposed limitations of certain principles of
FL (and especially
those that express patterns of inference mirrored in our use of ordinary language, such as the
LOI, the
LOC and the
LEM) -- is that they
invariably collapse into incoherence, as we have just seen.
[FL = Formal Logic; LOC = Law
of Non-Contradiction.]
Which is why, once again, we can say with
complete confidence that no one (not even Hegel) could possibly understand Hegel!
The rest of Dulckeit's article either (i) focuses on
the perceived weakness of Russell's Theory of Descriptions and his Logical
Atomism, which I don't propose to defend, or (ii) is a reprise of points already
covered.
In conclusion, it leaves a bitter taste in the
mouth having to rake over issues that should have been consigned to the
philosophical rubbish dump 170 or more years ago; but, for as long as philosophers
and intellectuals
require their own brand of consolation (which they often find in Mystical Hegelianism,
Cartesianism, Kantianism, Platonism, Heideggerian 'Being-ism', a priori
Lacanian 'Psychology', 'Marxist dialectics', or wherever), I suppose someone
will always have to take out the trash. Too bad is has to be me.
[What I mean by "consolation" can be
ascertained by reading 'Idealism: A Victorian Horror-Story, Parts I and II', in
Stove (1991), pp.83-177. However, in relation to Stove's work, readers should
take note of the caveats I have posted
here.]
Appendix E -- Hegel Conjures 'Contradictions'
Out Of Thin Air
[The material below has been adapted from
Essay Eight
Part Three. Remember, if you are
viewing this with Mozilla Firefox, you might not be able to read all the
symbols I have used.]
"When the
principles of Essence are taken as essential principles of thought they become
predicates of a presupposed subject, which, because they are essential, is
'everything'. The propositions thus arising have been stated as universal Laws
of Thought. Thus the first of them, the maxim of Identity, reads: Everything is
identical with itself, A = A: and negatively, A cannot at the same time be
A and Not-A. This maxim, instead of being a true law
of thought, is nothing but the law of abstract understanding. The propositional
form itself contradicts it: for a proposition always promises a distinction
between subject and predicate; while the present one does not fulfil what its
form requires. But the Law is particularly set aside by the following so-called
Laws of Thought, which make laws out of its opposite.
It is asserted that the maxim of Identity, though it cannot be proved, regulates
the procedure of every consciousness, and that experience shows it to be
accepted as soon as its terms are apprehended. To this alleged experience of the
logic books may be opposed the universal experience that no mind thinks or forms
conceptions or speaks in accordance with this law, and that no existence of any
kind whatever conforms to it." [Hegel (1975), p.167
§115.
Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.
Bold emphasis added.]
[LOC = Law of
Noncontradiction; LEM = Law of Excluded Middle; LOI = Law of Identity.]
Hegel nowhere tells us what these letter "A"s are. [Why
that matters has been explained in detail
here.] Nevertheless, for the
sake of argument, let us concede that the LOI is something like the following:
L1a:
p = p.
[Where "p"
designates a proposition, statement or spoken
token,
or even type,
declarative/indicative sentence, (etc.), depending on one's
philosophy of logic.]
Or,
perhaps even:
L1b:
∀(x)
[Fx = Fx].
[Where
"∀(x)...x" is the
universal
quantifier, and "F(ξ)"
is a one-place,
first-level predicate
expression (i.e., predicable, when interpreted). The other symbols I
have used below are explained
here.]
Incidentally, L1b is ill-formed, and roughly 'says', "Everything true of an
object is identical with every truth about that object." It
should, of course, be:
L1c:∀(x)
[Fx
ºFx],
which roughly reads
"For any object, whatever is true of it is equivalently true of that object."
Indeed, a pointless 'proposition'!
Even then, neither of these
would have any bearing on the relation they are supposed to have with their
alleged 'dialectical negative' or 'opposite' -- as
Lawler alleged.
However, that might be the case with the following (we will see):
L2:
p cannot at the same time be p and not be p.
Nor
would either have anything to do with so-called "assertibility
conditions":
L3: One
cannot assert that p is true and at the same time, and in the same respect,
assert that p is false.
That is
because there are no rules for deriving either L2 or L3 from L1a or L1b (or from
less formal versions of either), or, indeed, from anything analogous. And it isn't
hard to see why. [More about this presently.]
[Of course,
L3 might itself prove to be acceptable for other reasons. Excepting the points
I made
above (about a similar looking
sentence), I will pass no opinion on that here; but L2 and L3 certainly do
not follow from L1a or L1b, or from their alleged 'dialectical-negative' versions (or
even from less from formal versions of one or both, as we will soon see).]
However, as noted above, the
real problem here is that if the
negative particle attaches to singular terms (i.e., Proper Names and
Definite Descriptions) so that it is
interpreted as an operator mapping singular terms onto 'negative' singular
terms (whatever that means!), it can't also be a sentential operator mapping a
sentence or proposition onto its negation, which is what it has to do in
relation to the LEM and
the LOC.
That is,
if the following were the case:
P1: N*(A)
º ¬*A.
Or even:
P2: N*(A) = ¬*A.
[Where "N*" is just such a general 'negative operator'
(i.e., "Neg..."), "A" is a name variable
again, and
"¬*" is the 'negative' particle in this modified logic. (I have used asterisks to
highlight the radically non-standard nature of the symbols I have employed here.)]
Of
course, given the above syntax, P1 is ill-formed, too. That is because neitherN*(A)nor¬*A are propositions, sentences, or clauses.
['Negating' a name on its own simply yields another Noun Phrase, not an indicative
sentence or clause, while "º"
can only operate on propositions, indicative sentences or clauses.] When actual names are
inserted -- so that P1 yields, say, "Neg(Socrates) if
and only if Not(Socrates)" -- it can be seen for what it is, unvarnished
nonsense --
as "Neg(Socrates) is identical with Not(Socrates)" is, too.
On the other hand, if the negative particle above is a
sentential operator mapping a sentence or proposition onto its negation, then
it can't also be an operator mapping names in the above manner.
P3: N(A)
º ¬A.
P4: N(A) = ¬A.
[Where "N" is a negative operator
("Neg..."), "A" is now a propositional
variable, and "¬" is the negative particle in standard logic
("It is not the case that..."), which maps a sentence onto its negation.]
But, in this case,P4 would be ill-formed, too, since "=" can only be flanked by singular terms,
not propositions. Once more, if we insert actual sentences into P4, so that
it yields, for example, *"Neg(Paris is in France) is identical to it is not the case that Paris
is in France" we would see just as quickly that it is no less nonsensical.
P3,
on the other hand, seems alright as it is; while "Neg(Paris is in
France) if and only if it is not the case that Paris is in France" is
certainly odd, it isn't nonsense,
but that is only because N
now works as a surrogate for sentential or propositional negation.
Once
again, that is why it is so important to keep track of the denotation of each
letter A that Hegel and Lawler used --,
or rather, mis-used -- and why much was made of it
earlier. [And why it is important to be
clear about the precise logical role played by the negative particle.]
Recall, Hegel thought he could derive the LOC from the LOI by
claiming that the LOI "stated negatively" is, or implies, the LOC. To that end, he
argued that the LOI is "A = A", and hence that (negatively) it is also "A cannot at the
same time be A and not A" -- or, "¬(A & ¬A)".
[Of course, there are other ways of expressing the
'negative form' of the LOI; for example, it could be ¬[(A = A) & (A =
¬A)]. However, the latter
form presents problems of its own; these are explored later on in Essay Eight
Part Three and in Note 2.]
But, as far as
the LOC and the LEM are concerned, A can only stand for a proposition,
a
declarative, an
indicative sentence, or even a statement (again, depending on one's philosophical logic)
-- i.e., it goes proxy for expressions that are capable of being true or false.
By
way of contrast, in the LOI, A goes proxy for a singular term; it isn't a
propositional, or a sentential, variable. So,
for example, "Caesar" -- a singular term -- on its own isn't capable of being true or false.
Hence, if
"¬" is taken to be a propositional or sentential operator, again,
mapping truths onto
falsehoods, or vice versa,¬A would make
no sense --
"It is not the case that Caesar" is, once more, nonsensical.
Alternatively, if A is a sentential or propositional
variable, ¬(A & ¬A) would become "It is not the case that Caesar
is identical with Caesar and Caesar is not identical with Caesar" (where, for
instance, "A" stands for
"Caesar is identical with Caesar", and not just "Caesar" on its own, as would be
the case in the LOI), which seems to make sense -- but only if one is
thinking of questioning the LOI.
The other form mentioned above
-- i.e.,
¬[(A = A) & (A = ¬A)] --
fares little better (even if it isn't patent nonsense), becoming, for
example: "It is not the case that ((Caesar is identical with Caesar) and (Caesar
is identical with not Caesar))" --
that is, if ¬
now appears to function as both a sentential, or a propositional, operator and
an operator on singular terms!
Who exactly is this "not Caesar" person? [I have considered this
particular topic in more detail,
here. That is
quite apart from the fact that this example is susceptible to the fatal
objection
mentioned earlier.]
On the other hand, if ¬ operates on names, or singular terms, then
¬(A & ¬A)
would make no sense, either. In that case, ¬(A & ¬A) would become "Not (Caesar
and not Caesar)". But, what does that mean? It isn't even a proposition. "Not Caesar" isn't an expression that is capable
of being true or false, nor is "Not (Caesar and not Caesar)". In which case, given this use of
¬, ¬(A & ¬A) can't be the LOC. "Not (Caesar and not Caesar)"
isn't the LOC, nor is it even a contradiction; it is either plain gibberish or it isn't a proposition.
The
other form (i.e., ¬[(A = A) & (A = ¬A)]) isn't much better since it pans out as: "Not ((Caesar is identical with Caesar) and (Caesar is identical with not Caesar))".
[This isn't to suggest that the negative particle can't attach to
names (on that, see
here),
only that when it does, it assumes an entirely different role -- and
hence it takes on a new meaning -- different from the role it occupies when it
operates on sentences or propositions. Indeed, as we have
seen, when the
negative particle attaches to a name (in what appear to be relational expressions
(e.g., "Paris is no Vienna", or "Brutus is not Caesar")), its role changes
dramatically. The sentences just quoted become "Brutus is other than Caesar" and
"Paris can't be compared with Vienna".]
The
dialectical dilemma is now quite stark:
(1)
If ¬ operates on names, or singular terms, and if A is a
singular term variable, then A = A certainly seems to make
sense. But, in that case, the 'negative form' of the LOI -- ¬(A & ¬A), or even
¬[(A = A) & (A = ¬A)] -- turns out to be plain and unvarnished nonsense
when names are inserted once more: "Not
(Caesar and not Caesar)", (or "Not ((Caesar is identical with Caesar) and (Caesar is identical with not
Caesar))"!
(2)
On the other hand, if ¬ operates on sentences or propositions, mapping
them onto their negations, and if A is a
sentential or propositional variable, then the LOI, (A = A), would
become, for example: "Caesar is identical with Caesar is identical with Caesar
is identical with Caesar" (interpreting A in "A is identical with
A" as the
proposition "Caesar is identical with Caesar", again, yielding
"Caesar is identical with Caesar is identical with Caesar is identical with
Caesar"), which isn't the LOI!
Recall that in option (2), A has to go proxy for a proposition
or sentence (in this case "Caesar is identical with Caesar"), not a name.
Exception might be taken to the use of A to stand for the
proposition "Caesar is identical with Caesar".
DM-fans can't
in fact lodge this objection since, as we have seen,
according to them and their sloppy syntax/semantics,
these As can be anything we
please!
In that case, let us take any randomly
selected proposition to replace each A in the LOI. That having been done,
not much changes: "Paris is in France is identical to Paris is in France".
(Interpreting the A here as
"Paris is in France").
Remember this doesn't yield "'Paris is in
France' is identical to 'Paris is in France'", but "Paris is in France is
identical to Paris is in France". Is anyone prepared to accept that as an example of the
LOI?
[In case someone is so prepared, I will consider that
desperate (and unwise) move presently.]
So, Hegel was
only able to 'derive' the LOC from the LOI by allowing A
to slide effortlessly between two radically different semantic and syntactic roles:
between (i) denoting singular terms and (ii) denoting propositions, 'judgements', or sentences
(and, in fact, denoting a whole host of other things besides -- such as processes, concepts,
relations, relational expressions, etc., etc. -- on that, see an
earlier section of Essay Eight Part Three).
But, as soon that has been done, the
negative particle changes its meaning in the above manner -- that is, it changes
from a sentential operator to a name modifier, and we end up with unvarnished nonsense,
as we have seen.
If we
now choose to ignore the above fatal defects in Hegel's argument, and if L2
had have been:
L2a:
p cannot at the same time be identical with p and not be identical with
p,
things might work out differently (no pun intended).
[That is, if we allow the "A" above to be "p is identical with
p" (or, as in the example considered earlier, we allow
"A"
to be something like "Paris
is in France", and ¬
reverts to its role as a sentential operator, since p now goes
proxy for a proposition, or indicative sentence, etc.).]
Alas, even then,
the problems associated with Hegel's
'derivation' won't go away. Quantifying across propositions (if
that were
possible, and if we could make sense of the use of an "=" sign between propositional
variables/tokens), we might be able to obtain the following:
L4:
∀(p) [(p = p)
®
¬(p ≠ p)].
[This says: "If a proposition is identical
with itself then it is not the case that it is not identical with itself."
(On a side issue, some logicians are quite happy to quantify across propositions
-- or sentences/statements -- but, while this might be a handy formal device, it
can't relate to anything in a natural language. On that see Glock (2003),
pp.102-36, and Hacker (1996), p.288, n.65).]
Or,
perhaps more simply:
L4a:
[(p = p)®
¬(p ≠ p)].
But,
exactly how this implies the LOC, as Lawler says Hegel maintained, is still
unclear.
Perhaps the following
might work. From L4a, by well known rules, we can obtain:
If we now replace
(p = p) with Γ and (p ≠ p) with ¬Γ we could
obtain the following from L6:
L7:
¬(Γ
&
¬Γ).
[Again, these and other symbols were explained
here.]
Which, of course, looks likethe LOC.
Unfortunately, we have as yet no rules for
parsing the identity sign in the required manner, i.e., so that
(p ≠
p)
º
¬(p
= p). Until we do, this derivation can't work. [There are,
however, other
serious problems with this 'derivation'; on that see Note 2.]
[On the rules we do
have, see
Bostock (1997), pp.323-33
(this links to a PDF),
Lemmon (1993), pp.159-67, and Quine (1974),
pp.221-26.]
But, even if we had such rules, we can see thatin
order to obtain L7, the alleged LOI (i.e., in this case,
p =
p) had to be
combined with its supposed
Hegelian 'other'
(i.e., ¬(p
= p))
[or is it (p ≠ p)?]),
and then with its double negation (i.e., perhaps,
¬(p ≠ p)) in a
conditional. However, as we have seen, it is far from clear how L7 can be
derived from p = p
on its own, or even from its alleged 'negative form'.
L7:
¬(Γ
&
¬Γ).
Even so, it is worth
pointingout again that
because a proposition isn't an object, it isn't the sort of thing that could
either possess, or lack, identity. In that case,
if it were an object (and, per impossible, lacked identity), nothing could follow from it. On
the other hand, if, per impossible,
it were identical with itself, it would once more be an object, not a proposition
-- and,
again, nothing would follow from
it. Again, quite apart from this, it also suffers from the
fatal objection mentioned
above.2
Either way, we hit a brick wall.
Nevertheless, it could be argued that in
logical schemas like, say:
L9:∀(x)
[Fx = Fx],
and:
L10:
(∀x)(∀y)(∀F)
[(FxºFy)®(x = y)],
there is an unambiguous
identity sign between propositions (or between two tokens of the
propositional inscription,"Fx") in L9, and an equivalence sign
between Fx and Fy
(in L10). If so, it could be argued that the counter-claims made earlier (against Hegel)
are incorrect.
[Incidentally, L10 is otherwise known as the
"Identity of Indiscernibles", which we met in
Essay Six. Loosely
translated it reads: "Any two objects that share every property in common are
identical."]
But,
logicians who use either of these signs (between propositional
variables/tokens) do not imagine that inscriptions on the page are
identical. They variously interpret them as expressing a truth-functional
relationship between the results of applying F(ξ), for example, to names, or
to objects
(again, depending on the philosophy of logic to which they adhere), yielding an
identity (or a stencil that expresses an equivalence relation) of some sort between abstract objects (i.e., sets, courses of values, graphs,
ranges, classes, and the like), or between the truth-values of the interpreted
sentences that finally emerge as a result, etc., etc.
So, these signs in effect
express rules that are applicable to other signs/symbols; they don't express an
identity (or an equivalence) between lifeless marks on the page, or even between propositions that exist
in an ethereal realm somewhere.
[To be sure, there are,
and have been, philosophers and logicians who hold, or who have held, such views, but they, too,
have simply confused propositions with
propositional signs, or even with objects of some sort. On this, see
Glock (2003), pp.102-36, and Hacker (1996), p.288, n.65, once more. A
propositional sign is constituted by the physical marks on the page or the
screen. A proposition is what is expressed by the use of such a sign.]
Indeed, the second of the above (i.e., L10 -- reproduced below)
shows that this is so by implicitly interpreting the equivalence sign as a
symbol whose use in this particular stencil implies an identity between
objects (or variables that take the names of objects, in this case x
and y). In that case, schemas like L9 and L10 don't contradict what was
maintained earlier, which was that where the sign for identity is used, it
expresses a relation between objects
(or between an object and itself -- or, between its/their names), not between
concepts, predicates or propositions.
L9:∀(x)
[Fx = Fx].
L10:
(∀x)(∀y)(∀F)
[(FxºFy)®(x = y)].
Sure, we can introduce a sign that is
typographically identical to the identity sign (no pun intended), and insert it
between concepts and propositions (in fact, some modern logicians and
philosophers do just that, especially when they try to recruit identity to other
areas of philosophy, such as the alleged identity between 'mental'/psychological
events and brain processes).
But, if this new sign is
the same as the identity sign already in use, that would be to treat concepts and propositions as objects,
once more. On the other hand, if this new sign isn't the same as the identity sign
already in use, then it can't express identity, but must express
'identity', which would, of course, mean that the 'philosophical problem of
identity' would remain unaffected by these terminological manoeuvres. Unless, of
course, we mean something different by "identity" in each case (irony intended).
And, if that were so, we would need a different sign for each of these different
meanings of "identity" -- double irony intended, too -- or risk confusion.
At which point, we would have gone
round in yet another circle.
L9:∀(x)
[Fx = Fx].
L10:
(∀x)(∀y)(∀F)
[(FxºFy)®(x = y)].
Whether
or not these symbols capture the full range of meanings available to us in
scientific contexts -- or
even in ordinary language --, I will leave to one side for the present (but,
it is worth adding that
Essay Six
returned a negative verdict in this regard).
Of course, in schematic sentences like
L1b/L9, "=" would be replaced by "º";
that is, by a biconditional or equivalence symbol (indeed, as we saw
earlier). That is because "=" features
in two-place linguistic functional expressions (i.e., "ξ=ζ"), which can only take names or singular terms as arguments.
So, as noted earlier, L1b/L9 are ill-formed as they stand. Once more, there
are and have been philosophers and logicians who hold that the identity sign can be
used between non-singular terms, but they have yet to explain why this doesn't
imply that this novel use of such signs, or these variables/non-singular terms, have a different meaning.
Indeed, we could
introduce a general 'identity' sign, and define it as follows:
Df:
"Ω₳ Ψ",
where "Ω"and"Ψ"
stand for singular terms or concept expressions of any level, and "₳"
expresses a general identity between them.
Even then,
it would require a cogent argument to show that the equal sign, =,
is identical with this new sign, ₳;
and how might
that be
achieved, for goodness sake?
This would, of course, leave it quite mysterious whether or not the word
"identical" in "= is
identical with ₳"
is itself identical
with the first or the second use of these two signs, prompting the very same
question (no irony intended) about the word "identical"
used to ask that
very question -- and so on, ad infinitem!
Nevertheless, one thing
is clear: MFL and ordinary language succeed in capturing the full range of words we have for
identity (etc.) far better than the syntactic and semantic 'dialectical
mess' we find in Hegel's 'Logic' and now
in DL. In fact, as Essays Three through
Eight show, DL can't handle the simplest of
objects (such as a
bag of sugar!),
let alone anything more complex.
[DL = Dialectical
Logic; LEM = Law of Excluded Middle. MFL = Modern Formal Logic.]
Hence,
and once again, the suggested Hegelian 'derivation' of the LOC (i.e., the one
expounded by Lawler)
can't work if these As are read as objects, or the names of objects (since objects/names
can't be true or
false) -- nor, indeed, can it work if
propositions are viewed as objects,
either.
Once
more, that is why it is so important to be clear about the denotation of
symbols we use in logic -- and why such a fuss was made about this
earlier.
1.Much of this Essay is a development of ideas aired in Ryle (1949, 1959), Cowley
(1991), Davidson (2005), the
work of the late
Peter Geach, and, of course,
Frege and
Wittgenstein.
[On that, see
here.]
The importance of this subject (Abstractionism) for the history of
Traditional Thought is outlined in Davidson (2005), pp.76-140. [I distance
myself, however, from Davidson's neat 'solution' to this 'problem' (pp.141-63),
but this isn't the place to go into that.]
Be this as it may, a perceptive critique of
Davidson can be found in Ionescu (2007). This topic is also discussed in detail in
Gaskin (2008) and Gibson (2004). [See also Note 15a.] In addition, cf.,
Professor
E J Lowe's review in the Times Higher Education Supplement (partially
quoted
below),
which also contains a short summary of the philosophical 'problems' associated
with the traditional approach to the growth and nature of knowledge. I will briefly discuss Gaskin's
'solution' to the
unity
of the proposition conundrum in a future re-write of Part Two of
this Essay.
The main areas in the philosophical and
historical background to this topic are explored in Tugendhat (1982). There is an
excellent survey of where the debate is now situated (i.e., concerning the 'reference
of predicates') -- or, at least where it was a decade or so ago -- in MacBride
(2006). Having said that, MacBride doesn't consider the effect the
traditional view -- that predicates do refer -- has on the
unity of
the proposition. [On this,
see also
Essay Four
Part One.]
Bertell Ollman
has recently written a highly influential account of the mythical process of
abstraction, arguing along more naturalistic lines in order to
conceive of
abstraction as a cognitive limiting, or narrowing process of some sort, in which he claims we all
engage, without offering an ounce of proof from a single psychological study,
experiment or survey to that effect. Of course, as we will see he isn't the only one to adopt this
ancient idea, nor is he the only one who fails to provide any proof that this
process even exists. His attempt to render this ancient fairytale comprehensible has
been critically examined in
detail in
Part Two
of this Essay. [Cf., Ollman (2003), pp.59-110.]
In addition, an analysis of the following will be added to
the appendices at
a later date:
(i)
Evald Ilyenkov's
work [i.e., Ilyenkov (1975, 1977, 1982), for example],
(ii)
Alex
Callinicos's analysis of Marx's use of abstraction
[i.e., Callinicos (1978)], and (iii) Some thoughts on Sayer (1981, 1992) and Sayer (1988).
Finally, any revolutionaries reading this who might be tempted to criticise my reliance on Wittgenstein's work
should
read this and
then perhaps think again.
1a.Following
Plato and
Aristotle,
Traditional Theorists defended 'abstractions' and 'the process of abstraction'
on the basis that it enabled them to construct general theories -- or even
form general ideas -- about nature and
society. It was claimed that sense experience could only inform us about particulars, about the immediate, about this or that
object. Hence, 'the process of abstraction' was seen as both important and necessary
for the development of human knowledge, a facility that takes humanity beyond the immediate and the particular
to the general.
Of
course, that argument in itself is rather suspect since it is possible to
encounter the general in experience -- for example:
G1: I
have just checked; all the chickens in the yard are still alive.
G2:
As this video shows, everyone on the demonstration was chanting "Tories out!"
G3:
We sold all the papers we were given to sell on the march yesterday.
G4: I
counted them myself. Everyone in the room voted to strike.
G5:
Every flower in this garden was planted by me and my partner.
G6:
Every single book in this library was bought with public funds.
G7: I
painted every panel in this fence myself.
G8: I
have studied every planet in the Solar System myself, over many years.
G9:
Look! Everyone in the stadium has left. All 75,000 of them.
G10: Did you
see? Everything he ever wrote just went up in flames!
G11:
The insurance agent has just confirmed that every stick of furniture was
destroyed by the earthquake.
And
so on.
It could be
objected that the above examples fail to cover universal
generality, so they aren't relevant. Naturally, that depends on what is meant by
"universal generality", here. Every one of these examples covers restricted universality
(and the reader can confirm that for herself by checking every single one of
them, thereby adding yet another example to the list of our capacity to 'experience the
general'). While it is correct that we can't in general experience examples
of the 'absolutely universally general', but, as Parts One and Two of this Essay
have shown, they can't be accessed by this mythical 'process of abstraction',
either. Even so, we are still able to speak about 'absolute' universal
generality in ordinary language, when for example, we talk about every star in
the universe, or every proton in existence. All that is required is a mastery of
language, not recourse to the shadowy 'process of abstraction'.
It
could be argued that this misses the point; no scientific law could be based on
such limited, local generalisations.
On the contrary,
they are based on them all the time.
That is the point of statistical sampling. No scientist, or team of scientists,
can possibly observe, collect, record and process every conceivable fact even
about, say, the planet Jupiter, let alone anything else.
Re-labelling these
'abstractions',
"idealisations", would be no help, either, since the same awkward questions
would apply just as much to these mysterious 'entities' as they do to 'abstractions'. As we will see
in
Essay Thirteen Part Two, the traditional view of "idealisation" is no clearer than
that of "abstraction" -- except, perhaps, the word "idealisation" more
obviously gives the game away,
openly advertising its
Idealist pedigree.
Again, some might
appeal to "scientific laws" at this point to give these
inchoate
terms (i.e., "abstraction" and "idealisation") some sort of
material/physical solidity, but, as we will
also see, the word "law", as it has traditionally been used and
understood, is no less Idealist, having been
imported into science from
the social sphere, where it relates to a series of norms enforced by the
state (or some other body that has such powers delegated to it by the state), which were thenprojected onto nature. And
that theoretical
segue was itself aimed at lending credence to
an
even more ancient doctrine, which held that the universe is under the control of a Cosmic Will
of some sort, an idea that was in turn motivated by the need to 'justify' or
rationalise the status, power and authority of the State. This would then be
used to support, justify, even rationalise, the idea that the state itself
represents, or reflects, the 'Divine Order', the 'Will of
the Gods'. So, here we have laws 'legitimately' enforced by the State mirroring 'laws'
'legitimately' enforced by
'God'. The 'law-governed', rational order 'mirroring' the law-governed state.
[On this, see Milton (1981, 1998), Needham (1951a,
1951b), Ruby (1986), Swartz (1985,
2009), and
Zilsel (1942). However, this also takes us into areas which
overlap with the nature and use of 'thought experiments', a topic
that will be discussed in
more detail in Essay Thirteen Part Two,
when it is published.]
Finally, as this Essay unfolds we will see that this
approach to 'abstract general ideas' (or 'concepts'), beloved of Traditional
Philosophers and DM-theorists, only
succeeds in
delivering an opposite result: itdestroys generality, and that in
turn would
completely
undermine science itself.
1b.Of
course, the answer to such questions has usually been that we ascertain general
concepts or ideas by a 'process of abstraction' (or even by some sort of vague 'intuition',
augmented, or not, by a cursory appeal to 'the
light of reason'). The rest of this Part of Essay
Three, and indeed
Part Two, will
put this 'explanation' under sustained pressure.
1b0. On this, see
Cornford (1997), pp.191-97, Cowley (1991), and Lazerowitz and Ambrose (1976), pp.145-84.
1b1.
In fact, according to DM-theorists, 'abstractions' are supposed to
be products of the 'mind'; in which case, it is difficult to see if there is a clear distinction, or
even a difference, between the use of the word "abstraction" -- in
conjunction
with other terms that
supposedly designate abstract general ideas (such as "Manhood", "The
Population", "abstract labour") -- and
whatever these words supposedly refer to or 'reflect'
either in 'reality' or 'the mind'. The question is: Do phrases like "Manhood",
"The Population", and "abstract labour" refer to ideas 'in the mind' or to
something in 'extra-mental reality'? As we will see, DM-fans run the answers to
such questions
together as a matter of course. One minute it is the former, the next it is the
latter; sometimes it is both at the same time.
In which case, at this site -- unless I
am discussing Plato's 'Forms', or I am trying to figure out what these 'abstractions' actually
designate in 'the mind' (or, indeed, in 'extra-mental reality') --,
I will sometimes run-together 'abstraction' and whatever it is that
'abstractions' supposedly 'reflect' or 'refer
to' in
'reality' or the 'mind'. This shouldn't create too much confusion since this seems to be what
most dialecticians do, anyway -- that is, they confuse talk about talk with talk about
'things'.
1b2. On this, see for example, Cowley (1991),
pp.85-116.
1c. An
'Abstract
Particular' is like a genuine particular (such as the chair you are
now sat in/on (if you are), the screen you are looking at -- or even, you),
to which we could, if we so choose, give a Proper Name, or pick out by the use of
singular terms -- such as the following definite description, "the screen you are now looking at", or
even this pronoun, "I mean him over
there", often accompanied by a gesture of some sort. The difference is that 'abstract particulars' don't appear to
exist anywhere in the world around us. They are, however, still capable of being
designated by the use of names (which turn out to be Proper Names) or other
singular terms (such as "The
Form of the Good", "Manhood", or "The Population").
[I
am, of course, summarising my interpretation of the theory I am criticising, not outlining my own ideas!]
However, as noted in the main body of this
Essay, the
extension of an abstraction (to use a more
contemporary buzz word) is
also supposed to be general.
That is, the extension of each relevant abstract term is supposedly
all cats,
all dogs, all men/women, the entire population, all
electrons, etc.
Be that as it may, even while
abstractions are supposed to do this (i.e., they supposedly designate the set of all
men, or the set of all 'persons, for
example), they are manifestly singular in form, since they also refer to
'Man', or 'The Population'.
They appear to name a class, collection or set, and Proper Names
are employed to that end. So, "Manhood" is the Proper Name of the Abstract Particular
'Manhood', since that word, "Manhood", uniquely designates 'Manhood',
and nothing else.
Unfortunately, while the use of such
terms is
intended to help account for, or express,
generality, it ends up destroying it -- plainly, since neither a singular term nor
the particulars ('abstract' or 'concrete') they supposedly designate are general.
The chair you are sat
on isn't all chairs there are or have ever been, the screen you are now using
isn't every screen there has ever been or will ever be. Nor can "the chair you
are sat on" or "the screen you are now using" refer to all chairs or screens
there are or have ever been. [That point will, I hope, become a little clearer
as this Essay proceeds.]
It could be argued that classes, sets and
collections preserve generality, they don't obliterate it. As we will
soon see, the opposite is in fact the case.
1d. I am
of course speaking of the sort of collections (as classes of objects) that
are supposedly found in nature and society (howsoever they themselves are characterised),
not of the classes or sets that are found in mathematics or any other formal discipline.
1d1.
Concerning this obscure notion -- i.e., "concrete universal" --,
Hegel scholar, Michael Inwood,
had this to say:
"[W]hen Hegel speaks of the 'concrete concept' and of
'concrete universality' he usually has at least two points in mind: that
concepts or universals are not sharply separate from the perceptible concrete --
and that they are not sharply separate from each other, that e.g., the concept
of universality is not sharply distinct from those of particularity and
individuality." [Inwood (1993), p.30.]
Make
of that what you can.
1e.
Indeed, we find dialecticians talking as if the words they use for the 'abstractions' they have conjured into existence
turn out to bethe
Proper Names of ideas,
concepts, or categories --, or, they are what these names supposedly refer to or
'reflect' either in the world or in 'the
mind' (often these are simply run-together). We will encounter
several more examples of this 'dialectical-interpretation' as this Essay unfolds.
[In fact, Ilyenkov (1982)
(inadvertently) makes several somewhat similar points without realising their
significance -- or, indeed, the fatal implications this poses for this entire way of 'doing
philosophy'.]
Here are a few examples, taken from
several 'dialectical'-sources that argue along similar lines:
"Given the name lion, we need neither the actual vision of
the animal, nor its image even: the name alone, if we understand it, is the
unimaged simple representation. We think in names." [Hegel
(1971), p.220, §462. Bold emphasis added.]
"To define the subject as that of which
something is said, and the predicate as what is said about it, is mere trifling.
It gives no information about the distinction between the two. In point of
thought, the subject is primarily the individual, and the predicate the
universal. As the judgment receives further development, the subject ceases to
be merely the immediate individual, and the predicate merely the abstract
universal: the former acquires the additional significations of particular and
universal, the latter the additional significations of particular and
individual. Thus while the same names are given to the two terms of the
judgment, their meaning passes through a series of changes." [Hegel (1975), p.234.
Bold emphasis added.]
"It seems correct to begin with the real and the
concrete…with e.g. the population…. However, on closer examination this proves
false. The population is an abstraction if I leave out, for example, the classes
of which it is composed. These classes in turn are an empty phrase if I am not
familiar with the elements on which they rest…. Thus, if I were to begin with
the population, this would be a chaotic conception of the whole, and I would
then, by further determination, move toward ever more simple concepts, from the
imagined concrete towards ever thinner abstractions until I had arrived at the
simplest determinations. From there the journey would have to be retraced until
I had finally arrived at the population again, but this time not as the chaotic
conception of a whole, but as a rich totality of many determinations and
relations…. The latter is obviously scientifically the correct method. The
concrete is concrete because it is the concentration of many determinations,
hence the unity of the diverse." [Marx (1973),
pp.100-01.
Bold emphases added.]
"The identity of thought and being, to express myself in
Hegelian fashion, everywhere coincides with your example of the circle and the
polygon. Or the two of them, the concept of a thing and its reality, run side by
side like
two asymptotes, always approaching each other but never meeting. This difference
between the two is the very difference which prevents the concept from being
directly and immediately reality and reality from being immediately its own
concept. Because a concept has the essential nature of the concept and does not
therefore prima facie directly coincide with reality, from which it had
to be abstracted in the first place, it is nevertheless more than a fiction,
unless you declare that all the results of thought are fictions because reality
corresponds to them only very circuitously, and even then approaching it only
asymptotically." [Engels to Conrad Schmidt (12/03/1895), in Marx and Engels
(1975b), p.457. Bold emphasis added.]
"Shachtman
obviously does not take into account the distinction between the abstract and
the concrete. Striving toward concreteness, our mind operates with abstractions.
Even 'this,' 'given,' 'concrete' dog is an abstraction because it proceeds to
change, for example, by dropping its tail the 'moment' we point a finger at it.
Concreteness is a relative concept and not an absolute one: what is concrete in
one case turns out to be abstract in another: that is, insufficiently defined
for a given purpose. In order to obtain a concept 'concrete' enough for a given
need it is necessary to correlate several abstractions into one -- just as in
reproducing a segment of life upon the screen, which is a picture in movement,
it is necessary to combine a number of still photographs.
"The
concreteis a combination of abstractions -- not an arbitrary or subjective
combination but one that corresponds to the laws of the movement of a given
phenomenon." [Trotsky (1971),
p.147. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this
site. Bold emphases added.]
