If you are using Internet Explorer 10
(or later), you might find some of the links I have used won't work properly
unless you switch to 'Compatibility View' (in the Tools Menu); for IE11 select
'Compatibility View Settings' and then add this site (anti-dialectics.co.uk). Microsoft's new browser,
Edge, automatically
renders these links compatible; Windows 10 does likewise.
However, if you are using Windows 10,
Microsoft's browsers, IE11 and Edge, unfortunately appear to colour these links
somewhat erratically. They are meant to be mid-blue but those two browsers
render them intermittently light blue, yellow, purple and red!
Firefox and Chrome reproduce them correctly.
Several browsers also appear
to underline
these links erratically. Many are underscored boldly in black, others more
lightly in blue! They are all meant to be the latter.
Unfortunately,
Internet Explorer 11 will no longer play the video I have embedded below. As far as I can tell, it plays as intended in other Browsers.
However, if you have
Privacy Badger [PB] installed, they won't play in Google Chrome unless you
disable PB for this site.
Having said that,
I have just discovered that this video will play in IE11 if you have
upgraded to Windows 10! It looks like the problem is with Windows 7 and earlier
versions of that operating system.
As is the case with all my
work, nothing here should be read as an attack
either on Historical Materialism [HM] -- a theory I fully accept --, or,
indeed,
on revolutionary socialism. I remain as committed to the self-emancipation of the
working class and the dictatorship of the proletariat as I was when I first became a revolutionary
thirty-five years ago.
The
difference between
Dialectical Materialism [DM] and HM, as I see it, is explained
here.
~~~~~~oOo~~~~~~
This Essay depends on much
that has been established in
Part One,
which
should therefore be read in conjunction with it.
It is important to note
that a good 50% of my case
against DM has been relegated to the
End Notes. This has been done to allow the main body of the Essay to flow a little more
smoothly. This means that if readers want to appreciate fully my case against
DM, they will need to consult this material. In many cases, I have qualified my
comments (often adding greater detail and substantiating evidence), and I have
even raised objections (some obvious, many not -- and, indeed, some that will
have occurred to the reader) to my own arguments -- which I have then answered.
[I explain why I have adopted this tactic in
Essay One.]
If readers skip this material, then my answers to any
objections they might have will be missed, as will the extra evidence and
argument.
[Since I have been
debating this theory with comrades for over 25 years, I have heard all the
objections there are! Many of the more recent on-line debates are listed here.]
Several readers have
complained about the number of links I have added to these Essays because they
say it makes them very difficult to read. Of course, DM-supporters can hardly
lodge that complaint since they believe everything is interconnected, and
that must surely apply even to Essays that
attempt to debunk that very idea. However, to those
who find such links do make these Essays difficult to read I say this: ignore them -- unless you want to access
further supporting evidence and argument for a particular point, or a certain
topic fires your interest.
Others wonder why I have linked to familiar
subjects and issues that are part of common knowledge (such as the names of
recent Presidents of the
USA, UK Prime Ministers, the names of rivers and mountains, the titles of
popular films, or certain words
that are in common usage). I have done so for the following reason: my Essays
are read all over the world and by people from all 'walks of life', so I can't
assume that topics which are part of common knowledge in 'the west' are equally
well-known across the planet -- or, indeed, by those who haven't had the benefit
of the sort of education that is generally available in the 'advanced economies',
or any at
all. Many of my readers also struggle with English, so any help I can give them
I will continue to provide.
Finally on this specific topic, several of the aforementioned links
connect to
web-pages that regularly change their
URLs, or which vanish from the
Internet altogether. While I try to update them when it becomes apparent
that they have changed or have disappeared I can't possibly keep on top of
this all the time. I would greatly appreciate it, therefore, if readers
informed me
of any dead links they happen to notice.
In general, links to 'Haloscan'
no longer seem to work, so readers needn't tell me about them! Links to
RevForum, RevLeft, Socialist Unity and The North Star also appear to have died.
In addition,
phrases like "ruling-class theory", "ruling-class view of reality",
"ruling-class ideology" (etc.) used at this site (in connection with
Traditional Philosophy and DM), aren't meant to
suggest that all or even most members of various ruling-classes
actually invented these ways of thinking or of
seeing the world (although some of them did -- for example,
Heraclitus,
Plato,
Cicero,
and
Marcus Aurelius).
They are intended to
highlight theories (or "ruling ideas") that are conducive to, or which rationalise the
interests of the various ruling-classes history has inflicted on humanity, whoever invents them.
Up until
recently this
dogmatic approach to knowledge had almost invariably been promoted by thinkers who
either relied on ruling-class patronage, or who, in one capacity or another, helped run
the system
for the elite.**
However, that will become the
central topic of Parts Two and Three of Essay Twelve (when they are published); until then, the reader is
directed here,
here, and
here for
more
details.
[**Exactly
how this applies to DM will, of course, be explained in the other Essays
published at this site (especially
here,
here,
and
here).
In addition to the three links in the previous paragraph, I have summarised the
argument (but this time aimed at absolute beginners!)
here.]
Finally, a word of warning: this is
perhaps the most convoluted and difficult of the Essays so far published at this site.
I have tried many times to simplify it and make it clearer but I am far from sure I have
succeeded. Even so, I will continue striving to render this
Essay more straight-forward and easier to follow in the many re-writes that this will require
over the next few years.
Having said that, I have also explained
here
why there is an emphasis on
simplicity and clarity at this site, so despite the above comment DM-fans can console themselves with the
thought that, as difficult as this Essay is, it palls into insignificance
next to the prolixity of Hegel's 'Logic'.
~~~~~~oOo~~~~~~
As of March 2024, this
Essay is just over 73,000
words long; a summary of some of its main ideas can be found
here.
The material presented
below does not
represent my final view of any of the issues raised; it is merely 'work in
progress'.
Anyone using these links must remember that
they will be skipping past supporting argument and evidence set out in earlier
sections.
If your Firewall/Browser has a pop-up blocker, you will need to press the
"Ctrl" key at the same time or these and the other links here won't work!
I have adjusted the
font size used at this site to ensure that even those with impaired
vision can read what I have to say. However, if the text is still either too
big or too small for you, please adjust your browser settings!
In
Part One of this Essay, it was argued that not only have dialecticians made
no attempt to tell us -- even vaguely -- what their "Totality" is, so
that we might have some idea what their theory is actually about, it is
in fact impossible for them to do so. That isn't just because such an endeavour would
itself be riddled with paradox and confusion, it is because of the defective
logical and conceptual tools
dialecticians inherited from
Hegel
have only succeeded in crippling their ability to account for anything whatsoever,
never mind their
"Totality". In the end, the DM-"Totality"
turns out to be no different from
Nirvana,
about which (logically) nothing could be said.
[That explains the many
allusions to the via
negativa of Mystical Theology there were in Part One.]
In this Part of Essay Eleven we will see how this
insurmountable problem has completely hobbled DM-Wholism -- the idea that
the mysterious "Totality" forms a Cosmos-wide Unity where part and whole are
interconnected by "internal
relations" so that the nature of each is determined by all, and the nature
of all is determined by each.
[The doctrine of "internal relations" will be
further dissected in Essay Four Part Two.]
As I pointed out at
the end of Part One (as
well as here and
here), the
belief that everything is part of an interconnected Whole is shared by most
versions of ancient and modern Idealism, as well as all known forms of Mysticism. That is
particularly true of the strain of Esoteric Mysticism which shaped Hegel's
obscure ideas:
Hermeticism.
"Another parallel between Hermeticism and Hegel is the doctrine of
internal relations. For the Hermeticists, the cosmos is not a loosely connected,
or to use Hegelian language, externally related set of particulars. Rather,
everything in the cosmos is internally related, bound up with everything
else.... This principle is most clearly expressed in the so-called Emerald
TabletofHermes Trismegistus, which begins with the famous lines
'As above, so below.' This maxim became the central tenet of Western occultism, for it laid
the basis for a doctrine of the unity of the cosmos through sympathies and
correspondences between its various levels. The most important implication of
this doctrine is the idea that man is the microcosm, in which the whole of the
macrocosm is reflected.... The universe is
an internally related whole pervaded by cosmic energies." [Magee (2008),
p.13. Quotation marks altered to conform to the
conventions adopted at this site. Paragraphs merged.]
However, that particular topic will be addressed in more detail
in Essay Fourteen Part One (summary
here; see
also here and
here); this
Part of Essay Eleven will focus mainly on the finer details of this obscure
doctrine -- that is, if any sense can be made of them --, and not so much with
from where
this ancient dogma originated.
Finally, since this entire project began as a
critique of Rees (1998), I will begin with his attempt to give some sort of account
of DM-Holism.
Integral to Rees's
less than half-hearted 'definition'
of the "Totality" is the following analysis of the relationship between part and
whole:
"[W]hen we bring these terms
[belonging to the totality] into relation with each other their meaning is
transformed…. In a dialectical system, the entire nature of the part is
determined by its relationships with the other parts and so with the whole. The
part makes the whole, and the whole makes the parts. In this analysis, it is not
just the case that the whole is more than the sum of the parts but also that the
parts become more than they are individually by being part of a whole…. [F]or dialectical
materialists the whole is more than the simple sum of its parts." [Rees (1998),
pp.5, 77. Paragraphs merged.]1
As usual,
no evidence is given
in support
of these universal theses. Instead, a few trite examples
are wheeled out that supposedly 'illustrate' their validity (they will be examined
below), but, as
is the case with other areas of Dialectical Mysticism, it is assumed that the mere assertion
of a bold thesis will command our respect, if not our complete acceptance.
Anyone who rejects, disagrees with, or even questionsthese dogmatic theses
has obviously failed to get the point and clearly doesn't 'understand' dialectics.
Nevertheless, there appear to be several related claims that are being advanced by Rees (and others
-- on that, see Note 1):
G1: The entire nature
of a part is determined by its relation with the other parts and with the whole.
G2: The part makes the whole and the
whole makes the part.
G3: The whole is more than the sum of
its parts.
G4: Each part becomes more
when it is part of a whole than it would otherwise have been (individually)
apart from that whole.
However, given the nature of the "Totality",
G4 can't be correct. If all parts are already situated somewhere inside
this mysterious 'container' (the "Totality"), how is it possible for them to become
"more than they [were]
individually" on their own? Surely, the whole point of this theory is that parts
can't exist as individuals separate from the whole?
Universal interconnectedness was supposed to have established that there
is an intimate and universal connection between every part and the Universal
Whole. If so, how can parts become "more"
than they were individually when they have never been, and will never exist as, isolated individuals?
Surely, parts are
supposed to be like those who we were once told smoke
Strand cigarettes -- aren't they?
It could be argued in response to this that
when
parts enter into new relations with other parts or with other wholes they do become
more than they would have been (or had once been) otherwise.
However, if everything is already
part of some whole-or-other, and all sub-wholes are parts of the
Mega-Whole -- the "Totality" --, and everything is ("internally")
inter-linked all the time with
everything else, how is this possible?
All parts are parts of some whole-or-other,
and hence all parts are parts of this Universal Ensemble; so, they
are always and everywhere essentially conditioned by everything else, so we are
told.1a
Of course,
some DM-apologists might want to argue that not all things are "internally"
related. But, that can't be
correct. G1 tells
us that the entire nature of a part is determined by its relation to all the other
parts, and to the whole; external relations can't effect these intimate,
'logical', connections. They could only come about if the interconnections that any part has with all the others are
"internal" (i.e., 'logical' or "essential"). If this weren't so, then
any agglomeration of matter would
constitute an organised whole, and an organism, say, would be no different from
a heap of body parts or organs. [More on this later. See also: Note 1a; link above.]
G1: The entire nature
of a part is determined by its relation with the other parts and with the whole.
G2: The part makes the whole and the
whole makes the part.
Be this as
it may, parts plainly do not enter the universe from the 'outside'. It isn't as
if they were stored away in a sort of 'metaphysical ante-chamber', hermetically
sealed-off from the rest of nature until they joined everything else in this 'cosmic
drama'.
Note what Levins and Lewontin had to say on
this:
"The first principle of a
dialectical view, then, is that a whole is a relation of heterogeneous parts
that have no prior independent existence as parts. The
second principle, which flows from the first, is that, in general, the
properties of parts have no prior alienated existence but are acquired by being
parts of a particular whole." [Levins and Lewontin (1985), p.273. Bold emphases
added.]
If so, how is it possible for these parts to become "more" than they had been
before? They remain part of the "Totality" either side of any subsequent
moves they make or incorporations in which they become involved. So, they should stay the same whatever happens -- that is, if their entire
nature is determined by their relation with the whole, the Mega-Conglomerate
called the "Totality", as indicated above. Since they are interconnected at all
times with everything else, from where does this
semi-miraculous novelty arise? How can they become "more" than
they were before? Surely, the only way that they could become "more" would be if
their entire nature wasn't
determined by the Whole, by the "Totality"?
An appeal to Engels's first 'Law' at this
point (i.e.,
the one that asserts that "quantity" passes over into "quality", etc.) would be to no avail. As we saw in Essay
Seven and Note 1a, this 'Law' is far too fragile
and insubstantial to bear any weight put on it. But even if that weren't the case, precisely what constitutes
a "quantity" and what a "quality"
in this case would
be
entirely unlcear.2
Anyway,
if this 'Law' could have the above effect (so that a merely quantitative
local increase of parts might at some point "pass over" into a local
"qualitative" change, introducing localised novelty), then the entire
nature of the part wouldn't be determined by its "internal" relations with
the Whole, but would be determined by its relations with other local
parts of the Whole. How the latter can alter the logical properties of a
body (so that its qualitative nature changes as a result) is, therefore,
still a mystery.
In short,
it isn't easy to see how novelty can emerge in a dialectical universe.
[This particular topic has been discussed at length in Essay
Seven Part One, and
will be explored in more detail in Essay Three Part Three.]
Despite this, if we were less than careful when
attempting to identify
the parts, it turns out that we might end up dividing the Whole -- or, alternatively, we might end
up confounding the parts when identifying the Whole --, which we saw was the
case with general terms and particulars (as they feature in Traditional Philosophy),
in Essay Three
Part Two.