"[A]ll science generalizes and abstracts from
'empirically verifiable facts.' Indeed, the very concept of 'fact' is itself an
abstraction, because no one has ever eaten, tasted, smelt, seen or heard a
'fact,'which is a mental generalization that distinguishes actually existing
phenomena from imaginary conceptions. Similarly, all science 'deductively
anticipates' developments -- what else is an hypothesis tested by
experimentation? The dialectic is, among other things, a way of investigating
and understanding the relationship between abstractions and reality. And the 'danger of arbitrary construction' is far greater using an empirical method
which thinks that it is dealing with facts when it is actually dealing with
abstractions than it is with a method that properly distinguishes between the
two and then seeks to explain the relationship between them." [Rees (1998), p.131.
Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.
Bold emphasis added.]
"This law of identity of opposites, which so perplexes and
horrifies addicts of formal logic, can be easily understood, not only when it is
applied to actual processes of development and interrelations of events, but
also when it is contrasted with the formal law of identity. It is logically true
that A equals A, that John is John…. But it is far more profoundly true that A
is also non-A. John is not simply John: John is a man. This correct proposition
is not an affirmation of abstract identity, but an identification of opposites.
The logical category or material class, mankind, with which John is one and the
same is far more and other than John, the individual. Mankind is at the same
time identical with, yet different from John." [Novack (1971), p.92.
Bold emphasis added.]
"In popular usage, the adjective 'abstract' often means
'vague' or 'removed from reality'. The sense in which the term is used here is different; an
abstract concept, or an abstraction, isolates in thought a one-sided or
partial aspect of an object. What we abstract from are the many other
aspects which together constitute concrete objects, such as people,
economics [I'm sure Sayer means economies here -- RL], nations,
institutions, activities and so on. In this sense an abstract concept can be
precise rather than vague; there is nothing vague about abstractions such as
'temperature', 'valency', 'gender', 'income elasticity of demand', or 'the
circuit of money capital'. And the things to which these abstractions refer need
be no less real than those referred to by concrete concepts. Hence the
abstract and the concrete should not be aligned with the distinction between
thought and reality." [Sayer (1992),
p.87. Bold emphasis alone added.
The page numbering is completely different in the Second Corrected Edition,
i.e., Sayer (2010), p.59.]
"While thought and ideas, like language, originate from
labour, men likewise develop their thinking and their ideas in the course of the
whole of their social activity....
"Ideas are not the products of a pure intellectual
process, nor are they mere automatic responses to stimuli reaching us from
external objects. They are produced by human brains in the course of human
social activity. They reflect the connections of men with one another and
with the external world, the real conditions of men's existence....
"The first and most elementary ideas are ideas directly
derived from immediate practical intercourse with other people and surrounding
objects. They are formed by giving names to the common features of things
recognisable in perception....
"In such ideas are more or less directly reflected the
salient features of objects and human activities as we are immediately aware of
them in perception. Such ideas constitute the basic, elementary equipment of
human thought and communication. They are expressed in words denoting
familiar objects, and everyday activities....
"Such are our ideas of the things about uswith
which our normal affairs are concerned, such as men and women, tables, chairs,
motor cars, trees, flowers, dogs, cats., etc., etc.; of sensible properties of
things, such as red, blue, hard, soft, big, small, and so on; and of actions and
relations, such as running, walking, falling, above, below, etc., etc....
"The feature of such elementary ideas is that they have a
concrete, sensuous content, because to them correspond objects directly
perceptible to the senses....
"Can we form ideas to which no directly perceptible object
corresponds? Yes, of course, we can, and we do. For example, men are directly
perceptible objects, and their properties of being tall, short, thin, fat, and
so on, are directly perceptible properties. But we also think of men in terms
other than these, although nothing directly evident to the senses corresponds to
what we think about them....
"One needs only to point to a fat man, and someone
running, and say 'I mean that a man like that is doing that'. If, on the other
hand one says 'The capitalist exploits the workers', one is still referring to
certain familiar sensible objects (men), but one is at the same time making
a generalisation about them which refers to a relationship between them which is
not open to immediate observation but which requires a very elaborate definition
in terms of other relationships. One cannot explain what one means by
'capitalist' and 'exploitation' in the same way as one can explain what one
means by 'fat' and 'running'....
"It is to such ideas that the term 'abstract' is commonly
applied." [Cornforth (1963), pp.57-60. Quotation marks altered to conform
with the
conventions adopted at this site. Bold emphases added.]
Even though Cornforth gestures
at accepting the social nature of language, knowledge and 'cognition', his
analysis is little better
than that offered by
Hobbes,
Locke and
Descartes, which, naturally, places him in the
bourgeois
individualist camp -- at least as far as his theory of knowledge is
concerned. [The "little better" aspect here arise from Cornforth's appeal to
"practice", but,
as we have seen, an
appeal to
practice would be to no avail.]
As
noted above, for Cornforth, as for Hegel, Hobbes, Locke, Descartes and all the
rest, words that supposedly give expression to our ideas and concepts are
"names" (and, with respect to these 'abstractions, they are Proper Names) that "refer to" or "designate"
certain objects.
Hence, the naming or pointing relation is the paradigm that dominates
Cornforth's thought (as it does the theories of the others mentioned or quoted above); but, because he/we can't point to something in immediate
experience that answers to certain words (or is it that he/we can't point to
certain ideas hidden away 'in the mind', or in a heaven with 'the gods'?), he classifies them as 'abstractions' -- which is precisely the
line taken by Ancient Greek Theorists, albeit expressed in an entirely different
idiom. [In relation to that, see
here. On this topic in general,
see Hacking (1975).]
Finally, Cornforth thinks that ostension (i.e., pointing
at
or to something) is a perfectly straight-forward way to explain the meaning of a word, but it isn't. On that,
see Hacker (2005), pp.81-106.
Of
course, Cornforth's approach to language is something Marx himself had railed
against (alas, only in his early work):
"Is it surprising that everything, in the final
abstraction -- for we have here an abstraction, and not an analysis -- presents itself as a logical category? Is it surprising that, if you
let drop little by little all that constitutes the individuality of a house,
leaving out first of all the materials of which it is composed, then the form
that distinguishes it, you end up with nothing but a body; that if you leave out
of account the limits of this body, you soon have nothing but a space -– that
if, finally, you leave out of account the dimensions of this space, there is
absolutely nothing left but pure quantity, the logical category? If we abstract
thus from every subject all the alleged accidents, animate or inanimate, men or
things, we are right in saying that in the final abstraction the only substance
left is the logical categories. Thus the metaphysicians, who in making these
abstractions, think they are making analyses, and who, the more they detach
themselves from things, imagine themselves to be getting all the nearer to the
point of penetrating to their core….
"Just as by means of abstraction we have transformed
everything into a logical category, so one has only to make an abstraction of
every characteristic distinctive of different movements to attain movement in
its abstract condition -- purely formal movement, the purely logical formula of
movement. If one finds in logical categories the substance of all things, one
imagines one has found in the logical formula of movement the absolute
method, which not only explains all things, but also implies the movement
of things...." [Marx (1978),
pp.99-100.Bold emphases alone added.]
"The
philosophers have only
to dissolve their language into the ordinary language, from which it is
abstracted, in order to recognise it, as the distorted language of the actual
world,
and to realise that neither thoughts nor language in themselves form a
realm of their own, that they are only manifestations of actual life."
[Marx
and Engels (1970), p.118. Bold emphasis alone added.]
Hence, it is quite clear that in this early work, Marx connected abstractionism
with linguistic distortion -- as a result of which what was supposed to be
general is particularised --, which is, of course, the line adopted
at this site.
Indeed, Marx underlined this very point -- that
is, that philosophers invent names for their 'abstractions' -- thereby
distorting ordinary
language:
"If from real apples, pears,
strawberries and almonds I form the general idea 'Fruit', if I go further
and imagine
that my abstract idea 'Fruit', derived from real fruit, is an entity
existing outside me, is indeed the true essence of the pear, the apple,
etc., then -- in the language of speculative philosophy –- I am declaring
that 'Fruit' is the 'Substance' of the pear, the apple, the
almond, etc. I am saying, therefore, that to be an apple is not essential to the
apple; that what is essential to these things is not their real existence,
perceptible to the senses, but the essence that I have abstracted from them and
then foisted on them, the essence of my idea -– 'Fruit'. I therefore
declare apples, pears, almonds, etc., to be mere forms of existence, modi,
of 'Fruit'. My finite understanding supported by my senses does of
course distinguish an apple from a pear and a pear from an almond, but
my speculative reason declares these sensuous differences inessential and
irrelevant. It sees in the apple the same as in the pear, and in the
pear the same as in the almond, namely 'Fruit'. Particular real fruits
are no more than semblances whose true essence is 'the substance' -- 'Fruit'....
"The ordinary man does not think he is saying
anything extraordinary when he states that there are apples and pears. But when
the philosopher expresses their existence in the speculative way he says
something extraordinary. He performs a miracle by producing the
real natural objects, the apple, the pear, etc., out of the unreal
creation of the mind 'the Fruit'….
"It goes without saying that the speculative
philosopher accomplishes this continuous creation only by presenting universally
known qualities of the apple, the pear, etc., which exist in reality, as
determining features invented by him, by giving the names of the
real things to what abstract reason alone can create, to abstract formulas of
reason, finally, by declaring his own activity, by which he passes
from the idea of an apple to the idea of a pear, to be the self-activity
of the Absolute Subject, 'the Fruit.'
"In the speculative way of speaking, this
operation is called comprehending Substance as Subject, as an
inner process, as an Absolute Person, and this comprehension
constitutes the essential character of Hegel's method." [Marx and Engels
(1975a), pp.57-60. Bold emphases alone added.]
From this, we can
clearly see Marx explicitly
contrasting the
"philosopher's" approach to 'abstract
knowledge' with the way that ordinary human
beings think and talk. It is also worth underlining the fact that Marx points
out that philosophers turn general words in to Proper Names (in this case the
"Absolute Fruit", or just "Fruit"), and while the abstractions to which they
supposedly refer are what is really real, the actual fruits we see around
us are mere "semblances":
"I am saying, therefore, that to be an apple is not essential to the
apple; that what is essential to these things is not their real existence,
perceptible to the senses, but the essence that I have abstracted from them and
then foisted on them, the essence of my idea -– 'Fruit'....
Particular real fruits are no more than semblances whose true essence is 'the substance' -- 'Fruit'....
"Having reduced the different
real fruits to the one 'fruit' of abstraction -– 'the Fruit',
speculation must, in order to attain some semblance of real content, try somehow
to find its way back from 'the Fruit', from the Substance to the
diverse, ordinary real fruits, the pear, the apple, the almond etc....
"It goes without saying that
the speculative philosopher accomplishes this continuous creation only by
presenting universally known qualities of the apple, the pear, etc., which exist
in reality, as determining features invented by him, by giving the
names of the real things to what abstract reason alone can create, to
abstract formulas of reason, finally, by declaring his own activity, by
which he passes
from the idea of an apple to the idea of a pear, to be the self-activity
of the Absolute Subject, 'the Fruit.'...
"...and this comprehension constitutes the essential character of Hegel's
method." [Ibid. Bold emphases alone added.]
However, as we will see when we examine the way that DM-theorists
analyse predicative expressions, they too transform 'abstract general terms'
(supposedly expressed by
predicables
-- follow the link for an explanation of that word) into the Proper Names of
abstract
particulars. It is here where the aforementioned distortion occurs
--, which move, if valid, would destroy both generality and the capacity
we have in language to say anything at all
Finally, it is instructive to find out that even right-wing ideologues like
Jordan Peterson also promote 'abstractionism'
(without once attempting to explain how it is logically, or even
psychologically, possible):
"If
you have a set of things and you abstract out
from them a common element,
you can make a strong case that the common element is more real than the set of
things from which you abstracted it.
That's the whole utility in abstraction."
[Quoted from
here.
Bold added.]
So,
according to that numpty, the world of 'abstractions' is more real than the world you see around
you. This is in fact an excellent summary of 'reality' as DM-fans also see
things:
the universe gains its 'essence' from an Ideal world of 'abstractions'.
This differs from Ancient Greek Mysticism in words alone.
On
the problems this set of ideas creates, see Note Two; this topic is
entered into in more
detail in Part
Two.
2.As we shall also see, the nature of this mysterious 'process' is difficult to describe,
even if you believe in it. [Several examples of DM-theorists trying to
explain this mysterious 'process' are given
above and in
Appendix B.]
Here are
just a few of the serious problems it faces:
(1)
If the 'process of abstraction' is indeed a 'mental activity', how would it be
possible for each abstractor to know if they had arrived at the correct abstract
concept of anything at all, or, indeed, anything in particular? Indeed, the
notion that there could be a 'correct' abstraction loses all meaning if there is
no way to check. With what, or with whom, could any of the supposed results be
checked? Since this 'process' is supposed to take place in 'the mind', no one
would have access to a single 'abstraction' produced by anyone else, nor would
each abstractor have access to the 'abstractions' they produced only a few
moments earlier. An appeal to memory would be to no avail since
memories are also supposed to make use of abstractions, which would themselves be
subject to the very same doubts. There is in fact no way to break into this
'abstractive circle', no way to check.
An appeal to the existence of a public language would be to no
avail, either. Again, if each abstractor 'processes' their 'abstractions' in the
privacy of their own heads, no one would be able to tell
whether AbstractorA meant the same as AbstractorB by his or her use of
the relevant words
(or the relevant 'concepts' -- like "Substance", "Being", "Nothing",
"The Population", "abstract labour", etc., etc.) drawn from the
vernacular, or elsewhere.
Definitions would be no help, either, since, just like memory, they also employ
'abstractions' -- so, they, too, would
be subject to the same awkward questions. For how could AbstractorA know what
AbstractorB
means by any of the abstract terms she has processed without access to her
'mind'? AbstractorB can't point to anything which is 'the meaning' of a single
abstraction she might be trying to define, so she can't use an
ostensive definition to help AbstractorA understand what she means
(even if meanings could be established that way).
No particular, or
no singular term, can give the meaning of any abstraction or abstract term under
scrutiny (as those who accept this theory intend, not as I have
criticised it -- so I am not contradicting my claim that these abstractions are
really the Proper Names of abstract particulars). That being so, the same 'difficulties' would confront the general terms
supposedly employed in
any definition used to that end, and so on...
And, it is even less use appealing to the 'logic of concepts',
which drives 'thought' along, as, say, a staunch follower of Hegel might attempt to do. Not only is it
unclear what Hegel's terminology actually means (any who doubt this might like to try
to explain, say,
these passages), but even if all he had ever said were
crystal clear, since he was the first to concoct this 'dialectical process',
'thought' can't
inevitably be driven along these lines -- otherwise we wouldn't have needed Hegel to deliver the good
news to us. Of course, it could be argued that he was the first to reveal what we all
somehow manage to do without realising it, or, even, that he revealed what 'the
speculative philosopher' does, or should do, whether or not he realises it,
too. [Or,
to be more honest, this is what Hegel, or anyone else who has swallowed his ideas,
gestures at doing, by producing page-after-page of obscure jargon.] Naturally, this just
labels the problem, it doesn't constitute an effective response.
I
will, however, postpone replying to this particular riposte until
Part Two of this Essay.
Until
then it is sufficient to note that 'thought' can only take this route if we are
prepared to accept without question the logical, classical, and Hegelian blunders
outlined in this Essay (as well as
here and
here); in which case,
such 'thought' deserves all the confusion
it attracts to itself as a
result.
Moreover, even if abstractions were arrived at in
a 'more law-like
way' -- as the 'mind' tries to grapple with scientific knowledge, à la Hegel
--,
it would still be unclear how any one mind could possibly check the
'abstractive' results of any other in order to ascertain whether or not either or both
of them had arrived at the same Ideal
result. Indeed, how could
anyone trapped in a Hegelian world of internally processed, 'Jackson
Pollock-like Concepts' decide if they even meant the same by the word "same",
for goodness sake!
Figure Four: Stop Press! At
Last, An
Accurate Representation Of Hegel's 'System'
Has Been
Discovered In
The Basement Of An
Art Gallery In
Minsk
"In the speculative way of speaking, this
operation is called comprehending Substance as Subject, as an
inner process, as an Absolute Person, and this comprehension
constitutes the essential character of Hegel's method." [Marx and Engels
(1975a), p.60. Bold emphases alone added.]
This
is an inner process which is in principle impossible to check, even by one
the doing the processing!
Finally, it is even less use responding (as some have done) that we have to
assume such things otherwise we would be faced with a yawning chasm of extreme
scepticism. That is because the theory itself implies extreme scepticism, as
Essay Ten
Part One has shown.
(2) If,
as some versions of this theory appear to imply, abstractions are produced by
some sort of subtractive process -- as
more and more specific features are disregarded, indeed, as Marx himself noted
(re-posted
below) -- in order to derive increasingly
general terms, exactly who decides which parts should be subtracted first, second or
third? For example, do we start by abstracting a cat's whiskers, its curiosity or its purr? Do we ignore its position or its
number? And, if all of this is processed 'in the mind', who is to say that everyone does
exactly the same things to exactly the same subtracted parts, in the same order
or in the same
manner as anyone else?
In answer to this objection, one DM-theorist tells us the following:
"Abstraction is the mental identification, singling out of some object from
its connections with other objects, the separation of some attribute of an
object from its other attributes, of some relation between certain objects
from the objects themselves. Abstraction is a method of mental
simplification, by which we consider some one aspect of the process we are
studying. The scientist looks at the colourful picture which any object
presents in real life through a single-colour filter and this enables him to
see that object in only one, fundamentally important aspect. The picture
loses many of its shades but gains in clarity. Abstraction has its limit.
One cannot abstract the flame from what is burning. The sharp edge of
abstraction, like the edge of a razor can be used to whittle things down
until nothing is left. Abstraction can never be absolute. The existence of
content shows intrinsically in every abstraction. The question of what to
abstract and what to abstract from is ultimately decided by the nature of
the objects under examination and the tasks confronting the investigator.
Kepler, for example, was not interested in the colour of Mars or the
temperature of the Sun when he sought to establish the laws of the
revolution of the planets." [Spirkin (1983),
p.232.
Bold emphases and link added.]
But, concerning
the example to which Spirkin refers, it wasn't the object (Mars) that decided
"what to abstract and what to
abstract from", it was
Kepler
who did. And, if this 'process' takes place in the 'mind' -- since it is
"a method of
mental simplification" -- all the problems outlined above (and below) will
simply reassert
themselves.
Naturally, if 'abstractions' are cobbled-together by a process of
generalisation, or law-like development, then these questions
will still apply,
but
in this case perhaps in reverse order.
(3) The actual process of mental subtraction is
difficult to conceive, too. When we ignore the various parts of the objects we
are supposedly performing this trick upon, is it like some sort of mental
striptease? But, if we take away too much, how might we know whether the rest of
this ceremony has been performed on the same 'mental' object with which we began?
While we might all start with, say, a
chaffinch, after
its feathers, beak, claws, colour, song, wings,
size and number have been stripped away, how might we distinguish the amorphous
blob left behind from a
similarly processed
Axolotl? Or,
someone's grandmother? Or, indeed, the
Crab Nebula? Of course, if its number
has been 'abstracted', we won't even be able to do that, will we? If we can't
distinguish two such chaffinches from one such (number having been sent
to the benches), we certainly won't be able to distinguish
one chaffinch from two, or, indeed, one chaffinch from
one Axolotl.
Of course, abstractionists are never quite this crude;
they restrict themselves to rather more well-behaved "concepts", "categories"
or refined "ideas", those they trust to 'reason', or better still, to
'dialectical'/'speculative' thought. But, these shadowy beings are
even more
obscure. Does, therefore, the 'concept' of
Kermit
the Frog have legs, a head and a stomach full of worms? If not, then we
might wonder if this concept genuinely applies to him. If it does, we might
wonder even more what the difference between him and his 'concept' is. If
there is none, then Kermit would be no less Ideal. On the other hand, if there is a
difference, how do we know this 'concept' belongs, or even applies, to Kermit?
Worse still, any conclusions drawn about the 'concept' of Kermit
the Frog, or indeed amphibians in general, would apply to that 'concept', not to its
supposed slimy external correlate. This would seem to be the case unless we are now to suppose that,
just like a Black Magic Doll, whatever we do to the 'concept', we do to the real object
it is said to reflect or represent. Of course, Idealists
might not be able to distinguish reality from illusion, anyway, but materialists
would be unwise to stumble into that dense fog alongside them -- or, indeed, adopt a
'philosophical' technique that can't in the end tell fact from fancy, or frog from fog.
Figure Five: Dialectics -- Caught On The Hop?
And how exactly does one dissect a concept? Do concepts
possess an 'objective' anatomy, which any rank amateur can slice, dice, poke or prod? Are there
manuals we can consult, instruction books we can check, experts we may e-mail or
engage with on
Facebook?
To be
sure,
just like Father Christmas, and the Tooth Fairy, the
Traditional Tale about 'abstraction' is deeply engrained in our
(intellectual) culture --
you will even find
psychologists who assure us that we can all construct or apprehend
"abstractions" in the intimate confines of our skulls, even if they go rather
quiet (or indulge in no little hand waving) when asked to fill in the details --
to such an extent that experience has taught me to avoid questioning this
mythical 'process' in polite company or risk being treated like someone who has
just confessed to murder.
Here
is Marx's argument debunking this approach to 'abstraction:
"Is it surprising that everything, in the final
abstraction -- for we have here an abstraction, and not an analysis -- presents itself as a logical category? Is it surprising that, if you
let drop little by little all that constitutes the individuality of a house,
leaving out first of all the materials of which it is composed, then the form
that distinguishes it, you end up with nothing but a body; that if you leave out
of account the limits of this body, you soon have nothing but a space -– that
if, finally, you leave out of account the dimensions of this space, there is
absolutely nothing left but pure quantity, the logical category? If we abstract
thus from every subject all the alleged accidents, animate or inanimate, men or
things, we are right in saying that in the final abstraction the only substance
left is the logical categories. Thus the metaphysicians, who in making these
abstractions, think they are making analyses, and who, the more they detach
themselves from things, imagine themselves to be getting all the nearer to the
point of penetrating to their core….
"Just as by means of abstraction we have transformed
everything into a logical category, so one has only to make an abstraction of
every characteristic distinctive of different movements to attain movement in
its abstract condition -- purely formal movement, the purely logical formula of
movement. If one finds in logical categories the substance of all things, one
imagines one has found in the logical formula of movement the absolute
method, which not only explains all things, but also implies the movement
of things...." [Marx (1978),
pp.99-100. Italic emphases in the
original.]
Nevertheless, this
Emperor has no clothes, abstract
or
concrete; indeed, there isn't even so much as a drop of blue blood in
'his' veins -- as both halves of this Essay seek to demonstrate.
Worse still: there
isn't even an Emperor -- clothed or naked!
This
ruling idea has been
sat on its Epistemological Throne
for long enough; time to wheel out a very material guillotine and do 'an
Oliver'.
2a. These obscure
terms-of-art will be examined in Part Six of this Essay.
2b. It could be argued
that this confuses "individuals" with "particulars", or at least with "concrete
particulars". This seemingly minor terminological wrangle is easily
settled. Unless otherwise stated, I am of course using these two terms as they
might be employed in ordinary speech, where, even though they have slightly
different connotations, are interchangeable in most of the relevant contexts
that appear in
this Essay. [On this, see Note 22a0.] For Hegel, it
seems that a "particular" is an "individual" of a certain type, after some
('dialectical'? or 'pre-dialectical'?) thought has been applied to it:
"To define the subject as that of which
something is said, and the predicate as what is said about it, is mere trifling.
It gives no information about the distinction between the two. In point of
thought, the subject is primarily the individual, and the predicate the
universal. As the judgment receives further development, the subject ceases to
be merely the immediate individual, and the predicate merely the abstract
universal: the former acquires the additional significations of particular and
universal, the latter the additional significations of particular and
individual. Thus while the same names are given to the two terms of the
judgment, their meaning passes through a series of changes." [Hegel (1975), p.234.
Bold emphasis added.]
"We have shown that the determinateness which was a result
is itself, by virtue of the form of simplicity into which it has withdrawn, a
fresh beginning; as this beginning is distinguished from its predecessor
precisely by that determinateness,
cognition rolls onwards
from content to content. First of all, this advance is determined as beginning
from simple determinatenesses, the succeeding ones becoming ever richer and
more concrete. For the result contains its beginning and its course has
enriched it by a fresh determinateness. The universal constitutes the
foundation; the advance is therefore not to be taken as a flowing from
one other to the next other. In the absolute method the Notion
maintains itself in its otherness, the universal in its particularisation,
in judgment and reality; at each stage of its further determination it raises
the entire mass of its preceding content, and by its dialectical advance it not
only does not lose anything or leave anything behind, but carries along with it
all it has gained, and inwardly enriches and consolidates itself." [Hegel
(1999), p.840. §1809.Boldemphasis alone added. I have used the on-line version here, but
have corrected several minor typos. I have informed the editors over at the
Marxist Internet Archive.]
Should this distinction still be unclear to the reader, they
ought perhaps refer their concerns to Hegel's
shade
for further clarification. Or, failing that they might want to consult Inwood
(1992), pp.302-05. [And good luck making sense of that!]
However, from the above we can see that
Hegel runs together linguistic expressions and
extra-linguistic entities (i.e., he confuses talk about talk with talk
about the world), for example, when he says:
"In point of
thought, the subject is primarily the individual, and the predicate the
universal. As the judgment receives further development, the subject ceases to
be merely the immediate individual, and the predicate merely the abstract
universal: the former acquires the additional significations of particular and
universal, the latter the additional significations of particular and
individual." [Hegel, loc cit. Bold added.]
2c. On this, see Livio
(2009). For an extreme version of this view of 'reality', see Tegmark (2008,
2015). See also
here.
2d.
There is more on this below. For the early history of these moves, cf., Barnes (2009) and
Havelock (1983). [See also
Note 29.]
3.
Substantiation for these rather sweeping statements will be provided in Essay Twelve
(summary
here).
3a. These remarks might
prompt some readers into thinking I am a
Positivist,
or even an
Empiricist, but that would be a serious
mistake; on that, see
here.
"Now that Critical
Criticism as the tranquillity of knowledge has 'made' all the mass-type
'antitheses its concern', has mastered all reality in the form of
categories and dissolved all human activity into speculative dialectics, we
shall see it produce the world again out of speculative dialectics. It goes
without saying that if the miracles of the Critically speculative creation of
the world are not to be 'desecrated', they can be presented to the profane mass
only in the form of mysteries. Critical Criticism therefore appears in
the incarnation of Vishnu-Szeliga ["Szeliga"
was thepseudonym of a young
Hegelian, Franz Zychlinski -- RL] as a mystery-monger....
"The
mystery of the Critical presentation of the Mystéres de Paris is the
mystery of speculative, of Hegelian construction. Once Herr
Szeliga has proclaimed that 'degeneracy within civilisation' and rightlessness
in the state are 'mysteries', i.e., has dissolved them in the category 'mystery',
he lets 'mystery' begin its speculative career. A few words will
suffice to characterise speculative construction in general. Herr
Szeliga's treatment of the Mystéres de Paris will give the application
in detail.
"If from real apples, pears,
strawberries and almonds I form the general idea 'Fruit', if I go further
and imagine
that my abstract idea 'Fruit', derived from real fruit, is an entity
existing outside me, is indeed the true essence of the pear, the apple,
etc., then -- in the language of speculative philosophy –- I am declaring
that 'Fruit' is the 'Substance' of the pear, the apple, the
almond, etc. I am saying, therefore, that to be an apple is not essential to the
apple; that what is essential to these things is not their real existence,
perceptible to the senses, but the essence that I have abstracted from them and
then foisted on them, the essence of my idea -– 'Fruit'. I therefore
declare apples, pears, almonds, etc., to be mere forms of existence, modi,
of 'Fruit'. My finite understanding supported by my senses does of
course distinguish an apple from a pear and a pear from an almond, but
my speculative reason declares these sensuous differences inessential and
irrelevant. It sees in the apple the same as in the pear, and in the
pear the same as in the almond, namely 'Fruit'. Particular real fruits
are no more than semblances whose true essence is 'the substance' -- 'Fruit'.
"By
this method one attains no particular wealth of definition. The
mineralogist whose whole science was limited to the statement that all minerals
are really 'the Mineral' would be a mineralogist only in his
imagination. For every mineral the speculative mineralogist says 'the
Mineral', and his science is reduced to repeating this word as many times as
there are real minerals.
"Having reduced the different
real fruits to the one 'fruit' of abstraction -– 'the Fruit',
speculation must, in order to attain some semblance of real content, try somehow
to find its way back from 'the Fruit', from the Substance to the
diverse, ordinary real fruits, the pear, the apple, the almond etc. It is as
hard to produce real fruits from the abstract idea 'the Fruit' as it is
easy to produce this abstract idea from real fruits. Indeed, it is impossible to
arrive at the opposite of an abstraction without relinquishing the
abstraction.
"The speculative philosopher
therefore relinquishes the abstraction 'the Fruit', but in a
speculative, mystical fashion -- with the appearance of not
relinquishing it. Thus it is really only in appearance that he rises above his
abstraction. He argues somewhat as follows:
"If apples, pears, almonds
and strawberries are really nothing but 'the Substance', 'the
Fruit', the question arises: Why does 'the Fruit' manifest itself to me
sometimes as an apple, sometimes as a pear, sometimes as an almond? Why this
semblance of diversity which so obviously contradicts my speculative
conception of Unity, 'the Substance', 'the Fruit'?
"This, answers the
speculative philosopher, is because 'the Fruit' is not dead,
undifferentiated, motionless, but a living, self-differentiating, moving
essence. The diversity of the ordinary fruits is significant not only for my
sensuous understanding, but also for 'the Fruit' itself and for
speculative reason. The different ordinary fruits are different manifestations
of the life of the 'one Fruit'; they are crystallisations of 'the
Fruit' itself. Thus in the apple 'the Fruit' gives itself an apple-like
existence, in the pear a pear-like existence. We must therefore no longer say,
as one might from the standpoint of the Substance: a pear is 'the
Fruit', an apple is 'the Fruit', an almond is 'the Fruit', but
rather 'the Fruit' presents itself as a pear, 'the Fruit'
presents itself as an apple, 'the Fruit' presents itself as an almond;
and the differences which distinguish apples, pears and almonds from one another
are the self-differentiations of 'the Fruit' and make the particular
fruits different members of the life-process of 'the Fruit'. Thus 'the
Fruit' is no longer an empty undifferentiated unity; it is oneness as
allness, as 'totality' of fruits, which constitute an 'organically
linked series of members'. In every member of that series 'the
Fruit' gives itself a more developed, more explicit existence, until finally, as
the 'summary' of all fruits, it is at the same time the living
unity which contains all those fruits dissolved in itself just as it
produces them from within itself, just as, for instance, all the limbs of the
body are constantly dissolved in and constantly produced out of the blood.
"We see that if the
Christian religion knows only one Incarnation of God, speculative
philosophy has as many incarnations as there are things, just as it has here in
every fruit an incarnation of the Substance, of the Absolute Fruit. The main
interest for the speculative philosopher is therefore to produce the existence of the real
ordinary fruits and to say in some mysterious way that there are apples, pears,
almonds and raisins. But the apples, pears, almonds and raisins that we
rediscover in the speculative world are nothing but semblances of apples,
semblances
of pears, semblances of almonds and semblances of raisins, for
they are moments in the life of 'the Fruit', this abstract creation of
the mind, and therefore themselves abstract creations of the mind.
Hence what is delightful in this speculation is to rediscover all the real
fruits there, but as fruits which have a higher mystical significance, which
have grown out of the ether of your brain and not out of the material earth,
which are incarnations of 'the Fruit', of the Absolute Subject.
When you return from the abstraction, the supernatural creation of the
mind, 'the Fruit', to real natural fruits, you give on the
contrary the natural fruits a supernatural significance and transform them into
sheer abstractions. Your main interest is then to point out the unity of
'the Fruit' in all the manifestations of its life…that is, to show the
mystical interconnection between these fruits, how in each of them 'the
Fruit' realizes itself by degrees and necessarily progresses,
for instance, from its existence as a raisin to its existence as an almond.
Hence the value of the ordinary fruits no longer consists in their
natural qualities, but in their speculative quality, which
gives each of them a definite place in the life-process of 'the Absolute
Fruit'.
"The ordinary man does not
think he is saying anything extraordinary when he states that there are apples
and pears. But when the philosopher expresses their existence in the speculative
way he says something extraordinary. He performs a miracle by
producing the real natural objects, the apple, the pear, etc., out of the
unreal
creation of the mind 'the Fruit'. And in regard to every object the
existence of which he expresses, he accomplishes an act of creation.
"It goes without saying that
the speculative philosopher accomplishes this continuous creation only by
presenting universally known qualities of the apple, the pear, etc., which exist
in reality, as determining features invented by him, by giving the
names of the real things to what abstract reason alone can create, to
abstract formulas of reason, finally, by declaring his own activity, by
which he passes
from the idea of an apple to the idea of a pear, to be the self-activity
of the Absolute Subject, 'the Fruit.'
"In the speculative way of
speaking, this operation is called comprehending Substance as Subject,
as an
inner process, as an Absolute Person, and this comprehension
constitutes the essential character of Hegel's method." [Marx
and Engels
(1975a), pp.57-60. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted
at this site. Italic emphases in the original.]
"Is it surprising that everything, in the final
abstraction -- for we have here an abstraction, and not an analysis -- presents itself as a logical category? Is it surprising that, if you
let drop little by little all that constitutes the individuality of a house,
leaving out first of all the materials of which it is composed, then the form
that distinguishes it, you end up with nothing but a body; that if you leave out
of account the limits of this body, you soon have nothing but a space -– that
if, finally, you leave out of account the dimensions of this space, there is
absolutely nothing left but pure quantity, the logical category? If we abstract
thus from every subject all the alleged accidents, animate or inanimate, men or
things, we are right in saying that in the final abstraction the only substance
left is the logical categories. Thus the metaphysicians, who in making these
abstractions, think they are making analyses, and who, the more they detach
themselves from things, imagine themselves to be getting all the nearer to the
point of penetrating to their core….
"Just as by means of abstraction we have transformed
everything into a logical category, so one has only to make an abstraction of
every characteristic distinctive of different movements to attain movement in
its abstract condition -- purely formal movement, the purely logical formula of
movement. If one finds in logical categories the substance of all things, one
imagines one has found in the logical formula of movement the absolute
method, which not only explains all things, but also implies the movement
of things...." [Marx (1978),
pp.99-100.
Italic emphases in the original.]
"With the theoretical equipment inherited from
Hegel it is, of course, not possible even to understand the empirical, material
attitude of these people. Owing to the fact that
Feuerbach
showed the religious world as an illusion of the earthly world --
a world which in his writing appears merely as a phrase -- German
theory too was confronted with the question which he left unanswered: how did it
come about that people 'got' these illusions 'into their heads'? Even for the
German theoreticians this question paved the way to the materialistic view of
the world, a view which is not without premises, but which empirically
observes the actual material premises as such and for that reason is, for the
first time, actually a critical view of the world. This path was
already indicated in the Deutsch-Französische Jahrbücher -- in the
Einleitung zur Kritik der Hegelschen Rechtsphilosophie and Zur Judenfrage.
But since at that time this was done in philosophical phraseology, the
traditionally occurring philosophical expressions such as 'human essence',
'species', etc., gave the German theoreticians the desired reason for
misunderstanding the real trend of thought and believing that here again it was
a question merely of giving a new turn to their worn-out theoretical garment --
just as
Dr.
Arnold Ruge, the
Dottore
Graziano
of German philosophy, imagined that he could continue as
before to wave his clumsy arms about and display his pedantic-farcical mask.
One has to 'leave philosophy aside' (Wigand, p.187, cf., Hess,
Die letzten Philosophen, p.8), one has to leap out of it and devote
oneself like an ordinary man to the study of actuality, for which there exists
also an enormous amount of literary material, unknown, of course, to the
philosophers. When, after that, one again encounters people like
Krummacher
or 'Stirner',
one finds that one has long ago left them 'behind' and below.
Philosophy and
the study of the actual world have the same relation to one another as
onanism
and
sexual love. Saint Sancho, who in spite of his absence of thought -- which
was noted by us patiently and by him emphatically -- remains within the world of
pure thoughts, can, of course, save himself from it only by means of a moral
postulate, the postulate of 'thoughtlessness' (p.196 of 'the book'). He
is a bourgeois who saves himself in the face of commerce by the banqueroute
cochenne [swinish bankruptcy -- RL] whereby, of course, he becomes not a
proletarian, but an impecunious, bankrupt bourgeois. He does not become a man
of the world, but a bankrupt philosopher without thoughts." [Marx
and Engels (1976), p.236. Bold emphases alone added. Quotation marks altered
to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Links added.]
"One of the most difficult tasks confronting
philosophers is to descend from the world of thought to the actual world.
Language is the immediate actuality of thought.Just as
philosophers have given thought an independent existence, so they were bound to
make language into an independent realm. This is the secret of philosophical
language, in which thoughts in the form of words have their own content. The
problem of descending from the world of thoughts to the actual world is turned
into the problem of descending from language to life.
"We have shown that thoughts and ideas acquire an
independent existence in consequence of the personal circumstances and relations
of individuals acquiring independent existence. We have shown that exclusive,
systematic occupation with these thoughts on the part of ideologists and
philosophers, and hence the systematisation of these thoughts, is a consequence
of division of labour, and that, in particular, German philosophy is a
consequence of German petty-bourgeois conditions. The
philosophers have only
to dissolve their language into the ordinary language, from which it is
abstracted, in order to recognise it, as the distorted language of the actual
world, and to realise that neither thoughts nor language in themselves form a
realm of their own, that they are only manifestations of actual life."
[Marx
and Engels (1970), p.118. Bold emphases alone added.]
So,
for Marx, Philosophy had to be left "aside" since it was based on distorted
language and is full of empty abstractions. In my experience, when DM-fans read
these passages they either totally ignore them or they re-configure them to say the opposite of what they actually say -- on a par
with the supposed followers of the 'Prince
of Peace', who enjoined Christians to "love
their enemies", but whose 'followers' then attempt to justify war and capital
punishment. [For more on this, see
here.]
We have already seen what
Lenin thought of Philosophy
-- except, of course, about his own amateur attempts to do some
himself, in, for example,
MEC
and
PN.
4. This isn't intended to be an exhaustive
survey or analysis of these terms (indeed, we have
yet to see just such a survey or analysis from DM-theorists themselves, who seem more
content to repeat the same tired old ideas from generation to generation without
subjecting them even to perfunctory critical analysis, as the many passages quoted
in this Essay amply confirm. The aim here is to attempt to clarify what DM-theorists might think they mean when they employ these
terms. As the reader will
no doubt soon realise, this is an impossible task; that is because DM-theorists
themselves don't appear to know what they mean when they use these
terms -- often characterising 'concrete objects', for example, as objects
of thought, as opposed to objects in 'reality', all the while imagining they
mean the latter instead of the former. Spirkin, quoted below, is an excellent
example of this confusion.
[However, this isn't surprising given the points raised in Note Two, above.
Nor is this surprising given Hegel's own confused and confusing use of such terms. On this,
see for example, Grier (1990). I will examine Grier's
article in a future re-write of this Essay.]
I am in the process of adding to
Appendix B
passages taken from a wide range of DM-theorists, who tell us what they think they mean by
"the abstract" and "the concrete". Here, for example, is
what Spirkin had to say:
"The
abstract and the concrete. The concept of 'the concrete' is used in two
senses. First, in the sense of something directly given, a sensuously
perceived and represented whole. In this sense the concrete is the starting
point of cognition. But as soon as we treat it theoretically the concrete
becomes a concept, a system of scientific definitions revealing the
essential connections and relations of things and events, their unity in
diversity. So the concrete appears to us first in the form of a sensuously
observable image of the whole object not yet broken down and not understood
in its law-governed connections and mediations, but at the level of
theoretical thought it is still a whole, but internally differentiated,
understood in its various intrinsic contradictions. The sensuously concrete
is a poor reflection of phenomena, but the concrete in thought is a richer,
more essential cognition. In contrast to the abstract the concrete is only
one moment in the process of cognition, we understand it by comparing it
with the abstract. Abstraction usually suggests to us something 'mental',
'conceptual', in contrast to the sensuously observable. The abstract is also
thought of as something one-sided, poor, incomplete, separated, or as a
property, a relation, a form, etc. withdrawn from its connection with the
whole. And in this sense not only a concept but even an observable image,
for example, a diagram, a drawing, an abstract painting, stylisation, a
symbol may be abstract. The category of abstraction is contradictory. It is
dead, one-sided, separated from the living phenomenon, but it is also an
essential step towards the knowledge of a concrete fact brimming with life.
We call knowledge abstract also in the sense that it reflects a fragment of
reality, as it were, stripped down, refined and thereby impoverished.
"Abstractions are 'bits' of whole objects, and our thinking works with such
'bits'. From separate abstractions thought constantly returns to the
restoration of concreteness, but each time on a new, higher basis. This is
the concreteness of concepts, categories, and theories reflecting unity in
diversity.
"What do we
mean by cognition as a process of ascent from the abstract to the concrete?
'...[C]ognition rolls onwards from content to content.
First of all, this advance is determined as beginning from simple
determinatenesses the succeeding ones becoming ever richer and more
concrete. For the result contains its beginning and its course has
enriched it by a fresh determinateness. The universal constitutes the
foundation; the advance is therefore not to be taken as a flowing
from one other to the next other. In the absolute method the
Notion maintains itself in its otherness. the universal in its
particularisation, in judgment and reality; at each stage of its further
determination it raises the entire mass of its preceding content, and by its
dialectical advance it not only does not lose anything or leave anything
behind, but carries along with it all it has gained, and inwardly enriches
and consolidates itself.' [Georg Wilhelm Friedrich
Hegel's Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe. Fünfter Band. Wissenschaft der
Logic. Berlin, 1834, Verlag von Duncker und Humblot, S.348-49. (This is in
fact
Hegel (1999), p.840. §1809.)] Seen in this light, the process of abstraction is a
realisation of the principle: one must step back in order to get a better
view. The dialectics of the cognition of reality lies in the fact that by
'flying away' from this sensuously given reality on the 'wings' of
abstraction, one may from the heights of concrete theoretical thought better
'survey' the essence of the object under investigation. Such is the history
and logic of scientific cognition. Here we have the essence of the Marxist
method of ascent from the abstract to the concrete. According to Marx, this
method is the means by which thought assimilates the concrete, reproduces it
by linking up concepts into an integrated scientific theory, which
reproduces the objective separateness of the objects and the unity of its
essential properties and relations. The concrete is concrete because it is a
synthesis of many definitions, and, consequently, a unity of the diversity.
The principle of concreteness means that we must approach facts of natural
and social life not with general formulas and diagrams but by taking into
exact account all the real conditions in which the target of our research is
located and distinguish the most important, essential properties,
connections, and tendencies that determine its other aspects." [Spirkin
(1983), pp.233-34. Italic emphases
in the original. I have used the translation found in Hegel (1999), not
Spirkin's version. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions
adopted at this site. Minor typo corrected.]
From this it appears that Spirkin views the
'concrete' initially as an object of perception -- "something directly
given, a sensuously perceived and represented whole. In this sense the concrete
is the starting point of cognition." Later, when it has been 'processed' correctly, the
'concrete' becomes a
more rounded or sophisticated object of thought: "The sensuously concrete is a poor
reflection of phenomena, but the concrete in thought is a richer, more essential
cognition."
But, it turns out that the abstract is
also an object of thought --
"Abstraction usually suggests to us something 'mental', 'conceptual', in
contrast to the sensuously observable." So, both 'the concrete' and 'the abstract' are
for Spirkin both objects of thought; the only difference being that one is more
rounded or richer while the other is "one-sided".
In which case, it is hard to see how Spirkin's
theory can break out of the world of internally processed objects of thought
in
which he has situated it. Moreover, as we shall see in Part Two (a summary of
the argument is given below),
Spirkin has clearly trapped himself in a solipsistic
universe, a world in which each
intrepid abstractor is forever imprisoned. We shall also see that an appeal to
practice -- or even social knowledge -- can't help break him out of this subjective, Idealist
dungeon.
Indeed, this is the inevitable fate of all Abstractionist
theories, DM or otherwise.
Since
both 'the abstract' and 'the concrete' are objects of thought, Spirkin
has no way of knowing whether or not the 'concrete objects' of this theory
(howsoever much they have been 'internally processed') actually correspond with
anything in 'extra-mental reality'. Plainly, that is because all he has
available to him are yet more 'objects of thought' -- i.e., the 'concrete
objects' and 'abstractions' produced by previous bouts of mental gymnastics. Indeed, he has
no way of knowing there is an 'external world' for anything to
correspond with. Given the fact that, for Spirkin, all knowledge is based on 'mental
processing' like this, and on these mysterious abstractions, these 'objects of thought'
(if his theory were true),
there is no way out of this circle. Spirkin has thus entombed his knowledge in a solipsistically
'closed universe'.
It is no use appealing to practice
to rescue this theory from the subjective, Idealist prison into which
Spirkin has cast it. That is because, if this theory were true, all that each
intrepid abstractor would have available
him/her are yet more objects of thought, perhaps with an extra abstract label attached
to each, such as, "produced by practice", which is about as
convincing as pinning this note on an $11 bill:"This is a genuine
item of currency". Each supposedly 'concrete object'
met in practice will be 'reflected' in the mind of a given abstractor as an image,
if Lenin is to be believed. But, we have already seen that this theory
can't escape from that
closed world of
images. Hence, all that practice can deliver are yet more
images
of practice, as opposed to practice itself, locking this theory in yet
another subjective circle.
Practice can't magically change these
objects of thought into genuine, 'extra-mental objects', since, as we have
seen, practice is
itself trapped in this solipsistic world -- given that practice can only
'latch onto reality' via yet more of these 'concrete objects of thought'/'images'.
Once more,
there is no way out of this Idealist circle. Spirkin can't 'jump
out of his head' to check that the deliverances of practice are anything other
than objects of thought, or images. And, the same fate awaits all those
who have unwisely followed Spirkin into this dungeon.
The
same can be said about the DM-theory of knowledge in general. All
that DM-theorists have are 'images', just like Lenin and Spirkin.
6.
The rather schematic presentation in the main body of this Essay isn't meant to suggest that DM-theorists
hold that there are
no 'dialectical' interconnections between these terms, only that if
there are any, they have been remarkably coy about precisely what these
might be. [On this, see Essay Eleven
Part One.]
7.
On this, see Inwood (1992), pp.29-31, Grier (1990), and Cook (1973).
8.Physicists tell us that every photon, for example, is identical to every other
photon (this has been neatly illustrated
here). Here is how Philosopher of Science, Steven French, put things:
"It
should be emphasised, first of all, that quantal particles are indistinguishable
in a much stronger sense than classical particles. It is not just that two or
more electrons, say, possess all intrinsic properties in common but that -- on
the standard understanding -- no measurement whatsoever could in principle
determine which one is which. If the non-intrinsic, state-dependent
properties are identified with all the
monadic
or relational properties which can be expressed in terms of physical magnitudes
associated with
self-adjoint operators that can be defined for the particles,
then it can
be shown that two
bosons or two
fermions in a joint symmetric or anti-symmetric state respectively have the
same monadic properties and the same relational properties one to another.
[French and Redhead (1988); see also Butterfield (1993).] This has immediate
implications for
Leibniz's Principle of the Identity of Indiscernibles which, expressed
crudely, insists that two things which are indiscernible, must be, in fact,
identical."
However, the above was published in 2011, but French has has now (i.e., in 2019)
re-written this follows (over at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy):
"Now, of course, both quantum and classical
objects of the same kind -- such as electrons, say -- are indistinguishable in
the sense that they possess all intrinsic properties -- charge, spin, rest mass
etc. -- in common. However, quantum objects are indistinguishable in a much
stronger sense in that it is not just that two or more electrons possess the
same intrinsic properties but that – on the standard understanding -- no
measurement whatsoever could in principle determine which one is which. If
the non-intrinsic, state-dependent properties are identified with all the
monadic or relational properties which can be expressed in terms of physical
magnitudes standardly associated with self-adjoint operators that can be defined
for the objects, then it can be shown that two bosons or two fermions in a
joint symmetric or anti-symmetric state respectively have the same monadic
properties and the same relational properties one to another. [French and
Redhead (1988); see also Butterfield (1993).] This has immediate implications
for the Principle of the Identity of Indiscernibles which, expressed crudely,
insists that two things which are indiscernible, must be, in fact, identical."
[French
(2019). Bold emphases and links added. Referencing conventions altered in
line with those adopted
at this site.]
The above
passage has been slightly modified, again; this is the new version [i.e.,
French and Bigaj (2024)]:
"Now, of course, both quantum and classical objects of the same kind -- such as
electrons, say -- are indistinguishable in the sense that they possess all
intrinsic properties -- charge, spin, rest mass etc. -- in common. However, it
may be argued that quantum objects are indistinguishable in a much stronger
sense in that it is not just that two or more electrons possess the same
intrinsic properties but that -- on the standard understanding --
no measurement whatsoever could in principle determine which one is which.
If the non-intrinsic, state-dependent properties are identified with all the
monadic or relational properties which can be expressed in terms of physical
magnitudes standardly associated with self-adjoint operators that can be defined
for the objects,
then it can be shown that two bosons or two fermions in a joint symmetric or
anti-symmetric state respectively have the same monadic properties and the same
relational properties one to another.
[French and Redhead (1988); see also Butterfield (1993), Dieks and Versteegh
(2008).] This has immediate implications for the Principle of the Identity of
Indiscernibles which, expressed crudely, insists that two things which are
indiscernible, must be, in fact, identical." [French
and Bigaj (2024). Bold emphases added.
Referencing conventions altered in
line with those adopted
at this site.]
Of course, French offers his own solution to this
'difficulty' -- but
it isn't one that challenges the identity of quantal particles, just their lack
of individuality.
And,
Nobel Laureate,
Paul Dirac,
made a similar point this way:
"If a system in atomic physics contains a number
of particles of the same kind, e.g., a number of electrons, the particles are
absolutely indistinguishable. No observable change is made when two of them are
interchanged…." [Dirac (1967), p.207.]
However, as pointed out
here, one might well wonder how anyone could
possibly know whether or not two particles had been interchanged if they are all
indistinguishable. On the other hand, Pure Mathematician that he was, Dirac
might merely be making a theoretical point on a par with the following: "If we
swap one number in this equation for another (identical) number, no change will
be observed: 2 + 3 = 5". We can see this perhaps more clearly with this example:
"Two plus three equals five" is mathematically indistinguishable from "2 + 3 =
5" even though "2" and "Two", for instance, are plainly distinguishable.
A
(relatively) recent discussion of these issues can be found in French and
Krause (2006), Brading and
Castellani (2003), and Castellani (1998), Hilborn and Yuca (2002), and Ladyman and Bigaj (2010). [See also the Wikipedia entry
here, and the
references in French
and Bigaj (2024).]
8a. This topic is
analysed extensively in Essay Eleven Parts
One and
Two.
8b.
On this, seePart Three of this Essay (when it is published); some of this material has been posted temporarily
here. See also
Essay Ten Part One, where
this point has been greatly expanded upon.
9.
Anyone who doubts this should flip through
Gerry Healy's writings
-- for example,
Healy (1990). For afters, try
Dunayevskaya (1982, 2002), James (1980),
Zizek (2012,
2015),
Bhaskar (1993), or
Ilyenkov (1982).
Or, indeed, the Mother Lode buried in Hegel's work, which is even more 'bracing'.
9a.
This allegation is
substantiated in Essay Twelve (summaries
here and
here).
10.
This theme will be explored at length in Essays Nine
Part One, Twelve
Part One
(as well as in other Parts of
Twelve), and Fourteen Part One
(summaries
here,
here,
and
here).
11.
This isn't
strictly
true. There are a handful of works in the DM-tradition that make someattempt
(albeit unsuccessfully) to clarify these
terms. Their relevant comments have been posted in
Appendix B.
See also Note 4, above.
12.In fact, Marx doesn't
actually do what he says he does in this passage; he merely gestures at
doing it, and his gestures are about as substantive and convincing as the hand
movements of stage magicians. That isn't to disparage Marx. Das Kapital
is perhaps one of the greatest books ever written; but it would have been an
even more impressive work if he had omitted what few (superficial) examples
there remain of methods employed in traditional thought. There is more on
this in
Part
Two. [Also on this,
see Essay Nine Part One,
especially
here and
here.]
And,
yes, I know the passage quoted in the main body of this
Essay is from the Grundrisse, but that fact doesn't affect the point being made.
12a. However, readers are
encouraged to take note of
these
caveats.
I have added to
Note 1e
above several quotations from DM-theorists that support this contention --
i.e., that they begin, not with general ideas or concepts, but with the Proper
Names of
Abstract Particulars. Indeed,
in Spirkin's case (as noted
above), he seems to think we begin with 'concrete particulars':
"The
abstract and the concrete. The concept of 'the concrete' is used in
two senses. First, in the sense of something directly given, a sensuously
perceived and represented whole. In this sense the concrete is the starting
point of cognition. But as soon as we treat it theoretically the concrete
becomes a concept, a system of scientific definitions revealing the essential
connections and relations of things and events, their unity in diversity. So the
concrete appears to us first in the form of a sensuously observable image of the
whole object not yet broken down and not understood in its law-governed
connections and mediations, but at the level of theoretical thought it is still
a whole, but internally differentiated, understood in its various intrinsic
contradictions. The sensuously concrete is a poor reflection of phenomena, but
the concrete in thought is a richer, more essential cognition." [Spirkin
(1983), pp.233-34. Italic
emphases in the original; bold emphasis added.]
Which is puzzling since,
as we have seen, Lenin and Engels claimed
that 'the concrete' will only emerge, or the 'objects of cognition' will
only be declared 'concrete', at the end of a "infinite" epistemological
journey. In which case, it isn't easy to see how 'cognition' can begin
with 'the concrete'.
12b.
Readers unfamiliar with the style of argument about to be developed might be
tempted to respond that this is just
"semantics" (or even that it is a classic example of "pedantry");
they perhaps conveniently forget that
Hegel's
'pedantic' derivation of 'the dialectic' was itself based on "semantics".
But, they should try that particular objection out on Marx:
"One of the most difficult tasks confronting
philosophers is to descend from the world of thought to the actual world. Language is the immediate actuality of thought. Just as
philosophers have given thought an independent existence, so they were bound to
make language into an independent realm. This is the secret of philosophical
language, in which thoughts in the form of words have their own content. The
problem of descending from the world of thoughts to the actual world is turned
into the problem of descending from language to life.
"We have shown that thoughts and ideas acquire an
independent existence in consequence of the personal circumstances and relations
of individuals acquiring independent existence. We have shown that exclusive,
systematic occupation with these thoughts on the part of ideologists and
philosophers, and hence the systematisation of these thoughts, is a consequence
of division of labour, and that, in particular, German philosophy is a
consequence of German petty-bourgeois conditions. The
philosophers have only
to dissolve their language into the ordinary language, from which it is
abstracted, in order to recognise it, as the distorted language of the actual
world, and to realise that neither thoughts nor language in themselves form a
realm of their own, that they are only manifestations of actual life."
[Marx
and Engels (1970), p.118. Bold emphases added.]
As he
points out, philosophers (and now dialecticians) only seem to get away with the verbal tricks
about to be exposed bydistorting language --
which is, clearly, a form of 'semantics'.
Independently of this, it isn't too clear how such objectors
would respond to someone who claimed that, say, Marx's distinction between the
"relative" and the "equivalent" form of value is "just semantics", or "arrant
pedantry". Or, who said the same of Hegel's distinction between "individuals"
and "particulars".
As I
have pointed out in Essay Eight Part Three:
Even
the soft left reformist UK paper, The Daily Mirror, knows the importance
of using the right words (in this case in an article about the difference
between "migrant" and "refugee"):
"Using the right words for the right things is very
important. It's how we manage to communicate across languages and borders, via
keyboards and tweets and picture captions. Using the wrong words means you
stop communicating -- it means that at best you begin to mislead, and at worst
you lie. For example, Newton's law of gravity states that the force of
attraction between two bodies is directly proportional to the products of their
mass. In other words, apples fall downwards because the earth is bigger than an
apple. Imagine if just one of those words meant the opposite of what we think it
does. We couldn't send a lander to Mars because we wouldn't know where it was,
jet engines would make no sense so there'd be no package holidays, and we'd all
think dancing on the ceiling like
Lionel
Richie was an option. If you don't get the words right, you get
everything else wrong." [The
Daily Mirror, 02/09/2015. Paragraphs merged. Bold
emphases and link added.]
Do the above 'pedantry-hounds' take Lenin to task
for writing passages
like the following?
"'Sense-perception
is the reality existing outside us'!! This is just the
fundamental absurdity, the fundamental muddle and falsity of Machism, from which
flows all the rest of the balderdash of this philosophy and for which
Mach and
Avenarius have been embraced by those arrant reactionaries and preachers of
priestlore, the immanentists. However much V. Bazarov
wriggled, however cunning and diplomatic he was in evading ticklish points, in
the end he gave himself away and betrayed his true Machian character! To say
that 'sense-perception is the reality existing outside us' is to return to
Humism,or even Berkeleianism, concealing itself in the fog of
'co-ordination.' This is either an idealist lie or the subterfuge of the
agnostic, Comrade Bazarov, for sense-perception is not the reality
existing outside us, it is only the image of that reality. Are you
trying to make capital of the ambiguous Russian word sovpadat? Are you
trying to lead the unsophisticated reader to believe that sovpadat here
means 'to be identical,' and not 'to correspond'? That means basing one's
falsification of Engels à la Mach on a perversion of the meaning of a
quotation, and nothing more.
"Take the
German original and you will find there the words stimmen mit, which
means to correspond with, 'to voice with' -- the latter translation is literal,
for Stimme means voice. The words 'stimmen mit' cannot mean
'to coincide' in the sense of 'to be identical.' And even for the
reader who does not know German but who reads Engels with the least bit of
attention, it is perfectly clear, it cannot be otherwise than clear, that Engels
throughout his whole argument treats the expression 'sense-perception' as the
image (Abbild) of the reality existing outside us, and that therefore
the word 'coincide' can be used in Russian exclusively in the sense of
'correspondence,' 'concurrence,' etc. To attribute to Engels the thought that
'sense-perception is the reality existing outside us' is such a pearl
of Machian distortion, such a flagrant attempt to palm off agnosticism and
idealism as materialism, that one must admit that Bazarov has broken all
records!
"One asks, how
can sane people in sound mind and judgment assert that 'sense-perception [within
what limits is not important] is the reality existing outside us'? The earth is
a reality existing outside us. It cannot 'coincide' (in the sense of being
identical) with our sense-perception, or be in indissoluble co-ordination with
it, or be a 'complex of elements' in another connection identical with
sensation; for the earth existed at a time when there were no men, no
sense-organs, no matter organised in that superior form in which its property of
sensation is in any way clearly perceptible.
"That is just
the point, that the tortuous theories of 'co-ordination,' 'introjection,' and
the newly-discovered world elements which we analysed in Chapter I serve to
cover up this idealist absurdity. Bazarov's formulation, so inadvertently and
incautiously thrown off by him, is excellent in that it patently reveals that
crying absurdity, which otherwise it would have been necessary to excavate from
the piles of erudite, pseudo-scientific, professorial rigmarole."
[Lenin
(1972), pp.124-26. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions
adopted at this site. Italic emphases in the original; bold emphases and links added.]
"Try
for once to think over the words you use to compile your phrases,
comrades!" [Lenin, 'Intellectualist Warriors Against Domination by the
Intelligentsia', Nashe Ekho, No.5, March 30, 1907. Quoted from
here.]
If they
have taken Lenin to task for his 'semantics', or his 'pedantry', they
kept that pretty quiet! Clearly, using the right language was clearly important to
Lenin.
Unsurprisingly,
Trotsky concurred:
"It is
necessary to call things by their right names." [Trotsky
(1971), p.56.]
With such
sloppy
disregard for
logic,
disdain
for 'commonsense' and ordinary language, compounded by an unwise
predilection for
Mickey Mouse Science,
is it any wonder that genuine ruling-class theorists dismiss the work of
Dialectical Marxists as unworthy even of comment -- or, indeed, view it with no little
contempt
--, and, more importantly, workers in their hundreds of
millions ignore all they have to say?
Of course,
the DM-approach to 'criticising' this doctrine
(i.e., 'abstractionism')
begins by
taking the traditional moves
themselves for granted, and ends by simply nibbling around the edges to try to show how
those moves are flawed in this or that minor respect or detail -- in the end appropriating them anyway.
However,
when we ignore the traditionalists and
follow Marx's advice, thereby focusing our
attention on "ordinary"
-- or
non-"distorted" -- language, we can see thatit is the
moves themselvesthat are defective. This
entire way of theorising is bogus
from start to finish -- upside down or 'the right way up'.
13.
Why that is so will be explained presently. The
locus
classicus of the modern discussion of this topic is Frege
(1892), upon which much of my own thinking has been based.
14.
Again, on this see
Part Two. Anyone who doubts
the veracity of these comments (that DM-theorists have had to concoct convoluted
language in order to try to fix a pseudo-problem, which they inherited from ideologues of the
class enemy) should flip through
Gerry Healy's writings
once more -- only this time, as punishment!
Failing that, they might like to try to make sense of Bhaskar's, Dialectics,
Zizek's Less Than Nothing,
or his Absolute Recoil, or, indeed, the work of those listed
here.
[May I suggest that anyone brave enough to follow these suggestions has a bottle of
painkillers at the ready?]
15.
One would like to be able to say what
"dialectical abstractionists" could possibly mean in this context; perhaps
something like: "Abstract particulars have replaced general…(?)", but language
supplies us with no useable terms.
One could say that "abstract particulars" have replaced "general particulars", but
only at the risk of confusing the reader even more; plainly since the phrase "general
particular" is about as clear as "round square".
Even so, if any dialecticians want to
"grasp"
that misbegotten phrase, they are welcome to it.
[May I suggest firmly
round the throat?]
15a.Or, we could use
Quine's device:
"➊
killed ➋"
and "➊
killed ➊",
respectively -- the numerals have been put in circles to distinguish them from
numbers proper.
Following on from
Frege, the simplest way of understanding the
Greek symbols used at this site (such as "ξ")
is to view them as place-holders or
gap-markers (the meaning of those
remarks will be explained
presently).
I
haven't used "x" here since it is generally taken to be a "bound
quantifier variable" (i.e., as in (Ex)(Fx); e.g., in "For some
x, x is a warmonger", we are here interpreting "F(ξ)" as "ξ
is a warmonger". Of course, colloquially, "For some
x, x is a warmonger" would translate out as, "Someone is a warmonger",
or, as the next example below shows, in mathematics "x" is a functional-variable
expression.
[However, on the caution required when using the word
"variable", see Essay Seven
Part One. The term "bound quantifier
variable" is explained
here. "E" is the
existential quantifier, and "F" is a one-place, first-level predicate
letter. (These terms are also explained below.)]
So, the mathematical rule expressed by, for instance,
"f(x) = 2x + 1" (which ranges
over a suitably
defined
domain, etc.), maps
numerals (for example, "3") onto other numerals
(in this case "7") -- that is, if we remain at the level of linguistic
expressions.
Or, if we want to speak about the mathematics involved: 3
is mapped onto 7.
In like manner, the linguistic-functional expression "ξ
is a warmonger" maps ordinary Proper Names, not onto numerals, but
onto
indicative sentences -- which, in this instance, would yield
true sentences for
"Tony Blair" and "George W Bush", respectively, but a false
sentence for "Noam Chomsky",
if we replace the gap-marker, ξ, with each name,
respectively, as here:
[This
isn't to suggest that this is how Frege saw things (for example, the phrase "linguistic function"
can't be found in his work, as far as I am aware). I am in fact adapting an idea that Peter Geach floated in
Geach (1961). (See also
Note 16, below.)]
This
linguistic device represents a convenient way of expressing generality,
since the term "ξ
is a warmonger" can be used to map an indefinite number of Proper Names onto and
indefinite number of indicative sentences, using the general noun "warmonger".
This will yield both true sentences and false sentences (illustrated below). In
that case, generality arises from the way we use language, not from an
'abstract' idea/term, or from some mysterious 'Form' or 'Universal'.
At a stroke this undercuts 2400
years of useless Metaphysics.
It could be
objected that the term "warmonger" is vague and imprecise. Maybe so, but that
doesn't affect the logical point being made. The
linguistic function
concerned maps Proper Names onto indicative sentences, some of which will be true and some
of which will be false. [I have said more about vagueness
here and
here. See also Note 15b, below.]
Any who continue to object might be placated somewhat by the following examples:
Here "ξ
is a river" maps "The Mississippi" and "The Potomac" onto the true sentences,
F1a and F2a, respectively, but "Lake Placid" onto the false sentence, F3a.
The way we are able to use such
place-holder
and gap-marker letters -- like "ξ"
-- express formal rules for specifying what can legitimately be substituted for them
with grammatically appropriate terms taken from a formal vocabulary, or
words drawn from ordinary language, depending on the circumstances. In the
above examples, "ξ" holds place
for, or is a gap marker to be completed by,
singular terms -- such as, "Noam Chomsky", "Lake Placid", or "The 43rd
President of the United States".
One-place, first-level linguistic functions enable
the mapping of singular terms -- such as "Tony Blair" or "George W Bush"
-- onto sentences like F1-F3.
Two-place, first-level linguistic functions enable
the mapping of two singular terms onto sentences (these will often yield
what are called "relational expressions") -- for example:
F4: Romeo loves Juliette.
F5: Rome is bigger than Istanbul.
The formal expression
of the linguistic function involved here is the one we met in the main body of
this Essay, namely: F(ξ,ζ).
In this case:
if "Romeo" and "Juliette" are substituted for "ξ"
and"ζ", respectively, and "ξ
loves ζ" replaces "F(ξ,ζ)",
this will produce F4, above. F5 results from the substitution of "Rome" and "Istanbul" for "ξ"
and"ζ", respectively, and "ξ
is bigger than ζ" for "F(ξ,ζ)".
Some
might wonder why we write "F(ξ,ζ)"
this way when what replaces it is this: "ξ
loves ζ". Why don't we write "ξFζ",
which would at least mirror the order of the terms used in "ξ
loves ζ"? Well, "F(, )"
is a functional expression, and that is how such expressions are often characterised
in mathematics, and this convention has carried over onto modern logic. It
isn't hard to see why. "F(ξ,ζ)"
tells us that this function operates on two singular terms, in that order and
no other. "ξFζ" is a
jumble, which would become even more of a mess if we moved to three-place,
first-level linguistic functional expressions.
So,
the expression "G(ξ,ζ,η)" might be used to express the
(highlighted) pattern in
this sentence:
F6: "Paris
is bigger than Rome
but smaller than New York",
where "ξ
is bigger than ζ but smaller than η" replaces "G(ξ,ζ,η)",
with "Paris", "Rome" and "New York" substituted for the three
Greek place-holder letters,
respectively. The order of the Greek letters inside the brackets tells us the order
in which they should appear in "...is bigger than...but smaller than...", and
hence
where the three Proper Names of those capital cities are also to be substituted.
If we didn't
do this, how would we write the above otherwise? "ξGζη", or
"ξζGη"?
Readers will no doubt now be able to appreciate how much
this mess would quickly worsen if we moved to 4-, 5-place, or even n-place,
first-level linguistic functional expressions, where n is indefinitely large.
However, using a modified version of the above, we could cope with such
an
eventuality relatively easily in logic -- perhaps this way: "H(μ1,
μ2,
μ3,...,
μk,...,
μn)".
Try
doing anything even remotely like this in, or with, Hegel-speak, or even the resources
that were available in
AFL!
Second-level linguistic functions involve the use of
quantifier expressions
-- in natural languages, these are noun or adverbial phrases, such as "Every", "Some", "Any", "Most",
"Nothing", "Never", "Always", etc. Since I haven't used any second-level
linguistic-functional expressions in this Essay (i.e., to make such points) I will say no more about them,
here.
As far as I can
determine there are as yet no articles published on the Internet that make this method of
analysis clear or even easy to follow (I will, however, link to any that appear
over the next few years -- or if
anyone brings some to my attention). The best two that are
available can be accessed
here
and
here.
[The first of these unfortunately uses blank spaces for place-holders,
and so isn't entirely
rigorous; the second is rather more advanced.]
Update August 2011:
Alex Oliver has published an excellent article that explains this method of
analysis with admirable clarity; it can be accessed as a PDF,
here -- although those new to this way of analysing language won't find it
easy going. [This has now been published as Oliver (2010).]
Update January 2018: In the last few years several more introductions
to this sort of logic have been posted on-line, but the vast majority appear to
have been produced by University Computer Science Department lecturers, who approach
this topic from a totally different angle and, like so many 'introductions'
to University Mathematics, they assume the reader already understandswhat they are trying to teach! In fact, most of them make a dog's dinner of Formal Logic.
However, the best short article on this aspect of
Frege's work is still Geach (1961), which isn't easy, either, even though it is scrupulously
accurate and admirably clear.
The best two introductions to this way of analysing sentences
are
Lemmon (1993) and Mates (1972), although the
latter approaches this topic from a radically different direction, and
will prove to be far
more challenging to those new to modern logic. The latter might find Schumm (1979) some help, since it is a teaching aid
to Lemmon's book.
To
those new to the subject, it is worth pointing out that modern logic is
difficult.
As is the case with mathematics, one can't simply read a logic book.
They have to be studied slowly and very carefully. Moreover, anyone
wanting to master the subject has to do all the exercises! Anything
less than thatis just a waste of time and effort.