That is, on the one hand, we might end up linking each part only with one
part of the Whole (i.e., the sub-whole to which it becomes a part -- for
example, when DM-theorists tell us that a heart is only a heart when it is in
some body or other), but not the entire Whole (thus undermining Universal
Interconnectedness). On the other hand, if we argue that the entire nature of
the part is determined by its relation to the Whole (the "Totality"), then every
part in the entire universe must be identical (or virtually identical),
since whatever minor local differences there are in each such relation will be
completely swamped by their relation to the Whole, thus confounding the parts. Otherwise, we will have to
abandon the claim that the entire nature of the part is determined by its
relation to the Whole, since its nature will actually be determined by its relation to
the local whole of which it is a part. For example, if the entire nature of a
heart is determined by its relation to the "Totality", then it won't matter if
it is in a body or not. On the other hand, if it does so matter, then the entire nature of a
heart can't be determined by its relation to the "Totality".
Again, one will look in vain in the writings of dialecticians for any guidance
on these issues --, which means that DM isn't just
Mickey Mouse Science,
it is Minnie Mouse
Metaphysics, too.
Because of this, I am forced (once more) to consider
whether or not there are any viable options
available to DM-theorists which might enable them at least to give some sort
of an account of these 'dialectical' parts as and when they are incorporated
into their respective 'dialectical' wholes that doesn't sunder the parts or divide the Whole
in the above manner.
In
order to keep track of the parts involved, they will be 'time-stamped' -- so to
speak --, as will the relevant wholes, too.
[In what follows, "T"
will be used to refer to various different "Totalities" (whether or
not these are the Mega-"Totality" itself, or some local Minor-"Totality", such
as an animal's body), "t" will be employed to
designate temporal intervals of arbitrary duration, and "p" for
some
randomly-chosen part at a
specific time. In addition, the subscript "i" will be used to refer to any
randomly-selected element drawn from the set indicated; hence, "ti" refers to any
such temporal interval. Also, "pt,r"
will be used to designate the different members of the set of parts which exist at a
given moment; hence, "p1,1"
is short for "part one at t1",
"p1,2"
for "part two at t1",
"p2,1"
for "part one at
t2",
and so on.]
First, let
any "Totality",
Ti,
be the sum of all its time-stamped parts at each ti.
Consider, for example, part p1,1,
the entire nature of which (at t1)
is determined by its relation to whole, T1.
Let the
'same' part (at a later time, t2)
be p2,1,
such that its ("essential") nature is either different from, or perhaps even the same as it
had been
at t1.
[Let either of these be such in relation to
T2,
the new whole that must emerge as a result, as the case may be.]
Hence, T1
will be the
mereological sum of all such
time-stamped parts, p1,r, at t1
(i.e., Σp1,r); the 'new' "Totality", T2,
will be those parts at t2
(i.e., Σp2,r), and so on.
["Σ" is a summation sign,
and here stands for "the sum of...". So, "Σp1,r"
means "the sum of all the parts at t1",
and "Σp2,r"
means "the sum of all the parts at t2".
Hence, Tn
is Σpn,r,
or "the sum of all the parts at tn"
--, i.e., the "Totality" at or during the nth time interval.]
In view
of this, it is worth asking: What precisely is the entire "Totality" meant to be here?
It seems
there are
three distinct possibilities:
(1) The "Totality" is
only one of
T1,
T2,...,
or Tn;
or,
(2)
The "Totality" is the sum of all these time-stamped "sub-Totalities" -- e.g.,
T1
+ T2
+...+ Tn
(i.e., ΣTr);
or
(3) The
"Totality" is something else.
If (2) were
correct, then each Ti
wouldn't really be a whole simpliciter; it would be a sub-whole -- since
each
would be part of the bigger whole (i.e., it would be a part ofΣTi).
If, on the other hand, (1) were correct,
it
would
mean that each "Totality" will have
been misnamed,
since, plainly, none of them would be the "Totality". That is because, for any
Ti,
there would be n-1 otherTis
that will have been excluded.
Either way,
this obscure 'entity' should now perhaps be
demoted, and broken to the ranks, as it were, since it, too, would be part of a bigger
Whole -- hence, at best, each Ti would merely be a sub-"Totality".
Plainly, option (3) would take us
back to where we were in Essay Eleven
Part One. Readers are directed there for more
details
In
addition, (1) would seem to imply that the duration of these sub-"Totalities"
could be, and probably is, exceedingly
short -- each being ephemeral
in the extreme, reduced as they now are to time-sliced collections of such time-stamped parts,
all of which would 'exist' for much less than a nanosecond (that is, if all things are
constantly changing, as DM-fans assure us they are).
But, as we
have seen
here, this
would in turn mean that in order to account for objects and events 'inside' any
particular "Totality", Ti,
an appeal would have to be made to events and processes that were either
(i) non-existent or (ii) weren't parts of that "Totality", at
that time.
Naturally, this would make the
original introduction of this mysterious entity (i.e., the "Totality") pointless
--, in view of the fact
that it was meant to help DM-theorists account for just such objects and
processes.
Furthermore,
option (2)
implies that as
ΣTi grows in size (with the incorporation of each new Tk)
it would either be (2a) Subject to change, or it would in fact be (2b) Identical
to the four-dimensional
manifold discussed
in
Part One of this
Essay.
But, and
once more, (2a) would imply that there
was no such thing as the
"Totality" (since it would be ever-expanding). Worse still, it would mean
that, whatever it actually is, the "Totality" would in fact be 'composed'
largely of non-existent parts (i.e., those Tis that 'exist' only in the past). (2b), of course, would imply that
nothing could change. [Why that is so was explained in
Part One
of this Essay.]
Despite the above, an attempt might be made to account for
the 'dialectical' passage through time of these
time-specific "Totalities", as each brings into existence the next in line
(presumably because of the operation of their own "internal contradictions").
But, this response itself faces the
serious difficulties highlighted in Essay Seven
Part Three, where it was pointed out that
in relation to development,
DM-theorists are
decidedly unclear as
to
whether
(i) These "internal
opposites" bring about change, or whether,
(iii) Objects/processes
actually change into their opposites.
Generalising this, it would now be unclear whether or not the entire "Totality" changes
because of:
(a) Its own internal opposites, or whether,
(b) It creates these
opposites as it
changes -- or even whether,
(c) It turns into its opposite.
But, what is the 'opposite' of
a "Totality"? A vacuum? A 'Nullity'? A 'Nothing'?2a
Again,
as far as (a) is concerned, the origin of
these 'opposites' would itselfbe obscure, just as it would be unclear how they
could cause change (especially when it is recalled that change actually
produces
them, not them it; we saw this in Essays
Five, Seven
Part Three, and Eight Parts
One,
Two and
Three).
If the
above points are rejected for some reason, and it is maintained that opposites
aren't in fact produced by anything else (that is,
if change doesn't produce these opposites), then they must either be eternal or
they must be self-created beings.
Once more, it could be argued that objects and processes can have many
opposites. Some cause change, and some are produced by it. Either or both of
these are subsequently altered in turn by their own (new) dialectical opposites, as the
NON unfolds.
[NON = Negation of the
Negation.]
However, as we saw
here, Hegel postulated for each object or process its own internally-linked, unique
"other" He had to do this to forestall the disastrous consequences of his
adoption of 'Spinoza'sGreedy Principle' [SGP] -- i.e., "Every
determination is also a negation" -- and, of course, in order to
refute Hume's
criticisms of rationalist theories of causation. The problem here is that if an object or
process merely turns into "what-it-is-not" (where this "what-it-is-not" is
required by Hegel's 'logic' to make the nature of an object or process
"determinate"), then it could in fact develop into anything whatsoever.
On
that basis, but without Hegel's caveat (that each object or process has its own
internally-linked, unique
"other"), since Tony Blair, for example, isn't Mt
Everest, or Jupiter, or a
Slime Mold
(as far as we know), not a socialist, or an egg plant, he must
turn into one or more of
these 'opposites', and countless others, too. So, if this Hegelian 'safety
feature' is removed (i.e., that each object or process has a unique "other"
that it
turns into), anything could turn into anything else (as a result of such a
profligate and careless 'use of negation').
[We found that Hegel himself
slipped
up in this regard, too, since the SGP is in fact unworkable. That will be
demonstrated in Essay Twelve Part Five. See also Essay Three Part One,
here
and
here.]
Of course, it could be argued that the processes mentioned above stretch back
into the mists of time; there, not only are the many and varied states of
affairs extant in nature interconnected 'dialectically'
(which means that it is in fact inadmissible to separate them, one from another, as has
been done in this Essay), one state ('moment') of the universe is caused (or, perhaps better,
it is mediated) by an earlier one, and so on indefinitely.
But, this just reproduces
all the problems more usually associated with Theism, specifically those connected
with the question, "Who created 'God'?" In this case, if
everything needs a prior
cause (or 'mediation'), and that itself must be one of these 'internal opposites' (or
is itself part of a relation with one such), the question would naturally arise:
"Precisely what created, or 'mediated', that opposite?" Pushing this
back into the indefinite (or 'infinite'?) past is no solution at all; we
certainly don't accept a similar a cop out when Theists come out with it. Either it is the case that
opposites cause change (and so must be self-caused beings themselves -- minor
deities, as it were), or they are brought into existence by change, and so can't
cause it.
Burying
this under
several tons of
dialectical jargon would no more be acceptable here than it would be if Theists
tried the same dodge with respect to their jargon about 'God' and 'His' mysterious
'nature', 'properties', and 'powers'.2b
So, it
won't do to appeal to a 'dialectical' interplay between cause and effect
(dragging in that even more obscure notion, "mediation") -- on the lines,
perhaps, that the
comments above separate cause from effect, when they are in fact 'internally'-connected
--, since the origin of this dialectical interplay would be subject to the very same
unanswerable query.
This is, of course, why Theists in the end had to appeal to 'logical' principles
inherent in 'the Deity' to account for the uncreated nature of 'God' -- burying
'His' existence, say, in 'His' nature,
à
laAnselm
-- or, admitting that this is all just big a 'mystery', and should simply
be "grasped" as
an article of faith.
[Of course, dialecticians will have to do something similar -- indeed,
they do.]
To be sure,
Hegel had a 'solution' to this quandary
that ran along 'logical' lines. That itself was based on obscure,
Hermetic goings-on between
'Being', 'Nothing' and
'Becoming' –- which 'solution' will be
destructively analysed in Essay Twelve
(summary
here). However, unless we can find
some physical evidence that these mysterious
entities kicked off the
Big Bang (or whatever it is that scientists finally
conclude about the origin of The Universe), neither science nor consistent materialism will have
much use for them.
Naturally, only
Idealists will cavil at this point.
If, on the other hand,
these opposites are produced by something else (inside the "Totality"?), that
option would collapse (i) into (ii): these opposites would be produced by, but
wouldn't cause,
change. The adoption of (iii), of course, would amount to the
abandonment of any sensible account of development, for it would then be unclear what makes
anything change into its opposite (if anything does).
(i) These "internal
opposites" bring about change.
(ii) They are createdby change.
(iii) Objects/processes
actually change into their opposites.
It could be objected once
more that the "Totality" is in fact a dynamic whole, changing over time as a
result of its 'internal contradictions'. The above comments seem to want to 'freeze-frame
it',
and then
bemoan
its lack of internal cohesion and complain about the
absence of change!
Or, so it could be argued...
But,
quite apart from the problems this volunteered reply faces (analysed in great detail in Essay Eight
Parts
One,
Two, and
Three), the first sentence of the
last but one paragraph is of indeterminate meaning itself. That is because
we have yet to be
told what this nebulous entity (i.e., the "Totality") actually is. As it
stands, that sentence is no clearer than is this one: "It could be objected that
God is a dynamic Being...".
Hence, the word "dynamic" can't of itself provide this 'theory' with a viable life-line since
we have as yet no idea precisely what is being called dynamic, here --,
i.e., no
more than
we would if someone called 'God' "dynamic".
In short,
just as soon as
the "Totality" is fragmented in the above manner, by the introduction
of temporal constraints, it proves impossible to restore to it any sort of unity.
On the other hand, if no temporal constraints are imposed upon it,
then either the "Totality" can't change, or the notion itself fails to relate to
anything in the physical world.
So,
either (a) we are confronted by a new "Totality" at each instant in time,
comprised of all the time-stamped parts at that moment, or (b) the 'same'
"Totality" must encompass every time zone and sub-"Totality" in
an all-inclusive, over-arching domain.
However, in the latter
case, the "Totality" would once again contain things that do not (now) exist (namely
those time-stamped parts from the past (and the future?)). In the former case, there
would be a potentially infinite number of "Totalities" with no links between
them, which would therefore be explanatory of nothing at all.
Independently of the
above, it could be argued that since
relations between the parts change, their nature must change, too. [This was in
fact discussed in Note 1a.]
Putting aside for the moment the serious problems this attempted
rebuttal faces when confronted with the other DM-thesis that change is
internally-generated, not externally-motivated-- in response, let us assume the
following:
P1: Part, p1, is an element that enters into a relation with whole, W1,
and W1 is itself part of the
"Totality", T.
[For ease of reference, I have dropped
the complicated labelling system introduced
earlier. In that case, "p1"
now merely refers to the first randomly selected part of
W1,
leaving reference to time out of the equation, for now.]
Here, p1
is clearly also part of T -- as is W1. But, by becoming
part of W1,
p1doesn't cease to be part of
T, and neither does W1. In its relation to T,
neither p1 nor W1 could become
"more"
than they once were, since they are both still parts of T -- and not part
of, say, T1, some other
"Totality".
Recall that G1 and G2 assert that the
entire nature of a part (like p1, or
even
W1)
is determined by its relation with other parts and with the whole. Unless we add
a rider to these two theses -- for example, that parts can become "more"
than they were by remaining parts of the same whole (and hence that the
entire nature of the part isn't determined by its relation to the
whole (i.e., with the "Totality"), but by its relation to a 'sub-whole', say W1), or that a whole can alter
even
though it retains the same parts -- neither p1 nor
W1
can change. Of course, if W1
can't change, then p1
can't either, since p1 fluctuates in line with
W1,
according to G1 and G2.