Since
writing the above, I have
just read a particularly
lucid explanation of this way of analysing indicative sentences (although it
blurs the distinction between numerals and numbers!):
"Frege's consuming interest in logic and the foundations
of mathematics encouraged him to form a new and clearer view of the nature of
predicates. Consider operations like that of adding. This operation is expressed
by the plus sign. But a plus sign by itself has no role until numerals are
placed on each side of it; then the resulting expression stands for a number,
eight, for example, if the numerals are '5' and '3'. This though leads to the
realisation that we should think of the plus sign as containing two spaces, one
to the left and one to the right, which are really part of the
expression. We can write in 'x' and 'y' to keep track of these spaces, but these
letters do not name anything: they simply mark the spaces. Being clear about the
spaces becomes important when we want to distinguish between, say, 'x times x'
and 'x times y': the first expresses the operation of squaring, the second that
of multiplication generally. The plus sign and the sign for multiplication are
functional expressions, as is the sign for a negative number. The first two
express the operation of mapping a number onto their sum and onto their product,
and the third expresses the operation of mapping a number onto its negative.
Frege called such expressions 'incomplete' or 'unsaturated.' They are incomplete
in the sense that they carry blanks or empty spaces with them. They are
completed by filling in the blanks.... Needless to say, there are
non-mathematical functional expressions like 'the capital of x', 'the father of
y', or 'the midpoint between x and y'....
"Frege noted that predicates are incomplete in much the
way functional expressions are: they contain blanks to be filled in with names
or
quantified
variables.
This leads to the simplified notion of a predicate which is current in modern
logic: a predicate is any expression obtained from a sentence by subtracting one
or more singular terms. Thus predicates are like functional expressions; one
gets a functional expression by deleting one or more singular terms from
expressions like '5 + 8'. Since '5 + 8' is a complete expression obtained by
filling the blanks of a plus sign (a functional expression) with names of
numbers, it seemed natural to Frege to propose taking predicates as functional
expressions which become complete when the blank or blanks are filled in. This
move ensures the unity of the sentence...." [Davidson (2005), pp.131-32.
Italic emphasis in the original; quotation marks altered to conform with the
conventions adopted at this site.]
Davidson
then highlights the serious weakness of
several other things Frege went on to argue, which means that while he sees Frege's work as a
major advance in our understanding of predication, in the end he rejects Frege's way of
analysing predicate expressions. However, I think the modified Fregean view outlined in
this Essay (but more fully in the references I have cited) succeeds in
circumventing Davidson's criticisms. Having said that, it should be stressed
once
again that there is nothing that forces us to adopt this or any other
view of predication, if they are aimed at solving the 'problem of predication' -- since it isn't a problem to begin with!
Human beings have been 'predicating' for thousands of years so there can
be no problem. Difficulties only arise when Traditional Philosophers (and
DM-fans) try to turn predicates into the Proper Names of abstract particulars -- creating a spurious 'problem' which then needs 'solving'.
Once more, the neo-Fregean view outlined in this and other Essays
at this site has the distinct advantage of preventing predicates
from being interpreted as just such names, in any shape or form. [Not that ordinary language needs any
assistance from this or any other approach to predication (ancient or modern).]
So, there are
distinct advantages to this
neo-Fregean way of analysing predication; several of them will be outlined later in this Essay. However, for
present purposes, the main advantage is that it isn't possible to interpret schemas like "ξ
is a warmonger" as a Proper Name of anything, least of all of an
Abstract Particular
-- nor yet the Proper Name of
any sort of 'mental entity' -- since it isn't a name, to begin with. It expresses
(in use) a
linguistic function (a rule).
This
approach also incorporates the word "is" into the
predicate expression (or, rather, into the linguistic-functional expression),
short-circuiting questions about
whether
or not it is an "is" of identity or an "is" of predication.
[However, as we will see, there are many different ways of analysing such
sentences, especially where relational expressions are under consideration.] No less important is the fact that it allows us to drop entirely from logic the words "predicate"
and "predication",
thereby casting into
oblivion another two-and-a-half millennia of wasted effort, wrong turns and aimless
metaphysics -- at the same time as
completely
undermining a
key 'argument' in Hegel's 'Logic'. No small benefit, these!
The same can't be said about the results
of subject-predicate analysis
presented
in Traditional Logic, which will often confuse a predicate expression
with a
predicate, and represent such 'predicates' in the following way: "Man", "Manhood",
or "Being", making them
look like Proper Names of some sort. So, the alleged predicates -- "Man", or "Manhood"
-- appear to designate, or
name, a class, concept, category, group, idea, 'mental construct', or Abstract
Particular, all of which readings would destroy the generality captured by the
original predicate expression (for reasons explored in the main body of
this Essay). The post-Fregean approach using "ξ
is a man" specifically avoids that bear trap.
Unfortunately, subsequent
Logicians and Philosophers were only too eager to wander blindly into that trap,
adopting something that later came to be called 'Term
Logic', the seeds of which were originally sown in
and by
Aristotle's
logic, which was largely based on a traditional analysis of
'predicates'. The quotations taken from several DM-sources (which were posted to
Note 1e,
Appendix B,and also throughout this Essay), expounding the 'process of
abstraction', illustrate quite clearly how dialecticians have also wandered
blindly into the same trap. George Novack (inadvertently) provided us with a
particularly good example of this (but
there are many others):
"This law of identity of opposites, which so perplexes and
horrifies addicts of formal logic, can be easily understood, not only when it is
applied to actual processes of development and interrelations of events, but
also when it is contrasted with the formal law of identity. It is logically true
that A equals A, that John is John…. But it is far more profoundly true that A
is also non-A. John is not simply John: John is a man. This correct proposition
is not an affirmation of abstract identity, but an identification of opposites.
The logical category or material class, mankind, with which John is one and the
same is far more and other than John, the individual. Mankind is at the same
time identical with, yet different from John." [Novack (1971), p.92.
Bold emphasis added.]
By concentrating on "man" as the assumed
'predicate' (instead of "ξ
is a man"), Novack reduces this word to the Proper Name of an idea, category, set,
concept, or
class, thus destroying its generality, and thereby
the unity of the proposition.
[While
Novack doesn't explicitly say "man" is the Proper Name of
anything specific
(even though it is plain from what he does say that "man" is indeed
just such a name; for example, when he says "The logical category or material
class, mankind...is at the same time identical with, yet different from John" --
for Novack, "mankind" is now the Proper Name of the "logical category or
material class, mankind"), other DM-theorists
do. [Again,
see Note 1e and
Appendix B for examples.]
The
traditional analysis of 'predicates'
not only conflates what is said about certain "subjects" with the means
by which we say it, it also predisposes theorists to think of "man" as
the Proper Name of an 'object of thought' -- since the word plainly doesn't name
anything in the 'outside world', as the late Fraser Cowley noted:
"Since a kind is to be found wherever there are particular
things of the kind, it can have various geographical locations. The lion is
found in East Africa. Lions are found in East Africa. It makes no difference
whether we say 'the lion' or whether we say 'lions': what is meant is the kind
of animal. To say that it can be seen in captivity far from its remaining
natural habitats does not contradict the statement that it is found in East
Africa. A kind is not a class: the class of lions is nowhere to be found...."
[Cowley (1991), p.87. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions
adopted at this site.]
When
we look at this 'problem' through 'traditional spectacles' we seem compelled to search for
something that the word "man" names, just as we might look for someone
called "Socrates" or "Tony Blair". The temptation then becomes irresistible to
look insideourselves in order to try to locate that supposed referent
-- and from this simple error of
syntax sprang the entire body of Traditional Metaphysics and Philosophy of
Mind. Paraphrasing
Wittgenstein: a whole cloud of metaphysics condensed in -- or, rather, distilled out of -- a drop of grammar. [Wittgenstein (2009), p.233,
§315;
(1958),
p.222. (This links to a PDF.) The online edition has the page numbering all
wrong; it puts this sentence on p.22*6 (sic!).]
However, since the use of "ξ
is a man" expresses the (possible) application of a linguistic rule,
the temptation to confuse it with something 'in the mind' -- or with the Proper
Name of something 'internal', or even of something which is in 'heaven', perhaps
residing with 'God' (etc.) -- completely vanishes. At a stoke, that removes the entire topic from its former location in
a hidden, internal
world of mythical and uncheckable 'mental' processes -- or, indeed, from the ghostly world of
Forms, Universals, Ideas, Images, Categories and Concepts --, and lodges it squarely in
the public domain. Hence, given this analysis, the mastery, or the use, of a concept is no more
mysterious than the acquisition of a linguistic skill, publicly exercised and
capable of being inter-subjectively taught and checked.
That
represents another distinct advantage
this way of analysing language
offers (further outlinedbelow). The use of Greek
letters -- as in "ξ
is a man" -- reminds us that that inscription is (properly) to be viewed as
the expression of a rule. Unfortunately, I have yet to find a book (or article) that
outlines the above points (about concepts and rules, or the topics advanced
here and
here), even though this is
a key idea underlying both Frege and Wittgenstein's work. [However, I have
access to an introduction to logic produced by my old University's Philosophy
Department that goes through some of these points in detail, but I can't publish
it on-line. If anyone knows of books or articles that fill this gap, I'd
appreciate it if they
informed me.]
For
those who want to read more, some of the issues raised here are covered in Gibson (2004). Even more comprehensive is Gaskin (2008);
however, I need to add that I don't accept Professor Gaskin's
'metaphysical' solution to this pseudo-problem, but this isn't the place to go into
that topic. (I will say more in Part Two, though.) See also, Davidson (2005),
pp.76-163, and Noonan (2001). Cf., Professor Gaskin's on-line article,
here,
and the review of Gaskin's book,
here. The serious weaknesses and limitations of Traditional Logic are
covered in Geach (1968, 1969b, 1972b). On the superiority of the 'new logic'
introduced by Frege, see
here.
Since writing the
above, Noonan (2001) has now become available on-line; the section on linguistic functions can be accessed
here -- although, the author unfortunately employs
ordinary gaps (distinguished by the use of
different brackets) in place of gap-markers like "ξ"
and "ζ".
15b. As pointed out in
Note 15a, this isn't to
suggest that only Proper Names can replace "ξ".
Some
readers might object that certain predicates, like "ξ
is a socialist", are vague, in which
case, as we saw earlier, we can
easily change the predicable under consideration to "ξ
is a river". That done, the exemplars would now become:
F1a:
The Mississippi is a river.
F2a:
The Potomac is a river.
F3a: Lake
Placid is a river.
Once
more: two of the above are true and one is false. Nevertheless, these propositions all share a
common pattern, expressed by "ξ
is a river".
Any who now worry that "river" is also vague can console themselves
with the thought that just as soon as it has been decided what does or what does not count
as a river, a truth-value can be assigned to the above sentences. Of course, if
that can't be decided, then the above weren't
propositions to begin
with. But logic can't legislate on what counts as an empirical
fact.
However, it is worth adding here that if it
can't be decided what counts as a river, that would mean our concept of a river will have been
rendered useless. Worse still, if we can't decide over something as
straight-forward as this, can we
even be sure
we have a handle on any of our words, including "vague". If not, then the
objection itself fails since it will have employed a word that no one
understands -- i.e., "vague". On the other hand, if we do have a handle on "vague", then
the objection will fail anyway, since we would, in that event, have a handle on
"river", too -- since "vague" is a much more complicated term than "river".
16.As noted above, this analysis depends on a view of propositions I don't expect
many DM-theorists -- if any -- will
accept.
Nevertheless, the rationale for this sort of analysis will become clearer as the argument
unfolds. [On that, see
above -- and below -- as well as
Note 40.]
Sentences aren't names, either. That can be seen by the way we comprehend the former,
which is different from the way we understand the latter. [That particular point is defended in Essays Eight
Part Three
and Thirteen
Part Three;
readers are directed there for more details See also
Geach (1972c), as well as
here.]
In addition, although the main body of this Essay says that "ξ
is made of glass" is general in form, it would be more useful at this
point to regard it as the expression of a rule whose proper application is
revealed by the open-ended generation of true or false sentences by those proficient in the
relevant natural language.
This comment
might form part of a "form of representation".
It
isn't being assumed here that
human beings actually proceed this way -- although it does help explain how we
form certain sentences, and how we make the inferences we do from such sentences. The term "form of representation" is
explained in Glock (1996), pp.129-35. It is also explained
here and
in Essay Eight
Part Two. Its use will be further justified in
Essay Thirteen Part Two. These aforementioned patterns are part
of what we show by our use of language, but which can't be put into
true/false indicative sentences; i.e., this is what our use of language shows
but can't be
said, to paraphrase Wittgenstein, again. (On this, see
McGinn (2001); this links to a PDF.) It might now be wondered how it could
be that we can't say any of this when it has just been said. The answer
to that is quite plain; what has just been said concerns the expression of
a linguistic rule, and rules can't be true or false, just practical or
otherwise. (That was the point of saying "These patterns are part
of what we show by our use of language, but which can't be put into
true/false indicative sentences(emphases added)." That is, these rules can't be said by
means of true/false
indicative sentences, but they can be elucidated by means of indicative
sentences.
Consider someone who is trying to teach someone else how to play chess, how the
pieces move, how they can capture other pieces, etc., etc. In doing this, they
will explain the rules perhaps using the indicative mood: "The Queen moves like
this, and this...". Of course, the rules can also be expressed in the imperative
mood, too: "Move your Rook like this...", "The King has to move this way...",
but that isn't absolutely essential. In addition, the rules of the game can be
taught by practical demonstration -- by simply playing! Novices can even learn
by just watching others play, asking the odd question or two. But, these rules
aren't descriptive (hence they can't be true or false), they are prescriptive.
If, per impossible, they could be false, for example, then some other rule -- such as, "The
Bishop doesn't move diagonally, it moves in a zig-zag fashion, like this" --
could be 'true'. But, "The Bishop doesn't move diagonally, it moves in a zig-zag
fashion like this" isn't an alternative rule for the Bishop in chess, since the way that
that piece moves
defines what the word "Bishop" means in that game. The rules of chess elucidate how that word
and others are used and how the pieces behave. If a 'Bishop' were to move (legitimately) in
any other way, it would be part of an different game, not chess!
Some might
argue that a rule in chess such as, "The Bishop moves like this..." is
in fact true. So, the above comments are misguided. But, if that were the case, "The Bishop moves like this..." would
then be descriptive not prescriptive, making this an assertion,
which could be true or could be false. But, anyone who now claimed that such
rules weredescriptive (and, in this case, were true) would have no answer to someone
else who retorted "Well,
I'll move it any way I like!". Other than an to appeal to tradition, to how the
game has always been played in the past, they could make no response. So, in order to
proscribe the antics of such maverick chess players, "The Bishop moves like
this...", and sentences like it, would have to be viewed prescriptively, and thus
as rules, not descriptions. Rules are enforced because they are
prescriptive. It would make no sense to enforce a description in such
circumstances.
Of course, "The Bishop moves like this..." is a correct (or true)
description of, or assertion about, a rule in chess in the sense that anyone who used it would be
speaking truly about the rules themselves; but, the prescriptive nature of this
rule doesn't depend on such truthful reports, but on the application of that rule, a
rule which
defines how certain pieces must move.
How this might work in a non-Indo-European language I haven't a
clue, but since I am not trying to make a metaphysical point here this isn't
an
embarrassment for the approach adopted at this site. Unfortunately, it is
for the view promoted by dialecticians, as will be made clear
later on.
Once again, this way of viewing predicate expressions might cause
some confusion, if not alarm. Not only will it look rather odd to those not versed in modern logic,
or
Analytic Philosophy,
it might even seem perverse, "academic", or, indeed, thoroughly "bourgeois". Those who might
be tempted to feel this way should recall that the analysis of propositions
that dialecticians have adopted was invented by Medieval Theologians, and introduced into
'dialectics' itself by a quintessentially bourgeois academic, Hegel. [More on that
later.]
Despite this,
the
strength and usefulness of the modern method of analysing
indicative sentences derives from the fact that traditional ways
of viewing predicates (or predicate expressions -- often these two were
conflated) encouraged their confusion with Proper Names
(or other singular terms), which,
as we have seen,
destroys
the generality implicit in our use of language. In stark contrast, as noted above,
it isn't possible to confuse "ξ
is made of glass" with a Proper Name, still less with the name of
the results of an 'internal' and
uncheckable 'mental process'. Furthermore, this way of
looking at predicates (which are perhaps better described as linguistic-functional
expressions, which
map names onto certain sentences -- on this, see Note 15a) brings out the clear connection
they have with rules, and hence with the social nature of language
and
publicly performable and checkable verbal skills. That is because "ξ
is made of glass" is clearly an incomplete expression that requires a
human being to complete it with an appropriate term. The rule-governed way
that this is achieved means that it is capable of being learned, and hence
capable of being employed and checked in the open, as opposed to
it representing a hidden process, secreted away in an uncheckable, inner world of 'the mind', as traditional ruling-class
and DM-thought would have us believe (for example, in relation to the 'process of abstraction').
Nevertheless, it is important to note that this modern
approach to predicate expressions is merely being advocated
here as one way of seeing how we manage to generate certain sentences; no one is suggesting
that this is the only way this can be comprehended or analysed, or that
it gives a complete view of this skill, nor even that it is literally how we do this.
This is
simply a way of
highlighting clear patterns in the sentences we do in fact produce, which factors
also help us understand the inferences we make. This
is not, therefore, to advance a theory of any sort. On the contraryIt
promotes an interpretative rule
that assists in the elucidation of the use of certain key aspects of language. Furthermore, as an added
bonus this approach doesn't destroy generality
or threaten the unity of the proposition. As such, it connects our
use of language with generality through the notion of repeatable rules
that govern the use of what we take to be general noun-, or verb-phrases, which
is capable of being taught (largely by example), and
hence capable of being scrutinised and studied in social and historical contexts.
Because of that alone, never mind anything else, it
has everything to recommend it to any Marxists interested in challenging Idealism.
Clearly, this isn't the place to defend such a view of language in depth
(however, on that see Note 28
below). Nevertheless, the core arguments developed in this Essay do not depend on this
method of analysis being
either correct or even apposite. Indeed, even if the latter were completely misguided, it would still be the case that
dialecticians follow tradition and transform general words into the Proper Names of
abstract particulars, destroying
generality. Moreover, the same
considerations apply
to DM-theorists' use of
general terms in the jargonised,
ersatz
'language' they inherited from generations of mystics and boss-class hacks.
A brief account of the history of the
introduction of the word "concept"(or Begriff) into Philosophy
(in the 17th
century, by Leibniz), can be accessed in Caygill (1995), pp.118-21. For Hegel's use
of this word and its cognates, see Inwood (1992), pp.58-61.
17. That
was in fact the intention behind all the stage-setting in, for example, Sayer
(1992), pp.12-117 -- concerning the 'theory-laden' nature of observation, etc.
--, except in Sayer's case, it was expressed in terms that only succeed in
undermining what he thought he was trying to say. That is, his analysis turns what is a socially-acquired skill (the intelligent use of general terms
in ordinary language) into a
privatised, internal
'process of abstraction'. [On this, see
Appendix B.] [In the Second Corrected
Edition the page numbering is completely different; in this case it is Sayer
(2010), pp.8-79.]
19.
As noted above, DM-theorists
of course
appear to accept this point in principle, but in practice they do the
exact opposite.
It is worth adding here that when I say the following (in the main body of
this Essay):
Whatever is done to try to describe a particular, or an individual in this way,
it will always involve the use of general terms.
I am not denying that
ostensive definitions may be used to help identify
certain particulars, in specific circumstances, but even that will only succeed
if it is carried out against an already settled linguistic and social background where
singular terms function in the way that has been indicated above.
That point has in
fact been made in the main body, but it is worth underlining.
Z1: He had De Gaulle to Adenauer to his time
sheet.
Well,
not a very good joke, but only those long enough in the tooth to know to whom these
Proper Names refer
will perhaps
appreciate it -- or,
maybe not.
On this, see
Note 22, below.
On Proper Names in general, see Linsky (1977), as well as Baker and Hacker
(2005), pp.113-28, 227-49. See also Hanna and Harrison (2004), pp.63-158.
However, I cite that work
with an added caveat: its authors have adopted the misguided 'Causal
Theory' of names. In spite of that, it has many valuable things to say
on this and related topics.
21.
Special cases aside -- such as the reading of a roll call, the dictation of a
telephone directory, or someone demonstrating a feat of memory, etc. --, the
utterance of nothing but singular terms wouldn't be comprehended by anyone -- in
the sense that no one would understand what the individual uttering that string
of words was trying to say even though they might understand every single word uttered.
That
isn't because it would be too difficult for our finite minds to grasp such a
list, it is
because there would be nothing there to grasp.
[For more on the logic of
lists, see
Geach (1968), pp.168-91
(this in fact links to the 3rd
(1980) edition, so the page numbers are different:
pp.191-218); and Geach (1979), pp.62-72.]
The linguistic context alluded to in the main body of this Essay
needn't always be an indicative sentence. It could be a sentence
fragment (clause), or, indeed, a one-word sentence. But, even there, these expressions would only
make sense because of the longer sentences in which they, or their constituent
parts, could be, and typically are, embedded.
For example, we would fail to understand the
phrase "in Das Kapital" if no one had ever used it in a
sentence before, if none of its constituent words had ever been used in that
way, or if there were no place in
the language that allowed for its use -- i.e., if, say, books, or the use of titles like
this, had never been invented by human beings.
[Again, on
this see Note 22, below.]
21a. Here, I am
deliberately blurring the distinction between the meaning of a word and the
sense of a sentence. I say much more about this in Essay Thirteen
Part Three.
[For
those not in the know, the late
Marjorie Proops
was a UK 'agony aunt' a generation or so ago. And, for
the benefit of those for whom English
isn't their first language, the joke revolves around confusing the Proper Noun, "Proops", with a non-existent
verb, "to proop", which, even though it isn't a word in English,
suggests something uncomplimentary or defective about the individual concerned.]
It
shouldn't need pointing out, but symbols don't (and can't)
determine their own meaning; clearly, it is human beings who do that. We may
only conclude the opposite if we are prepared to
fetishise words, turning them into agents in there own right,
which are not only
capable of explaining themselves to us, but are, over time, able to 'recall'
their own 'correct meaning' and then repeatedly impose that 'meaning' on us. In
the cold light of day, while the falsehood of the idea that
they can do this might seem reasonably clear, the vast majority of philosophers and DM-theorists appear to
be oblivious of it and talk as if they accept this doctrine as gospel truth -- that
is, that words
(or 'signs', as we find in
Voloshinov's
theory) can
indeed determine what we are constrained to say by means of them, or conclude
about them. That helps explain why so many think language is a prison, or that
'it' constrains thought. That idea is, of course, just another way that idealism
has dominated Traditional Thought.
[How and
why traditionalists do
this will be examined in Essays Nine,
Twelve Parts One to Seven, Thirteen Part Three, and Fourteen Part Two.]
Knowing how to use,
understand -- or, indeed, in comedy, deliberately misconstrue
-- a word goes hand-in-hand with knowing what
sort of expression it is -- i.e., what station it occupies in language, to
paraphrase Wittgenstein. Eric Morecambe's joke above brings this point out
rather well. So do these:
4) Worker: "Boss, I deserve a rise. I do the work
of two men!"
Boss: "Ok, tell me who the other
guy is and I'll sack him!"
5) Question: "How do you make a Venetian Blind?"
Answer: "Poke him in the eye!"
Wittgenstein once said that a serious philosophical work could consist entirely
of jokes (this aside was reported in Malcolm (2001), pp.27-28). Indeed, he went
on to say this:
"The problems arising through
a misinterpretation of our forms of language have the character of depth.
They are deep disquietudes; their roots are as deeply rooted in us as the forms of
our language, and their significance is as great as the importance of our
language -- Let's ask ourselves: why do we feel a grammatical joke to be
deep? (And that is what the depth of philosophy is.)" [Wittgenstein
(2009),
§111, pp.52e-53e; Wittgenstein (1958),
§111, p.47e. Italic emphases in the original. The two translations
differ only slightly.]
Much
of Traditional Philosophy is based on the misconstrual of ordinary words --
as Marx also
noted -- and that is how and why much of comedy works. As
this website points out, comedy is partially
based on the following verbal glitches:
Misunderstanding:
Joe is holding a large girder in the
round. Fred is holding a large hammer.
Joe: "When I nod my head, you hit it."
Fred nods.
Fred hits Joe over the head with the
hammer.
Pun and Wordplay:
A: My dog has no nose.
B: How does he smell?
A: Awful
To which we might add:
A: Did you hear about the Judge with no
thumbs -- Justice Fingers?
I have added several more jokes involved in
the use of "Nothing" and related words (in order to counter the misuse of that
word in Traditional Thought, and Hegel's work, as well as DM),
here.
So,
the compound name, "Karl Marx", only functions as a
Proper Name (i.e., that is its "station" in language) because of the
way we use it. It isn't a name
simply because of
its reference to Karl Marx. If that were the case, it would be a name before it was
a name! "Karl Marx" is a Proper Name because of the way we use it in sentences
to talk about him -- and
because of the way it was related to Marx during his lifetime and after his
death (etc.), and, of course, because of the practice we have of naming
children,
for instance. But, there had to be a place already in language and social
practice for Proper
Names to be so used, otherwise they would just be noises, or marks on the
page/screen.
Incidentally, this allows an explanation to be given of how words
change their meaning over time. This process wouldn't be under human control (i.e.,
not always under our conscious control) if the meanings of
words were determined by non-social factors. In fact, the way that many
theorists account for the meaning of words suggests that there is some sort of
permanently fixed 'semantic halo'
(as it were) surrounding each word -- perhaps called their "real meaning" --, which
accompanies them wherever they go, and which asserts itself
upon us whenever we employ them. Again, that would make words the
agent here (fetishising them), with us the patients.
Wittgenstein used the word "Bedeutungskörper"
("meaning-body") to characterise the 'semantic halo' theory. This point is well-expressed in
the following passage (taken from a review of
Cultural
Software, by J M Balkin):
"Balkin thinks that
he has avoided metaphysical difficulties by locating cultural information at the
'subindividual' level (p.x),
but in reality he reifies an entity called 'information' that has an extremely
dubious ontological status. Although the author drops Ludwig Wittgenstein's name
in several places, his book is a prime example of what Wittgenstein
unflatteringly calls the
Bedeutungskörper (meaning-body)
method of philosophizing (Philosophical
Grammar, edited by Rush Rhees and Anthony Kenny [Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1978 (referenced in this Essay as Wittgenstein (1974)
--
RL)], p.54). In this method, a thinker's intelligence is held captive by the
prejudice that behind each sign there must be an invisible nonlinguistic entity
called its 'meaning,' even though he can offer no criteria for its existence
that are independent of the criteria he uses to ascertain the existence of the
sign and what people do with it." [Wolcher
(1999), p.297. Quotation marks have been altered to conform with the conventions
adopted at this site. (This links to a PDF.)]
On
Proper Names in general, see Harrison (1979), and Hanna and Harrison
(2004), pp.63-158 -- although, as noted earlier, the latter work makes far too many concession to the
Causal Theory of Names. Hence, it should be read in conjunction with Baker
and Hacker (2005), pp.227-49, and Linsky (1977). On the "semantic halo" theory, see Glock (1996), pp.239-41, Hacker
(2000), pp.83-85, and Shanker (1987), pp.293-99, 316-17. On this, see also
Part Two.
Finally, some
readers might
be tempted to conclude that the comments in the main body of
this Essay depend on the so-called 'Cluster
Theory' of Proper Names (the main competitor to the Causal Theory,
mentioned above), but that isn't so. I don't propose to substantiate that
particular riposte in this Essay, except perhaps to deny that I am offering any theory at
all. Why that is so is explained in Essay Twelve
Part One, and
here.
22ab. On
this topic, see Owen (1971); also see Brown (2003), Barnes (1982), pp.155-99,
Guthrie (1978), pp.1-80, Frede (1992), McDowell (1982), Mourelatos (2008), and
Pelletier (1990). Also see Note 22a0 directly below, as well as Note 22a.
22aa. Of course, in
a restricted sense, general terms can be used to talk about groups, complexes or
collections -- which is why we have
collective nouns, for instance. But, it is a moot point whether
general
(or common) nouns are
'referring expressions',
to begin with. I hope to say more about that later in this
Essay, and in Part Two.
22a0.
As noted in
the Introduction to this Essay, the use of
the word "nominalisation"
here is slightly misleading, so in many places I have used "particularisation"
alongside it. Hence the traditional approach to predication either turns (i) verbs into names,
or
verbal nouns
(nominalisation), or (ii) general names into Proper Names, thus
particularising them as the names of
Abstract Particulars.
So
far as we know, the 'problem of predication'
first emerged in Plato's
work. In the Sophist (261d-264b),
Plato argued that the simplest form of proposition comprised a name
(onoma) and a verb (rhēma) -- such as: "Theaetetus runs". If this is put into the
(traditional) subject-copula-predicate
form -- perhaps as "Theaetetus is running", but far more likely as "Theaetetus is a runner" --, we can
see where the nominalisation of the verb ("runs") into a verbal noun
("runner") occurs. [Plato (1997b),
pp.284-88.]
However, despite what Plato said, there appear to be languages that manage to
cope quite well without a copula, or even an explicit verb, and in which sentences like "Peter
happy" make sense -- cf., Davidson (2005), p.76. On this, see also
Note 22a, below.
Unfortunately, in the Ancient Greek of Plato's day there
was no distinct word for "word"; "onoma" served doubly for "name" and
"word", and "rhēma" for what we would now call a "verb". This makes it rather
difficult to untangle what Plato actually meant by "names", or,
indeed, whether he
committed some of the errors I have actually attributed to subsequent theorists. [On this,
see Fine (1977). Whether or not Fine manages to rescue Plato from the
syntactical blunders I have associated with the philosophical tradition that
descended with modification from Aristotle I will leave others to decide.] One
thing is plain, however, Plato certainly confused describing and attributing with
naming. I
will deal with that particular issue in Essay Twelve Part Five.
In the
Sophist, Plato outlines these ideas
in a discussion between an
Eleatic "Stranger" (who appears to
have been a follower of
Parmenides) and a character called
"Theaetetus":
"Stranger. Then, as I was saying, let
us first of all obtain a conception of language and opinion, in order that we
may have clearer grounds for determining, whether not-being has any concern with
them, or whether they are both always true, and neither of them ever false.
"Theaetetus. True.
"Stranger. Then, now, let us speak of
names, as before we were speaking of ideas and letters; for that is the
direction in which the answer may be expected.
"Theaetetus. And what is the question
at issue about names?
"Stranger. The question at issue is
whether all names may be connected with one another, or none, or only some of
them.
"Theaetetus. Clearly the last is
true.
"Stranger. I understand you to say
that words which have a meaning when in sequence may be connected, but that
words which have no meaning when in sequence cannot be connected?
"Theaetetus. What are you saying?
"Stranger. What I thought that you
intended when you gave your assent; for there are two sorts of intimation of
being which are given by the voice.
"Theaetetus. What are they?
"Stranger. One of them is called
nouns, and the other verbs.
"Theaetetus. Describe them.
"Stranger. That which denotes action
we call a verb.
"Theaetetus. True.
"Stranger. And the other, which is an
articulate mark set on those who do the actions, we call a noun.
"Theaetetus. Quite true.
"Stranger. A succession of nouns only
is not a sentence any more than of verbs without nouns.
"Theaetetus. I do not understand you.
"Stranger. I see that when you gave
your assent you had something else in your mind. But what I intended to say was,
that a mere succession of nouns or of verbs is not discourse.
"Theaetetus. What do you mean?
"Stranger. I mean that words like
'walks', 'runs,' 'sleeps,' or any other words which denote action, however many
of them you string together, do not make discourse.
"Theaetetus. How can they?
"Stranger. Or, again, when you say
'lion,' 'stag,' 'horse,' or any other words which denote agents -- neither in
this way of stringing words together do you attain to discourse; for there is no
expression of action or inaction, or of the existence of existence [the being of
something that is -- RL] or
non-existence indicated by the sounds, until verbs are mingled with nouns; then
the words fit, and the smallest combination of them forms language, and is the
simplest and least form of discourse.
"Theaetetus. Again I ask, What do you
mean?
"Stranger. When any one says 'A man
learns,' should you not call this the simplest and least of sentences?
"Theaetetus. Yes.
"Stranger. Yes, for he now arrives at
the point of giving an intimation about something which is, or is becoming, or
has become, or will be. And he not only names, but he does something, by
connecting verbs with nouns; and therefore we say that he discourses, and to
this connection of words we give the name of discourse.
"Theaetetus. True.
"Stranger. And as there are some
things which fit one another, and other things which do not fit, so there are
some vocal signs which do, and others which do not, combine and form discourse."
[Plato (1997b), 261d-262d, pp.285-86; I have used the online version from
here and
here. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this
site.]
Donald Davidson informs us that in Greek the copula was often
incorporated into the noun/verb phrase and counted as a verb:
"In the Sophist Plato had limited the discussion to
names of human agents and verbs of action, but Aristotle explicitly broadens the
scope of both names and verbs. Subject expressions for Aristotle include both
common nouns like 'animal' and names like 'Philo'. In the Categories
Aristotle provides a list of predicate types (κατηγορίαι -- categories, RL).
These comprise the category of substance (man, horse), of quantity (four cubits
long), of quality (white, grammatical), of relation (double, half, larger), of
location (in the Lyceum, in the agora), of time (yesterday, last year), of
posture (lying down, sitting), of dress (shod, in armour), of action (cutting,
burning), and of affection (being cut, being burned).
"It is not altogether clear whether the predicate (or
verb) includes what we express in English by the copula 'is' and its variants.
Aristotle says that 'health' is a name, but 'is healthy' is a verb. In Greek 'is
healthy' is a single word (ύγιαίνει). This would be right,
but he also says
verbs are names...." [Davidson (2005), p.91. Italic emphases in the
original, bold emphasis added. On this, see also Note 22c,
below.]
"The need to introduce an entity to explain the function
of verbs or predicates has been assumed or postulated or argued for by most
philosophers who have been interested in the structure of sentences and the
thoughts that sentences can be used to express.... It is reasonable to ask why philosophers have not
succeeded by now in solving this simple, though absolutely basic, problem."
[Ibid., pp.93-94. Paragraphs merged.]
This 'problem' is now at least 2400 years old, and we are
no nearer to finding solution than Plato was. Despite this, the answer to Davidson's question is
reasonably clear: this 'problem' is a direct result of the syntactical wrong
turn analysed in detail in this Essay,
which naturally means this is a
pseudo-problem. Since Hegel was one of the philosophers who was interested in
"the structure of sentences" he was simply a more recent example of an
ivory tower 'thinker'
whose 'logic' had been thoroughly compromised by this age old error.
The untoward result of this syntactical
slide was succinctly explained
by Professor E J Lowe (in his review of
Davidson (2005)):
"What is the
problem of predication? In a nutshell, it is this. Consider any simple
subject-predicate sentence, such as..., 'Theaetetus sits'. How are we to
understand the different roles of the subject and the predicate in this
sentence, 'Theaetetus' and 'sits' respectively? The role of 'Theaetetus' seems
straightforward enough: it serves to name, and thereby to refer to or stand for,
a certain particular human being. But what about 'sits'? Many philosophers have
been tempted to say that this also refers to or stands for something, namely, a
property or universal that Theaetetus possesses or exemplifies: the property of
sitting. This is said to be a universal, rather than a particular, because it
can be possessed by many different individuals.
"But now we
have a problem, for this view of the matter seems to turn the sentence
'Theaetetus sits' into a mere list of (two) names, each naming something
different, one a particular and one a universal: 'Theaetetus, sits.' But a list
of names is not a sentence because it is not the sort of thing that can be said
to be true or false, in the way that 'Theaetetus sits' clearly can. The
temptation now is to say that reference to something else must be involved in
addition to Theaetetus and the property of sitting, namely, the relation of
possessing that Theaetetus has to that property. But it should be evident that
this way of proceeding will simply generate the same problem, for now we have
just turned the original sentence into a list of three names, 'Theaetetus,
possessing, sits.'
"Indeed, we are
now setting out on a vicious infinite regress, which is commonly known as
'Bradley's regress', in recognition of its modern discoverer, the British
idealist philosopher
F. H.
Bradley. Bradley used the regress to argue in favour of absolute
idealism...." [Lowe
(2006). Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at
this site.]
As Davidson also points out, attempts to
solve this artificial problem have in different ways motivated every traditional
theory of predication since Plato's day, and hence much of logic, ancient and modern -- and that includes the
bowdlerised logic taught in the universities of Kant and Hegel's day,
which they learnt and then
put to mis-use.
[On this, see Kenny (2006), pp.11-13.
Cf.,
Geach (1972b), George and Van Evra (2006), and Beaney (1996).]
Having
said that, Paul Redding points out (in Redding
(2007), pp.85-114) that Kant had been at pains to criticise the
Term Logic
philosophers inherited from medieval logicians, and that he distinguished
singulars from particulars. A singular is typically supposed
to be something
given in experience/perception (which Kant confusingly calls an "intuition")
before it has
been subsumed under a universal (or before it has been conceptualised -- an
obscure process that
later came to be called the "myth
of the given" by
Wilfrid Sellars).
A singular is apparently therefore a bare "this". A
particular, on the other hand, is always a "this such" (i.e., an
individual of a certain sort), which has been
subsumed under a universal and which has therefore been conceptualised. Hegel
accepted this distinction but criticised Kant's mishandling of it. For Hegel,
apparently, what is given in perception has already been conceptualised
(so there are no 'bare particulars' (individuals) -- to use more recent jargon),
rendering Kant's distinction between immediate intuition (perception) and subsequent
conceptualisation (subsumption under an appropriate universal) entirely misconceived.
However, as argued in this Essay, Hegel
misguided analysis of general terms --
turning them into the Proper Names of Abstract Particulars in a thoroughly
traditional manner -- undercut his entire argument since it destroyed the generality he
hoped to find in his appeal to 'concepts'. He also forgot that we are taught how
to use words related to these 'particulars' as we are taught to speak. So, he
mis-characterised these particulars as "already having been conceptualised" (my paraphrase!)
not noticing, or remembering, he was also taught how to use such language
when a child, he didn't teach himself.
As individuals we 'conceptualise' nothing independently of having been
socialised into a linguistic community. Naturally, I don't expect Idealists to
accept that response, but Marxists committed to the social nature of language
and knowledge should need no persuading.
[Incidentally, that undermines Redding's futile attempt to recruit
Wittgenstein to Hegel's cause.]
Be this as it may, it can be shown (but
I will not do so here) that modern attempts to 'solve' this 'problem' (for
example, those found in Davidson (2005) or Gaskin (2008)) fall into the same
trap. [More on that in Essay Twelve.]
[The historical background
to all this can be found in Tugendhat (1982). So, this is one more "ruling
idea" that evidently still rules!]
Of course, the point is that there is
no 'problem of predication'. The generality that a sophisticated theorist
like Davidson seeks can't be found in the symbols we use, for they know nothing
of the world, nor of how we think, talk or are socialised. As has been pointed out several times
in this Essay, and at this site: it is wehumans who express
generality by
our open-ended use of such words. We bring life to language, not
the other way round. As noted several times, to suppose otherwise would be to fetishise the products of the
interaction between human beings (i.e., words) as if they were in charge, or as if
they
were the agents.
As we will see, this is just one implication
of the ancient idea that the world has an underlying
'rational' structure, that the universe is the expression of the 'word' of some 'god',
that it was created by the use of 'divine language', and
hence that language can capture all of this because it, not matter, constitutes the real essence of the world.
That doctrine was in turn fed by, and feeds in return, the further idea that 'rationality'
properly belongs only to nature and its 'Maker'
-- since the world is in effect just 'condensed language (a belief explicit in magic and
the incantations of priests, implicit in Traditional Thought, for example). On
this view, the world possesses a 'logic', and it is the aim of Philosophy (or
even of Science) to uncover it; truth lies in, and originates with, the Whole and
descends on humanity (or, rather, on a select group of human beings) in their attempt to 'reflect' it.
It is also implicit in the idea that logic encapsulates the 'laws of thought'
and can inform us about the 'deep structure' of 'reality'.
[On that, see Essay Four Part One,
here and
here.]
One consequence of this is the other ancient idea that the world is really a
mathematical object or structure, which is an idea that underpins much of modern
Physics.
The original, class-motivation for the invention
of these time-worn doctrines will be explored in Essay Twelve (summary
here), as will the
ideology that sustains it even to this day.
As
noted above, this
also underpins
the idea that the universe is a mathematical object.
[Again, on this, see Livio
(2009). For an extreme version of this view of 'reality', see Tegmark (2008,
2015). Much of
Roger Penrose's popular work is also predicated
on this idea; cf., Penrose (1989, 1995, 2005, 2011). That is also true of the
popular work of
Brian Greene, an
über-guru of
M-theory (formally 'String Theory'); cf., Greene (1999, 2004).
22a. On
this, see
Lovejoy (1964). [This links to a PDF.] The long and sorry tale is spun out in Copleston (2003),
especially Volumes One to Seven. See also,
Tugendhat (1982). For the early modern period, see Bono (1995).
Cf., also, Gregorios (2002), Guthrie (1986a, 1986b), and Wallis (1972).
On Plato's discussion of this topic in the
Sophist,
see Cornforth (1935), pp.165-331, Ackrill (1997b), Brown (1994, 2003), and Davidson
(2005). [Cf., Note 22a0,
and Note 22ab, above.]
Perhaps the best single paper on this is Owen (1966). Cf., also the detailed
study in Kahn (2003). See also Pelletier (1990).
On Leibniz, see Mercer (2001), especially pp.173-78, but this
theme runs right through the whole of her book. On Newton and the "Cambridge
Platonists" (specifically
More and
Cudworth),
see Koyré (1957, 1968); see also, Dobbs (2002), pp.94, et seq.
22a1. On this, see
for example Havelock (1983). [See also
Note 29.] These assertions will be fully substantiated in Essay Twelve
(summary here).
22b. No
attempt will be made here to justify this latest batch of rather bold claims (but see Note 22a);
however, a detailed analysis of these and other points, and how they apply to
DM, will be undertaken in the remainder of this Essay. Their ramifications will
also be explored
throughout the rest of this site.
Finally, the effect on science of this traditional approach to knowledge will be
discussed in more detail in Part Two of this Essay,
as well as in Essay Thirteen Part Two
(when it is published sometime in 2022).
22c.
This theory is most commonly attributed to the great Medieval Logician,
Jean Buridan (1300-1358)
-- and, I might add, erroneously so. As the late Peter Geach notes,
Buridan
certainly held the Two Name Theory of Predication; but the
basic shape of The Identity Theory of Predication had in fact been sketched centuries earlier. [There is a useful article on
this available as a PDF,
here.]
This
theory is criticised in Geach (1970), pp.22-46, and Geach (1972b), on which many
of my own ideas in this area are based:
"Aristotle, like Adam, began right but soon wandered into a wrong path with
disastrous consequences for his posterity.... Aristotle's [later adoption of the
interchangeability thesis whereby a predicate expression could become a subject
term] marks a transition from the original name-and-predicable theory to a
two-term theory.... Aristotle going over to the two-term theory was a
disaster....
"Aristotle's
fall into the two-term theory was only the beginning of a long degeneration.
Aristotle never rejected the distinction between an expression's naming
an object and an expression's being truly predicated of an object, though
of course his theory committed him to saying that one and the same expression
could stand now in one relation, now in the other. But it is a natural further
step to identify naming with being predicable of and to declare
explicitly that the two terms of a
categorical
[proposition -- RL] are two names. So we pass from the
two-term theory to the two-name theory. This
two-name theory
is best
known in England from
John Stuart Mill's
Logic; Mill explicitly calls terms 'names', and speaks of many-worded
names when he means syntactically complex terms. And Mill's term 'denoting'
simply embodies the fundamental confusion of the two-name theory between the
relations of being a name of and being predicable of.
"Mill was not a very subtle or hard-working formal
logician; his main interests lay elsewhere. The two-name theory has had a long
history and much stronger representatives than Mill. It was the predominant
theory of the Middle Ages, and was expounded by such great men as
William of Ockham and Jean Buridan; though
there was a minority party of logicians who insisted that naming and predicating
were radically distinct, and this minority had the support of
Aquinas.... The two-name
theory is like the theory that planetary motion has to be reduced to uniform
circular motion. Mill's version of the theory is like a crude astronomy in which
each planet moves in a simple circular orbit around the Sun; its breakdown is
manifest. By increasing the number of logical devices we get something like
Copernicus' astronomy, which by assuming considerable complexity of circles
would fit the facts with few notable discrepancies. But just as
Kepler
could sweep away this complexity at the price of introducing a more
sophisticated geometrical construction -- an ellipse instead of a circle -- so
we get a simpler and more powerful logical theory if we distinguish names and
predicables from the outset.
"Let us briefly consider some of the special troubles of
the two-name theory. If what is predicated has to be a name, we get one or other
of two awkward consequences. We may find ourselves recognizing as names what by
any decent standard are not names, like 'on the mat', 'going to the fair'. Or we
may insist that a predicate-term be properly dressed as a noun-like phrase, that
it be 'put into logical form', before we will recognize it as a term, or as a
predicate at all. 'Brutus stabbed Caesar' clearly says, predicates, something
about Brutus and also something about Caesar. A man who has good logical
perceptions will see this directly from the meaning of the sentence. But a
two-namer cannot officially recognize that a predication is there at all until
he has before his eyes the appropriate pair of names, say, 'Brutus' and 'stabber
of Caesar' or 'Caesar' and 'one stabbed by Brutus'. Of course, he then owes us
an explanation of how such many-worded names as 'stabber of Caesar' and 'one
stabbed by Brutus' may be formed from 'Brutus stabbed Caesar'....
"If a proposition consists of two names, it must also
contain a linking element to hold them together; remember
Plato's point that a
mere string of names does not make up an intelligible bit of discourse. Two-name
logicians in fact assign such a linking role to the grammatical copula, in
English the verb 'is' or 'are'. This was a further departure from Aristotle, who
held that a proposition may consist simply of two terms. (The verb 'applies to'
in the schema 'A applies to B' was meant only to give a sentence a lecturer can
pronounce, not to supply a link between 'A' and 'B'.) And so there arose many
perplexities as to the import of the copula.
"For the two-name theory, the copula has to be a copula of
identity. For, in its pure form, the two-name theory says that an affirmative
proposition is true because the subject and predicate terms name one and the
same thing: 'Socrates is a philosopher' is true because one of the individuals
named by the common name 'philosopher' is also named by the proper name
'Socrates'. But it is easy to slide away from this position. On the two-name
theory, the common name 'philosopher' is here used as [the] name of every
philosopher. But if we express this carelessly in the form
The term 'philosopher' denotes all philosophers
then it is easy to slide over to the view that what
'philosopher' denotes...is not any and every philosopher, but rather the class
of all philosophers.
"By this slide the rake's progress of logic that I have
described has reached its last and most degraded phase: the two-class
theory of categoricals. The subject and predicate are now said to denote two
classes. (The terms are also said to be two classes; for the writers who
hold the two-class theory are mostly very neglectful indeed of the distinction
between sign and thing signified.)...." [Geach (1972b), pp.44-53. Italic
emphases in the original; quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions
adopted at this site. Links added; italic emphases in the original. There then follow several rather technical objections to
this theory; anyone interested can now read these on-line,
here.
(This links to a PDF.)]
Incidentally, Geach uses the word
"predicable". Briefly, a predicable is a predicate expression that
could be employed to
predicate something of someone or something. It becomes a predicate when it has
been so predicated.
Compare it, for example, with "breakable" and "broken".
It goes without saying that this Essay
has over-simplified
this complex question; it doesn't pretend to be a PhD thesis! A fuller account can be found in Geach
(1968),
and Davidson (2005) -- but readers must not assume that Geach and Davidson see
eye-to-eye on this topic (or, indeed, on much else besides!).
[A supporter of this site -- who
attended Professor Geach's lectures (entitled The Theory of Meaning) in
the academic year 1977-78 -- will be publishing
at this site sometime in the future the comprehensive notes he took of that
series, which will perhaps explain these distinctions
more fully -- that is, if permission can be obtained from Professor
Geach's literary executors.]
22d.
Of course, in Buridan's logic the usual sorts of abstractions make no appearance
(such as "Being", etc., but his theory was far more sophisticated than this might
at first sight suggest; on that, see the link in
Note 22c above,
and Note 25 below). However, they
certainly do feature in Hegel's work, only
there they
have become engulfed in an impenetrable fog generated by his fondness for Hermetic jargon and
obscure
terminology.
As we will soon see, the attributing term here in fact turns out
to be 'Identity',
which is itself a
nominalisation of the identity relation/relational
expression, in this case, supposedly, the diminutive verb "is".
E11: Blair [some form of attribution inserted
between the two halves] Manhood.
"The
great basic question of all philosophy, especially of more recent philosophy, is
that concerning the relation of thinking and being. From the very early
times when men, still completely ignorant of the structure of their own bodies,
under the stimulus of dream apparitions came to believe that their thinking and
sensation were not activities of their bodies, but of a distinct soul which
inhabits the body and leaves it at death -- from this time men have been driven
to reflect about the relation between this soul and the outside world. If, upon
death, it took leave of the body and lived on, there was no occasion to invent
yet another distinct death for it. Thus arose the idea of immortality, which at
that stage of development appeared not at all as a consolation but as a fate
against which it was no use fighting, and often enough, as among the Greeks, as
a positive misfortune. The quandary arising from the common universal ignorance
of what to do with this soul, once its existence had been accepted, after the
death of the body, and not religious desire for consolation, led in a general
way to the tedious notion of personal immortality. In an exactly similar manner,
the first gods arose through the personification of natural forces. And these
gods in the further development of religions assumed more and more extramundane
form, until finally by a process of abstraction, I might almost say of
distillation, occurring naturally in the course of man's intellectual
development, out of the many more or less limited and mutually limiting gods
there arose in the minds of men the idea of the one exclusive God of the
monotheistic religions.
"Thus
the question of the relation of thinking to being, the relation of the
spirit to nature -- the paramount question of the whole of philosophy --
has, no less than all religion, its roots in the narrow-minded and ignorant
notions of savagery. But this question could for the first time be put forward
in its whole acuteness, could achieve its full significance, only after humanity
in Europe had awakened from the long hibernation of the Christian Middle Ages.
The question of the position of thinking in relation to being, a question which,
by the way, had played a great part also in the scholasticism of the Middle
Ages, the question: which is primary, spirit or nature — that question, in
relation to the church, was sharpened into this: Did God create the world or has
the world been in existence eternally?
"The answers which the philosophers gave to this question split them into two
great camps. Those who asserted the primacy of spirit to nature and, therefore,
in the last instance, assumed world creation in some form or other -- and among
the philosophers, Hegel, for example, this creation often becomes still more
intricate and impossible than in Christianity -- comprised the camp of idealism.
The others, who regarded nature as primary, belong to the various schools of
materialism.
"These two expressions, idealism and materialism, originally signify nothing
else but this; and here too they are not used in any other sense. What confusion
arises when some other meaning is put to them will be seen below.
"But
the question of the relation of thinking and being had yet another side: in what
relation do our thoughts about the world surrounding us stand to this world
itself?Is our thinking capable of the cognition of the real world? Are
we able in our ideas and notions of the real world to produce a correct
reflection of reality?In philosophical language this question is called
the question of identity of thinking and being, and the overwhelming majority of
philosophers give an affirmative answer to this question. With Hegel, for
example, its affirmation is self-evident; for what we cognize in the real world
is precisely its thought-content -- that which makes the world a gradual
realization of the absolute idea, which absolute idea has existed somewhere from
eternity, independent of the world and before the world. But it is manifest
without further proof that thought can know a content which is from the outset a
thought-content. It is equally manifest that what is to be proved here is
already tacitly contained in the premises. But that in no way prevents Hegel
from drawing the further conclusion from his proof of the identity of
thinking and being that his philosophy, because it is correct for his
thinking, is therefore the only correct one, and that the identity of thinking
and being must prove its validity by mankind immediately translating his
philosophy from theory into practice and transforming the whole world according
to Hegelian principles. This is an illusion which he shares with well-nigh all
philosophers." [Engels
(1888), pp.593-95. Bold emphases added; minor typos corrected.]
24.
Again, it could be argued that in a sentence like:
E12: Cicero is Tully,
one particular is being asserted of another. This claim
will be dealt with in Note 24a0 andNote 24ab
--, and, again, presently in the main body of this
Essay. However, on this, see Professor Geach's comments in Note 22c.
24a0.
It could be
argued that it is
possible to predicate one individual of another -- or, rather,
it might be thought that Proper Names can be predicated of named individuals --, as in:
But, in this case, we plainly have two predicate
expressions "ξ
is really called Peter" and "ζ is really called Mount Godwin-Austen"
applied to
another named individual, not two names predicated of either.
Of course, it is possible to say things like this:
P3: K2 is Mount Godwin Austen.
But, this an identity
statement. If we want to analyse it as a subject-predicate proposition, then the
predicate will be "ξ
is Mount Godwin Austen",
which doesn't even look like a name.
To be sure, modern logicians might want analyse the
logical form of P3 as follows:
P4: ξ is ζ,
that is, as a two-place
**first level
predicate expression, which itself might be a partial interpretation of, F(ξ,ζ),
for example. Nevertheless,
the word "predicate" here isn't being used in the same way in
modern logic as it was in Traditional (Aristotelian) Logic. This can be seen
from the fact that both of the following would be regarded as first level
(one-place) predicables in modern logic:
P5: "ξ isMount Godwin Austen."
P6: "K2is ζ".
This sort of analysis wasn't available
to Traditional Logicians.
Moreover, the "is" in P3 would be treated as an
"is" of identity in the sort of Traditional 'Logic' under
discussion here.
P3: K2 is Mount Godwin Austen.
So, P3 could be seen as an identity
proposition or as a predication, depending on how we might want to analyse
it.
Admittedly, we can reshape logic as we see fit,
and agree, for example, that in P3, "Mount Godwin Austen" is being predicated of
K2, and thus that a Proper Name can be predicated of a named individual
-- not predicated of another Proper Name (on this, see Note 24ab)
but who that name stands for. However, if we
do that, we will need to distinguish between those predicates that are
Proper Names and
those that aren't. On the other hand, if we don't draw such a
distinction, then the generality expressed by what we now call
predicates would be lost, and propositions would just become lists. Moreover,
the distinction between naming and describing or attributing would vanish, too.
[There are, of
course, other reasons for rejecting this non-standard analysis; they were
rehearsed in the main body of this Essay. See also
Professor Geach's comments in
Note 22c.]
**As
noted earlier, a first level predicate in
modern logic is one that maps a singular term (e.g., a Proper Name or Definite
Description) onto a proposition; so the expression in P5 will map "K2" onto
the proposition in P3.
"One/two-place" refers to the
number of singular terms the predicate expression will take to form a
proposition. Clearly, it is a one-place predicate in P5, but
two-place in P4. [But, as pointed out in Note 15a,
I prefer to call these linguistic functional expressions. More details
here.]
P5: "ξ isMount Godwin Austen."
P3: K2 is Mount Godwin Austen.
P4: "ξ is ζ".
24aa.
Of course, in his original syllogistic theory, Aristotle was dealing with propositions that employed
what are now called
quantified expressions (e.g.,
those using "all",
"every", "nothing", "some", etc.),
which were themselves subsequently viewed as Proper Names, too! Aristotle's syllogisms didn't
use Proper Names like "Socrates".
This, however, doesn't affect the points being
made in this Essay since it soon became commonplace to ignore Aristotle's strictures on
the nature of the syllogism and populate them with non-quantified propositions.
Indeed, many today who either don't know this, or who probably don't care, quote the
following hackneyed
argument as a paradigm
example of an Aristotelian syllogism when Aristotle himself would have
repudiated it:
However, since the expressions used in Aristotle's
syllogisms were interchangeable, with subject and predicate terms swapping
places, the temptation became irresistible to regard them both
as
Proper Names of some sort,
as
Peter Geach noted earlier. With these considerations in mind, it is easy to see why many would begin to
regard
A1-A3 above, for instance, as an example of an Aristotelian syllogism.
24ab.
The reason why one object can't be true of
another, or even said to be true of another, is that -- to state the obvious --, objects aren't linguistic
expressions (on that, see
here). In order to see help this, the reader
should look at any two objects in their surroundings -- say, a chair and a table
-- and then ask: "Can a chair be true of a table?" The absurdity of thinking one
object can be true of another will now become reasonably clear. Of course, it is
entirely possible to say something true about the relation between objects (and
processes), but that is an entirely different matter. To say that Mount Everest
is taller than
Denali (Mt McKinley) is not to assert the one
of the other. Even to ask whether Mt Everest is true of Denali exposes the
absurdity of the 'idea' itself.
Instead, consider now two
Proper Names:
"Tony Blair" and "Margaret Thatcher". Ask a similar question: "Can 'Margaret Thatcher'
be true of 'Tony Blair'?" [Because of the
conventions adopted at this site, these two
names have been put in single quotes to indicate we are using Proper Names,
not speaking about the individuals named by them.]
As above, the absurdity of thinking a
Proper Name
can be true of another Proper Name will also become apparent.
Of course, a Proper Name will
apply to a given individual -- if there is someone who has that name --,
but the Proper Name itself won't/can't betrue of another Proper Name. Consider
a sentence
used earlier,
"Cicero is Tully". "Tully" isn't and can't be being predicated of "Cicero"; if that were the
case, then the word "Tully" would apply to the word "Cicero", not the
individual, Cicero, which is absurd. In that case, in place of "Cicero is
Tully", we will have been considering "'Cicero' is 'Tully'".
What is actually taking place here (i.e., with respect to "Cicero is Tully", and
if we insist on viewing this as a predication, and as Professor
Geach noted -- link below) is that "ξ is Tully" is being predicated of
the man, Cicero, not his name!
But
don't ask (or, don't confuse the above with this question): "Can what is true of
Margaret Thatcher be true of Tony Blair?" since that isn't to ask whether one
Proper Name can be true of
another Proper Name, but whether Blair and Thatcher can have true things
said in common about them, which would require the use of predicate expressions,
not
Proper Names as such.
[Again, see
Professor Geach's comments in
Note 22c.]
24a. Incidentally, this
theory
created serious 'problems' understanding the nature of falsehood.
If, for example, it is false
to say:
B1: Blair is a socialist,
then the identity this sentence is alleged to report between
"Blair" and "socialist" is rather hard to explain.
And
it won't do to claim that the above sentence is false
simply because the following is true:
B2: Blair
is
not identical with a socialist.
That is because the green "is"
in B2 can't be subjected to the same analysis (i.e., it isn't feasible to suggest that it, too, must be an "is" of identity) -- or
it would risk becoming incomprehensible, as in:
B3: Blair
is identical with
not identical with a socialist,
if the green "is" in B2
were replaced with what it is supposed to mean, i.e., "is identical with"
in B3.
[And,
if we believe in 'essences', B2 is a much about what Blair 'essentially' is as
"Blair is a man". (On that, see
below.) This topic is explored further in Part Four of this Essay, where
we will see that this is one source of the 'difficulties' that all forms of Idealism
(and that includes DM) face when its theorists try to account for falsehood.
This doctrine meant that falsehoods often came to be seen as relative truths,
as we will see is the case with DM-theorists.]
This
is quite apart from the fact that both B1 and B2 could both be true together. B1
would become true if say Blair became a socialist, and B2 is true since it is
always the case that Blair isn't identical with someone who is a socialist --,
for instance, he isn't identical with Lenin or
Bernie Sanders.
B1: Blair is a socialist.
B2: Blair
is
not identical with a socialist.
It could be
objected
that B2 should be read as follows:
B4: Blair
is identical with someone
who
is not a socialist.
But, this faces the same problems; if the two occurrences of "is" in B4
are of identity, and stand for "is identical with", we can surely form the
following from it:
B5: Blair is identical with identical with
identical with someone who is identical with identical with not a socialist.
Or, even:
B6: Blair
is identical with someone who is identical
with someone who is identical with someone
who is not a socialist.
And then:
B7: Blair is identical with someone who is
identical with someone who is identical with someone who is identical with
someone who is identical with someone who is identical with someone who is
identical with someone who is not a socialist.
As each "is" in B4 is replaced with what now
seems to be the rule (that is, "is" really is the same as "is identical with
someone who is", and not just "is identical with"), to give B6, and the same again
with each "is" in B6, to yield B7.
And so on...
As before,
only those who reject the view that the "is" of
predication is always one of identity have any right to object at this point. Of course, those
who hold the view that the "is" of predication is only sometimes the
"is" of identity need to supply criteria that distinguish the one from the other. But
even then, such criteria would have to be of the form:
B8: The criterion that distinguishes the
two isX.
From which we can now obtain the following:
B9: The criterion that distinguishes the
two is identical with X.
Or even:
B9: The criterion that distinguishes the
two is identical with identical with X.
And
so on, as each highlighted "is"
is replaced by "is identical with", and we end up with the same dialectical
mess.
However,
Hegelians might want to call propositions like
the following "essential", in that they tell us what kind of being
Blair is:
J1: Blair is a man.
That is, while J1-type sentences help
identify an individual, that isn't the case
with B1-type sentences:
B1: Blair is a socialist.
In which case, it could be maintained that
one of the core counter-arguments aired in this
Essay is thoroughly misguided. [But "Lenin is a socialist" does identify
Lenin. Is it an "essential" judgement? On the other hand, "Blair isn't
a socialist" also appears to inform is what is 'essential' to Blair.]
What, though, are we to say of J2:
J2: J1 is an essential
proposition.
It, too, must be an 'essential proposition'
since it tells us what kind of proposition J1 is! In that case, the "is" in J2
must also be one of identity; it must stand for "is identical with". If so, we
face the same explosion as we met above, as each successive "is" is replaced
with what it is supposed to be, "is identical with":
J2a: J1 is identical with an
essential proposition.
J2b: J1 is identical with
identical with an essential proposition.
J2c: J1 is identical with
identical with identical with an essential proposition.
J2d: J1 is identical with
identical with identical with identical with an essential proposition.
And so on...
Which means that anyone who accepts this
theory can't actually tell us what it implies without generating such a potentially infinite
series. Fortunately, this fatal defect doesn't afflict alternative accounts of
predication, as we will see below.
It is also worth pointing out is the fact that
Hegel actually used the sentence "The rose is
red" to motivate this defective theory of his; there is no way that "The rose is
red" can be viewed as an
"essential" proposition. In other words,Hegel
torpedoed the above DM-response nearly two centuries ago -- since it now seems
that any use of "is" is 'essential'! [I return to
discuss this peculiar sentence again,
here.]
Of course, this isn't the only reason
for rejecting this ancient theory, which is why this Essay has rather concentrated on the
bogus grammatical moves that generated it over two thousand years ago.
[I have dealt with one attempt to explain what
Hegel was banging on about,
here.]
25. The corruptions introduced into
AFL by the old 'Term Logic' are outlined in Geach (1968, 1972b)
--
see above.
On the Identity Theory of Predication, see
here, and
here.
On Buridan,
here.
it is worth recalling that this would be the case only if E12 were to be read
as:
E16a: There is an identity relation between Cicero and Tully.
But,
E16a is a viable proposition only because of the articulation provided by words that don't function as
Proper Names, as was argued earlier in the main
body of this Essay. [On this,
see Long (1984).]
28.
Of course, this point partially relies on a fundamentally important Fregean
distinction between singular terms and predicate expressions (or linguistic
functions, as these were later called) -- or more generally between objects and
concepts --, which I won't attempt to defend here. On this, see Note 4, above, and Essay
Four Part One.
[Cf., Beaney (1996), Dummett (1981a,
1981b), Geach (1961, 1972a), Kenny (1995), Noonan (2001) and Weiner (1990,
2004). Although I have referenced Oliver (2010)
above, this author makes several serious
errors over his interpretation of Peter Geach's work in this area. I don't
propose to defend that allegation in this Essay.]
Nevertheless, even if this 'new logic' were misguided in some way, the
fundamental distinction we draw in language between naming, describing
and attributing
(never mind what logicians tell us) would still be valid, which more importantly motivates and informs the
core ideas outlined in this Essay. [On the aforementioned distinction, see
here.]
29.
From what little of the record we possess, this degeneration can actually be
seen taking place in the work of Ancient Greek
Philosophers. On this, see Essays Twelve and
Fourteen (summaries
here,
here
and
here).
Cf.,
Barnes (2009),
Havelock (1983), Kahn (1994, 2003), Lloyd (1971), and Seligman (1962).
See also, Professor Geach's comments in
Note 22c.
30. We will come across this
escape clause -- i.e., "their existence cannot be confirmed by any known method,
so their actuality can only be verified by 'indirect means'" -- several more times
in other Essays published at this site, but in more detail in Essay Three Part Four. Of
course, DM-theorists use this 'get-out-of-jail-free' card
in order to distinguish themselves from those disreputable "crude
materialists" -- i.e., those of us who are
consistent historical materialists, but who
also prefer to think that science should be based on evidence not
linguistic chicanery, boss-class ideology, a priori dogma, and
Mystical Hermeticism.
How absolutely awful of us. We plainly have no
shame...
In addition, it is worth emphasising that the import of item (3)
(concerning the allegedly defective nature of ordinary language when it comes to
science and philosophy) finds no support whatsoever from the
following long quotation from
The Holy Family --
quite the opposite in fact:
"The mystery of critical
presentation…is the mystery of speculative, of Hegelian construction….
"If from real apples, pears,
strawberries and almonds I form the general idea 'Fruit', if I go further
and imagine that my abstract idea 'Fruit', derived from real
fruit, is an entity existing outside me, is indeed the true essence of
the pear, the apple, etc., then -- in the language of speculative
philosophy -- I am declaring that 'Fruit' is the 'Substance' of
the pear, the apple, the almond, etc. I am saying, therefore, that to be an
apple is not essential to the apple; that what is essential to these things is
not their real existence, perceptible to the senses, but the essence that I have
abstracted from them and then foisted on them, the essence of my idea -- 'Fruit'….
Particular real fruits are no more than semblances whose true essence is
'the substance' -- 'Fruit'….
"Having reduced the different
real fruits to the one 'fruit' of abstraction -- 'the Fruit',
speculation must, in order to attain some semblance of real content, try somehow
to find its way back from 'the Fruit', from the Substance to the
diverse, ordinary real fruits, the pear, the apple, the almond etc. It is
as hard to produce real fruits from the abstract idea 'the Fruit' as it
is easy to produce this abstract idea from real fruits. Indeed, it is impossible
to arrive at the opposite of an abstraction without relinquishing
the abstraction….
"The main interest for the
speculative philosopher is therefore to produce the existence of the real
ordinary fruits and to say in some mysterious way that there are apples, pears,
almonds and raisins. But the apples, pears, almonds and raisins that we
rediscover in the speculative world are nothing but semblances of apples,
semblances of pears, semblances of almonds and semblances
of raisins, for they are moments in the life of 'the Fruit', this
abstract creation of the mind, and therefore themselves abstract
creations of the mind…. When you return from the abstraction, the
supernatural creation of the mind, 'the Fruit', to real natural
fruits, you give on the contrary the natural fruits a supernatural significance
and transform them into sheer abstractions. Your main interest is then to point
out the unity of 'the Fruit' in all the manifestations of its
life…that is, to show the mystical interconnection between these fruits,
how in each of them 'the Fruit' realizes itself by degrees and
necessarily progresses, for instance, from its existence as a raisin to its
existence as an almond. Hence the value of the ordinary fruits no longer
consists in their natural qualities, but in their speculative
quality, which gives each of them a definite place in the life-process of 'the
Absolute Fruit'.
"The ordinary man does not
think he is saying anything extraordinary when he states that there are apples
and pears. But when the philosopher expresses their existence in the speculative
way he says something extraordinary. He performs a miracle by
producing the real natural objects, the apple, the pear, etc., out of the
unreal creation of the mind 'the Fruit'….
"It goes without saying that
the speculative philosopher accomplishes this continuous creation only by
presenting universally known qualities of the apple, the pear, etc., which exist
in reality, as determining features invented by him, by giving the
names of the real things to what abstract reason alone can create, to
abstract formulas of reason, finally, by declaring his own activity, by
which he passes from the idea of an apple to the idea of a pear, to be
the self-activity of the Absolute Subject, 'the Fruit'.
"In the
speculative way of speaking, this operation is called comprehending Substance
as Subject, as an inner process, as an Absolute Person, and
this comprehension constitutes the essential character of Hegel's
method." [Marx and Engels (1975a),
pp.57-60. Emphases in the original.]
I make no
apologies for quoting the
above passage at length again since it
almost single-handedly demolishes the DM-theory of abstraction. It is a pity that in later life Marx and Engels seem to
have lost touch with the
philosophical clarity they revealed in this early work. In many respects
this quotation anticipates much of
Frege and Wittgenstein's approach to 'abstract ideas', even
if what they had to say was expressed in a completely different philosophical idiom.
So, instead of Marx and Engels aping the methods of Traditional Thinkers, here
we find them repeatedly using ordinary terms to ridicule the bizarre
conclusions drawn by them. Indeed, they counterpose everyday
language to the obscure terminology invented by such theorists.
"The ordinary man does not
think he is saying anything extraordinary when he states that there are apples
and pears. But when the philosopher expresses their existence in the speculative
way he says something extraordinary. He performs a miracle by
producing the real natural objects, the apple, the pear, etc., out of the
unreal creation of the mind 'the Fruit'." [Ibid. Bold added.]
This, of
course, echoes another, and
even more apposite
passage from the German Ideology:
"For philosophers, one of the most difficult
tasks is to descend from the world of thought to the actual world.
Language is the immediate actuality of thought. Just as philosophers
have given thought an independent existence, so they had to make language into
an independent realm. This is the secret of philosophical language, in which
thoughts in the form of words have their own content. The problem of descending
from the world of thoughts to the actual world is turned into the problem of
descending from language to life.
"We have shown that thoughts and ideas acquire an
independent existence in consequence of the personal circumstances and relations
of individuals acquiring independent existence. We have shown that exclusive,
systematic occupation with these thoughts on the part of ideologists and
philosophers, and hence the systematisation of these thoughts, is a consequence
of division of labour, and that, in particular, German philosophy is a
consequence of German petty-bourgeois conditions. The philosophers would only
have to dissolve their language into the ordinary language, from which it is
abstracted, to recognise it as the distorted language of the actual world, and
to realise that neither thoughts nor language in themselves form a realm of
their own, that they are only manifestations of actual life." [Marx
and Engels (1970), p.118. Bold emphases alone added.]
The example set by Marx and Engels
here (when their minds were young and
strong) I have
tried to emulate in this Essay and at this site. In which case, any readers who find fault with my approach should rather
re-direct their fire at the young Marx and Engels for their attempt to
re-focus our attention
on
ordinary language, an away from the distorted,
rarefied abstractions of
boss-class Philosophers.