G1: The entire nature
of a part is determined by its relation with the other parts and with the whole.
G2: The part makes the whole and the
whole makes the part.
Perhaps these serious initial problems can be circumvented in some way, perhaps not. I will
leave that time-bomb in the lap of DM-fans for them to try to defuse.3
Independently of all this, there is an obverse difficulty concerning the "more"
alluded to in G3 and G4, if that comparative is
taken at face value. This can be seen if G3 and G4 are
supplemented in the following way:
G3: The whole is more than the sum of
its parts.
G4: Each part becomes more when it is
part of a whole than it would otherwise have been (individually) apart from that
whole.
G5: Let whole, W1, have
parts, pw1-pwn, and let
pw1-pwn
form a set, Pw.
G6: Let the 'same' parts when not parts
of W1 be
p1-pn, and let
p1-pn form a set of parts, P.
G7: For any
pwi, and
any pi,
let pwi >
pi (where
pwi and
pi are the ith members of Pw
and P, respectively).
G8: Let the sum of the parts that are
elements of Pw be
Σpwn, and the sum of the
parts that are elements of P be Σpn.
G9: Either: W1 >
Σpwn.
G10: Or: W1 >
Σpn.
[">" means "is greater than".]
In ordinary language, G9 and G10 translate
out as the following:
G9a: The Whole is greater than
the sum of the parts it already has.
G10a: The Whole is greater than the sum
of the parts as they were before they became its parts.
Now, there are several
difficulties with this attempt to make DM-Wholism clear. The first centres on
G7 and its ordinary language translation, G7a:
G7: For any
pwi, and
any pi,
let pwi >
pi (where
pwi and
pi are the ith members of Pw
and P, respectively).
G7a: Any part of a whole is greater than
that part was before it was incorporated into that whole.
[G4: Each part becomes more
when it is part of a whole than it would otherwise have been (individually)
apart from that whole.]
At first
sight it looks like one of G7 or G7a might capture the thought intended by G4,
but
that can't be so. That is because the wording of G7 and G7a actually permits
the following (which isn't what was intended by G4):
G11:
pw1 >
p2.
G11a: pw1 >
p1.
The
problem here is that G11 says that a certain part
of a whole is greater than some other part, not necessarily the 'same'
part, before it became incorporated into that whole.
Now,
what G4 appears
to imply is G11a, where comparisons are drawn between the 'same' part either
side of incorporation into the relevant whole. Of course, this assumes that a
one-one relation can be set up (even in theory) between a part before and after its absorption into W1.
But, the difficulty here is that if a part becomes more when it enters
into a subsequent ensemble/system than it had been on its own, it mightn't be possible to specify of
any part that it was the same part after its
integration into some whole-or-other as it was before. In turn, it wouldn't
therefore seem
possible to say that the said part was more
after incorporation than it was before. If there is no way to say they are the
same part before and after, then it can't be said that one of them has become
"more". G11 brings this difficulty out by
changing the subscripts.
Unfortunately, DM-Wholism appears to mean
that after assimilation a part might not be the same part it had
been before incorporation because of the "greater than" descriptor
that applies to it upon amalgamation. In fact, this comparative is much more than a
simple "greater than", since we are also told that the entire
nature of each part is determined by its relation to the other parts and to the
whole of which it is a part. So, the
entire nature of the part is transformed by incorporation into the new whole of
which it becomes a component. In which case, it can't be the same as it was before
incorporation, and hence "more" can't apply to it, as pointed out in the
previous paragraph. If it isn't the same part, it can't be "more" than it used
to be any more than fish can be a mammal. There is no "it" here for that
comparative to attach itself to.
It could be argued that it would surely be possible to identify the parts in
question either side
of incorporation despite such changes. Consider an example here: a human
heart outside the body is physically the same as it would be inside the same
body, even though a functioning heart is more than just a material object
when incorporated into its host. As such, it would be operating as an integrated organ,
which allows it to
fulfil a certain role in relation to the entire organism of which it is now a
part.
Or, so it might be argued...
This
alleged counter-example will be considered in more detail
later, but for present
purposes it is sufficient to point out that a heart outside the body is not the same
physical object it had been inside. Not only does it lose some matter
(blood, etc.) when extracted, the electrical, hormonal and other chemical inputs
cease. Moreover, the body, too, isn't the same without a heart. So, the above description
is not only inaccurate, it is prejudicial, for neither heart nor body are the
same either side of removal/incorporation.
Furthermore, hearts
aren't added to bodies as a sort of after-thought, so that it becomes
possible confirm or confute the above comparisons. Hearts develop alongside the
rest of the organism. This means that an animal without a heart (plainly!)
wouldn't be
identical with one that had a heart; indeed, that animal would be defective in the
extreme, and thus non-viable. The same goes for hearts themselves, if they are
situated outside
a given body.
So, it isn't too clear what if anything can be concluded from such a misleading description.
Certainly, a heart isn't physically the same, and it isn't even 'dialectically' the same, given such
radical surgery. In that case, we still lack a perspicuous account of what the
DM-alternatives before us really amount to.
Of
course, even if the above DM-objection were accepted, it would actually work against DM. If it is
indeed possible to identify a heart before and after it had been put in a
given body, then it isn't the case that it is completely different because of
the new sub-Whole of which it is now a part, contrary to what G1 and G2
asserted:
G1: The entire nature
of a part is determined by its relation with the other parts and with the whole.
G2: The part makes the whole and the
whole makes the part.
So, if,
according to G1, the entire nature of the part is determined by the new
relation it has with that body, then it must be completely different
after it has been put in that body. But, if the above DM-counter-claim is
correct, it isn't completely different, so G1
and G2 are false.
The dilemma that
confronts dialecticians is thus quite stark:
(1) No part could be the same
before and after assimilation
(since each part isn't just "more" than it was before, it is completely
different, because its entire nature will have been changed as a result
of the "internal relations" operating inside that whole), according to
G1; or,
(2) If eachpart is
the same after incorporation, that would mean there can't have been any change
to those parts as they entered into this new whole, and so they won't now be
"more" than they were before -- and hence their entire nature won't have changed.
In the first case, it would be
impossible to say, concerning some part, whether or not it was greater before, later, or
at any time, since, ex hypothesi, it will have entirely
changed in the process -- if we are to believe G1 and G2.
The
assumed change here
is so radical that it would be rather like asserting that a stadium was greater
than a symphony, or, perhaps, that a ham sandwich was greater than a science fiction novel --
since, according to DM-theorists, in such circumstances there will have been a logical change to the 'objects' in
question (in view of the new "internal relations" enjoyed by part and whole).
Of course, it could be
countered that these
latest comparisons aren't apposite, since the parts that are of interest to
dialecticians are far more similar either side of incorporation than such
distantly related or even totally unrelated objects are.
But, if that is so, then the entire nature
of the part can't be determined by the new whole it enters into -- and, if that,
too, is the case, an important strand of DM-Wholism will go out of the window with it.
In short, it is now clear that G1 and G4 can't be held true together.
G1: The entire nature
of a part is determined by its relation with the other parts and with the whole.
G4: Each part becomes more when it is
part of a whole than it would otherwise have been (individually) apart from that
whole.
G2: The part makes the whole and the
whole makes the part.
In fact, the situation is
far worse eventhan this: before incorporation not only will an individual part not be a
part of the new whole (since it hasn't joined it yet!), not even
this new whole will be the same whole for it to join -- and
that is for the reasons expressed by G1 and G2. In turn, that is because, before and after amalgamation parts
and wholes must both become different (indeed, entirely different!) from what they once were.
Simple
comparisons like this can't, therefore, be made for part or whole either
side of any supposed union. Hence, without serious distortion, no aspect of this
metaphysical fantasy is describable -- even by anyone who seriously believes it. That is
because nothing is either comparable or contrastable before and after
amalgamation. In any such development, entire natures of parts and wholes
must change, if G1 and G2 are to be believed. That is, entire natures --
not 90%, or 95%, nor yet 99% -- must be 100% different (unless the word
"entire" is be interpreted ironically). G4, therefore, isn't defensible as
it stands, and it isn't at all clear how it might be repaired without abandoning
G1, or, indeed, without ditching other fundamentally important DM-theses.4
In the second case, clearly, G1
and G2 would have to be revised or abandoned. G3 is similarly ambiguous:
G3: The whole is more than
the sum of its parts.
G9: Either: W1 >
Σpwn.
G10: Or: W1 >
Σpn.
G9a: The Whole is greater than
the sum of the parts it already has.
G10a: The Whole is greater than the sum of
the parts as they were before they became its parts.
As indicated above, G3 might imply
one or other of G9 and G10 (or their ordinary language counterparts, G9a and G10a). In that case, the following question suggests itself: Is the whole
greater than the sum of
the parts before amalgamation (i.e., G10/10a), or after (i.e., G9/9a)?
But, G10/G10a can't be correct. That is
because, before incorporation the (same) whole plainly wouldn't exist for a comparison
to be made with any new whole that
might arise
after the event. That is in turn because (according to G2) the nature of the whole is
determined by its relation to its parts, including this new one. Hence,
before this particular part became a part of some whole or other, that whole
couldn't have been the same as it subsequently became, for it didn't exist.
This means that
G3 must imply G9/G9a (which I will return to consider in more detail
later).
G9: Either: W1 >
Σpwn.
G9a: The Whole is greater than
the sum of the parts it already has.
As we
shall see, the problem with Metaphysical Holism (or even DM-Wholism) is that it isn't in fact possible to
identify parts separately from wholes at any time during any transaction between
them, for to do so would be to sunder the organic unity supposedly governing
everything in the universe, and from which in turn both part and whole derive their entire
natures.
Furthermore, it is impossible to do so even in thought,
and for
the same reason -- as was outlined above. Perhaps it would be better to say here
that to separate the parts from the whole (even in thought) is to change their
nature (in thought), and hence to misidentify or misconstrue them (according to
G1). If so, this type of Holism/Wholism can't even be described
(without it falling apart -- no pun intended).
G1: The entire nature
of a part is determined by its relation with the other parts and with the whole.
[However, as we will see in Note 5,
the
situation is even worse if we throw in the infinitary nature of DM-epistemology.]5
"[W]hen we bring these terms
[belonging to the totality] into relation with each other their meaning is
transformed…. In a dialectical system, the entire nature of the part is
determined by its relationships with the other parts and so with the whole. The
part makes the whole, and the whole makes the parts. In this analysis, it is not
just the case that the whole is more than the sum of the parts but also that the
parts become more than they are individually by being part of a whole…. [F]or dialectical
materialists the whole is more than the simple sum of its parts." [Rees (1998),
pp.5, 77. Paragraphs merged.]
The opening sentence of this quotation
seems to suggest that this entire exercise is merely methodological, that
it need not imply anything about reality itself. Otherwise, what would be the
point of saying: "when we bring these terms into relation with each other
their meaning is transformed"? [Emphasis added.]
But, if the world is
dialectically-structured before we investigate it, then whatever we do
can't affect the nature
of the part/whole relation in reality, surely? Of course, Rees might simply be
making a point about our comprehension of the part/whole relation as it features
in "subjective dialectics".6
Even
so, there is a further problem that Rees and others have missed: If it were true that we humans are
also parts of
the Whole, any change we initiate -- even
in thought -- must have an affect on the rest of the "Totality"!
This new twist now raises alarming
possibilities dialecticians have plainly failed to noticed.
Indeed, at first sight it looks like DM-Wholism
implies that thought in fact 'determines' "Being" (just as "Being"
'determines' thought), as Hegel maintained -- that is,DM-Wholism means
that the nature of reality depends on our thoughts about it (and vice versa)!
G1: The entire nature of a part
is determined by its relation with the other parts and with the whole.
G2: The part makes the whole and the
whole makes the part.
The only apparent interpretation of G1 and G2
that might neutralise the above alarming, Idealist conclusion would be one that declared that it is
only our understanding of the parts that is altered when we adopt this
viewpoint, as Rees maintained -- nothing more.
And yet, if that
were so, how could G1 or G2
remain true? If our thoughts are in fact part of the 'Totality', and are
determined by their own "internal relations" with it, and all parts
inter-determine one another likewise -- as indeed they do so to the entire nature of the whole according to G2 --, then not only must it
be true that reality determines our thoughts about it, our thoughts about
reality must determine reality in return. If this weren't so, G1 or G2 would
have to be revised, or abandoned, once more. If the part makes the whole (and
vice versa), then even the most insignificant thought about reality must be
altered by -- and must alter in return -- all of nature, on this view.
[The
'relative importance' or 'remoteness' defence has been defused
here.]
The
Idealist implications of DM have been reasonably clear up to now in the
Essays published at this site; here, we find
them totally confirmed by DM-Wholism.8
Theoretical considerations like these are
unlikely to cut much ice with DM-fans. Hence, a discussion of the more
concrete claims advanced in
TAR and other DM-texts
(that are connected with this issue) is clearly called for.
[DB = Dialectical
Biologist, i.e., Levins and Lewontin (1985).]
The first problem here is that Rees and other
DM-theorists provide us with few examples of what they mean -- that is, examples
that are supposed to illustrate the rule (or the 'law') they claim governs the
relationship between parts and wholes, supposedly right across the universe and
not just locally. However,
Rees does mention one particular example, which had in fact been lifted from DB.
Alas, even this turns out to be a rather unfortunate choice.
As
was the case with the more theoretical examples considered earlier, this particular example of the
part/whole relation is connected with the following (hackneyed) formula
that Holists incant from generation to generation:
"For dialectical materialists
the whole is more than the simple sum of its parts." [Rees (1998), p.77.]
To this the authors of DB
added the following comment:
"The fact is that the parts
have properties that are characteristic of them only as they are parts of
wholes; the properties come into existence in the interactions that makes the
whole. A person cannot fly by flapping her arms simultaneously. But people do
fly, as a consequence of the social organisation that has created airplanes,
pilots and fuel. It is not that society flies, however, but individuals in
society, who have acquired a property they do not have outside society. The
limitations of individual physical beings are negated by social interactions.