31.
Attentive readers will no doubt have noticed that LIMPE readily collapses into
LIE.
More on that
presently.
31a.
This is an allusion to "Mitochondrial Eve",
the hypothesised ancestral mother of us all. However, in this case, what we
might claim to know about all that has existed, or could exist, has been spun from
this mythical character, John, and his
'inner being' by the simple expedient of running a single sentence about him
through a Dialectical Mangle.
John can indeed be likened to the
Cosmic Egg of classical mysticism.
And so are you!
So are we all! Any subject-predicate sentence about each and every one of us which uses that
innocent-looking verb, "is", implies the same about any and all of humanity,
and the rest of the entire universe. We are
the same as Mythical John. We are all unwitting conduits for such easily-won
'Super-Knowledge'.
It is only
your unwise adherence to 'commonsense', 'formal
thinking' and a
failure to 'understand' dialectics that prevents you, dear reader, from seeing
this simple fact for yourself!
"The
Judgmentis the notion in its particularity, as a
connection which is also a distinguishing of its functions, which are put as
independent and yet as identical with themselves not with one another. One's first impression about the Judgment is the
independence of the two extremes, the subject and the predicate. The former we
take to be a thing or term per se, and the predicate a general term
outside the said subject and somewhere in our heads. The next point is for us to
bring the latter into combination with the former, and in this way frame a
Judgment. The copula 'is', however, enunciates the predicate of the
subject, and so that external subjective subsumption is again put in abeyance,
and the Judgment taken as a determination of the object itself. The etymological
meaning of the Judgment (Urtheil) in German goes deeper, as it were
declaring the unity of the notion to be primary, and its distinction to be the
original partition. And that is what the Judgment really is.
"In its abstract terms a Judgment is expressible
in the proposition: 'The individual is the universal.' These are the terms under
which the subject and the predicate first confront each other, when the
functions of the notion are taken in their immediate character or first
abstraction. (Propositions such as, 'The particular is the universal', and 'The
individual is the particular', belong to the further specialisation of the
judgment.) It shows a strange want of observation in the logic-books, that in
none of them is the fact stated, that in every judgment there is still a
statement made, as, The individual is the universal, or still more definitely,
The subject is the predicate (e.g. God is absolute spirit). No doubt there is
also a distinction between terms like individual and universal, subject and
predicate: but it is none the less the universal fact, that every judgment
states them to be identical.
"The copula 'is' springs from the nature of the
notion, to be self-identical even in parting with its own. The individual and
universal are its constituents, and therefore characters which cannot be
isolated. The earlier categories (of reflection) in their correlations also
refer to one another: but their interconnection is only 'having' and not 'being', i.e. it is not the identity which is realised as identity or
universality. In the judgment, therefore, for the first time there is seen the
genuine particularity of the notion: for it is the speciality or distinguishing
of the latter, without thereby losing universality.
"Judgments are generally
looked upon as combinations of notions, and, be it added, of heterogeneous
notions. This theory of judgment is correct, so far as it implies that it is the
notion which forms the presupposition of the judgment, and which in the judgment
comes up under the form of difference. But on the other hand, it is false to
speak of notions differing in kind. The notion, although concrete, is still as a
notion essentially one, and the functions which it contains are not different
kinds of it. It is equally false to speak of a combination of the two sides in
the judgment, if we understand the term 'combination' to imply the independent
existence of the combining members apart from the combination. The same external
view of their nature is more forcibly apparent when judgments are described as
produced by the ascription of a predicate to the subject.
"Language like this looks
upon the subject as self-subsistent outside, and the predicate as found
somewhere in our head. Such a conception of the relation between subject and
predicate however is at once contradicted by the copula 'is'. By saying 'This
rose is red', or 'This picture is beautiful', we declare, that it is not we who
from outside attach beauty to the picture or redness to the rose, but that these
are the characteristics proper to these objects. An additional fault in the way
in which Formal Logic conceives the judgment is, that it makes the judgment look
as if it were something merely contingent, and does not offer any proof for the
advance from notion on to judgment. For the notion does not, as understanding
supposes, stand still in its own immobility. It is rather an infinite form, of
boundless activity, as it were the punctum saliens of all vitality, and
thereby self-differentiating.
"This disruption of the
notion into the difference of its constituent functions -- a disruption imposed
by the native act of the notion -- is the judgment. A judgment therefore means
the particularising of the notion. No doubt the notion is implicitly the
particular. But in the notion as notion the particular is not yet explicit, and
still remains in transparent unity with the universal. Thus, for example, as
we remarked before (§160n),
the germ of a plant contains its particular, such as root, branches, leaves,
etc.: but these details are at first present only potentially, and are not
realised till the germ uncloses. This unclosing is, as it were, the judgment of
the plant. The illustration may also serve to show how neither the notion nor
the judgment are merely found in our head, or merely framed by us. The notion is
the very heart of things, and makes them what they are. To form a notion of an
object means therefore to become aware of its notion: and when we proceed to a
criticism or judgment of the object, we are not performing a subjective act, and
merely ascribing this or that predicate to the object. We are, on the contrary,
observing the object in the specific character imposed by its notion.
"The Judgment is usually taken in a subjective
sense as an operation and a form, occurring merely in self-conscious thought.
This distinction, however, has no existence on purely logical principles, by which the judgment is
taken in the quite universal signification that all things are a judgment. That
is to say, they are individuals which are a universality or inner nature in
themselves -- a universal which is individualised. Their universality and
individuality are distinguished, but the one is at the same time identical with
the other.
"The interpretation of the judgment, according to
which it is assumed to be merely subjective, as if we ascribed a predicate to a
subject is contradicted by the decidedly objective expression of the judgment. The rose
is red;
Gold is a metal. It is not by us that something is first
ascribed to them. A judgment is however distinguished from a proposition. The
latter contains a statement about the subject, which does not stand to it in any
universal relationship, but expresses some single action, or some state, or the
like. Thus, 'Caesar was born at Rome in such and such a year waged war in Gaul
for ten years, crossed the Rubicon, etc.', are propositions, but not judgments.
Again it is absurd to say that such statements as 'I slept well last night' or
'Present arms!' may be turned into the form of a judgment. 'A carriage is passing
by' should be a judgment, and a subjective one at best, only if it were
doubtful, whether the passing object was a carriage, or whether it and not
rather the point of observation was in motion: in short, only if it were desired
to specify a conception which was still short of appropriate specification....
"The abstract terms of the judgement, 'The
individual is the universal', present the subject (as negatively self-relating)
as what is immediately concrete, while the predicate is what is
abstract, indeterminate, in short the universal. But the two elements are
connected together by an 'is': and thus the predicate (in its universality) must
also contain the speciality of the subject, must, in short, have particularity: and
so is realised the identity between subject and predicate; which being thus
unaffected by this difference in form, is the content." [Hegel (1975),
pp.230-34,
§§166-169. Italic emphasis in the original;
bold emphases added. Several paragraphs merged.]
This passage will be analysed
extensively in Essay Twelve. [See also
below,
here and
here.]
I have
moved
a longer passage from Hegel (1999), which develops this point in more detail (that used to be here) to the
Appendix. [And, good luck to anyone trying to understand it!]
32.
One or more of these ideas can be found in the
writings of the
Scholastics, as well as the works of Leibniz,
Kant and Hegel. Alas, they are still being promoted in the books and articles of
rather too many modern logicians and philosophers. [On this, see Peter Geach's comments
above.]
33. Again,
that
is because John is not Julius Caesar, not Ghandi, not George W Bush,
not the
youth at the supermarket
checkout, not a vegetable, not a planet, not…
'Spinoza's
Greedy Principle' (henceforth,
"SGP" -- in Hegelian terms: "every determination is also a
negation") is now sent in off the bench since it supposedly helps
distinguish John
from everything else in the universe, while at the same time connecting him with the
rest of humanity. The argument appears to be that whatever identifies and differentiates
humanity indirectly identifies
and differentiates John, too, and
vice versa.
Even though he is fictional, John now comes to symbolise all that is true of human beings,
and indeed, ultimately, all that is true of every last particle in the entire universe,
each in its own way.
But,
this 'principle' (which was in fact a throw-away line in one of
Spinoza's letters!) is "greedy" since its appetite is boundless and
impossible to contain. That is because John is also not Santa Claus, just
as he is not the first man to eat Madagascar, not the saliva on
Jabba the Hutt's
chin, not the last person to see
Lord Lucan alive... The SGP now allows those so
minded to link John with anything that can be named or
described, no matter how strange this connection might seem; it is considered
a viable connection just so
long as a negative particle can be attached to it in the above manner.
Clearly, this has disastrous consequences for the DM-Totality; on the basis of shaky logic like this (i.e., that every 'determination is also
a negation'), the DM-Totality must contain some rather bizarre 'beings' -- in fact, it must contain every weird item
imaginable, all of which
supposedly define John!
It
could be replied that these determinations don't imply
the existence of these 'weird and wonderful' entities. However, as we will see in Essays Eight
Part Three and Eleven
Parts One and
Two, the SGP isn't so easily
tamed.
[I have also dealt with the objection
that Hegel in fact argued that we can't just use negation "arbitrarily", so the above
comments, and those below, are thoroughly misguided,
here.]
This
shows that the SGP is not just a completely useless principle, it is inimical to
genuine materialism, into the bargain. No good complaining that this is ridiculous; the SGP
is ravenous and will eat such complaints for breakfast -- it having been granted a stomach that can contain more than the
entire universe,
courtesy of
the fertile imagination of a handful of Idealists and Mystics.
This is quite apart from the fact that the SGP confuses what we
might be trying to say with the means by which we say it -- the
message for the medium. That is, of course, about as sensible as confusing the
food you eat with the frying pan you used to cook it, or with the farm that
originally produced it!
Even
worse, the SGP
-- which neither Hegel nor Spinoza even so much
as attempted to prove, justify, or defend -- falls foul of the analysis of
language developed in Essay Twelve
Part One, summarised
here. [More about this in Essay Twelve Part Five.]
In
fact, for Spinoza and for Hegel, the SGP was really about the indeterminate
nature of 'God', in relation to 'whom' everything in the universe is a negation:
"How
precisely is the view of infinity as negation of negation (i.e., negation of the
finite) related to Spinoza's understanding of determinatio negatio est?
The following passage from Hegel's 1816 review of
Jacobi's Werke seems to be crucial in this context. Notice that in
the second sentence of the passage Hegel points out a major shortcoming
of Spinoza's formula:
'Everything depends here on the correct understanding of the status and
significance of negativity. If it is taken only to be the determinateness of
finite things (omnis determinatio est negatio), then we are already
thinking of it outside of absolute substance and have allowed finite things to
fall outside of it; our imagination maintains them outside of absolute
substance. Conceived of in this way, however, negation fails to be seen as
internal to the infinite or internal to substance, which is supposed
rather to be the sublated being of finite things. -- Yet the manner in which
negation is internal to substance has in fact thus already been said....
Substance is supposed to be the sublation of the finite, and that is just to say
that it is the negation of negation, since it is precisely negation which
we took to be definitive of the finite.' [The author is here quoting Hegel's
Heidelberg Writings, pp.8-9 -- RL.]
"Hegel's main point seems to be that
one cannot introduce negations arbitrarily into the substance, unless
they are already contained in the very notion of substance (in fact, nothing
should be externally introduced into substance since substance is supposed to be
self-sufficient). According to Hegel's reading, Spinoza's claim that finite
things are mere negations of the infinite is inexplicable since Spinoza cannot
explain the origin of these negations. Hegel frequently charges Spinoza
with introducing modes and attributes arbitrarily without providing any
explanation how they develop from the substance. In a similar manner,
Schelling argues, 'one still naturally demands to know how these limitations
of being get into [Spinoza's] God.' Since negation cannot be arbitrarily (or
externally) introduced into the substance, the substance must contain it in its
very essence. According to Hegel, this essential negative element of the
substance is the negation of finite things (as negation of negation). As a
result, one must expand the domain of the 'every determination is negation'
formula, and affirm that even the substance (the infinite) is also what it is by
virtue of negating what it is not. In other words, negativity must not be 'taken
only to be the determinateness of finite things.'" [Melamed
(2015), pp.181-82. Formatting and quotation marks altered to conform with
the conventions adopted at this site. Links added.]
As
usual, much of this is as clear as mud (I am not referring here to
Professor Melamed's commentary, but to the obscure ideas we find in Hegel!).
Here
is Hegel himself:
"With regard to the determinate, Spinoza
established this thesis: omnis determinatio est negatio [all
determination is negation -- RL]. Hence only the non-particularized or the
universal is. It alone is what is substantial and therefore truly actual. As
a singular thing, the soul or the mind is something limited. It is by negation
that a singular thing is. Therefore [the singular thing] does not have genuine
actuality. This on the whole is Spinoza's idea." [Quoted in
Melamed (2015), p.179. Bold emphasis alone
added. Professor Melamed attributes this passage to Hegel (1995b), p.154,
however I can't find it on the page he cites, nor in the section on Spinoza,
pp.252-90. A Google search also failed
to locate it. In an e-mail reply, Professor Melamed said that the reference in
his article is slightly inaccurate. He thinks the correct reference should be to
p.154 of the Oxford edition of the Lectures on the History of Philosophy,
1825-26, volume III, not the University of Nebraska edition which I have
referenced as Hegel (1995b). Both editions are, apparently, substantially
different, having been based on separate students' lecture notes. I haven't yet
been able to check the Oxford edition. If anyone knows a different source for
this passage, please
let me know.]
"[F]or of a truth there exists the One into
which everything enters, in order to be absorbed, but out of which nothing
comes. For as Spinoza has set up the great proposition, all determination
implies negation (supra, p. 267), and as of everything, even of thought in
contrast to extension, it may be shown that it is determined and finite, what is
essential in it rests upon negation. Therefore
God alone is the positive, the affirmative, and consequently the one substance;
all other things, on the contrary, are only modifications of this substance, and
are nothing in and for themselves. Simple determination or negation belongs
only to form, but is quite another thing from absolute determinateness or
negativity, which is absolute form; in this way of looking at it negation is the
negation of negation, and therefore true affirmation. This negative
self-conscious moment, the movement of knowledge, which pursues its way in the
thought which is present before us, is however certainly lacking to the content
of Spinoza's philosophy, or at least it is only externally associated with it,
since it falls within self-consciousness. That is to say, thoughts form the
content, but they are not self-conscious thoughts or Notions: the content
signifies thought, as pure abstract self-consciousness, but an unreasoning
knowledge, into which the individual does not enter: the content has not the
signification of 'I.' Therefore the case is as in mathematics; a proof is
certainly given, conviction must follow, but yet the matter fails to be
understood. There is a rigid necessity in the proof, to which the moment of
self-consciousness is lacking; the 'I' disappears, gives itself altogether up,
merely withers away. Spinoza's procedure is therefore quite correct; yet the
individual proposition is false, seeing that it expresses only one side of the
negation. The understanding has determinations which do not contradict one
another; contradiction the understanding cannot suffer. The negation of negation
is, however, contradiction, for in that it negates negation as simple
determination, it is on the one hand affirmation, but on the other hand also
really negation; and this contradiction, which is a matter pertaining to reason,
is lacking in the case of Spinoza. There is lacking the infinite form,
spirituality and liberty. I have already mentioned before this (pp. 93, 94;
129-137) that Lullus [Ramon
Llull -- RL] and Bruno [Giordano
Bruno -- RL] attempted to draw up a system of form, which should
embrace and comprehend the one substance which organizes itself into the
universe; this attempt Spinoza did not make." [Hegel
(1995b), pp.285-87. Links and bold emphasis added.]
Hence, the SGP has impeccable mystical credentials.
But,
there are problems.
For example: anyone who accepted the 'rationale' embodied in the SGP would only
have succeeded in exposing
their defective grasp of Proper Names -- more specifically the
Proper Names for, or the Proper Names of, human beings. So, if someone
(other than an infant, or perhaps a foreign-language speaker) had to be told that
John wasn't the
Tadpole
Galaxy, wasn't a grain of sand on
Coney
Island beach, wasn't one of Julius Caesar's fingernails, or wasn't Tony Blair's left foot,
that would raise serious doubts about their grasp of language --, or, and
far more likely, their sanity. In
fact, anyone who didn't know that "John" was the name of, or for, a man
would struggle to comprehend "grain of sand", "Galaxy" and "left foot",
let alone anything more complicated!
Hence, the SGP is a doubly useless principle; anyone who applied it in order to
"affirm", or "determine", anything about anything else would
surely also fail to understand any of its supposed 'results'. And we
can go further: anyone who didn't know that "John" was the name of, or for, a
man would surely fail to grasp the SGP, itself!
In fact, anyone familiar with
English, who heard the name "John" would know that it is conventionally used to
name male human beings. The same applies to the use of Proper Names for
human beings in German and
all other Indo-European languages (and, I suspect, that is the case with all
natural languages).
Furthermore, how would it be possible to 'determine' that John was a man if,
first of all, it had to be determined that he wasn't, say, George W Bush, wasn't
the Tower of London, wasn't the Potomac River...? The answer to that is
reasonably plain: it wouldn't be possible to 'determine' that until it
had already been determined who or what George W Bush, the Tower of
London, the Potomac River, and a potentially infinite list of other individuals
or objects that aren't John, were -- with each element in that potentially infinite
set naturally attracting the very same questions. They would also need to be rendered
'determinate' with their very own potentially infinite list to keep them
company, too..., and so on.
[I have expanded on this objection more fully,
here.
In addition, it is connected with what I have to say about 'HEX' (i.e., 'Hegelian
Expansionism') in Essay Ten
Part
One.]
Finally, anyone who chose to traverse the 'dialectical' path to enlightenment,
and who applied the SGP, obtaining "John is a non-man" at the first port of
call, would also have exposed their defective grasp of language -- and that
would still be the case even if they then moved onto the final denouement, that
higher plane of semi-divine knowledge unavailable to mere mortals, the "John
is not a non-man" epiphany, except they might be given a prize for stating
the bleeding obvious as a result. What next, "Grass is green"?
It
could be
objected that the above comments display a serious misunderstanding
of the SGP. That is because determination is an attempt to be more
specific about a certain concept or object. So, calling John an animal is less
determinate than calling him a man. It has nothing to do with the fantasies
rehearsed above -- i.e., with
determining that "John isn't the Tadpole
Galaxy, isn't a grain of sand on
Coney
Island beach, isn't one of Julius Caesar's fingernails, or isn't Tony
Blair's left foot...". When we say "John is a man" we are simply saying he isn't
an animal (in the sense that he isn't just an animal).
The
problem with that response is that it presupposes we already know what an animal
is, and according to this theory that concept must attract its own negations, as,
indeed, will anything less determinate than it -- such as John is a living
organism, John is a physical object, etc. Negations associated with the latter
threaten to explode in like manner until they involve the sort of negations
mentioned earlier -- namely:
"John isn't the Tadpole
Galaxy, isn't a grain of sand on
Coney
Island beach, isn't one of Julius Caesar's fingernails, or isn't Tony
Blair's left foot...". [I have spelled out the details
here.]
It
could be responded that determination applies to more general terms, using
negation to render them less general and more specific. That isn't the case with
lists like the above. But, once more, that assumes we already know what "more
general" and "less general" mean, which, given this theory, we can't know until
we have fed them into the SGP mangle. In that case, the above list still applies;
this theory has no way of ruling it out -- other than by
special pleading. [That appears to be the
line adopted by
this commentator on Hegel's work.
The above comments neutralise Hegel's obscure caveat that we can't just use negation
"arbitrarily",
a vague term in itself.]
Moreover, the SGP is defective even before we attempt to put it to
misuse: If "Every determination is also a negation" is itself a 'determination'
telling us what counts as a determination),
then it must surely imply its own negation, namely: "Some determinations aren't negations"
(i.e., "Not every determination is a negation"). On the other hand, if it doesn't
imply this, then not every 'determination' implies a negation, after all -- this
one, for instance. Alternatively, if the SGP isn't itself a
'determination' (and hence in no need of a 'negation' to help it bumble along), then its
implications must be unclear, and so it can't be applied until they become clear.
Either way, the SGP self-destructs.
Attempts made by dialecticians to respond to these points (not that they have
responded, or even will respond, to them -- since they have clearly
accepted, or swallowed uncritically, this throw-away line --, so this sentence should
in fact read
"Attempts that might be made by dialecticians to respond to these points...")
will be considered in Essay Twelve Part Five (when it is published).
As
noted earlier, the
above commentator tries to makes this point:
"Hegel's main point seems to be that
one cannot introduce negations
arbitrarilyinto the substance, unless
they are already contained in the very notion of substance (in fact, nothing
should be externally introduced into substance since substance is supposed to be
self-sufficient)." [Melamed
(2015), p.181.]
This
looks like special pleading on Hegel's part, which I covered
earlier. [Hegel assumes we already understand
the "notion of substance", but we can't do that unless we have already hit it with the SGP.]
I return to this theme again, below, where I deal with Hegel's lame attempt to
analyse predication (here,
here,
here, and
here).
34. Incidentally, herein lie
the seeds of the DM-idea that all knowledge is only ever partial or relative, since the
individual (John) is here only partially or relatively linked (at least as far as 'subjective
dialectics' is concerned) with the universal, whereas the universal itself is,
plainly, 'infinite', presumably because it has no empirical limitations.
The idea that there are no real or complete falsehoods
-- just truths that are more-or-less partial
or "relative" -- also arises from defective logic like this; for if propositions are
comprised only of names conjoined by the identity sign, then such names can't
fail to name some object or other, or they wouldn't be names to begin with. In that
case, they can't be false, or completely false, of those objects -- to use traditional jargon for the
moment.
[More
details on this will be given in Part Four of this Essay. See also Note 24aa, above. However, on
this see Davidson (2005), pp.76-140.]
34a. In fact, this
line-of-argument 'allowed' Hegel to mount what seemed to him to be an effective
reply to
Hume's criticisms of rationalist theories of causation. More on that in
Essay Twelve. [This is also what sinks DM -- indeed, it is its gravedigger, if you
like.
(Apologies for that mixed metaphor!) Another nice 'unity of opposites', one feels. (On that, see
here.)]
35.
In Essay Twelve it will
be argued that this manoeuvre underpins both the RRT and LIE. It will also be
shown in Essay Nine
Part Two
just why DM-theorists are especially prone to accepting, or swallowing
uncritically, these esoteric dodges, tricks and ploys. [Summaries
here,
here,
and
here.]
[RRT = Reverse Reflection Theory of Knowledge;
to be explained in Essay Twelve Part Four (when it is published); LIE =
Linguistic Idealism, also
explained in Essay Twelve Part Four, and
here.]
36.
This topic is covered in more detail in Essays
Two, Twelve and Fourteen (summaries
here and
here).
36a. Why this is so will be established in detail in Essay Twelve
(summary
here), and the sordid
history underlying the formation and adoption of these ideas will be exposedin Essay Fourteen
Part One (summary
here). Even today -- never mind two-and-a half
thousand years ago when these nostrums were first dreamt up and then imposed on
reality -- what little evidence that DM-fans have scarped together signally
fails to support their theory -- on that, see
here.
37. As
Lenin admitted, without even
so much as a hint of irony, embarrassment, still less shame:
"The history of philosophy and the history of
social science show with perfect clarity that there is nothing resembling
'sectarianism' in Marxism, in the sense of its being a hidebound, petrified
doctrine, a doctrine which arose away from the high road of the
development of world civilisation. On the contrary, the genius of Marx consists
precisely in his having furnished answers to questions already raised by the
foremost minds of mankind. His doctrine emerged as the direct and immediate
continuation of the teachings of the greatest representatives of
philosophy, political economy and socialism. The Marxist doctrine is omnipotent because it is true. It is comprehensive
and harmonious, and provides men with an integral world outlook irreconcilable
with any form of superstition, reaction, or defence of bourgeois oppression. It
is the legitimate successor to the best that man produced in the nineteenth
century, as represented by German philosophy, English political economy and
French socialism." [Lenin,
Three Sources and Component Parts of Marxism. Bold emphases alone
added; paragraphs merged.]
Once more, exactly why the DM-classicists were
more than eager to
appropriate and then promote these ideas will be exposed in Essay Nine
Part Two.
In addition, it will be argued in detail later (and, as was pointed out inNote 33,
above), the attempt to read fundamental features of reality from language
alone ends up populating the world with a whole host of weird and wonderful beings,
including the
Tooth Fairy, the
Loch Ness Monster, and
Big Foot. On that basis, too, it would be possible
to infer the existence of anything seemingly implied by a false proposition. [On this, see Essay Eleven
Part One, and Part Four of this
Essay (when it is published).]
37a. But, of course,
these Intrepid Ancestral Abstractors must have been unaware of exactly what they were
inserting into the grammar
of
Proto-Indo-European --, unless, of course, we
are to suppose that ancient tribesmen and tribeswomen were also 'unconscious'
dialecticians who discovered all this stuff long before Hegel began screwing
around with the German language --, but which doctrines these ancient
people, somewhat curiously, then encoded into a rather minor
grammatical form of Indo-European, unhelpfully disguised as predicate
expressions when what they 'really meant' were identity statements!
The
fact that this is a minor grammatical feature of Indo-European grammar is easily
confirmed by anyone who makes a note of how many times a day, week, or year they
hear, utter, or read the "S is P" form (other than in
books and articles on philosophy, or when speaking to a DM-fan or to an Hegelian).
So, how many times in the last month have you, dear reader, said anything like
this: "The rose is red", "John is a
man", or "Gold is a metal"? Of course,
school grammar teaches pupils to locate the "subject" and the "predicate" of
certain sentences, but this isn't the same as the "S is P" form. Recall
that for Hegel's trick
to work there has to be an "is" of predication in there somewhere on
which he can inflict some 'dialectical hocus pocus'.
Admittedly, there are many different
copula expressions in Indo-European, which
employ verbs other than "to be" -- such as, "to have", "to want", "to find", some of which are
clearly of more recent origin --, but it is even more difficult, if not
impossible, to turn these into
an "is" of
identity, which is what Hegel requires elsewhere. [On that, see
here and
here.]
Hence, he has
little to say about the vast bulk of the sentences we use, even in Philosophy!
In that case, as noted
several times already, the "S is
P" form is a relatively minor part of a sub-category of
Indo-European grammar, which would be a rather odd place for intrepid Abstractors
of yesteryear to bury such a profound discovery, to say the least.
[On the limitations of the "S is
P" form, see Geach (1968), and Note 38.]
It could be objected that this doesn't really matter since philosophers
like Hegel are only interested in the "S is P" form. Maybe so, but even
then they found they had to tinker around with a participle of the copulative verb "to
be" (i.e., "is") to make their theory even seem to work,
and they only succeeded in doing that by destroying the capacity of language to
say anything at all.
If DM-fans are happy with that, they
are welcome to it.
38.
Indeed, other than in books and articles about this deeply flawed area of
sub-Aristotelian 'logic', when would such a sentence
about John ever be used?
By way of contrast, it might be instructive to see if there
are any dialecticians on this planet who can milk some dialectics out of any of the following
ordinary indicative sentences:
M1: John runs the local strike committee.
M2: There is something useful to read in John's
strike bulletin.
M3: Anything the bosses threaten us with, John
can outmanoeuvre.
M4: Any friend of John is no friend of
management.
M5: John is the strike committee now
-- since everyone
else has been arrested.
M6: John gave the leaflets to Ryan, who handed
them to Jamaal, who posted them to Saoirse (pronounced Sorsha), who left them with Miriam on her way to work.
M7: Every strike leader like John makes
mistakes.
M8: John is a real man; that's why comrades
respect him.
M9: John is in fact now a trans-woman,
but that shouldn't affect his/her role in the Union.
M10: The comrade who paid John is
staying with my sister.
M11: Anyone who admires John despises
most of those who
agree with the strike committee's recommendation that union members should accept management's
latest offer to all of those still on strike because they received nothing in
the last pay round.
Many of these aren't of the simple subject-predicate form
beloved of the fans of Dialectical/Stone Age Logic. In fact, I defy anyone enamoured
even of AFL, never mind DL, to try to
express M10 or M11, for example, in the logic of their choice -- and then in
DL.
To be sure, M11 is a rather extreme
example, but even part of it is way beyond the 'logic'
Hegel put to misuse -- and, indeed, way beyond AFL, too. [Consult, for example, Mates
(1972) on how to translate such sentences into MFL.] Even so, sentences of
comparable complexity are used in modern mathematics and mathematical logic all
the time -- cf., Mendelson (2009).
Furthermore: although the words "John...is
staying with my sister" appear in M10, there is noproposition "John...is
staying with my sister" anywhere in M10. Indeed, the phrase "...is staying
with my sister" isn't true or false of John, but of the individual who paid John. Again, this
perfectly ordinary, straightforward sentence (with an ever so slightly
more complex predicate) is way beyond Traditional Logic, let alone the
sub-Aristotelian 'logic' Hegel dumped on humanity. There are countless sentences like this, as anyone familiar with English well knows. The same is also true of German
and French, and I
am sure of many other languages, including Russian.
But, Lenin must have uttered sentences like these
many times throughout his
life (albeit, not necessarily about John, nor, perhaps, any as complex as M11). Why then did he ignore such
everyday examples?
The answer is
reasonably clear: he uncritically accepted the word of a
card-carrying mystic.
38a. Of course, it
could be argued, à la
Feuerbach, that theological propositions are in
fact a
reflection of something -- namely the alienated view that humanity has of
itself. In that case, the subject-predicate form used in H2 expresses this ideological
'view'.
H2: God is our father.
Maybe
so, but no one would argue that just because ofthis such sentences were true, or even partially or 'relatively' true. Indeed, there would be no point
in dialecticians arguing that there is no evidence for believing in the
existence of 'God' if all that a 'dialectical theist' had to do in reply is
point to the subject-predicate form as proof that 'He' must exist -- perhaps on
the following lines: "Since sentences like H2 have
had this truth programmed into them by intrepid abstractors from earlier
generations, there must be a God...". Which DM-fan is going to accept that
as a valid response?
If the
"is" of predication
were one of identity, we would be able to argue as follows:
N1: Lenin is a man.
I.e., Lenin = Man.
N2: Trotsky is a man.
I.e., Trotsky = Man.
N3: Therefore, Lenin is Trotsky.
I.e., Lenin = Trotsky.
Of course,
because Lenin isn't Trotsky, this 'contradiction' must
mean that either Vladimir Ilyich Ulyanov will turn into Lev Davidovich Bronstein beyond the grave, or he
will be locked in eternal struggle with him in Dialectical Heaven. As
Plekhanov (and
several other
DM-worthies) assure
us:
"And so every phenomenon, by the
action of those same forces which condition its existence, sooner or later, but
inevitably, is transformed into its own opposite…." [Plekhanov
(1956), p.77. Bold emphases alone added.]
So, since Vladimir Ilyich Ulyanov isn't Lev Davidovich Bronstein, he must one day
turn into him. Is this not, therefore, a sound dialectical proof that there is an after-life?
Who can possibly object?
It is coded into the logic of our language!
Should anyone take exception to this crazy example of
sub-Aristotelian 'logic' -- as they should(!) --, the dotty nature of at
least this part of
DL might become clear
to them.
Independently of the above,
it could be argued that DL deals with
named
individuals in the following way:
L1: Lenin is not not-identical with mankind.
So, the above 'derivation' (i.e., N1-N3) doesn't work.
Or, so
it could be claimed.
But, L1 is in fact:
L2: Lenin = not not-identical with mankind.
[Where the new "is" of predication in L1 has been replaced by its
'dialectical alter ego', the "is" of identity, again. Of course, this annoying
re-write can only be neutralised by a far more sensible, if not sophisticated, analysis of propositions
than is available to Stone Age Dialectical Logicians. Moreover, my use of
sentences like L2 doesn't commit me to the thesis that Lenin could sensibly be equated
with "not
not-identical with mankind", nor does it commit me to the doctrine that a predicable like "...not
not-identical with mankind" can operate as a singular term, or referring expression, and thus
legitimately flank one side of an "=" sign. I am merely exposing the absurdities
that flow from the 'logic' Hegel conned many of his readers into swallowing.]
Now throw in the following:
L3: Trotsky = not not-identical with mankind.
And once more we have:
L4: Lenin = Trotsky.
For those still in thrall to fractured logic
like this, the few
avenues available to them to try to extricate themselves from this dialectical
debacle are
considered below, near the end of Note 40 -- and in Essay Eight
Part Three -- and then blocked.
Again, in the above 'argument', if anyone objects to the use of
the present tense (in, say, N1: "Lenin is a man"), on the grounds that Lenin is
now dead, then they wouldn't be able to correct the following false belief:
L5: Lenin is a mountain in Norway,
with:
L6: No, Lenin is a man, sadly now dead.
In fact, even on that basis, it could
be
argued that since Lenin is dead, he is an ex-man -- as, indeed, is
Trotsky --; the argument would then proceed as before.
Diabolical Logic like this is not
quite so
easily tamed.
Consider then this version of the above 'argument':
N1a: Lenin is dead.
I.e., Lenin = Dead.
N2a: Trotsky is dead.
I.e., Trotsky = Dead.
N3: Therefore, Lenin is Trotsky.
I.e., Lenin = Trotsky.
Nevertheless,
it could be objected that Plekhanov (quoted
above)
was in fact referring to "phenomena", not dead communists. In that case,
consider the following individuals who, at the time of writing, were alive; the result will be no different:
39a.
It could be objected that these terms aren't being substituted
salva congruitate (i.e., they aren't being
substituted in a way that preserves their grammatical or syntactical role). However, the right to lodge that particular complaint was forfeited the moment predicate
expressions were deliberately confused with the Proper Names of abstract particulars,
and the "is" of predication was transmogrified into an "is" of identity.
But, the serious answer is, of course:
that is precisely what
this crazy theory implies!
Get over it.
39b. And it is to no
avail to re-write H1 using an "=" sign in an endeavour to forestall this
recursive use of "is
identical with" in place of the original "is":
H1: John is a man.
H1a: John = man.
H1b: John equals man.
That is because the "=" sign
means "is
identical with" (i.e., both for Hegelians and Marxist dialecticians), which plainly contains
yet another recursive "is".
Of
course, reading the "=" sign as "equals" (in H1b)
is far too weak, as we will discover
in Essay Six. But, even if it could
be read this way, that rather desperate ploy still won't work. That is because,
as has already been pointed out, the "=" sign still means "is equal to" which
will attract its own 'infinite' recursion.
[That thankless task is also left to the
reader to undertake.]
Moreover, similar intractable problems also
arise in relation to Lenin's statement:
H6: The individual is opposed to the universal.
And, by no stretch of the imagination can this be
replaced with, or be read as:
On the
contradiction implied in "John is a man", we might ask is John the only man? If
so, then the correct expression is "John is the man". So, if John is
a man, then there are other men. Joe is a man. Jack is a man. Andrew is a man.
If John is
identical with "a man", and Joe is identical with "a man", and Jack is identical
with "a man", then through some kind of transitivity of identities we reach the
contradiction that John is Joe.
John is Jack.
Rosa L will say
what is the contradiction in "John is Jack"?
It is that John
is not Jack, as stipulated above when we said there are other men besides John.
Jack is another man from John is identical with the expression John is not Jack.