The whole, thus, is not simply the object of interaction of the parts but is the
subject of action of the parts." [Levins and Lewontin (1985), p.273.]
The general idea here appears to
be that novel properties "emerge" (out of nowhere, it seems; they certainly
can't
be reduced to the microstructure of each part, or even of each whole --
according to Rees (1998), pp.5-8, and other dialecticians we will meet in Essay
Three Part Three), because of the new relationships that parts enter into when
they become incorporated into wholes -- coupled with the new natures
('essences'?) they acquire as a result.9
The above passage
appears to be claiming that:
(a) When human beings act as individuals (or, is it in less developed social
wholes?) they lack certain properties --, in this case, the power of flight.
Nevertheless: (b) As a result of their social organization, human beings
apparently gain new 'properties' collectively, in this case, again, the power of
flight -- even though as
individuals they still can't fly. The conclusion then seems to be that: (c)
Because of economic and social development (etc.) people acquire characteristics
that they wouldn't have possessed otherwise --, which appears to indicate that when they are
appropriately socially-organised, human beings become "more" than they would have
been without it.
But, once again, in what sense are human beings
"more" than they were before
flight became possible? Manifestly, they still can't fly. They don't
sprout wings, develop engines or grow sophisticated landing gear.10
Whatever meaning can be given to the "more" that human beings supposedly become,
it can't have resulted from the part/whole relation.
That is because immediately before or after flight finally became possible no
new wholes or parts actually came into existence -- nor did these new parts and
allegedly novel wholes become newly related, either.11
Hence,
even if these hackneyed sayings (i.e., G3 and G4) were true, flight wouldn't be one
of their exemplars.
G3: The
whole is more than the sum of its parts.
G4: Each
part becomes more when it is part of a whole than it would otherwise have been
(individually) apart from that whole.
It could be objected that the above is
incorrect. The point is that as the forces and relations of production develop
(and as new modes of production replace older modes), human beings enter into novel and more complex social and material
relations with one another.
These generate or facilitate new
capacities and possibilities that were unavailable in earlier social systems.
[HM = Historical
Materialism.]
Now,
this way of putting things won't be controverted here (or anywhere else
for that matter), but it is worth adding that this HM-style
re-formulation of the picture only works because the part/whole
metaphysichas been dropped. This can be seen by the way that the
language used in the above rejoinder only becomes available (and begins to make
sense) when the unhelpful metaphysical 'concepts' under review here have been
discarded. There is no mystery about the details of the social organisation of
production and the new capacities it makes available to human beings. But, this has
nothing to do with the alleged DM-connections between parts and wholes (for reasons given in previous paragraphs and in
Note 10).
Independently of this, it is worth wondering
how such a scenario could be made consistent with G1.
G1: The entire nature
of a part is determined by its relation with the other parts and with the whole.
G2: The part makes the whole and the
whole makes the part.
So, are we really meant to believe that
the entire nature of passenger, NN, say, is determined by her
relationship with the aeroplane she has just boarded? [Or is it with someother
whole that we must interconnect her?] Conversely, is the entire nature of this new
aeroplane/passenger ensemble determined in return by passenger, NN? What if she
missed the flight and passenger, MM, took her place? Would the entire nature of
that plane, and all on board, have (totally) changed as a result? It should do
if the entire nature of part and whole affect each other in the manner
suggested.
Once more: in all this, which is
part and which is
whole? Is the entire nature of airline passenger, MM, determined by his/her
relation with one or more of the following 'wholes': the aeroplane, the Airline, the Airport, the flight controller,
the factory that built the aeroplane, the other passengers, the man at the
check-in desk (and his sick grandmother), MM's whole life up to that point, the entire earth and its history, the
cluster of galaxies of which ours is a part…?
Which one of these is the 'whole' that makes
MM "more"?
Moreover, do we include in the part, here,
passenger MM's hand luggage, her glasses, her clothes, her unborn foetus, the
cells now sloughing off her skin, the air coming out of her lungs, the
material she just flushed down the loo?12
Which parts and which wholes are
in the end entirely constitutive of, say, passenger, NM, in seat 26 -- minus
his toupee, sun glasses and copy of The Da Vinci Code, which he left at
home by accident? What if he hadn't
forgotten any of these items?
And, would an aeroplane be more of an aeroplane
if
there were 100 people board it as opposed to 99? Is the airport itself more
than it would otherwise have been if passenger, MN, had failed to check-in last Sunday at
19:02?
But, all these would have to be the case if the
entire nature of each part and whole is determined in the way that G1 and
G2 assert. In that case, passenger, MN, must indeed be greater than he would
have been had he not flown last Sunday; and the same would be true of the airport.
And if MN repeats this journey regularly, over many years, is there no end to
how much more she will become? It is a wonder she doesn't explode.
Is
this the case with anything
else? Is the entire nature of the universe enhanced as a result? If everything
is interconnected (in order for it to be true that the nature of the whole is
determined by its relation to the parts), and inter-linked by these
mysterious "internal relations", then the universe must be more of a
universe than it used to be because MN checked in last Sunday. To be sure, had
MN's cosmic significance not escaped her on the day in question, she
would surely have been much more careful.
[It could be argued that the above
considerations are ridiculous since DM-Holism is concerned with organic
wholes, not conglomerations or aggregations. But, we have already seen
that the passenger/plane example in DB isn't an organic whole, and looks for all the
world like a conglomeration/aggregate! Anyway, I return to this topic in much
greater detail below (where I question
whether the distinction between organised wholes and aggregates (etc.) can
successfully be maintained).]
In Essay
Three Part One, we saw
this DM-thesis (about parts and wholes) is a direct consequence of Lenin's reading of Hegel, and
thus his derivation of a set of inter-galactic truths from a sentence
like "John is a man"! Here, then, is the 'rationale' underlying Hegel and
Lenin's use of such sentence (although Hegel used 'The rose is red'), and from
which Lenin claimed all of dialectics flowed:
Now, the correct
'dialectical' analysis of propositions like this reveals the following deeper
truth: ordinary language vaguely alludes to an
identity between subject and predicate names (or the objects they designate;
Hegel continually mixes the two up, and so do his latter-day acolytes,
DM-theorists). But, this can't be correct, because no
particular can be identical to a universal. This then leads "speculative reason"
dialectically to the opposite conclusion that the subject of such an ascription
of identity isn't and can't be identical with the said
predicate (now interpreted as a named abstract particular). So, in
reality John can't be identical with this predicate, or with what it 'names' (i.e.,
John isn't
identical with Man, or
'Manhood'). 'Thought' is thus led to the negation of this putative identity.
[It is worth adding the following
two points, here:
(1) In traditional Logic
and Grammar, a predicate is that part of a proposition/sentence which is used to
say something about whatever is named by the subject term. So, in "John is a
man", "John" is the subject, and "is a man" (or, according to many, just "a
man") is the predicate. Hegel then resurrected a Medieval theory (invented by
Roman Catholic theologians -- now called 'The Identity Theory of Predication' --
which re-interpreted the "is" here, not now as one of prediction, but of
identity. So, in this case John is now said to be identical with Manhood,
a supposed universal term. From word-juggling like this, 'the dialectic'
emerged!
(2) An 'abstract
particular'
is like a genuine particular (such as the chair you are
now sat in (if you are), the screen you are looking at -- or even, you),
to which we can, if we so choose, give names, or pick out by the use of
singular terms (such as "the screen you are now looking at", or "him over
there"). Except, 'abstract particulars' don't appear to
exist in the world around us. They are, however, still capable of being
designated by the use of names or other
singular expressions (such as "The
Form of the Good", "Manhood", or "The Population").
However, as noted in the
main body of Essay Three Part One, abstractions are supposed to be general
(they supposedly pick out all cats, all dogs, all
men/women, all electrons, etc.), and yet they are in fact particular
in form (since they speak of "Man/Womanhood", or "The population").
Unfortunately, when used by those who seek to account for generality (i.e., our
capacity to refer to all cats, or all dogs), 'abstract particulars' in fact only
succeed in destroying it. Plainly, this is because neither a singular term nor a
particular can be general -- the chair you are sat on is not all chairs there
are or have ever been, the screen you are now using is not every screen there
has ever been or will be. Nor can "the chair you are sat on" or "the screen you
are now using" refer to all chairs or screens there are or have ever been. So,
and alas, every theory invented by Traditional Philosophers (and that includes
DM-theorists) ended up destroying generality, and with that went the
capacity language has for saying anything at all. (Further details can be found
in Essay Three
Part One.)]
But this, too, can't be
the entire truth, since John is essentially a man -- in that sense he is
identified by his essence. This once more leads 'thought' back in the
opposite conclusion once more, to the negation
of the former negation, yielding the final result that John is not
not-identical with Manhood -- all of which concepts are now understood in a new
and more 'determinate' light. This astounding conclusion now expresses an
'essential' truth about John -- and, indeed, about everything else in the entire
universe, since a similar 'analysis' reveals that every object and process is
essentially connected with its own 'other'
(on the origin and importance of that term, see
here), in a negative, and then in a 'doubly
negative', sort of way, along similar lines --, which 'liberating analysis' isn't available to those who are trapped either by
'formal thinking' or 'commonsense'. Or, of course, those who don't 'understand'
dialectics.
As part of these odd
proceedings,
Spinoza's
'principle' is dragged off the bench and sent into play, as a result of which we are informed that
every determination is
also a negation.
[On that, see
here, and
here. Incidentally, neither Hegel, nor Spinoza
(still less Lenin) even so much as attempted to justify this
'principle'.]
So, not only is
"thought" driven to opposite poles in its bid to differentiate an object like
John from all others (and this we are told necessarily involves in every single
case, negativity -- that is because, clearly, John is not Peter, not Fred, not
Tarquin…, neither is he a mountain, a planet, a coffee mug, a meteorite...),
"thought" is then forced to conclude that no individual object could be
identical with a
universal. In that case, John is not mankind. But, as we saw, a further
consideration of his 'concept', his
'essence', tells us he is also not not-mankind, which means his original
identity needs revising -- or, making more 'determinate', to use the buzzword.
John is thus made
'determinate' by negation (as is everything else). The whole here determines the
part and the part determines the whole, via negativity.
Hey presto,
it is now 'obvious' that everything in existence has negativity
(or 'difference') programmed into it, simply because dialectically-'enhanced' subject-predicate
propositions reveal this hidden truth to those with the eyes to see;and it is this
negativity which powers the universe.
The Big
Bang from the Big Re-write....
Several other
myth-begotten creatures of DM-lore owe their existence to this error of
simple syntax, one of them being the quasi-mystical "Totality". A reading of the "is" of predication as an "is" of identity
motivates the idea that everything must be inter-related.
The 'reasoning' runs something like this:
If, as in H1 below,
John is both identical and not identical with a universal, and
this universal has the infinite built into it (otherwise it wouldn't be
a universal), then John is only himself when he is viewed ininfinite
dialectical connection with everything else of the 'same' sort.
If John is now put in a
similar relation with all the predicates applicable to him (including all the
negative examples expressed in propositions like "John is not Blair", or "John
is not the Pope", "John is not an interstellar dust cloud"), then he is in fact
only an individual of the sort he is because of the seemingly endless and
infinite (negative and positive) connections he
actually has with everything in existence (i.e., all those "mediacies"
that
Lenin spoke about), which
alone give him
his 'determinate'
nature -- if we but knew what the latter was in all its infinite glory (which is why
Engels said what he did about the "asymptotic"
path to knowledge). Moreover, all these properties and relations are "internally
related" to John -- not externally, or materially, but 'logically' -- every last
one
guaranteed by a participle of the diminutive
and suitably
distorted
verb, "to be", namely "is".
H1: John is a man.
John thus assumes truly
cosmic significance; the whole of reality is linked to him and this makes
him what he essentiallyis. Not only that, but everything else is conditioned in like manner
by John in return. John is now at the centre of an intricate web of identities and
differences spanning right across all that exists, for all of time. This
unassuming individual is
now situated at the very heart the meaning universe -- and so is everyone and
everything else. All of reality defines what John means, all of reality is what
gives meaning to his existence and substance to his nature. To a small extent, all of 'Being' depends on him, and he depends
on all of 'Being' in return. "As above, so below",
as
the old Hermetic saying put things.
[The point of that
comment is that only the above family of language uses "is" as the
copula in predication. So, not only is this
Hegelian word-juggling bizarre in the extreme, it ishighly parochial.]
Who'd have thought it?
Even
so, one small step for John is a huge step for mankind. Innovative logic like
this can't be held in check, can't be restricted to just one individual; it has quite
expansive, if not imperialist aspirations as humanity itself now assumes universal significance. The
fate of our entire species now takes centre stage in John's meaning universe
(and not just his) -- the fate of every last atom of which is 'determined' by the semi-Divine
Logic built into 'reality' by
DL. Thus, whatever happens to
John, or to humanity, is interconnected with everything in existence, and vice versa.
Indeed, each of us has their cosmic role assigned them by linguistic
magic like this....
Not only is John related to the Whole, he is what he is
because this dialectically-'developed' diminutive verb implies he both is and is not identical (and then
not not-identical) with an infinite concept.33
Indeed, and in this way, every person,
atom, and tiny speck in the entire universe,
and every process in nature, for all of time, has assigned to it its
rightful 'mediated' place in the Infinite Whole. Every single object and process is identical
with, and not identical with, and then not not-identical
with its unique 'other', guaranteed by a 'logic' that
smuggled identity into sentences in place of boring old predication....
This view of reality pictures the logical structure of sentences
mirroring the logical 'essence' of 'Being'; everything is simultaneously both at
the centre of an infinite web of relations and at its periphery -- all are
at once insignificant and
yet
all
are cosmically important
(a 'unity of opposites'). Part and Whole are thus interlinked and inter-determine one another....
In this way, mystical
Christianity was smuggled into Marxism; linguistic chicanery of this sort is
no less bogus upside down as it is 'the right way up'.
Hegelian word-magic
and garbled,
sub-Aristotelian
'logic'like this -- as opposed to scientific
theory, experiment and observation -- is the real source of DM-Wholism, and
much else besides. Small
wonder then that it falls apart so readily upon examination.
It could be argued
once more that no DM-theorist in her
left mind would argue this way, and that is because the interconnections
mentioned above are not all of the same order or type. Some things in nature are
intimately inter-related; others more remotely so. In that case, local events
will have a vanishingly small effect on distant objects and processes in the solar system
-- never
mind the rest of the Galaxy, or, indeed, the universe at large (and vice
versa).
Fortunately, that response has been neutralised
here, and in Note 14.
In the above passage, the authors of DB
referred to the ability to fly as a "property" that humans acquired as
a result of social organisation, one they lacked earlier. But, is it correct to
call it a "property"? Should we not rather want to call it a "facility", or
perhaps a realisable "opportunity"? This is because no human
beings can actually fly, and they can't do so collectively, either. It
is
the machines we build that do all the flying!
But, if we still insist on calling it a
"property", then perhaps we shouldn't be shy and declare that, for example,
digital TV images are also "properties" that human beings have
acquired, or gained, as a
result of their new capacity to walk around electronics stores. Or, to
change the example: by inventing printing, humanity has perhaps acquired the
"property" of browsing in second-hand bookshops.
In any case, in what
sense is flying a
property? What if someone carried a parrot onto a plane? Would that bird
now have a double property? Perhaps the 'plane has acquired the property
of being able to say "Pretty Polly!" Or, what if, say, an eagle carried off a
rabbit? Would that hapless rodent thereby have acquired the new property of
flight? Or,
perhaps, the property of
being 'kidnapped' by winged assailants? Indeed, would the new 'eagle/rabbit-whole' be symmetrically unified
(as far as part/whole determinations are concerned, and as G1-G4 seem to
suggest)? Do eagles, therefore, acquire anything from rabbits when they enter into
such predatory part/whole ensembles? Does, for example, the eagle part of this
airborne duo acquire the rabbit part's ability to wriggle excessively when carried
off by large predatory birds? But where does this end? On a demonstration, for
example, do those protesting acquire the new property of being hit by police
billy clubs?
Figure One: Do You Acquire
Any Of These
Properties If A Cop Hits You?
Or, do those who use the Internet acquire the property of being
harassed by racist trolls?13
It could be argued that the above
considerations amount to little more than
pedanticnit-picking.
But, even if that were
so, far more serious problems afflict DM-Wholism than these relatively minor quibbles.
Precisely what these are may be
appreciated if we consider why the following would be an illegitimate
counterexample to G3:
G12: Part of a cat is bigger
than the whole of a mouse.
[G3: The whole is more than
the sum of its parts.]
Here a part (i.e., the cat's stomach,
say)
is bigger than a whole mouse, which seems to contradict G3.
Figure Two: Parts Bigger Than Wholes?
Superficially, the reason why G12 would
soon be ruled out as a legitimate
counterexample to G3 is that it confuses parts and wholes from different
animals. Indeed, that might also be one of the reasons why the
eagle/rabbit objection above
would also be rejected (along with some, or all, of the rest). But, if so, and since
passengers and aeroplanes are as separate as rabbits and eagles, or even cats
and mice, DB's own
example might have to be jettisoned for the same reason.
At any rate,
TAR's abstract
schema didn't mention this aspect of the part/whole relation (and neither
do other DM-theorists): i.e., that objections based on inter-systemic part/whole
connections aren't legitimate. However, it isn't easy to see how
counter-examples like these could be ruled out without fatally damaging DM-Wholism. If everything
is interconnected (and the entire nature of all that exists is determined by
everything else, mediated by that mysterious 'dialectical glue', those "internal relations"), then mice and cats' stomachs, eagles' claws and rabbits' fur,
Laurel and Hardy's bowler hats, custard powder and Quasars, and a whole host of other
things, must be interlinked as parts of The One Big Mega-Whole.
Figure Three: One
Inter-Linked Bowler?
Or Two Separate Hats?
Unfortunately, Rees and other DM-theorists
have so far failed to provide us with any way of deciding precisely what does,
and what does not, constitute a legitimate
system/part comparison in this area of DM.
[That merely underlines a problem highlighted earlier
-- as well as in
Part One. This also raises to a
topic this Essay has
been skirting around since the beginning: we have ignored distinctions
dialecticians draw between different types of wholes, and different kinds of
parts, important factors the omission of which appear to undermine much of
this Essay. That response I call 'Spirkin's Defence' [SD], which is covered in
detail in Note 14.]14
Anyway, rabbits and eagles, cats and mice
form part of the same food chain and ecological system. So, perhaps they are from
the same whole, after all? How are we to decide? What are the real, or the 'objective',
boundaries between parts and parts, parts and wholes, or even between wholes and
wholes? Are there any? Or, is this aspect of DM just as
'subjective' as we have found is the case with much of the rest?
DM-theorists certainly need to decide where
the boundaries of their parts and sub-"Totalities" lie so that they themselves
can figure out what this terminally-vague theory of theirs commits them to, if
nothing else!
[However, for reasons spelt out
here, they
are highly unlikely to take that piece of sound advice, even if they were
listening! Indeed, and to date, any
attempt to criticise this 'scientific theory' is met with
little other than blatant fabrication and personal abuse,
spiced-up with the use of de rigueur scatological language,
compounded by no little
special-pleading. A good example
of the latter tactic can be found
here. Readers should note the posts of one "Gilhyle", who
constantly advances this 'excuse'.]
Of course, the problem is that because we
know absolutelynothing about the "Totality" -- or what constitutes any of its
sub-"Totalities" (if it has any) --, or, indeed, anything about
its parts,15
we are in no position to reject any aspect of the entire universe as a
legitimate part of some whole-or-other, and vice versa.
And,
truth be told, neither are dialecticians!
In which case, for all
anyone knows, some
parts could be bigger than some wholes (several examples are given
below). Who is to say? We certainly
can't rule this out on an a priori
basis. The evidence from the material world -- as opposed to the
vague musings drawn from the Ideal DM-world, or even from a detailed perusal of
Hegel's Logic -- is quite plain: there are countless parts of animals
that are bigger than wholes of other animals. And, if we throw in the plant
kingdom, the evidence becomes overwhelming.
Anyway, what happens if the said cat
eats the said mouse? Has the mouse become "more" than it was before? As a
new part of this cat, is it now "more" than the whole mouse it once was when not
part of that cat? To be sure, it has become part of a new whole, but in
what sense has the mouse become "more" (of a mouse?) than it was before? This
question becomes all the more awkward when we remember that cats often dismember
mice when they eat them. So, when swallowed, the hapless rodent might not even be
a mouse. In that case, as far as this non-dialectical, ex-mouse is concerned,
would something less than a mouse
have become something more than a mouse?
This
is perhaps one "emergent property" that even DM-theorists might be reluctant to
swallow, even if the cat saves them the trouble of having to do it.16
It could be argued that the
molecules making up the mouse have become "more" than they were before since
they will in this case be absorbed into a higher organism. But, what if the
mouse is eaten by a crocodile, or consumed by a snake, or by ants -- or even by
bacteria? Is this aspect of DM-theory -- which tells us that parts become "more"
when absorbed into wholes -- sensitive to some sort of 'evolutionary pecking order'? In that
case, what if the cat eats a kitten? Or, if a lion eats a monkey? And what if
you, dear reader (the Dialectical Deity forbid!), were eaten by a lion? Would that
amount to part/whole evolutionary insubordination?
Again, it could be objected that all this is
thoroughly misconceived since DM-theorists are quite clear that they mean to
refer to parts that are integrated into the same system -- as G9 and G9a
indicate:
G9: W1 >
Σpwn.
G9a: The Whole is greater than the sum of
the parts it already has.
If so, many of the above
counter-examples could be dismissed as totally irrelevant since they patently ignore
this important detail. In fact,
TAR itself used an example lifted from an
article on Engels (written by Sean Sayers) to make this particular point
a little clearer:
"Of course, a living organism is
composed of physical and chemical constituents, and nothing more. Nevertheless,
it is not a mere collection of such constituents, nor even of anatomical parts.
It is these parts unified, organized and acting as a whole. This unity and
organization are not only features of our description: they are properties of
the thing itself; they are constitutive of it as a biological organism." [Rees
(1998),
p.77; quoting Sayers (1996), p.162.]
The idea here seems to be that it is the
integration of certain parts into the same organism (or system, or
whole) that changes them in specific ways; moreover, this is
constitutive and typical of relevant whole/part unions. In that case, it looks
like it is the organization of the parts into an integrated whole which
is the key feature, and that this isn't a separate (or separable)
component of that whole; on the contrary, it is an expression of the inter-relation of the
parts themselves that go to make that whole. And yet, we still await an
explanation of the logical or 'internal' links that are supposed to emerge as a
result of all this 'integrating'.
So, while there may be little outward
difference between, say, a heart that has been removed from an organism and the
same heart when it was operating inside its former owner, there is
nonetheless a real
difference not reducible to anything else relevant here. An integrated and working heart is a
functioning part of an organism; in such an environment that heart isn't what
it would otherwise be if it were detached from the body of its owner.
Or, so the argument might proceed...
To be
sure, we define a heart, for instance, as an organ that fulfils a specific
function in a body, but this just means that this
is a de
dicto, not a de re,
definition of that organ. Dialecticians need the connection they surmise here to be more than this;
the link between parts of an organism and that organism itself are meant to
be de re, and not just de dicto, but we have yet to be told how
it is possible to derive the latter from the former.17
This topic is examined in more detail in Note 14 and Note 17, and it will be picked-over
again presently. But, in advance of that, a few preliminary difficulties need
airing, not the least of which concerns the fact that this new
twist would make the example given in DB (the
one concerning the novel "property" of
flight) redundant -- unless, of course, we imagine human society is organic
in some way, or that human beings inside aeroplanes aren't the same as those waiting in
the departure lounge. Does anyone actually think there is a logical, or
'internal' link between such individuals and the aeroplanes they are about to
board? Does this hypothetical 'dialectical link' only kick in when they take their seats?
And,
how does this analogy help us understand class society? Are any of the
passengers on an aeroplane any the less human if they go by train or boat instead? Or, if they parachute off the 'plane?
Where is
the 'organic unity' we seek in this case?
Of course, it could be argued (indeed, it is
argued by those fond of talking this way) that there is an "internal"
relationship at work in Capitalist society, which, for example, organically
connects members of various classes to the system as a whole, and to members of
other classes. That response is also examined in
Note 11, Note 14
and Note 17.
However, since this involves issues
drawn from HM, that topic will largely be ignored at this site -- except,
"internal relations" will be subjected to destructive criticism in Essay Four
Part Two. Consequent on that, the application of such
"relations" to class society
will be given an entirely new interpretation, as will the alleged organicism
alluded to earlier.
Putting this to one side for the time being,
it is
worth pointing out that in general DM-apologists who are impressed with this
particular point (or with those found in the SD) will have to abandon Trotsky's criticisms of the LOI in order to
make this argument work. If not, we should have to admit that the following are
legitimate counter-examples to the organicist ideas
that
Sayers's argument
promotes:
G13: The whole of a baby elephant is
smaller than part of an adult elephant.
G14: The sum of the parts of
a baby
elephant is less than the whole of an adult elephant.
Why this is so will now be explained.
Compare G13 and G14 with G3:
G3: The whole is more than
the sum of its parts.
In
G13 and G14, we have two examples (concerning parts and wholes of living organisms) where G3 doesn't seem to apply.
In order to neutralise these two counterexamples, G3 must be re-interpreted
along lines suggested in G9 and the propositions that led up to it:
G4: Each part becomes more when it is
part of a whole than it would otherwise have been (individually) apart from that
whole.
G5: Let whole, W1, have
parts, pw1-pwn, and let
pw1-pwn
form a set, Pw.
G6: Let the 'same' parts when not parts
of W1 be
p1-pn, and let
p1-pn form a set of parts, P.
G7: For any
pwi, and
any pi,
let pwi >
pi (where
pwi and
pi are the ith members of Pw
and P, respectively).
G8: Let the sum of the parts that are
elements of Pw be
Σpwn, and the sum of the
parts that are elements of P be Σpn.
G9: Either: W1 >
Σpwn.
G10: Or: W1 >
Σpn.
[Recall, G9 means the following:
G9a: The Whole is greater than
the sum of the parts it already has.]
This means that G13 and G14 could be
neutralised
only if they were re-written as the following falsehoods (and then rejected on that
basis):
G15: The whole of a baby elephant is
smaller than part of the same baby elephant.
G16: The sum of the parts of a baby
elephant is less than the whole of the same baby elephant.
[G13: The whole of a baby elephant is
smaller than part of an adult elephant.
G14: The sum of the parts of
a baby
elephant is less than the whole of an adult elephant.]
G15 and G16 effectively neutralise the
implications
of G13 and G14, but only by making an overt appeal to the LOI! Hence,
dialectical quibbles over whether or not the word "same" can capture the fluid
nature of reality will have to be shelved, for if the word "same" is regarded as inadequate in G15 and G16 then it must be inadequate in the
following as well:
G17: The whole of a baby elephant is
smaller than part of the same elephant when it is an adult.
G18: The sum of the parts of a baby
elephant is less than the whole of the same elephant when it is an adult.
But, in G17 and G18 the use of the word
"same" allows for change through continuity, and, if anything, is closer
to its supposed 'dialectical' meaning than the 'same' word in G15 and G16.
Unfortunately, this now transforms G17 and G18 into effective
counterexamples to G9/G9a -- the only viable reading of G3 we could find.
G3: The whole is more than
the sum of its parts.
G9: Either: W1 >
Σpwn.
G9a: The Whole is greater than
the sum of the parts it already has.]
That
is because the 'whole' in G9/G9a has changed. That is, in G17, the whole that
used to be a baby elephant has now grown into a whole
constituting that same elephant when it has matured into an adult. So, at a
later date, one of that baby elephant's parts (for example, its torso) will have grown and become bigger
than it used to be, and would now be greater than the whole to which it once belonged
-- which earlier whole (i.e., the baby elephant) can't itself change since it is 'frozen' in the past.