(sic) So directly the
contradiction is that we have both John is Jack and John is not Jack at the same
time.
I have now made
the contradiction implicit in "John is a man" so explicit and patent that even
contradiction-blind Rosa L. should be able to see it. But thanks to Rosa for
pressing the point on this example from Lenin's philosophical notebooks, as it
is only in "contradiction" with Rosa that I was moved to move the thought to
full demonstration.
The
contradiction inherent in the verb "to be", "is", can be seen as the same as
that found in "self-reference" by modern mathematical philosophers like
Russell.
Russell's famous paradox
derived from the self-reference of "the set of all sets
that don't contain themselves". The wikipedia
article on paraconsistency notes the efforts at avoiding self-reference in the
logics after that.
In any sentence
with a verb form of the verb "to be" makes a reference, a self-reference, of
the subject of the sentence. The subject refers to itself in the predicate.
"John is a
man", is a reference of John to himself as "a man", a self-reference.
So, modern
mathematics rediscovered the paradoxes of self-reference that Hegel had
discovered, perhaps as described in the quote of Hegel adduced on this thread by
Rosa L. above. Paraconsistent
logics are propositionally weaker than classical logic
"It should be emphasized that Paraconsistent logics are propositionally weaker
than classical logic; that is, they deem fewer propositional inferences valid.
The point is that a Paraconsistent logic can never be a propositional extension
of classical logic, that is, propositionally validate everything that classical
logic does. In that sense, then, Paraconsistent logic is more conservative or
cautious than classical logic. It is due to such conservativeness that
Paraconsistent languages can be more expressive than their classical
counterparts including the hierarchy of Meta-languages due to
Tarski
et al. According to Feferman [1984]: '…natural language abounds with
directly or indirectly self-referential...yet apparently
harmless expressions -- all of which are excluded from the Tarskian framework.'
This expressive limitation can be overcome in Paraconsistent logic."
[RL: I have slightly
edited the above so that it conforms to the formatting principles adopted at
this site, as I have also done with Mr B's other comments below. I have not
altered any of his words or sentences. Links added;
several paragraphs merged.]
Of course, the above isn't Hegel's
argument, nor is it Lenin's, as we have seen.
Even so, the
main points of my response were as
follows (slightly edited):
(1)
Traditional theorists treat all words as names or singular designating
expressions (i.e., they are all supposed to 'refer' to this or that, and if we
can't find a this or a that in this world to which they can refer,
'abstractions' -- or, these days, 'entities'/'abstract objects' from meta-theory -- are invented for
them to designate). This is indeed yet another aspect of
Plato's Beard, as
Quine
called it.
(2)
Unfortunately, the traditional approach destroys the
unity of the proposition, and that is because it turns propositions into lists, and lists
say nothing. So, the 'propositions' that dialecticians finally end up with
destroy any capacity language has for expressing, not just generality, but
anything whatsoever, since
this approach transforms predicate expression into the names of
abstract particulars.
[Examples
of the above are given
below; a longer explanation can be found in
Essay Three Part One.]
(3) Dialecticians in particular are guilty of doing this when, following Hegel,
they transform the "is" of predication into
an "is" of
identity.
(4) And
they do this since it is the only way they think they can 'derive' their 'contradictions'.
(5) In so
doing they
actively resist the conventions of ordinary language, since the vernacular actually
prevents these verbal tricks from being performed.
This comrade
managed to fall foul of every single one of the above. Readers will note, too, that he
doesn't even attempt
to justify a key component in his argument, namely, that
the "is" here is one of identity, not of predication. Without this, his entire case falls apart.
Now, he asserts this:
Rosa L will say
what is the contradiction in "John is Jack" ?
No I
won't say that, nor anything like it. I'll merely point out that this comrade has constructed a classic
Reductio ad Absurdum [RAA] here, which now allows us to discharge one of the
premisses as false. Since we want to hang on to "John is a man", the premiss we
must reject as false is the one hidden in here:
If John is
identical with "a man", and Joe is identical with "a man", and Jack is identical
with "a man", then through some kind of transitivity of identities we reach the
contradiction that...
That is,
we must discharge the hidden clause, "'John is a man' is an identity statement".
So, all that this comrade has in fact done is provide us with a refutation
of his own
'theory'!
But, there is more.
Even supposing that the "is" here is an "is" of identity, then that can only
mean that this proposition:
B1:
John is a man.
Should read:
B2:
John = a man.
But, if
John is identical to a man, which man is this? That would be the first question we
would normally ask upon being informed of this startling fact. The only conceivable answer would be
that this man is... John! So, this brilliant theory ends up with "John is identical
with John"!
The comrade might
point this out, again:
On the
contradiction implied in "John is a man", we might ask is John the only man? If
so, then the correct expression is "John is the man".
But, who on earth would ask "Is
John the only man?" Someone with amnesia? Someone
with learning difficulties? A visitor from another planet? Someone suffering from dialectics?
Nevertheless, let us
suppose that we could find a benighted soul somewhere on this planet (other
than this comrade) who would ask such an odd question. In that case, the natural reply would be: "No,
there are plenty of other men...and, er..., do you perhaps need to see a psychiatrist?", which
sentence can't be press-ganged into
helping this comrade defend Hegel. Indeed, I am rather surprised that
he
failed to consider this more natural response to his own question. [But, then
again, I'm not
really.]
Unlike Marx, he clearly thinks our ordinary use of language
is an impediment, not a resource.
Even so,
and ignoring these relatively minor niggles, the identity relation operates between two names, singular terms or objects
(depending on how we interpret it).
This
forces us to conclude that for this comrade "a man" is a name (or some other singular
designating expression), and that it names or designates
an object, class, set, or category, etc -- as (1)-(5) above predicted. Indeed, it is quite plain that for
this comrade "a
man" is akin to a Proper Name. This can be seen by the ease with which he slides between
"John is a man" and "John is Jack". He clearly sees no difference between a
Proper Name and an indefinite description, or between a Proper Name and a predicate expression! Hence, the
only conclusion possible is that for him "a man" refers to an object of some sort (or
perhaps to an
abstract particular),
in the way that a Proper Name refers to its bearer. If
so, given his 'theory', "a man"
no longer functions as a general term since, manifestly, no object
(abstract or concrete) or singular term can be general.
Generality is a
feature of our use of language (as I argued in
Part Two of Essay Three).
Plainly, that is because, unlike human beings, linguistic expressions have no
social life and are totally incapable of collecting things
together in groups, classes or even sheep pens. To suppose otherwise would be to
fetishise language,
misconstruing the communal use of language as if it were a reflection the social
life of words.
So, by
assuming that all words are names, dialecticians end up with the following list:
B3:
Name/Identity-Relation/Abstract-Noun.
Or:
B4:
John/Identity/Man (Manhood, the Class of Men, etc.).
But, lists say
nothing, so this comrade's theory falls apart since it is now apparent that
dialectical 'propositions' like this are vacuous!
Instead of asking
himself whether it makes sense to say that a name could be identical with a
predicate -- or even that what it is that each word supposedly refers to or
'reflects' could be identical
with one another --, this comrade has swallowed Hegel's sub-Aristotelian 'logic' whole,
and without
blinking!
That suspicion is
amply confirmed by what follows:
The
contradiction inherent in the verb "to be", "is", can be seen as the same as
that found in "self-reference" by modern mathematical philosophers like Russell.
Russell's famous paradox derived from the self-reference of "the set of all sets
that don't contain themselves".
The Wikipedia
article on Paraconsistency notes the efforts at avoiding self-reference in the
logics after that.
In any sentence
with a verb form of the verb "to be" makes a reference, a self-reference, of the
subject of the sentence. The subject refers to itself in the predicate.
"John is a
man", is a reference of John to himself as "a man", a self-reference.
It isn't easy to see
how or why Paraconsistent Logic is relevant here, but readers will no doubt
notice how the word "reference" is indiscriminately thrown about the place as if
all words and sentences were denoting expressions; but we are offered no reason
to suppose that they can all be used referentially. Hence, we are simply
told, with no argument in support, that:
The
contradiction inherent in the verb "to be", "is", can be seen as the same as
that found in "self-reference" by modern mathematical philosophers like Russell.
Russell's famous paradox derived from the self-reference of "the set of all sets
that don't contain themselves"....
In any
sentence with a verb form of the verb "to be" makes a reference, a
self-reference, of the subject of the sentence. The subject refers to itself in
the predicate.
"John is a
man", is a reference of John to himself as "a man", a self-reference. [Bold
added.]
Once more, as
predicted in points (1)-(5) above, we see this comrade acknowledging here that a
verbactually refers, that is, that it is a Proper Name or some
other singular designating
expression! So, his 'propositions' have this form:
B5:
Name/Singular-Term/Abstract Noun.
Or:
B6:
John/Reference-to-Subject-in-Predicate/Man.
But, this is just
another list!
And, of course, this
isn't even remotely true:
The subject
refers to itself in the predicate.
The
subject in fact refers to John; that is why he was given that name!
"John"
doesn't refer to another symbol, but to John.
Nor is there anything to which it can refer in the predicate, since the
predicate isn't a container. [Of course, all this depends on what this
comrade means by "subject" and "predicate" -- but, as usual, he neglected
to say.]
So ends yet another
rather weak attempt to defend the indefensible. [More details
here.
I have developed this argument further
here.]
It is worth recalling that when interpreted normally
--
i.e., by normal human beings -- predication merely says
something of a named (or otherwise designated) individual or object; that is, it is a
description, or, in some cases, an attribution or an ascription.
[Some claim that a sentence like H1 is either an
'essential' predication, or it is a (partial) definition of the individual
concerned. That claim will be examined
below -- as it has
also been,
above.]
H1: John is a man.
So, "John is a man" just
asserts (or can be used to assert) something of whoever the name "John" designates -- or, better
still: "ξ is a man" can be used to form true (or false) sentences if the
relevant language has available, appropriate Proper Names conventionally used to
pick out men, human beings in general --, or, in the present case, this
particular (fictional) character, John.
Alternatively, as
Aristotle would
have said, the predicate "man" applies to whomever "John" names.
Looked at this way, there is no "is" anywhere in sight for dialecticians to magic into an identity.
[Other languages that lack the
copula, "is",
also proceed along similar lines. Of course, as with most things connected with
Aristotle, his ideas on predication are much more complex than the above might
suggest. Nevertheless, that doesn't affect the validity of the claim made above about
Aristotle's
paraphrastic use of "applies". On this, see Robin Smith's article on Aristotle's
Logic published at the Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy; i.e., Smith
(2019),
Section Seven. Since the present Essay isn't meant to be an exercise in academic
philosophy, I will say no more about this topic here. On this in general, see
Modrak (2001).]
Readers, however, might wonder how
the genuine "is" of identity fares under
such scrutiny (on this, see the
previous section); must it, too, explode in infinite confusion?
So, in
relation to sentences like
the following:
S4: Cicero is Tully,
aren't we forced to explicate this "is" in like manner (as in S5 and
S6)?
S5: Cicero
is
identical with Tully.
S6: Cicero
is identical with
identical with Tully.
[As the green "is" in S5 is replaced with what it supposedly means,
"is identical with".]
And
so on? If not, then this can't be a problem for
dialecticians either.
Or, so a counter-claim might proceed.
However, when we say that
"the 'is' that appears in S4
is one
of identity", the green
"is"
is itself one of predication (as
is the
one following it (i.e., the "is"
in this paragraph)
-- and the same comment applies to the one in the
brackets (namely, "is"), too!), which can be explicated,
à la Aristotle, and
thus isn't
essential to predication, along the following lines:
S7: Identical with Tully applies to Cicero.
Or, perhaps more colloquially:
S7a:
"Cicero" and
"Tully" are
two names of
the same individual; or, maybe,
S7b: Cicero has two names:
"Cicero" and "Tully"; or
even,
S7c:
Cicero's other name is "Tully".
DM-fans can't do this because they maintain that "is" is always
one of identity. Hence, their theory collapses
in the way I have indicated; whereas the Aristotelian/colloquial account does not.
However, Hegel thinks he has a reply to this 'Aristotelian'
riposte:
"To define the subject as that of which
something is said, and the predicate as what is said about it, is mere trifling.
It gives no information about the distinction between the two. In point of
thought, the subject is primarily the individual, and the predicate the
universal. As the judgment receives further development, the subject ceases to
be merely the immediate individual, and the predicate merely the abstract
universal: the former acquires the additional significations of particular and
universal, the latter the additional significations of particular and
individual. Thus while the same names are given to the two terms of the
judgment, their meaning passes through a series of changes." [Hegel (1975), p.234.
Bold emphasis added.]
So, Hegel justified his rejection of Aristotle's interpretation
on the grounds that this analysis gives us no information about the distinction
between a subject and a predicate. But, quite apart from the fact that this way
of looking at propositions (or even "judgements") is highly limited in itself
-- for example, it can't cope with complex sentences that Hegel himself used,
even in the above
passage, let alone throughout the rest of his work, or, indeed, in everyday life --, the supposed Aristotelian
analysis
tells us all we need to know. We can see this from the fact that Hegel, in
common with many pre-modern theorists, readily confused talk about talk
with talk about things. For instance, he tells us that "the
subject is primarily the individual and the predicate the universal", whereas a
predicate is a linguistic expression (predicates don't populate the
world!) while a "universal" isn't, which is something the analysis to which
Hegel took exception makes
quite clear. And, if we say that a predicate like this refers to a universal, we
will only have succeeded in transforming the general term involved into the
Proper Name of an abstract
particular, once more. Moreover, the subject is also linguistic expression;
in this case, it is a Proper Name. As
Peter Geach predicted, Hegel's adherence to the
two name theory, compounded by his conflation of talk about talk with talk
about the world, led him into profound confusion.
Indeed, we can see once again that Hegel has conflated
names with predicates:
"Thus while the same names are given to the two terms of
the judgment, their meaning passes through a series of changes." [Ibid.]
In that case, it is clear that, as confused
as Aristotle was over many things, he was a model of clarity next to this
Hermetic Harebrain.
Furthermore, it is this confusion of
talk about talk with talk about the world that motivated Hegel
into thinking that the development of his
own obscure thoughts were one with development in 'reality' -- surely the philosophical
equivalent of a madman who thinks he is 'God'!
Or, to put this another way: Hegel's confusion of
the "is" of identity with the "is" of predication -- or, in
fact, his rejection of
the significance of this distinction -- only makes sense if 'reality' is indeed Ideal,
where it doesn't really matter if these two verb forms are conflated, and talk
about talk is 'legitimately' confused with talk about the world.
Finally, Hegel failed to justify this
dubious move:
"As the judgment receives further development, the subject
ceases to be merely the immediate individual, and the predicate merely the
abstract universal: the former acquires the additional significations of
particular and universal, the latter the additional significations of particular
and individual." [Ibid.]
He nowhere explains (in a jargon-free passage) how, for example, the individual "acquires
the additional significations of particular and universal", nor how the
universal does something similar. The only conceivable way they could do this is if the
"is" of predication is reconfigured as an "is" of identity -- but,
that just
assumes what was to be proved and so can't be used to criticise Aristotle. Hegel
failed to show that Aristotle's analysis is
defective (or even of limited use and applicability), which he needed to do before he could
proceed to make this as-yet-unwarranted
syntactical switch, not the other way round.
[Hegel's other comments on "individuals",
"universals", and "particulars" will be destructively criticised in
Essay Twelve Part Five.]
40a. Of
course, there is always
Petula Clark's
truly awful song, London is London, which also uses two names (in what
follows, the video times given use 'decimalised' minutes and seconds --,
so, for example, 08:12 means 8 minutes, 12 seconds into the said video; if a time of the day (in the
UK) is intended, I will add "am" or "pm"; finally, calendar
dates also appear as they are recorded in the UK: Day/Month/Year):
"But still, Paris is Paris, and better Paris in
the winter than no Paris at all, n'est ce pas?" [Quoted from
here; accessed 23/04/2014.]
During
his 2012 re-election campaign, President Obama found he had to point out, rather
forcefully, that "Rape
is rape" in response to the Republican candidate for the Senate
race in Indiana,
Richard Mourdock
-- who came out with the outrageous comment that he was
opposed to abortion even when a woman had been raped, saying "When life begins
in that horrible situation of rape, that it is something that God intended to
happen" (quoted from
here). The actor,
Ashley Judd,
also used the same phrase -- at approximately 08:07 in the following video:
It
would be interesting to see how many DM-fans will want follow
Hegel, Engels, Lenin and Trotsky and
argue that since nothing is self-identical, rape both is and isn't rape, or
even that "No!" does and doesn't mean "No!" [On that,
see below.]
In 2012,
Ched Evans,
a UK football ("soccer") player, was convicted of rape. After serving half of his
five year jail sentence he was
released on licence. In November 2014, Stuart Gilhooly, of the Players Football
Association of Ireland, published a disreputable and feeble
defence of Evans.
Here is an exchange taken from
Jean Hatchet's deconstruction of that attempt
to 'defend' Evans (published
on the
Ending Victimisation
And Blame website; Gilhooly's words are in
single quotes):
"'The difficult element of this
discussion, though, is the part about the scale of the crime. There are people
who will say rape is rape.' Rape is rape, and degrees shouldn't come into it."
[Quoted from
here. Accessed 19/11/2014. Punctuation
modified;
paragraphs merged.]
A few days later, a BBC radio presenter, Nick Conrad,
broadcast a series of deeply offensive remarks about rape on Radio Norfolk; here is
part of a reply to him written by Lucy Hunter Johnston, published in The
Independent:
"Questioning the behaviour of the victim seeks to
absolve the attacker of blame, but there aren't varying shades of grey here. A
rapist is a rapist, whether he attacks in an alleyway, a living room or a swanky
hotel room. A rapist is still a rapist if he has had sex with his victim before.
Going home with someone is not consent. Being drunk is not consent. Your
wardrobe choices are not consent. No woman or man is to blame for the violence
committed against them; there is no right or wrong way to be raped." [Quoted
from
here; accessed 19/11/2014.]
One wonders how many Hegel-fans there are who might
disagree with these comments on the grounds that rape also isn't rape,
and a rapist also isn't a rapist, since both of these are paired with their 'dialectical opposites' ('clearly'
indicated by the
'different content' supposedly expressed between subject and predicate). Again,
one wonders, too, just how many DM-fans there
are who might be inclined to agree with the latter about this? [Although, there might be
several
such individuals in the UK-SWP. Is that why
there are
so many rape apologists in revolutionary parties
these days?]
Where and what exactly is the 'rational core' of rape-apology?
Rachel: "How come don't you
have a kitchen table?"
Charlie Crews: "I'm trying to
lead an uncluttered life."
Rachel: "A kitchen table
isn't clutter. A kitchen table is a kitchen table."
And,
the following is another brief conversation (this time taken from
The West
Wing,
Season
5, Episode 5, Constituency Of One)
concerning what seemed to some to
be an insignificant series of events in (fictional) US politics:
Amy: "It's nothing, Josh."
Josh: "Nothing is nothing."
Video Three: "Nothing Is
Nothing"
As
seems obvious, the "Nothing is nothing" comment amounts to a denial that
anything in politics is insignificant, since it is arguable that these two uses
of the same word, "nothing", have a different meaning. One is a
quantifier, the meaning of which is rather complex, and amounts to "There
isn't anything that...", while the other means something like "insignificant" or "can be
ignored". So, Josh's sentence cashes out as "There isn't anything which is
insignificant or can be ignored in politics."
We were even told that
"Nonsense is nonsense" in the fly leaf to Floyd and Shieh (2001).
In
the film,
Win A Date With Tad Hamilton!, one
character, Rosalee Futch, wonders why Tad Hamilton shows no interest in her, so
she whimpers "I'm nobody!". The reply comes back "Nobody is nobody!" By that, he
manifestly didn'tmean "Nobody is identical with nobody"!
Another
perfectly ordinary communicative act
was achieved
quite efficiently by the use of a colloquial tautology: we were told
that "A couple is a couple" in a discussion of gay marriage in The
West Wing,
Season 5, Episode 17, The
Supremes.
In an earlier series of The West Wing (Season
1, Episode 20, Mandatory Minimums),
during a discussion concerning whether or not
drug addiction is a medical problem, we were told that "Science is science"
(approximately 18:00 into the programme).
Josh:
"You spend your whole career trying to get in this room as if you're the one who
can square every circle, and it turns out..."
CJ:
"A circle is a circle."
As
part of a conversation about the stalled "Santos for President" campaign, the
margin for error in the polls, and the fact that the campaign seemed to be stuck
on "nine points down", Josh says "Nine points is nine points" (The West Wing,
Season 7, Episode 5, Here
Today, approximately 10:00 into the programme).
One
of the female characters in
HBO's
mini-series,
Show Me A
Hero -- aired in the UK on
Sky
Atlantic, 08/09/2015 --, in a discussion whether or not she should move
house, said: "My home is my home" (approximately 30:00 into
Episode 4). And, in the short-lived American cop show,
Backstrom (Season 1, Episode 2), aired on the UK Fox Channel,
10/09/2015, we were presented with the following conversation (approximately
08:00 into the
programme):
Backstrom (referring to two
guys he knew as a child): "They lived across the street. They tortured me every
day."
Valentine: "Um. Torture? You
mean literally with a blowtorch and pliers, or metaphorically when they called
you names and belittled your accomplishments?"
Backstrom: "Torture is
torture, Valentine."
In the summer of 2014,
James
Rodriguez, the Columbian football (soccer) star, had this to say about his proposed
transfer to
Real Madrid, as opposed to, say, a move to
Manchester United:
"I have a great deal of respect for other clubs
and admire the good football they play, but ultimately Real Madrid are Real
Madrid. I've always had a thing for them, like I said before." [Quoted from
here. Accessed 18/07/2014.]
Indeed, during
an English Premier League football (soccer) game
between
Arsenal FC and
Burnley FC, shown on BBC TV, 02/11/2014, the commentator
pointed out that despite the stolid defence mounted by Burnley, Arsenal were
bound to score -- after all "Arsenal are Arsenal", he opined. [The use
of a plural form of the verb "to be" here is apposite since "Arsenal" is a
collective term; "Arsenal is Arsenal" would therefore be grammatically
incorrect. The same also applies to "Real Madrid are Real Madrid".] And, on Sunday
afternoon, 22/03/2015, ex-Arsenal and
Barcelona
FC footballer,
Thierry
Henri, commenting on a lucky goal scored by
Loïc Rémy
for
Chelsea FC
in their game with
Hull City
AFC, had this to say: "At the end of
the day, a bit lucky, but a goal is a goal." The betting firm, Bet
Victor, went one better and ran with "A goal is a gaol is a gaol!"
slogan as part
of their advertising campaign during the
UEFA Euro
2016 Football Tournament:
Video Four: "A Goal Is A
Goal Is Goal!"
Similarly, during the BBC's
coverage of the match between England and Wales (during the same tournament), one of the commentators,
Robbie
Savage, queried the award of a free kick by the referee for a foul committed by a
Wales player, claiming it wasn't really a foul. The other commentator,
Martin
McKeown, was heard to say "A foul is a foul, Robbie" (16/06/2016, approximately
35:00 into the game). Later in the tournament, during the match
between Portugal and Croatia (25/06/2016) and near the beginning of extra time, the
commentators were talking about the merits or otherwise of the Portugal footballer,
Cristiano Ronaldo, when one of them said to the other: "Ronaldo is Ronaldo".
In relation to a penalty awarded against a
Bournemouth AFC defender,
Charlie Daniels, in match against
Crystal Palace FC, (27/08/2016), we were told the following on Sky
Sports TV (as part of a post-match referee panel review of such decisions):
"Dermot
[Gallagher
-- a retired referee -- RL]: '[Charlie] Daniels pulls the shirt back. [Mike]
Dean
[the match referee -- RL] made a stand last week and gave penalties for the same
thing. He's been consistent. It doesn't matter if he's moving away from goal,
a foul is a foul.'"
[Quoted from
here; accessed 27/09/2016.]
Apparently, "A win is a
win!", too, which we were told are "Five
important words you need to take to heart" if you want to win at
sweepstakes. It
is also the opinion of CNN anchor,
Wolf
Blitzer, who, in response to the news that
Donald
Trump was about to win the South Carolina Republican Party Primary for the
GOP nomination to run for President, concluded that "A win is a
win!" (20/02/2016). This was something he repeated several times as it became clear later on in the
campaign that
Hillary
Clinton was about to win the Kentucky Primary (in the Democratic
race) by less than 2000 votes, 17/05/2016. The same sentiment was echoed on CNN by
Hillary
Clinton's Chief Strategist,
Joel
Benenson, 19/03/2016, when asked about her prospects in the New York
Primary: "A win is a win!". Indeed, Trump Senior Adviser,
Jack Kingston, repeated this catch-phrase on
CNN (02/11/2016, at approximately 1:20 am), on
Anderson Cooper 360, when asked why
Republican Speaker of the House of Representatives,
Paul Ryan, wouldn't use Donald Trump's name:
"As we would say in sports, 'A win is a win!'"
The
same words were also used during a BBC programme --
Breakfast TV, 27/04/2017 -- in a
conversation about the comments attributed to snooker star,
Ronnie O'Sullivan, who said he would "rather
lose a good match than win a bad one". The on-air talent replied: "A win is a
win" (approximately 6:12 am).
In
like manner,
Joe Hart,
ex-Manchester City FC and ex-England
goalkeeper, had this to say about his team's new manager (in his interview with the BBC after their game
with
Sunderland
AFC, 02/02/2016): "Next season is next
season". And,
Daniel
Sturridge, an ex-Liverpool FC player, when asked about
events earlier in the season, had this to say (in his after-match interview on BT TV, approximately
10:15 pm, Thursday 10/03/2016): "The past is the past". The same words,
"The past is the past", were used by Australian rugby player,
Kurtley
Beale, on BBC Radio Five Live (30/08/2016, approximately 07:50
pm), when
describing his career to date. They were used again in September 2016 -- Season 1, Episode 1
of the
Netflix series,
Luke Cage,
approximately 09:00 into that video (Moment
of Truth) --, when the main character, Cage, referring to his
long lamented friend,
Henry 'Pop' Hunter, replied "The past is the
past". This phrase was also used in the US cop show,
NCIS (Season
7, Episode 2, Reunion); one of
the characters was reminiscing about her career to date, to which she added "The
past is the past" (about 38:00 into the show, broadcast on the
Universal Channel, 10/08/2017).
Moreover, in an episode
of
Russell Howard's Good News (repeated on the
Dave
cable channel, 22/04/2016), a member of the public was asked if it was time to
forgive
Ed
Milliband for defeating his brother in the election to the leadership of the
UK Labour Party four years earlier. Howard had this to say in response, "I don't care. Your brother
is your brother."
"The Legend of Billie Jean
is about a young woman who stands up for truth and justice...has sidekicks and a
nemesis and even has her own catchphrase in 'Fair is fair!'" [Quoted from
here.]
And,
the same phrase, "Fair is fair", was uttered by Mr Willis of Ohio in an episode
of The West Wing (Mr
Willis of Ohio, Season 1, Episode 6),
approximately 27:00 into the programme.
Indeed,
in a recent instalment of the
Sky
Atlantic programme,
Banshee (Season
2, Episode 2, Thunder Man), one of the
characters is faced with a 30-day jail sentence. Another character says that this is
no big deal, "It's only 30 days", we are told; but he receives a rebuke: "Prison is
prison!". Just as we were recently
reminded that "Jail
is jail". Moreover, the US 'legal' drama series,
The Good
Wife (Season 2, Episode 12,
Silly Season), had the main character,
Alicia
Florrick, reject a request that she intervene
in her husband's election campaign by saying "The campaign is the campaign".
Moreover, back in 2015, in relation to the
genocide of the Armenian people,
The Huffington Post told us that "Truth
is truth" (24/04/2015), a
sentiment shared by
the Director,
Steve McQueen, as he was commenting about the making of
12 Years A Slave.
Also on
Sky TV -- Goals on Sunday,
Sunday 22/02/2015 --, Chelsea FC's former manager,
José
Mourinho, when asked about his team winning the English League Cup back in
2005, replied: "A final is a final...a cup is a cup". John Luther, a character in
the
BBC crime series,
Luther
(repeated on
Alibi
TV, 21/02/2015, approximately 33:00 into Episode 3 of
Season 1), when asked about a particular murder, replied: "Murder is murder"
-- as did one of the detectives on
Blue Bloods (Season 6, Episode 13, Stomping Ground), aired on Sky Atlantic,
30/03/2016. We were also told that "Dirty money is dirty money" during the
Sky Living cop show,
Blindspot (Season 1, Episode 6,
Cede Your Soul), when one of the show's regulars tried to defend another
character on the show from accusations of receiving money for an alleged crime. Later in the
same series (Season 1, Episode 11,
Cease Forcing Enemy), after complaining that
even though the main
character was a qualified pilot, she couldn't fly the 'plane she happened to be
on, she
is then told by her
FBI handler: "A plane is a plane is a
plane" (about 36:00 into the programme). One of the actors in the US crime drama,
Law and Order: Special Victims Unit,
Casey Novak, in response to the rumour that she
had been fired from the show,
replied "Rumours are Rumours...".
Indeed, one comrade recently posted the following comment on a
discussion board: "Well, Art is Art, isn't it? Still, on the other hand,
water is water. And east is east and west is west...".
"Oh, East is East and
West is West, and never the twain shall meet,
"Till Earth and Sky
stand presently at God's great Judgment Seat;
"But there is neither
East nor West, Border, nor Breed, nor Birth,
"When two strong men
stand face to face, though they come from the ends of the earth!" [Quoted from
here.]
As well as the opening lines of the song,
Buttons
and Bows, from the film,
The Paleface: "East is east and west is west, and the wrong one I have
chose...". And, of course,
East is East was the title of a film
released
back in 1999.
Toward the end of the
Europa
League soccer match between
Chelsea FC
and
FC
Rubin Kazan, in April 2014, a sports commentator was heard to say -- in
response to an assertion that the status of the final of the Europa League isn't
to be compared with that of the final of the
Champions League --, "A European Final is a European Final." We all know
what he meant, even if we might disagree with what he said.
"Enough is enough"
has now become the most widely used and sloganised version of this linguistic form. In
mid-October 2016, it was also
the response evinced by the Republican Governor of
South Dakota,
Dennis Daugaard, in reaction to the latest, and
easily the worst, Donald Trump debacle -- his admission that
he could grope women with impunity (warning,
graphic and highly offensive language at that link). It was the
response, too, echoed by a retired Ohio judge three
weeks after Trump's inauguration. This sentence now crops up all over the
place. Here is what Nicholas Wade -- a prospective candidate for the Hastings and
Rye constituency in the 2017 UK Parliamentary Election, standing as an independent on an
anti-corruption ticket --
had to say in late April of that year: "Enough
is enough. There needs to be new influence in Parliament." And those words
were
even used on Twitter by the UK
People's Assembly (11/05/2017):
"Enough is enough! After 7yrs of Austerity we
simply can't afford another 5yrs of the Tories. THIS JUNE, DON'T VOTE MAY
#ToriesOut #GE17." [Capitalisation in the original.]
And,
here is what a football ("soccer") reporter from the Manchester Evening News
wrote after Manchester United's defeat to Danish team,
FC Midtjylland,
in February 2016:
"I wrote 'enough is enough'
after the dire display against Southampton less than a month ago believing it
couldn't get any worse and it shouldn't be allowed to...but then came this joke
in
Jutland...."
[Quoted from
here.
Link added.]
Then
there is this:
Video Five: Enough Is
Enough -- An Anti-Fascist Song
Another group,
Los Bravos from the 1960s, told us
back then that "Black
is Black" -- and even that "Grey is grey":
Video Six: Apparently,
"Black Is Black"
Update 26/07/2015: Also seen on Twitter (in relation to
this story in The Daily Telegraph, for which they later had to
apologise): "A lie is a lie is
a lie."
Figure Seven: "A Lie Is A
Lie"
Update September 2015:
The following appeared in The Guardian newspaper (concerning
the race to win the Democratic Party nomination to run for the White House in
the 2016 US Presidential Election, and the contest between
Hillary
Clinton and the "democratic socialist",
Bernie
Sanders):
"Plenty of other candidates
are making similar pitches, but few manage it as authentically as Sanders. 'Bernie is Bernie, he's down
to earth and he's not for special interests,' explains Chris Uhlenhopp, a
67-year-old former labourer at the nearby Maytag appliances factory, which once
employed 2,000 people." [Quoted from
here;
accessed 07/09/2015. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions
adopted at this site; paragraphs merged.]
Even
working class Americans appear to know how to refute Hegel -- albeit inadvertently.
And,
Sanders himself is reported to have said the following:
"Enough is enough. This great nation and its government belong to all of the
people and not to a handful of billionaires, their
super
PACs and their lobbyists." [Quoted from
here. Accessed 09/09/2015. Link added.]
Indeed, "Enough is enough" became a campaign slogan for Sanders in
the 2015/16 race for the Presidency; just as it is part of the title of an article over at the
Counterfire website: "'Enough
is enough': anger and escalation". And, in February 2016, we were even told
by the
BBC:
"Enough is enough: India women fight to enter temples."
Figure Eight: "Enough Is
Enough", Even For UK Teachers
Even
UK cops have employed this catch-phrase:
Figure Nine: Even For
UK Cops, "Enough Is Enough!"
A Google image search will soon reveal
that countless others have made placards proclaiming "Enough is enough!"
That search might even find the Anti-Capitalist website: "Enough
is Enough!"
Enough is too much even for the manufacturers
of
Fixodent:
Video Seven: "Enough Is Enough!",
Even For Fixodent
Apparently, the penny has dropped for at
least one 'patriotic' Trump supporter, for whom -- yes you guessed it -- "Enough
is enough":
Figure Ten: "Enough Is
Enough" -- Trump Voter Wises Up
Ex-UK Prime Minister, Theresa May, used this combination of words ("Enough is enough")
after the terrorist attack on London, 03/06/17 -- video
here. [Apologies to readers who might feel
nauseous after hearing this Tory fraud bang on about 'extremists' soon after arming
to the teeth the reactionary, extremist Saudi Arabian regime.]
Update October 2015:
Seen on Twitter (in relation to a petition demanding
justice for Tamir Rice),
"Enough is enough...when will our children
matter in America?"
Trevor Noah, the
current presenter of the
Daily Show, thought it pertinent to remind
his viewers that "A drunk is a drunk".
Update February 2016: Lord Hall, Director General of the BBC -- in a press
conference about the release of a report into the implication, or even
the complicity, of the BBC in the serial child sex abuses committed by
Jimmy Savile --
had this to say: "Sexual abuse is sexual abuse. It can never be excused."
[Live
on BBC Two, 25/02/2016, 11:03 am.]
If the above examples fail to convince
hard-nosed DM-fans, we have this from
Ai Ssu-ch'i
(a prominent
MIST and close collaborator of Mao):
"Unity is unity....
Centralised state power is centralised state power...." [Quoted from
here.]
Another
leading MIST, Kostas Mavrakis, also found it important to inform his readers that "Reactionaries
are reactionaries".
Update July 2016: After the
UK Euro-Referendum (23/06/2016), we were told the following (about the
intentions of the leading contender for the leadership of the
Tory Party):
"The front-runner,
Theresa May,
has stated that 'Brexit is Brexit' and will be taken at her word." [Quoted from
here, although
thousands have used the same words, ad nauseam, ever since.