G18 makes a similar point, only the other way around.
G17: The whole of a baby elephant is
smaller than part of the same elephant when it is an adult.
G18: The sum of the parts of a baby
elephant is less than the whole of the same elephant when it is an adult.
[IED = Identity in
Difference (i.e., "Improvised Explanatory Device").]
This returns us to a
problem that was aired in Part One of this Essay
(as well as in Essay Eight Part One). The obscure nature of the
"Totality", or, indeed, that of any of its sub-"Totalities",
alongside
the
dialectical equivocation over the meaning of "internal" (so that, one minute
it seems to mean "spatially internal", the next "logically or conceptually
internal") reveals that it is now impossible to neutralise this difficulty in any obvious way.
We saw in Part One (and earlier in this
Essay) that unless
dialecticians include the past as part of their "Totality" it wouldn't be
possible to account for development -- or even for their vague idea of 'change
through continuity' --, using the IED ploy.
But, as soon as the past is included,
and the Totality is seen as some sort of four-dimensional
manifold --,
where, unfortunately for dialecticians, there is no such thing as 'objective'
change -- and where 'change' is no more than our limited and 'subjective' view of things,
which means that the entire theory
would lose its Heraclitean
clout (indeed, the universe would become quintessentially
Parmenidean!).
On
the other hand, if this four-dimensional view of time is rejected, dialecticians
would have to admit that the "Totality" contained non-existent things as part of their now non-objective,
'objective' whole (sic) -- namely, those items now locked in the past, which no longer
exist!
Alternatively, once more, if the "Totality" doesn't contain the past, then in order to account for contemporary
class society -- or, for the state of the universe --, dialecticians would have
to appeal to things outside the "Totality" to account for things inside it, defeating the whole
point of introducing such an
obscure idea as the "Totality" in the first place.
And, as far as sub-"Totalities" are concerned,
the same problems apply, but on a more local scale. So, if one of these lesser
obscurities (these sub-"Totalities") is meant to be an object in
4-space too, then any 'change' it
undergoes will be no less illusory.
[The reason why I have introduced 4-space
here is that, if
Relativity Theory is correct, then each of us, and every object and process
in the universe, is a
manifold
stretched out in 4-space. If so, then the 'whole' that represents any such object at
one moment in time (which would be an
orthogonalhyperplane
slice through that manifold) will be smaller (i.e., occupy less
3-space) than a part of that object at a later time -- but only if that object
grows in size (i.e., occupies more of 3-space). In which case, a whole at an
earlier time will be less than its parts at a later time, let alone less than the sum of those parts -- as
we have seen was the case with G17 and G18 above.
Presently, I propose to examine some of the ramifications
of this idea, using the phrase "sub-'Totality'" in place of "orthogonal
hyperplane slice through that manifold", which, I think, is not only a little less
convoluted, it is easier to comprehend. So, in the comments below, one of these
"sub-Totalities" will be, for
example, the entire universe at a particular moment in its history. (This idea
continues from, and depends upon, ideas introduced
earlier and in
Part One. Unfortunately, they won't be
fully understood by anyone who has skipped this earlier section, or who hasn't read Part
One.)]
Once more, if this idea (from modern
Physics is rejected), then any "sub-Totality" [call it, "ST(01)"] out of which
another "sub-Totality" [call it, "ST(02)"] had developed will no longer
exist to provide an 'objective' account of why and how this development had
occurred, since ST(01) is locked in the past
and has thus ceased to exist. On the other hand, if
these earlier non-existent "sub-Totalities" are deemed to be part of the
over-arching "Totality" itself, the latter
would once again contain countless billions of these non-existent
"sub-"Totalities" (one for each
now non-existent 'moment' in the past).
[In
this case, ST(02) exists in the present while ST(01) does not.]
Alternatively, if the past isn't part of the
"Totality" --, and thus no past "sub-Totality" is part of the "Totality" --, we
would again have to appeal to things outside the "Totality" to account for things
inside it.
At the very least, if the past is
allowed back in and is still said to exist inside the "Totality" (that is
if ST(01) still exists!), then the immediate difficulties would return, for then some parts would be
bigger than some wholes, and vice versa, as G13 and G14 asserted (but
which is now made
plain in G17 and G18):
G13: The whole of a baby elephant is
smaller than part of an adult elephant.
G14: The sum of the parts of
a baby
elephant is less than the whole of an adult elephant.
G17: The whole of a baby elephant is
smaller than part of the same elephant when it is an adult.
G18: The sum of the parts of a baby
elephant is less than the whole of the same elephant when it is an adult.
In that case, some parts would be bigger than
earlier wholes, and some sums of parts would less than some later wholes of
the same animal as it developed.
On the other hand, if
"sub-Totalities" like ST(02) aren'tmanifolds in 4-space in their own right, then the above problems would simply resurface
in another form. In that case,
a "sub-Totality" like ST(02) would be ephemeral in the extreme -- having a 'duration' in
the 'specious' present (surely of much shorter length than a
yocto-second (i.e., less than 10-24s)),
and with no link to its former non-existent 'self' from which it had developed or
had emerge (i.e., it would have no link with ST(01)).
That is because, in the present, such links to the past wouldn't exist, either.
If they did still exist, they couldn't link anything with the past, since, in
order to exist
they too would have to be in the
present, not the past.
Here is why:
Call such a link, "L(01)"
(where L(1) doesn't exist at the same time as ST(02),
otherwise it would be part of ST(02)), and consider
again the connection betweenST(01)
and ST(02). Let L(01) connect ST(01)
with ST(02). But, if ST(01) no longer exists, since it lies in the past, then it
can't connect ST(01)
with ST(02), since one half of that 'link' is no longer there, and L(1)
doesn't exist in the present, either -- by definition.
On the other
hand, ifL(01) does indeed connect ST(01)
with ST(02), then it must exist in the present and hence be part of ST(02),
contrary to the definition.
[Naturally, this depends on treating the verb "exist" in odd ways. One minute it
relates to objects in the mega-manifold (in 4-space) that emerged out of 'The
Big Bang' -- so, even if a given object no longer exists as we perceive things
(for instance, a specific dinosaur), it still 'exists' in the mega-manifold --
the next it relates only to those objects as we now perceive them (for example,
Mount
Olympus).
It is important to add that I am neither accepting nor rejecting the idea that the universe
for all of time is a
changeless manifold in 4-space, here. However, it isn't easy to see how DM-fans can
exclude
this view of 4-space -- of course, other than with a dismissive sweep of the hand. I will,
nevertheless, add several comments about this view of 'reality' to Essay Thirteen Part Two.]
Recall that, when translated, G9 amounts to the following re-write of G9a:
G19: A whole is greater than the sum of
those parts when they are assembled as parts of that whole (not as they had been
before they were so assembled).
[G9: W1 >
Σpwn.
G9a: The Whole is greater than
the sum of the parts it already has.
G17: The whole of a baby elephant is
smaller than part of the same elephant when it is an adult.
G18: The sum of the parts of a baby
elephant is less than the whole of the same elephant when it is an adult.]
Of
course, the problem is that G17 and G18 introduce temporal comparisons between parts and wholes of
organisms
when they are considered at earlier or later times.
Naturally, some readers might not regard G17 and G18 as counterexamples to G9,
which doesn't itself include
temporal constraints of this sort -- although, if it were paraphrased along the
lines expressed in G19, it would contain an oblique reference to such temporal
factors.18 But, if that is so, G9 and G19
couldn't appear in a dialectical account of 'reality'. Quite apart from the four-dimensional
problems outlined above, if G17 and G18 lack any temporal constraints, they
would appear to freeze-frame both parts and wholes,
which would mean they are of no use to DM-theorists.
Maybe G9 could be altered to include a
suitable temporal reference, perhaps along the following lines:
G20: Let W1
and Σpwn at time t1 be Wt1
and Σpt1wn, respectively.
G21: Wt1 >
Σpt1wn.
Translated, G21 reads either
(i) the same as G21a,
or (ii) the same as G21b, depending on how abstract this option is deemed to be:
G21a: A whole at a given moment is greater
than the sum of its parts at that instant.
G21b: A whole at a given
moment is greater than the sum of its parts at the same time.
[G21a
focuses on moments in time interpreted as abstract instants (on this, see
Note 19, link below), while G21b leaves it open how we interpret these
moments.]
Re-written in this way, G21a would seem to rule
out some of the counterexamples listed above. However, quite apart from its 'un-dialectical'
implications -- it refers to the sorts of instants in time to which Trotsky took great
exception, and which would surely come to grief in the four-dimensional
minefield outlined earlier,19
this appearance is illusory.
That is because, for some systems, at some time,
the whole could in fact be less than the sum of its parts at that time. A
truncated list of examples illustrating this possibility is given below:
(1) A valuable diamond is dropped into
molten lead. On its own the diamond is worth, say, £10,000 ($19,000). But, as part of the
new
diamond/lead whole, it is now almost valueless, even while at least one of its parts is
worth £10,000 ($19,000).
There
are countless examples that run along
similar lines: a house might be worth £200,000 ($380,000), but as part of a forest
fire/house whole, it would be worthless; a car might be worth £7000 ($13,500), but as part
of a car/crusher whole it would be mere scrap; a "Big Mac" might be 'worth' 99p
($1.90) on its own, but as part of a rat/burger whole it would be valueless; and so on.
It
could be objected that these examples don't in fact involve the exact same moment in time.
This is correct, but onlyif "same moment" means "same abstract
instant". However, since that would 'freeze-frame' reality once more, that
response itself wouldn't appear to be of much use to DM-fans. On the other
hand, if "same moment" is interpreted along the lines suggested in G21b, many of the above
examples would still be relevant -- that depends, of course, on how we understand
the phrase "same time".
G21b: A whole at a given
moment is greater than the sum of its parts at the same time.
However,
the obverse of this is that if "same time" is defined too tightly,
or too narrowly,
in order to rule
out the above 'difficulties', then that would
impose on reality yet another
abstract, a priori structure. In fact, there are no 'objective' criteria here
to which we can appeal to stop this from happening -- or prevent a consequent slide into
'subjectivity' and idealism'' -- whatever is done. This is the permanent bind
that ensnares all metaphysical theories. At some point, Traditional Thinkers have to use
language in certain ways, often implicitly or explicitly setting-up new
conventions when they do so. The problem is that when this has been done, they invariably
interpret these new conventions as 'objective' features of reality, and not artefacts of these
conventions.
[How and why this
happens
is explained at length in Essay Twelve
Part One.]
The same comments apply,
mutatis mutandis, to the next batch
of counter-examples:
(2) Consider a set of non-zero forces aligned in a
couple
so that the resultant at some point is zero. In this case, each part is
greater than the whole (which is zero!), and the whole is equal to, but not
greater than the sum of the parts.
Of course, we could always apply the
SD here and argue that this isn't the
'right' sort of whole, but what if these forces operate inside an organism (or
indeed, inside Capitalism)? [This is quite apart from the fact that the SD is
itself shot through with vagueness, and hence is of little use to anyone -- as we saw in Note 14.]
(3) Consider a rope made from, say, 1000 strands of
material, with each strand, say, 0.5 metres long. Let these strands overlap one
another for approximately 90% of their length. Collectively, because of this
overlap the fibres stretch (as part of the whole rope) for only 50 metres.
However, the sum of the lengths of these strands taken individually is 500
metres -- which would be (and is!) their total length at that instant had they not been
woven into that rope. But, the rope is still only 50 metres long. Here the whole is considerably less than the sum of the
parts.
Indeed, every item of clothing is a counter-example to this trite rule,
for in each case the total length of all the strands of fibre constituting any
garment is greater than the length of that garment as a whole. And what goes for
garments goes for most manufactured goods, as well. What is more, this applies to the
parts of countless organisms, too; hence, the total length of all the muscle
fibres in a wombat is greater than the length of a whole wombat. And we needn't stop at
fury rodents; for instance, the total length of all the
xylem tubes in a tree is greater than
the length/height of that tree, and so on.
(4) Consider gases; let the volume occupied by two
different gases be, say, 1000 cm3. When mixed they react and now occupy
only, say, 750 cm3. Here the sums of the volumes of the parts when
separate is greater than the whole volume occupied together.
(5) A familiar feature relating to the
"form" of sports team players also illustrates the limitation of the
Wholist-mantra. Often, when in a different team, each player can play well below
"form". This happens quite often when football players, say, play for England.
So, here the sum of the performances of footballers
when they play for England
as a whole is less than that taken severally when not in that team, or in
some other team.20
Of course, some might
want to reject or neutralise
one or more of these
counter-examples because of their figurative or vague use of language (even
though not all of them are guilty in this respect, and even though DM-Wholism is
itself shot through with figurative language and impenetrable vagueness,
which means
dialecticians have no room to point any fingers in this regard!), or because
they aren't
relevant to what the part/whole relation 'really' means, as outlined in G1-G4.
However, since we are never told what DM-Wholism really amounts to, it is impossible to decide whether or not even this counter-claim is itself
legitimate.
G1: The entire nature
of a part is determined by its relation with the other parts and with the whole.
G2: The part makes the whole and the
whole makes the part.
G3: The whole is more than the sum of
its parts.
G4: Each part becomes more when it is
part of a whole than it would otherwise have been (individually) apart from that
whole.
Nevertheless, the real problem facing DM-fans,
it seems,
is how they can consistently disallow counterexamples like G17 and G18 -- or the
others listed above -- without undermining their version of the trite
Wholist-mantra (expressed by G3). Naturally, one way to do this might be to declare
(unconvincingly) that in the case of G17 and G18 the two organisms in question
weren't thesame animal. Ironically, as noted above, this would
mean that DM couldn't in fact handle change over time. That is because, if
on the one hand it is impossible to identify the same animal as it
changes over time, then it is equally impossible to say that the same
animal had changed into an adult (as opposed, for example, to having died,
disintegrated, disappeared, or having been eaten by a predator). But, on the
other hand, if we decide that in this case they are the same organism, then the counterexamples above (alongside
G17 and G18) would become legitimate, once more.
Naturally, if they aren't
the same organisms, then the IED defence (deployed
earlier) will have to be abandoned.
G17: The whole of a baby elephant is
smaller than part of the same elephant when it is an adult.
G18: The sum of the parts of a baby
elephant is less than the whole of the same elephant when it is an adult.
However,
it would seem that DM-theorists will need to make a desperate move like this --
that is, they would have to declare that the organisms referred to above weren't the same -- because of the 'un-dialectical'
thesis expressed by G21a:
G21a: A whole at a given moment is greater
than the sum of its parts at that instant.
Of course, if
it turns out that G21a is acceptable to
DM-theorists, it would rule out their neat formula applied to things that
do change, for, as we saw above (in G17 and G18), a whole at an earlier time can
(and mostly does) become less than one of its parts at a later time.
As it stands, G21a is very
un-dialectical since it only seems to be valid if nothing changes! Once more,
G21a looks as if it relies on instantaneous comparisons, something
Trotsky ruled out as abstract and inapplicable to things that exist in material
reality. However, if
parts can become bigger than the wholes they once were a part of, then G9
(and G3) will have to be rejected.
G9: W1 >
Σpwn.
G9a: The Whole is greater than
the sum of the parts it already has.
G3: The whole is more than the sum of
its parts.
To be
sure, many of the annoying counterexamples listed above only seem to work
because of their vague use of certain terms (i.e., "part", "whole",
"sub-Totality" and "Totality"). However, if these counterexamples were to be rejected by
dialecticians on
that basis (that is, if they were ruled-out simply because the vague
language they use is what creates problems), that would once more concede the point that this thesis (about part/whole
relations) can only be made to appear to work because of the imposition
on the world of yet more
a priori DM-dogma.
That, of course, would make this part of DM conventional, and metaphysical, and not at all
'objective'.
Anyway, many of the above counterexamples
used words in perfectly ordinary contexts. It is a moot point, therefore, on what 'objective' grounds they could be rejected
--, or at least repudiated on a basis that still
allowed the retention of the few
favourable examples of the part/whole relation DM-theorists have
scraped-together over the years, which are no less 'vague'.
However, if we are desperate to hang onto G9,
come what
may, then perhaps we could try the following re-write:
G22: For any time tk,
Wtk >
Σptkwk.
Translated this means:
G22a: At any subsequent time a whole is
greater than the sum of the parts of the same whole at that time.
[G21: Wt1 >
Σpt1wn.
G21a: A whole at a given moment is greater
than the sum of its parts at that instant.
G21b: A whole at a given
moment is greater than the sum of its parts at the same time.]
G22 and G22a
have altered G21 and G21a
so that they more closely resemble G21b, and
this might indeed neutralise several of the above
counterexamples, since they relate parts and wholes as they change
diachronically. Suitably altered, too, G22/G22a could rule out all reference to earlier
or later
times, as was the case with, say, G18.
G18: The sum of the parts of a baby
elephant is less than the whole of the same elephant when it is an adult.
Unfortunately however, G22 and G22a only work because of
a blatant use of the LOI
(i.e., "same whole", "same elephant") -- and this use can't be watered-down so that it now
becomes "approximately identical". This isn't just because the latter term is itself
parasitic on strict identity (on that, see
here), but any
such watering-down will sever this alternative's only life-line, collapsing it back
into earlier versions which had to be rejected for reasons outlined above. G22
and G22a only work because of the strictness of the terms they employ.
G22: For any time tk,
Wtk >
Σptkwk.
G22a: At any subsequent time a whole is
greater than the sum of the parts of the same whole at that time.
Anyway, one interpretation of G22 might require time to be
made of instants, as opposed to intervals, if this version of the part/whole
relation is to work. Since that would make this option 'un-dialectical', it, too, must be
rejected by DM-fans who are concerned with consistency (should there be
any who fall under that rubric!).
On the other hand, if we consider the tensed variable in G22,
highlighted in bold in G22a (its ordinary language equivalent):
G22a: At any subsequent time a
whole is greater than the sum of the parts of the same whole at that time,
and
interpret it as referring instead to a temporalinterval, then, as noted earlier, that interval would have to be arbitrarily restricted
so that the subsequent growth of the organism in question wasn't allowed to refute the thesis
under consideration. Otherwise any organic growth taking place in that interval (expressed in G13, G14.
G17 and G18) would falsify this option, as we saw earlier.
G13: The whole of a baby elephant is
smaller than part of an adult elephant.
G14: The sum of the parts of
a baby
elephant is less than the whole of an adult elephant.
G17: The whole of a baby elephant is
smaller than part of the same elephant when it is an adult.
G18: The sum of the parts of a baby
elephant is less than the whole of the same elephant when it is an adult.
This would be particularly
true in the case of rapidly
growing organisms.
Again, few of the above
arguments are likely to impress convinced DM-clones, let alone persuade them that
their neat formula is unreliable -- or even that it is itself 'un-dialectical'
in that it freeze-frames organisms and fails to consider their growth (as we saw
in the previous section)!
That
is perhaps because the arguments developed at this site use analytic techniques
uncongenial to the 'holistic' approach preferred by the DM-faithful.
However, that response itself ignores the
fatal objection that DM-Wholism can only be made even to seem to
work if organisms don't actually grow and develop --, which is an odd sort of thing to have to say about this
supposedly quintessentially developmental 'philosophy of change', DM!
Fortunately, however, we don't have
to employ such tactics alone to demonstrate the weaknesses of DM-Wholism.
Returning to the passage written by Sean
Sayers (quoted earlier):
"Of course, a living organism
is composed of physical and chemical constituents, and nothing more.
Nevertheless, it is not a mere collection of such constituents, nor even of
anatomical parts. It is these parts unified, organized and acting as a whole.
This unity and organization are not only features of our description: they are
properties of the thing itself; they are constitutive of it as a biological
organism." [Sayers (1996), p.162.]
Now, this argument only looks plausible
because it is based on a consideration of biological systems; hence, it fails to
explain how a generalised sort of Wholism operates throughout non-organic
nature, or indeed the rest of the universe.21
So, even if Sayers were correct, what he says
would be of little use in trying to understand the vast bulk of the
material world in Wholist terms. For example, what sense could be made of the
idea that a mountain is only a mountain because of its relation to the whole
(which whole)? Or that, the Sun was only the Sun because of its relation to…,
er..., well, what?21a
[Once more, we could appeal to the
SD here and claim that arbitrary
collections of objects aren't the sorts of wholes that
dialecticians consider to be of prime
importance. But, the Solar System is a system, and a mountain is part of a
geological system. The problem here is that, as we saw in Note 14 (as well as
Note 1a,
Note 3 and Note 11), the SD can't itself
distinguish dialectically significant wholes from arbitrary conglomerations; or,
at least, it can't do so on an 'objective' basis. The same comments apply SD-type responses to many of the counter-examples given below.
Registering that particular point here will save me having to make it over and over again as and when the
need might arise.]
When a wider selection of examples is
considered, further fundamental weaknesses in DM-Holism soon emerge. Consider,
for instance, a car. Do its parts cease to be what they once were if they are
removed from that vehicle? Does a wheel, for example, cease to be a wheel if it
comes off its axle? Or, if it is removed while the car to which it belongs is
being serviced? Is it any less of a wheel? Why replace it then? Does the axle
cease to be an axle when it loses a wheel? Is it, too, any less of an
axle? What would any replacement wheel be re-attached to then? Indeed, what happens
to a lorry with four doubled-up rear wheels if
it loses one while the other three remain on the axle? Would they still be
wheels, and would they still be on an axle if the entire nature of
a part is determined by its relation others, and to the whole?
In a similar vein, consider the following
unlikely conversation in the Parts Department of a garage:
NN: "Can I have a fan belt?"
NM: "Sorry mate, you can't because fan
belts are only fan belts when they are attached to the cooling system of
an engine."
Or, another in a café:
MM: "Can I have a slice of
cake?"
MN: "No, but you can have a
slice of non-cake, which used to be cake when it was attached to the
whole cake before we sliced it up for you."
If a part is only a part -- and its
nature is fully determined in the said manner when it is incorporated in
a whole --, the Parts Department in the above example is surely mis-named. It should be
called the "Non-Parts Department" -- or, perhaps:
Interested readers can now join in and
dream up their own 'Dialectical Menu' for the 'Wholist-café' mentioned earlier.
It could be objected that fan belts and the
like are what they are because they have been designed to fit
cars, and that it is this intended role or function that makes them parts of the
wholes they later join. But, this would make the part/whole relation impossibly
vague, for in that case we wouldn't know what is part and what is whole -- or
how they are connected -- until some intention or other had been
ascertained. And that difficulty would apply to the designers, too. How could
they form an intention to design this or that part if they couldn't
independently identify it first before they formed that intention? Imagine this
conversation in The Design Department:
MP:
What are you designing?
NP:
I don't know until I have finished it!
Plainly, there can be no intention
to manufacture a part of some whole if that part is only the part it later
becomes when it is located in that whole, which is manifestly the case with
a fan belt until it is so attached. In which case, we would have something
like the following:
An 'intention'
To Make-An-Unknown-'Object'-Whose-Nature-Remains-Obscure-Until-The-Latter-Has-Been-Determined-By-Its-Attachment-To-Another-'Something-Or-Other'-That-Is-Itself-Indeterminate-This-Side-Of-The-Aforementioned-Union-Into-A-New-Whole-Of-Some-Sort-Or-Other...
Worse still, this new
change of focus (onto intentions) might have untoward
teleological
implications for the parts of plants and animals, to say nothing of the rest of
the Universe. Was the Sun 'intended' to warm the earth and keep it in steady orbit? Are
the stars there merely to provide gainful employment for Astrologers? Or, maybe to assist
wayfarers traverse oceans?22
In
addition, consider cases where objects retain their identity ('designed' or
not), even though they feature in a temporary or semi-permanent whole for which they weren't actually 'intended'.
Examples of this would include instances where, say, an ordinary tool (such as a
hammer) is used in a 'non-standard' way -- to prop open a door, deter rioting
cops, or to smash the windows on buses carrying scabs. Or, where a house brick
might be used to weigh some papers down, frighten some more scabs, or
're-configure' a group of Nazis. In the latter case, the brick clearly remains a
brick throughout; the fact that it won't lose any of its usual properties if it
enters into, say, a new brick/'damaged-Nazi-whole' will be one of the reasons why
it would be recommended to that end. Are Nazis any more scum-like (or
brick-like) when they are in a new 'Nazi/brick whole' than they were before? Would this brick be more
of a brick when lobbed at a scab than it would be if it were thrown at members
of, say,
Britain First? Does the
said scab receive a similarly 'wholistic promotion' because the brick knocked him out? If
parts and wholes were entirely inter-determined in the way specified (by
means of those "internal relations"), most or all of these would be the case.
It
could be argued once more that the above aren't relevant counter-examples since
the items in question weren't originally designed to
feature in such systematic wholes, nor do they assume wider functional roles as
working units either in their old or in their new guises. But, we have been here already. A
response like this would rule out one or more of the few positive examples to
which that
Rees
and other DM-fans themselves appeal. For example, where is the 'organic unity' in the
aeroplane example that the authors of
DB advanced? Moreover, it would still fail to account for the altered roles
that systematically-functioning items often undergo as a result of
inter-systemic exchange -- even while they retain their 'identity'.
Consider, for instance, a seat from an old car; it could still be used (when
separated from that car) as a seat in a house, or as a display in a museum, or
as part of a barricade (while still serving as a seat for the barricaders).
If the properties of parts actually changed as a result of their separation from
the wholes they were 'meant' to fit (as this 'theory' implies they should) a
seat would no longer be of any use in such new surroundings.
And,
we don't have to invent weird and wonderful counter-examples
drawn from human interaction; consider cases where animals commandeer parts
taken from other animals and use them in the same, or nearly the same, way
as their former
owners had. For example,
Hermit Crabs
use the shells of other sea creatures as protection. Is such a shell more or
less of a shell in this new organic whole? The same question, it seems, could be asked
about
octopodia. [Film
here.]
What about holes in the ground,
or in trees,
used as 'homes' and successively occupied by rabbits, foxes, moles, badgers,
assorted birds, or even bees and wasps? Does a hole, therefore, become "more"
of a hole whole when it is part of, say, a new mole hole whole than when it was
part of a former vole hole whole? Indeed, does a mole or a vole become more or
less of a mole or a vole whole in their new mole or vole hole whole role?
Think, too, of wool and feathers gathered by birds to line their nests for warmth and padding. Again,
consider the way that human beings use animal skins to keep warm, employing the
latter in the same way their former owners used them. Does wool, for example,
become more of an insulator when it forms part of a new child/pullover whole
than when it was on the original sheep?
Does it become more woollen
when part of a scarf/worker ensemble?
What about the medical use of animal parts in human
bodies?
Xenotransplantation would be a non-starter if parts and
wholes were "internally related", as DM-theorists would have us believe.
Are
heart valves taken from pigs (and other animals) no longer valves when they
leave the body of the donor animal and are about to be transplanted into a human
heart?
Indeed,
beforeTony Cliff,
for example, received such a
valve, did he point out to the doctors that, on sound dialectical lines, it
would be
no use transplanting a pig's valve into his heart since it wasn't part of the
whole that constituted his body? If so, those concerned for his health forgot to make a note of
it at the time. [Birchall (2011), pp.542-43.]
Update July 2012: The
PBS Channel
has just carried a programme -- aired on UK cable TV, 26/07/2012 -- about a new
treatment being tried out in New Zealand using transplanted pig cells to manage
diabetes.
"Are pigs about to migrate from the dinner
table to the operating table? Using animals
as a source of organs for transplantation
into humans was once one of medicine's next
big things -- a solution to transplant
waiting lists.
"However, there have been problems with
rejection -- and recently stem cells have
been grabbing the spotlight. But some
researchers are now saying that transplants
from animals 'could soon become a reality',
but not necessarily as originally expected.
There is still a pressing need for organs.
In the UK there are 8,000 people on the
waiting list -- three die every day.