Accessed 03/07/2016.]
["Brexit" is
neologism standing for "British Exit"
from the European Union.]
When the BBC interviewed
Jean
Claude Juncker, The European Commission President, and asked him
whether there was any flexibility available to the UK over the 'free movement of
labour' after Brexit, he had this to say "The Treaty is the Treaty"
(28/06/2016).
In the wake of the
long-delayed
Chilcot
Report
into the 2003 Invasion of Iraq, a former soldier, Steven McLaughlin, was
interviewed by the BBC; after noting that even though the politicians involved
wear nice suits and are represented by PR companies, he added that they should
still be held accountable: "A criminal is a criminal", he said (Local
BBC News Northwest, 07/07/2016, 06:26 am). During
Wimbledon Fortnight, in an interview with
Peter
Norfolk on BBC One (08:45 am, 10/07/2016), we were told that, despite the fact
that some tennis players were disabled and in wheelchairs, when they play the
game, "Tennis
is tennis".
Approximately 25:00 into yet anther cop show,
Shades of Blue (shown on Sky Living in mid-July 2016), after
trying to defend her corrupt colleagues on the grounds that crime in her
Precinct was down,
Jennifer
Lopez's character is told by an FBI agent "Corruption is corruption".
And, in an interview on UK Channel Four News (19/07/2016) concerning the US Republican Party nominee for the Presidency, Donald
Trump, we were told by a US pundit "Trump is Trump" after he was asked
whether Trump would moderate his tone.
Update August 2016: In a discussion on BBC One (21/08/2016, approximately 00:50
am)
about the disqualification of the UK team in the Olympic Games final of the
4x400 relay race for a very minor foot violation,
Michael Johnson, the US sprinter, commented "The rule is the rule".
Update September 2016: Here is
the title of an open letter written by a doctor in reply to yet another bilious
attack on working people, courtesy of the UK Daily Mail: "Dear
Daily Mail, Enough is Enough".
We
even encountered the following sentence in The West
Wing (Season
2, Episode 8, Shibboleth,
approximately 10:00 into the film); the White House staff were discussing
the fate of a container load of hidden Chinese immigrants, who were also persecuted
Christians and who wanted to claim asylum. The Deputy Chief of Staff,
Josh Lyman, pointed out that the US Christian
lobby will want them admitted while the Chinese government will want them back,
while the "INS
will say 'The law is the law'".
Update October 2016: Australian actor and singer,
Kylie Minogue, thought it important to tell us
that
"Love is love" as part
of her campaign for LGBTQ marriage rights in Australia. Furthermore, "Love is love" was
also
one of slogans emblazoned on the placards
carried by activists fighting
for equal marriage rights for the LGBTQ community in Australia that same month.
It also forms
the title of a documentary about that
very community, just as it is also the
title of a book written by Shondrika Scott.
Figure Twelve: Apparently --
Love Is Love
We
were even informed on the BBCNews 24 Channel (08/10/2016, approximately
10:24 pm) that "Politics is politics", which was given in answer to the question why anyone could
possibly support Donald Trump
after his latest debacle. Indeed, one of the correspondents
working for UK Channel Four News, in a
report about a growing revolt in Parliament over the exact terms for Brexit,
informed viewers that supporters of a break with
the European Union in effect were replying that "A break is a break" (10/10/2016, approximately
07:06 pm).
Update 13/10/2016: The US First Lady,
Michelle Obama, also told her audience "Enough is enough!" in
response to the crude and offensive remarks uttered by Donald Trump in the 2016
Presidential Campaign, and earlier (approximately
11:12 into the following video):
Video Eight: Michelle Obama
--
"Enough Is Enough!"
Update 04/11/2016: UK Tories have been up in arms since the
High Court in London ruled that the UK
Government couldn't trigger
Article Fifty of the European Treaty,
initiating Brexit, without a vote in Parliament. The Tory
government is now planning to take this to the UK Supreme Court in order to have the
judgement overturned. In an interview with the BBC, Tory MP,
Bill Cash, a notorious anti-EU bloviater, had this to say: "The Supreme Court is the Supreme Court", when
asked about these moves (BBC News 24, 04/11/2016, approximately 07:34 pm).
Update 02/12/2016: During a Press
Conference, in answer to a question about the up-coming game against
Everton FC, José
Mourinho, the then manager of Manchester United, told reporters that "Everton is Everton".
Update 21/03/2017: In an
article published in The
Guardian, the Nigerian novelist,
Chimamanda Ngozi Adichie, had this to say in a
debate about gender identity: "A cis woman is a cis woman, and a trans woman is
a trans woman." The day before,
Michael Turner, Republican member of
The House of Representatives National Security Committee,
had the following to say (in a discussion about what was true or false about the
FBI's investigation into President Trump), "False is false" (20/03/2017,
approximately 01:10 pm, live on CNN).
Author and scientist,
Jeremy Bernstein, tells a story about a series
of lectures on Relativity he attended back in the 1950s, delivered by the
physicist,
Phillip Frank. Frank had just outlined the
famous
Double-Slit Experiment and was attempting to
describe the nature of electrons:
"What
were electrons -- waves, particles, both, neither? Electrons are electrons,
Professor Frank said." [Bernstein (2009), p.101. In fact the second sentence
should be "Electrons, Professor Frank said, are electrons." I have rendered it
the way I have so that the form "Fs are Fs" is plain for all to
see.]
Update 01/06/2017: During a radio interview on BBC 5 Live
(approx 09:10 pm), a woman who used to play for
Arsenal "Ladies" football/soccer team had this to say about games
(where her team played against less challenging sides), "Winning is winning".
Update 22/06/2017: Apparently, according to an interview about
declining electric guitar sales published in the
Washington Post, "Music is music".
Update 05/07/2017: The main character in the US TV
series,
Chance, had this to say when the value of a house he was
trying to sell was questioned, "The price is the price" (Season
1, Episode 4, The Mad Doctor,
approximately 07:00 into the programme).
Update 15/07/2017: In a television interview held at the
Wimbledon Tennis Tournament, when asked about
her tactics in the up-coming Women's Final, Spain tennis player and finalist,
Garbiñe
Muguruza,
said "My game is my game"
(approximately 01:45 pm, BBC Two).
Update 04/08/2017: We learnt today that in a conversation a few
months earlier between President Donald Trump and the Prime Minister of Australia,
Malcolm Turnbull, the latter had to remind
Trump -- in relation to an agreement over refugees, signed by President Barak
Obama, about which Trump wasn't happy -- that "A
deal is a deal". Incidentally, "A deal is a deal" is what Wyatt
Price, a character in the Netflix series,
The Man in the High Castle, had to say
(about 03:10 into
Season 3, Episode 6, History Ends).
Update 07/08/2017:
On BBC One, 06/08/2017, during the Pole Vault Final of the
2017 IAAF World Championship, one of the
commentators was underlining how important it is to complete a successful first
attempt, with the following words: "A first time clearance is a
first time clearance!" (approximately 07:35 pm).
Update 10/08/2017:
BBC Radio London carried a report about
the events that
weekend in commemoration of
The Battle of Lewisham, 13/08/1977 --
when the Nazis were stopped in their tracks by local people allied with anti-fascists.
As part of that report they interviewed one of the organisers of this series of
events, Dr John Price, who told a story of a local woman who back then had been
very fearful of 'foreigners' moving into her neighbourhood, but who subsequently
learnt to get along with them, sharing recipes and music: "People are people"
she said.
Update 12/08/2017:
Following on the
lethal Nazi violence in Charlottesville,
Virginia,
Cornell Brooks, the former President of the
NAACP,
criticised Donald Trump for his mealy-mouthed 'condemnation', saying "The facts
are the facts" (live on CNN, approximately 09:17 pm).
Update 14/08/2017: During a rather useless interview on CNN,
will.i.am, when asked whether representatives
of Big
Business who were condemning the above display of hate and racism are to be
believed, replied "Talkers are talkers" (approx 09:45 pm on
Quest Means Business).
Update 29/08/2017:
Don Lemon, a CNN anchor, responded to a
discussion of the 2016 US Presidential election with the following comment "The
results are the results" (CNN, 29/08/2017, approximately 03:45 am), and in this video
he informed his viewers that "A Nazi symbol is a Nazi symbol" (approximately 02:17), in
relation to CNN's firing of Republican troll,
Jeffrey Lord:
Video Nine: "A Nazi Symbol
Is A Nazi Symbol"
Update 22/09/2017: On the
Bill Maher Show on Sky Atlantic,
Bob Costas found it important to tell the
audience that "Evidence is evidence", in relation to the ongoing probe into Donald Trump
and his election victory,
which he repeated on CNN (12/12/2017, approximately 00:38 am -- but originally
broadcast in October the same year), when he was challenging the wild idea that
those who claim that American Football causes irreversible brain damage are
peddling a 'left-wing conspiracy to undermine America's game' -- "Evidence is
evidence", he said.
The same day
(22/10/2017), in an interview, we also heard Jeremy Corbyn tell us that "A wage cut
is a wage cut".
Update 10/10/2017: Approximately twenty-five minutes into the new
series on Sky Atlantic (The
Deuce, Season 1, Episode 3, The Principle Is All), created
by
David Simon, the executive producer of
The Wire, which seeks to expose the
growth of the pornography industry in New York in the early 1970s, one character
wondered if she could make sex films to sell in Europe (since they had much more
relaxed censorship regulations at that time), to which another character replied,
"Europe is Europe". And, in the Netflix series
Shooter (Season 2,
Episode 5), we were told that "Music is music" (approximately 28:30 into that episode).
Update 14/10/2017: In an interview on BBC Breakfast TV about
the misuse of drugs, the interviewee told the interviewer: "Safe drugs should be
safe drugs" (approximately 08:49 am) -- one supposes a
modal version of the "is" of predication
("should") is
no less relevant.
Update 21/10/2017: In a discussion on CNN about Donald Trump's
predilection for "truthful hyperbole" (i.e., lies),
Tony Schwartz (co-author with Trump of the best
seller,
The Art of the Deal), interjected "The truth
is the truth", to which CNN anchor,
John Berman, replied, "Facts are facts"
(approximately 02:20 am). As if to underline this point, CNN has been running a
"Facts are facts"
advert several times a day for many months,
aimed at countering the recent drift by the right-wing media in the USA
toward the denial of facts. Of course, 'facts' have been political footballs for all
ruling-classes for nearly as many years as the number of lies Donald Trump has told.
Update 29/10/2017: Again on CNN, in a programme entitled
Leading Women Japan, we were told that "A
sushi chef is a sushi chef" (approximately 01:45 am).
Update 07/11/2017: In a recent book about anti-fascism, the author
argues that the number of active UK fascists declined steeply in the years
immediately after WW2, and that was partly the result of anti-fascist action
itself and partly because the UK had withdrawn from Palestine -- preventing the
fascists fomenting anti-Semitism in Britain since there were now no Zionist
terror bombs there aimed at the UK military. Because of this, several
Mosleyite fascists swapped sides and became
anti-fascists. The author adds:
"Although many of the group [presumably those who changed sides -- RL] were
Zionists, the official stance of the group was 'Palestine is Palestine and
Hackney is Hackney. One situation has nothing
to do with the other'." [Bray (2017), p.234, footnote 145. Link added. The London Borough of
Hackney had at the time, and in places still has, a large
Jewish community.]
It
would surely be perverse to argue that what they really meant was "Palestine is
identical with Palestine, and Hackney is identical with Hackney".
Update 10/11/2017: About 29:00 into the Netflix series,
Ozark (Season 1, Episode 5,
Ruling Days), we were reminded that "Money is
money".
Update 23/11/2017: Even 'left-wing' UK news and polemics site,
The Canary, has joined in the fun (in an
article about the appalling treatment of the disabled by the current Tory
regime):
"I'm tired of writing about this, but I'm
more tired of ignorant politicians and their supporters ignoring my friends and
loved ones. Enough is enough." [Quoted from
here, accessed 23/11/2017).
Again, as noted earlier, everyone with an axe to grind, or is fed up with whatever they are fed up
with, now tends to use this set of words. Here are just a few more recent examples
(to add to the many cited earlier):
here,
here,
here,
here and
here. In fact, a Google search found
over 400,000 hits for this sentence alone!
Update 13/12/2017: After the Democratic Party scored a
narrow victory in the US Senate race in deep
red Republican, Alabama, Donald Trump tweeted "A win is a win." [I won't post a
link to Trump's Twitter feed because my computer might start oozing
sewage as a result.]
Update 20/12/2017: On CNN's Don Lemon show, Kierna Mayo, the former
editor of Ebony magazine, informed viewers that "News is news is news"
(approx 03:40 am) in response to the claim that those who watch
Fox and Friends don't know the difference
between news and entertainment.
Update 23/12/2017: On MUTV (Manchester United TV, approximately 10:42 pm), José Mourinho made the following comment about a decision taken by the referee
in the match against Leicester City FC -- referring to a card issued during the
match -- "A red is a red", and few days later (02/01/2018), after their
away win to Everton FC, he responded to questions about criticism of his players
with the following comment, "The criticism is the criticism."
Update 04/01/2018: UK TV Channel Five has just aired a film called
19th
Wife, which largely concerns
the murder of a 'prophet' in a
polygamous Mormon community. One character,
Jordan, who was investigating that murder and who was repeatedly refused access to a
police report, was told to stop asking for that report by his friend, Queenie,
who managed to persuade him to desist by reminding him that "No is no!"
(approximately 30:00 into the film). Indeed, a few days later UK Channel,
Film Four, aired the movie,
Now You See Me (06/01/2018); at about 15:00 into that film one of the characters is heard to say "A promise is a
promise!".
Update 23/01/2018: Apparently, once more, "Enough is enough" for the 'radical'
website,
The Canary, which waxed indignant, and
rightly so, about excessive teacher workloads in the UK:
"Enough is enough
"The public sector
pay cap means many teachers are
struggling to get by. There are
growing calls from teachers' unions to demand a
government-funded pay rise for teachers. And there's
a crisis in teacher recruitment and retention."
[Quoted from
here; accessed 23/01/2018. Bold emphasis and
links in the original.]
Update 27/01/2018: As part of a discussion on CNN about the
allegations that
Nikki Haley -- the
ex-US Ambassador to the United
Nations and former Republican Governor of South Carolina -- is having an affair
with Donald Trump,
Erin Gloria Ryan, a senior editor at
The Daily Beast, described this accusation
as a classic example of sexism, saying "Sexism is sexism" (04:40 am).
The
next day, the
Talking Pictures Channel aired the Laurel and
Hardy film,
Block-Heads, where Stan says, after he has
returned from World War One, "War is war" (at about 06:00 into the movie).
BBC TV also broadcast the movie,
What Doesn't Kill You; at one point in the
film, two
characters were shown discussing the money being offered by a third party for
kidnapping a dog, when one says "5000 is 5000" (about 12:00 into the
movie).
Update 03/02/2018: Near the beginning of the US cop drama, Blue
Bloods (Season 8, Episode 2,
Ghosts of the Past), in a discussion about
local politics, one character interjected, "A politician is a politician"
(approximately 06:00 into the programme), and in the excellent film,
Lincoln, 'Mrs Lincoln' came out with this
comment "The past is the past" (approximately 64:00 into the film).
Update 14/02/2018: UK BBC One aired the first episode of their new
mini-series, Collateral (aired at 09:00 pm on Monday 12/02/2018); about
07:00 in, as part of a discussion about the UK Labour Party,
one of the characters, Suki Vincent, came out with this comment: "The system is
the system". A week earlier,
Jeffrey Toobin, a CNN legal expert, informed
their viewers
that "Lying is lying" in a discussion of the Sex-Pest-in-Chief ensconced
in the White House, and in
Season 2, Episode 9 (Deception) of the
Sky Atlantic series,
House, one of the characters informed us
that "Attention is attention" -- approximately 20:00 into the
programme. Also seen on Twitter: "Power
is power".
Update 19/02/2018: In a report about male strippers, BBC reporter,
Emily Maitliss, informed viewers that one of the men
involved, who had been scratched by several women, replied "A
scratch is a scratch", when asked if it hurt. Two days later, on
CNN, we were told that "Talk is talk" (approximately 04:34 pm), and the next day,
also on CNN, viewers were informed that "A gold medal is a gold medal" (01:48
pm,
during coverage of the Winter Olympics).
Update 23/02/2018: During the BBC's coverage of the Winter Olympics,
we were told that "A medal is a medal" (approximately 01:58 pm, BBC One). The next
day during the BBC's coverage of the Olympic Curling competition,
Steve Cram informed viewers that "A bad shot is
a bad shot" (approximately 00:08 pm, BBC One). The same day, during the coverage of
the Bobsleigh competition in the same Olympics, one of the commentators thought
it important to tell us that "The rules are the rules" (10:42 am, BBC One).
Update 03/03/2018: Approximately 34:00 into the film,
The Revenant, we were told that "Business
is business", and approximately 24:00 into a re-run of the ITV series,
Endeavour, one of the
characters, 'Inspector Thursday', found it necessary to remind us that "Sudden
death is sudden death" (Girl,
Season 1, Episode 1). The same day, in relation to
the Mueller investigation into alleged Russian
interference in the 2016 US Presidential elections, Republican Congressman,
Tom Rooney, informed viewers that "His
investigation is his investigation" (CNN, approximately 08:50 am).
And we were
reminded that "An American is an America" in an
article highly critical of right-wing
pundit,
Ann Coulter (written by Brianna Rennix and published in
that excellent bi-monthly journal,
Current Affairs).
Even Canadian Marxist, Dave McNally found it
important to point out that "A tool is a tool,
a loaf of bread is a loaf of bread." [McNally (2001), p.119.]
Update 07/10/2019: US
Congresswoman,
Alexandria Ocasio-Cortez,
saw fit to
tell her Twitter followers that "A cage is a
cage" when referring to the high number of individuals incarcerated in the USA. Believe it or not,
in a later Essay
I have argued that
"A soul is a soul" (but readers should also check the context(!)).
"The law of Identity, I
stated, was not explicated as a coordinate principle till a comparatively recent
period. The earliest author in whom I have found this done, is
Antonius
Andreas, a scholar of
Scotus,
who flourished at the end of the thirteenth and beginning of the fourteenth
century. The schoolman, in the fourth book of his Commentary of Aristotle's
Metaphysics, -- a commentary which is full of the most ingenious and
original views, -- not only asserts to the law of Identity a coördinate dignity
with the law of Contradiction, but, against Aristotle, he maintains that the
principle of Identity, and not the principle of Contradiction, is the one
absolutely first. The formula in which Andreas expressed it was Ens est ens.
[Being is being -- RL.] Subsequently to this author, the question concerning the
relative priority of the two laws of Identity and of Contradiction became one
much agitated in the schools; though there were also found some who asserted to
the law of Excluded Middle this supreme rank." [Quoted from
here (accessed 04/10/2014).
Bold emphasis and links added.]
Which proves, if proof were needed, that this
is a feature of Latin, too.
This shows that in English -- and apparently in German, too --
sentences and clauses of the form "F is F" (or "Fs
are Fs") and "NN is NN" can be
informative (where "F" is a
verb-, or
noun-phrase, "NN" a Proper Name),
and that they are as common as the lies emanating from the
Trump White House. I suspect the same is the case with other Indo-European
languages.
Indeed,
this site tells us (clearly in French) that
"Rome est Rome", and
this one quotes Theresa May as follows: "Brexit
est Brexit".
In
order to preserve the reader's sanity, that is the very last example of this
locution I will quote or cite in this Essay!
None of the above
are telling us that, for example, "Rape is identical with rape",
or "A goal is identical with a goal", "A kitchen table is identical with a
kitchen table", "Power is identical with power", "No is identical with No" --
nor yet that "Enough is identical with enough"!
Update 11/07/2022:
Below, I
have responded to an argument in an on-line article that attempts to show that
sentences like the above are all just empty tautologies, which assumed fact also
(supposedly) implies change
is impossible(!).
41.
It isn't easy, therefore, to agree with much in this passage from
TAR:
"[I]t is impossible simply to stare at the world
as it immediately presents itself to our eyes and hope to understand it. To make
sense of the world, we must bring to it a framework composed of elements of our
past experience; what we have learned of others' experience, both in the present
and in the past; and of our later reflections on and theories about this
experience." [Rees (1998), p.63.]
For one thing, Rees failed to explain how it is possible for later generations build a
"framework" out of the experiences of earlier generations. Even if
the latter were accessible to anyone else (but, are the central nervous systems
of our ancestors open and available to us for inspection?), how could they build
"experiences" into "frameworks"? Does this apparent skill require some sort of training -- or
are we all supposed to be natural 'epistemological architects'?
Of course, it could be argued that Rees meant that later
generations learn from the reported, or the recorded, experiences of previous generations,
but even then we would still face the problem explaining how they can be built into
"frameworks".
And, who exactly does the building? Do we all have to rebuild from scratch --
single-handedly, using the entire body of human experience -- in effect
re-inventing the epistemological wheel? Or, do we accomplish this in small groups,
collectively?
The last option would seem to be the one favoured by anyone
committed to the social nature of language and knowledge. But, even then, how
does it work even here? Do we possess a sort of
collective 'consciousness' that enables us all to gain access the latest updates,
examining each other's 'inner representations' so we can compare notes? Do we intuit new knowledge and
install it in our brains as a group, directly, as a sort of job lot?
The above is in fact another way of expressing a point
made more fully in later Parts of Essays Three, and Thirteen
Part Three: DM-theorists have
clearly devoted
very little thought to the
implications of their avowed belief in the social and historical nature of
language and knowledge -- that is, over and above repeating the classic
'dialectical' formulations of either or both. Given the way dialecticians actually picture knowledge and language, it would
be a minor miracle if a single one of us ever formed the
same 'abstract' or 'concrete' idea as anyone else about anything whatsoever. Even worse, given the DM-view of the
LOI, none of us could
do this, anyway.
[More on this in
Part Two.]
In fact,
at best, lone
'abstractors' (if these mythical beasts of lore actually exist) would
be able to cobble-together concepts that only coincidentally
agreed with those of anyone else -- if, that is, the 'process of abstraction'
were itself viable, to begin with. And, even if there were such a coincidental
overlap, it would be impossible to verify any of the supposed results, just as
it would be impossible to confirm whether we all shared the same understanding
of the word "confirm", let alone "same" -- or
even the word "word", for goodness sake!
41a.
This passage
from TAR is rather odd in itself; it will be subjected to detailed analysis in
Essay Twelve Part Four.
42. Admittedly, John Rees is
here criticising Hegel's theoretical approach to knowledge. But, as
we shall see in other Essays posted at this site, the simple inversion of Hegel's system to
create
'Materialist Dialectics', its 'rational core'
-- even if
this were augmented by continual checks against reality, and constantly tested
in practice -- can't in any way alter its Idealist form, and hence
its content.
Several of Marx and Engels's works listed
below are linked to the Marxist Internet Archive, but since Lawrence &
Wishart threatened legal action over copyright infringement many of those links
no longer work. However, all of those Marx and Engels's writings can now be accessed
here.
Ackrill, J. (1997a), Essays On Plato And Aristotle (Oxford
University Press).
--------, (1997b), 'Plato And The Copula: Sophist
251-259', in Ackrill (1997a), pp.80-92, Allen (1965), pp.207-18, and Vlastos
(1971), pp.210-22.
Adelmann, F. (1975) (ed.), Philosophical
Investigations In The USSR (Martinus Nijhoff).
Allen, R. (1965) (ed.), Studies In Plato's
Metaphysics (Routledge).
Anscombe, G., and Geach, P. (1961), Three Philosophers (Blackwell).
Archer, M., Bhaskar, R., Collier, A., Lawson, T., and Norrie, A.
(1998) (eds.), Critical Realism. Essential Readings (Routledge).
Ayer, A. (1959) (ed.),
Logical Positivism (The Free Press).
Baker, G., and Hacker, P.
(1988), Wittgenstein. Rules,
Grammar And Necessity, Volume Two (Blackwell, 2nd ed.).
--------, (2005), Wittgenstein:
Understanding And Meaning. Volume One Of An Analytic Commentary On The
Philosophical Investigations. Part One: Essays (Blackwell,
2nd
ed.).
Barnes, J.
(1982), The Presocratic Philosophers (Routledge).
--------, (2001) (ed.), Early Greek Philosophy
(Penguin Books).
--------, (2009),
Truth, Etc. Six Lectures On Ancient Logic (Oxford University Press).
Beaney, M. (1996), Frege. Making Sense (Duckworth).
Bernstein, J. (2009), Quantum Leaps (Harvard University Press).
Bono, J. (1995), The Word Of God And The
Language Of Men, Ficino To Descartes, Volume One: Interpreting Nature In Early
Modern Science And Medicine (University of Wisconsin Press).
Brading, K., and Castellani, E. (2003) (eds.), Symmetries In Physics.
Philosophical Reflections (Cambridge University Press).
Bray,
M. (2017), Antifa. The Anti-Fascist Handbook (Melville House).
Brown, L.
(1994), 'The Verb "To Be" In Greek Philosophy: Some Remarks', in Everson (1994),
pp.212-36.
--------, (2003), 'Being In The Sophist: A Syntactical Enquiry',
in Fine (2003b), pp.445-78.
Callinicos, A. (1978), The Logic Of Capital.
Unpublished D.Phil. Thesis, Oxford University.
Castellani, E. (1998) (ed.), Interpreting Bodies. Classical And Quantum
Objects In Modern Physics (Princeton University Press).
Caygill, H. (1995), A Kant Dictionary
(Blackwell).
Cook, D. (1973), Language In The Philosophy
Of Hegel (Mouton).
Copleston, F. (2003), A History Of
Philosophy, Eleven Volumes (Continuum Press).
Cornford, F. (1935), Plato's Theory Of
Knowledge (Routledge).
--------, (1997), Plato's Cosmology. The Timaeus Of
Plato (Hackett Publishing Company).
Cornforth, F. (1963), Dialectical Materialism. An
Introduction. Volume Three: Theory Of Knowledge (Lawrence
& Wishart, 3rd
ed.).
--------, (1976), Materialism And The
Dialectical Method (Lawrence & Wishart, 5th ed.).
[A copy of the 1968 edition is available
here.]
Cowley, F. (1991), Metaphysical Delusion (Prometheus
Books).
Daston, L. (1994), 'Baconian Facts, Academic Civility, And The
Prehistory Of Objectivity', in Megill (1994), pp.37-63.
Daston, L., and Galison, P. (2007),
Objectivity (Zone Books).
Davidson, D. (2005), Truth And Predication (MIT Press).
Inwood, M. (1992), A Hegel Dictionary (Blackwell).
Ionescu, S. (2007), 'Davidson
And The Problem Of Predication'. [Unfortunately, this link no loner
works. As far as I know, this paper is only available
on-line.]
Jackson, T.
(1936),
Dialectics(Lawrence
& Wishart). [This links to a PDF.]
Jacquette,
D. (2006) (ed.), A Companion To Philosophical Logic (Blackwell).
James, C. (1980), Notes On Dialectics
(Allison & Busby). [Selections of Part 2 have been reproduced
here.]
Kahn, C.
(1994), Anaximander And
the Origin Of Greek Cosmology (Hackett Publishing)
--------, (2003), The Verb 'Be' In Ancient Greek (Hackett
Publishing).
Kneale, K., and Kneale, M. (1962), The Development Of Logic (Oxford
University Press).
Knuuttila, S., and Hintikka, J. (1986)
(eds.), The Logic Of Being. Historical Studies (Reidel).
Koyré, A. (1957), From The Closed World To
The Infinite Universe (The John Hopkins University Press).
--------, (1968), Newtonian Studies (University
of Chicago Press).
Kraut, M. (1992) (ed.) The Cambridge Companion To Plato (Cambridge
University Press).
Ladyman, J., and Bigaj, T. (2010), 'The
Principle Of The Identity Of Indiscernibles And Quantum Mechanics',
Philosophy of Science77, 1, pp.117-36.
Lawler, J. (1982), 'Hegel On Logical And
Dialectical Contradictions, And Misinterpretations From Bertrand Russell To
Lucio Colletti', in Marquit, Moran, and Truitt (1982), pp.11-44.
Lazerowitz, M., and Ambrose, A. (1976), Philosophical Theories
(Mouton).
MacBride, F. (2006),
'Predicate Reference', in Lepore and Smith (2006), pp.422-75.
Magee, G. (2008), Hegel And The Hermetic
Tradition (Cornell University Press). [The Introduction to this book can be
accessed here.]
Malcolm, N. (2001), Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir
(Oxford University Press, 2nd
ed.).
Mandel, E. (1976),
'Introduction' to Marx (1976), pp.11-86.
Marquit, E., Moran, P., and Truitt, W. (1982)
(eds.),
Dialectical Contradictions And Contemporary Marxist Discussions. Studies in
Marxism Volume Ten (Marxist
Educational Press).
Mates, B. (1972), Elementary Logic
(Oxford University Press).
--------, (1979),
'Identity And Predication In Plato', Phronesis24, pp.211-29, reprinted
in Knuuttila and Hintikka (1986), pp.29-47.
Mendelson, E. (2009),
Introduction
To Mathematical Logic (Chapman & Hall, 5th
ed.).
Mepham, J., and Ruben, D-H. (1979) (eds.), Issues In Marxist Philosophy.
Volume One: Dialectics And Method (Harvester).
Mercer, C. (2001), Leibniz's Metaphysics.
Its Origins And Development (Cambridge University Press).
Milton, J. (1981), 'The Origin And
Development Of The Concept Of The "Laws Of Nature"', Archives Europeénes De
Sociologie22, pp.173-95.
--------, (1998), 'Laws Of Nature', in Garber
and Ayers, Volume One (1998), pp.680-701.
Modrak, D. (2001), Aristotle's Theory Of Language And Meaning
(Cambridge University Press).
Mourelatos, P. (2008), The Route Of Parmenides (Parmenides Publishing.
Revised and expanded edition.).
Needham, J. (1951a),
'Human Laws And Laws Of Nature In China And The West (1)', Journal of the
History of Ideas 12, 1,
pp.3-32; revised version reprinted in Needham (1979), pp.299-331.
--------, (1951b), 'Human Laws And Laws Of
Nature In China And The West (2)', Journal of the History of Ideas 12, 2, pp.194-230; revised version
reprinted in Needham (1979), pp.299-331.
--------, (1979), The Grand Titration.
Science And Society In East And West (University of Toronto Press).
Noonan, H. (2001), Frege. A Critical Introduction (Polity
Press).
Novack, G. (1965), The Origins Of Materialism (Pathfinder
Press).
Owen, G. (1966), 'The Platonism Of Aristotle', Proceedings of
the British Academy51, pp.125-50; reprinted in Owen (1986),
pp.200-20.
--------, (1971), 'Plato On Not-Being', in Vlastos (1971), pp.223-67, Owen
(1986), pp.104-37, and Fine (2003b), pp.416-54.
--------, (1986), Logic, Science And Dialectic. Collected
Papers In Greek Philosophy (Duckworth).
Pelletier, F. (1990), Parmenides, Plato
And The Semantics Of Not-Being (Harvard University Press).
Penrose, R. (1989), The Emperor's New
Mind. Concerning Computers, Minds, And The Laws Of Physics (Vintage Books).
--------, (1995), Shadows Of The Mind
(Vintage Books).
--------, (2005), The Road To Reality. A
Complete Guide To The Laws Of The Universe (Vintage Books).
--------, (2011), Cycles Of Time. An
Extraordinary New View Of The Universe (Vintage Books).
Peters E. (1967), Greek Philosophical
Terms. A Historical Lexicon (New York University Press).
Pippin, R. (1978), 'Hegel's Metaphysics And
The Problem Of Contradiction', Journal of the History of Philosophy16, pp.301-12; reprinted in Stewart
(1996), pp.239-52.
Pitcher, G. (1978), 'Wittgenstein, Nonsense And Lewis Carroll',
in Fann (1978), pp.315-35.
Plato, (1997a),
Complete Works,
edited by John Cooper
(Hackett Publishing).
--------, (1997b),
Sophist, in Plato (1997a), pp.235-93.
--------, (1997c),
Timaeus, in Plato (1997a), pp.1224-91.
Robb, K. (1983) (ed.), Language And
Thought In Early Greek Philosophy (Monist Library of Philosophy).
Rosenthal, J. (1998), The Myth Of
Dialectics (Macmillan).
Ruby, J. (1986), 'The Origins Of Scientific
Law', Journal of the History of Ideas47, pp.341-59; reprinted in Weinert (1995), pp.289-315.
Russell, B. (1937),
The Principles Of
Mathematics (George Allen & Unwin, 2nd
ed.). [This links to a PDF of the Routledge 2010 edition.]
--------, (1961), History Of Western
Philosophy (George Allen &
Unwin).
Ryle, G. (1949), 'A Review Of Meaning
And Necessity By Rudolf Carnap', Philosophy24, pp.69-76,
reprinted as 'Discussion Of Rudolf Carnap: Meaning And
Necessity' in Ryle (1971a), pp.225-35.
--------, (1959), 'Philosophical Arguments', in Ayer (1959),
pp.327-44, reprinted in Ryle (1971b), pp.194-211.
--------, (1973), Problems Of Everyday Life (Monad Press).
--------, (1986), Notebooks 1933-35
(Columbia University Press). [Parts of this book can be accessed
here (this links to a PDF).]
Tugendhat, E. (1982), Traditional And Analytic Philosophy
(Cambridge University Press).
Urmson, J (1990), The Greek Philosophical Vocabulary ( Duckworth).
Vlastos, G. (1971) (ed.), Plato. A Collection Of Critical Essays.
Volume One: Metaphysics And Epistemology
(Doubleday Anchor).
Wallis, R. (1972), NeoPlatonism
(Charles Scribner's Sons).
Weiner, J. (1990), Frege In Perspective (Cornell
University Press).
--------, (1999), Frege (Oxford
University Press).
--------, (2004), Frege Explained. From
Arithmetic To Analytic Philosophy (Open Court). [This is a revised edition of Weiner
(1999).]
Weinert, F. (1995) (ed.), Laws Of Nature:
Essays On The Philosophical, Scientific And Historical Dimensions (Walter de
Gruyter).
White, J. (1996),
Karl Marx And The
Intellectual Origins Of Dialectical Materialism (Macmillan).
Wittgenstein, L. (1958),
Philosophical
Investigations,
translated by
G. E. M. Anscombe (Blackwell, 2nd
ed.). [This links to a PDF.]
--------, (1974), Philosophical Grammar,
translated by Anthony Kenny (Blackwell).
--------, (2009), Philosophical
Investigations, translated by G. E. M. Anscombe, revised by Peter Hacker
and Joachim
Schulte (Blackwell, 4th
ed.).
Wolcher, L. (1999), 'A
New And Superior Theory Of Ideology?', The Independent Review 4,
2, pp.291-302. [This is available
here as a PDF.]
Woods, A., and Grant, T. (1995/2007),
Reason In Revolt. Marxism And
Modern Science (Wellred Publications, Ist/2nd
edition).
[The on-line version now
appears to be the second edition.]
Zilsel, E. (1942), 'The Genesis Of The
Concept Of Physical Law', Philosophical Review51, pp.245-67; reprinted in Zilsel (2000),
pp.96-122.
--------, (2000), The Social Origins Of
Modern Science (Kluwer Academic Press).