"Several technologies are trying to meet the
demand. In August, a patient from London was
the first in the UK to have his
heart replaced with a mechanical one
while stem cells have been used for simple
structures such as the windpipe. However,
using stem cells to build more complicated
organs such as a heart is a long way off and
mechanical body parts are used in the short
term before an actual transplant. Using
animals as a source -- known as
'xenotransplantation' -- is another
potential solution.
"Whole organs
"Pigs have been used as a
source of heart valves, which control the flow of blood around the heart. Here
the pig cells are chemically stripped away and when the remaining structure is
transplanted, human cells grow around it. Stripping away the living material
would not work for most transplants -- nobody would want the heart that did not
beat.
"However, that living
material has a big problem, namely
rejection. The human immune system attacks
the pig tissue, which it recognises as
foreign. Dr David Cooper from the University
of Pittsburgh Medical Centre is one of a
group of researchers
arguing in the Lancet that the problems with organ rejection are
being overcome. Some pigs -- GTKO
[α1,3-Galactosyltransferase
Gene-Knockout -- RL] pigs -- have
been genetically modified. They no longer
produce a pig protein,
galactosyltransferase, which the immune
system would have attacked. The authors say
that this kind of rejection is 'not the main
cause of graft failure', however, 'other
issues have become more prominent'.
"Problems such as damaging blood clots and
inflammation will require further genetic
modification. As a result they say that:
'Overall, clinical pig organ
xenotransplantation will probably not be
undertaken in the next few years.'
"Smaller scale, greater promise
"While therapies are distant on the whole
organ level, they believe researchers are
getting closer to transplanting small
numbers of cells. In patients with
type 1 diabetes, the immune system
attacks islet cells in the pancreas, which
control sugar levels. Most people can manage
the condition with insulin, but some have
therapy to replace the lost cells. Around
one in 500 patients with type 1 diabetes
have unpredictable low sugar levels and only
those are currently suitable for the
treatment.
"However, in the UK there is a waiting time
of up to 18 months and the number of cells
which can be transplanted to each patient is
limited. The authors argue that using pigs
as a source for these cells is 'much more
encouraging', than using whole organ
transplants. They write: 'Because pig
insulin was given to patients with diabetes
for decades, and because a diabetic monkey
survived for more than one year supported
only by pig islets, clinical pig-islet
xenotransplantation will almost certainly be
physiologically successful.' Clinical trials
are underway in New Zealand to test that
theory.
"Dr Martin Rutter, senior lecturer at the
University of Manchester, said he was
'interested, but cautious'. He warned that:
'It is still not clear whether it is an
effective treatment or a safe treatment. If
it proves safe and effective it could be an
amazing development.'
"It has also been suggested that some cells
in the brain could be transplanted to ease
neurodegenerative diseases such as
Parkinson's or that pigs could be a
source of corneas. 'With regard to pig
tissues and cells, as opposed to organs, it
would seem that clinical xenotransplantation
could soon become a reality,' the
researchers conclude.
"NHS
Blood and Transplant said organs from
animals had huge potential for the future to
fill the gap between availability and
demand, but there were 'many complex issues
still to overcome' and that there was 'still
a long way to go'. It says until then,
getting more people to donate organs would
be the most successful strategy."[James
GallagherHealth reporter,
BBC News,
21/10/2011. Quotation marks altered to
conform to the conventions adopted at this
site; several paragraphs merged.]
And
there is this
from the BBC (in early 2014):
"I am standing in a
fully functioning operating theatre. A
surgeon and team of specialists in green
smocks are preparing to operate. But I'm not
in a hospital. I am on a farm deep in the
Japanese countryside. On the gurney about to
undergo the knife is a six-month-old female
pig....
"The unconscious pig
is about to become a surrogate mother -- and
the embryos she is now carrying are very
special. They are chimeric, that is, they
carry genetic material from two different
species. In a nearby shed Prof
Nagashima takes me to see his most prized
possessions. For this I have to change into
full smock, hat, boots and mask. It is not
to protect me, it is to protect the
occupants -- fully grown chimeric pigs.
"Halfway
down the
long
white
shed, I
am
introduced
to pig
number
29 -- a
large,
hairy
male
with
jutting
tusks.
Number
29 is a
white
pig, but
he is
covered
in
coarse,
black
hair.
More
importantly,
inside,
he has
the
pancreas
of a
black
pig. How is
that
possible?
It
starts
off by
making
what
Prof
Nagashima
calls
'a-pancreatic'
embryos.
Inside
the
white
pig
embryo,
the gene
that
carries
the
instructions
for
developing
the
animal's
pancreas
has been
'switched
off'.
"The
Japanese
team
then
introduce
stem
cells
from a
black
pig into
the
embryo.
What
they
have
discovered
is that
as the
pig
develops,
it will
be
normal
except
for its
pancreas,
which
will be
genetically
a black
pig's. But
this is
just the
first
step.
"In a
lab at
Tokyo
University
Professor
Hiro
Nakauchi
is
taking
the next
one, and
this is
even
more
astonishing.
Prof
Nakauchi
takes
skin
cells
from an
adult
brown
rat. He
then
uses
gene
manipulation
to
change
these
adult
skin
cells
into
what are
called
'iPS'
cells.
The
amazing
thing
about
induced
pluripotent
stem
cells is
that
they
have
many of
the same
characteristics
as
embryonic
stem
cells.
In other
words,
they can
develop
into any
part of
the
animal's
body. IPS
cells
were
first
created
in 2006
by
Japanese
medical
researcher
Dr
Shinya
Yamanaka.
In 2012,
he won
the
Nobel
Prize
for his
discovery.
In his
lab,
Prof
Nakauchi
has
succeeded
in using
these
iPS
cells to
grow a
brown
rat
pancreas
inside a
white
mouse.
"So why
is all
of this
so
important? The
ultimate
objective
of this
research
is to
get
human
organs
to grow
inside
pigs. By
itself,
that
would be
a
massive
breakthrough
for
science.
But what
Prof
Nakauchi
is
trying
to
achieve
goes
further.
He is
hoping
to
develop
a
technique
to take
skin
cells
from a
human
adult
and
change
them in
to iPS
cells.
Those
iPS
cells
can then
be
injected
into a
pig
embryo.
"The result, he hopes,
will be a pig with a human pancreas or
kidney or liver, or maybe even a human
heart. Not only that, the organ would be
genetically identical to the human from
which the skin cells were taken. This is one of the
holy grails of medical research: the ability
to reproduce a human organ that is
genetically identical to the person who
needs it. It could mean an end to donor
waiting lists, and an end to problems of
organ rejection.
"But there are many
potential obstacles ahead. The first is that
pigs and humans are only distantly related.
It is one thing to get a black pig pancreas
to grow inside a white pig, quite another to
get a human pancreas to do the same. Prof
Nakauchi is confident it can be done. He
thinks it will take at least five years, but
admits it could take much longer." [Taken
from
here; accessed 03/01/2014. Quotation
marks altered to conform to the conventions
adopted at this site. Several paragraphs
merged. Link added.]
Again, DM-fans should write to the doctors in
Japan and New Zealand mentioned above, as well as to the Lancet,
telling them that this research is a waste of time and money since the nature of
the relevant parts is determined by the whole, and so they can't be transplanted or engineered
successfully.
Except, as the first of the above articles
notes: parts of animals have already
been used in this way.
In
the summer of 2013 the
following appeared in the New Scientist:
"Mouse heart beats again
thanks to human stem cells
"A newly
beating heart is part-mouse, part-human. For the first time, a mouse heart has
been made to pulse again by stripping it of its own cells and rebuilding it with
human ones (see
video...).
"To create
the hybrid heart,
Lei Yang
at the University of Pittsburgh and
colleagues took the heart from a mouse and, in a process that lasted 10 hours,
removed all its cells. The remaining protein scaffold was then repopulated with
human heart precursor cells -- stem cells that had differentiated into the three
types of cell required for a heart. After a few weeks, the organ started to beat
again. 'Our engineered hearts contain about 70 per cent human heart precursor
cells, which provide enough mechanical force for contraction,' says Yang. The
precursor cells were derived from induced pluripotent stem cells generated from
human skin cells, and were then turned into cardiac precursor cells. A
previous study used human embryonic cells to achieve
similar results, but the success rate in converting them to beating heart cells
was very low.
"Although
the designer hearts do beat rhythmically, they aren't strong enough to pump
blood effectively and the team found that the heart's rhythm differed from a
normal mouse's heart. Yang thinks this is because the added cells were not as
mature as adult heart cells or properly synchronised. 'We did not rebuild the
whole cardiac conduction system, which could control the rhythmic beatings of a
heart,' he says. The team's next step will be to improve the mechanical and
electrical synchronisation of the heartbeat.
"Yang's
long-term goal is to create human hearts that can be used for transplants, for
drug testing and to better understand how a heart develops. 'Using our method,
we could generate both muscle and vascular-like structures in the engineered
heart constructs,' says Yang. 'We hope to make a piece of human heart tissue
soon but our dream is to regenerate a human heart organ.'
"The main
challenge is to scale up the system to work with human heart scaffolds. There,
the biggest problem will be the sheer number of cells needed to reseed a human
heart." [New
Scientist219, 2931, 24/08/2013. Quotation marks altered to
conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Several paragraphs merged. Links in the original.]
And now (in late January 2014), a major
break-though in stem cell production has been announced by Japanese scientists:
"Stem cell 'major
discovery' claimed
"Stem cell researchers
are heralding a 'major scientific
discovery', with the potential to start a
new age of personalised medicine. Scientists
in Japan showed stem cells can now be made
quickly just by dipping blood cells into
acid. Stem cells can transform into any
tissue and are already being trialled for
healing the eye, heart and brain.
"The latest
development,
published in the journal Nature,
could make the technology cheaper, faster
and safer. The human body is built of cells
with a specific role -- nerve cells, liver
cells, muscle cells -- and that role is
fixed. However, stem cells can become any
other type of cell, and they have become a
major field of research in medicine for
their potential to regenerate the body.
"Embryos are one,
ethically charged, source of stem cells.
Nobel prize winning research also showed
that skin cells could be 'genetically
reprogrammed' to become stem cells (termed
induced pluripotent stem cells)....
"Now a study shows
that shocking blood cells with acid could
also trigger the transformation into stem
cells -- this time termed STAP
(stimulus-triggered acquisition of
pluripotency) cells. Dr Haruko Obokata, from
the Riken Centre for Developmental Biology
in Japan, said she was 'really surprised'
that cells could respond to their
environment in this way. She added: 'It's
exciting to think about the new
possibilities these findings offer us, not
only in regenerative medicine, but cancer as
well.'
"The breakthrough was
achieved in mouse blood cells, but research
is now taking place to achieve the same
results with human blood. Chris Mason,
professor of regenerative medicine at
University College London, said if it also
works in humans then 'the age of
personalised medicine would have finally
arrived."
"He told the BBC: 'I
thought -- "my God that's a game changer!"
It's a very exciting, but surprise, finding.
It looks a bit too good to be true, but the
number of experts who have reviewed and
checked this, I'm sure that it is. If this
works in people as well as it does in mice,
it looks faster, cheaper and possibly safer
than other cell reprogramming technologies
-- personalised reprogrammed cell therapies
may now be viable.'
"For age-related
macular degeneration, which causes sight
loss, it takes 10 months to go from a
patient's skin sample to a therapy that
could be injected into their eye -- and at
huge cost. Prof Mason said weeks could be
knocked off that time which would save
money, as would cheaper components.... The finding has been
described as 'remarkable' by the Medical
Research Council's Prof Robin Lovell-Badge
and as 'a major scientific discovery' by Dr
Dusko Ilic, a reader in stem cell science at
Kings College London.
"Dr Ilic added: 'The
approach is indeed revolutionary. It will
make a fundamental change in how scientists
perceive the interplay of environment and
genome.' But he added: 'It does not bring
stem cell-based therapy closer. We will need
to use the same precautions for the cells
generated in this way as for the cells
isolated from embryos or reprogrammed with a
standard method.'
"And Prof Lovell-Badge
said: 'It is going to be a while before the
nature of these cells are understood, and
whether they might prove to be useful for
developing therapies, but the really
intriguing thing to discover will be the
mechanism underlying how a low pH shock
triggers reprogramming -- and why it does
not happen when we eat lemon or vinegar or
drink cola?'" [Quoted from
here; accessed 31/01/2014. Quotation
marks altered to conform to the conventions
adopted at this site. Several paragraphs merged. Link in the original. Although
this work was later exposed as a fraud, that
doesn't affect the argument. On that,
see below.]
And, in February 2014 we read the
following in The Independent:
"Human skin cells have been turned into stem cells which
have the potential to develop into fully-formed embryos, simply by bathing them
in weak citric acid for half an hour, a leading scientist has told The
Independent on Sunday. The
demonstration that the technique, which was pioneered on mouse cells, also works
on human skin cells raises the prospect of new treatments for incurable
illnesses, from Parkinson's to heart disease, based on regenerating diseased
organs in situ from a patient's own stem cells.
"Although there
is no intention to create human embryos from skin cells, scientists believe that
it could, theoretically, be possible to do so given that entire mouse embryos
have already been effectively created from the re-engineered blood cells of
laboratory mice. Creating the
mouse embryos was the final proof the
scientists needed to demonstrate that
the stem cells were 'pluripotent', and
so capable of developing into any
specialised tissue of an adult animal,
including the 'germ cells' that make
sperm and eggs.
"Pluripotent stem
cells could usher in a new age of
medicine based on regenerating diseased
organs or tissues with injections of
tissue material engineered from a
patient's own skin or blood, which would
pose few problems in terms of tissue
rejection. However, the
technique also has the potential to be
misused for cloning babies, although
stem cell scientists believe there are
formidable technical, legal and ethical
obstacles that would make this
effectively impossible.
"A team of
Japanese and American scientists
converted human skin cells into stem
cells using the same simple approach
that had astonished scientists around
the world last month when they announced
that they had converted blood cells of
mice into stem cells by bathing them in
a weak solution of citric acid for 30
minutes. The scientist who
instigated the research programme more
than a decade ago said that he now has
overwhelming evidence that the same
technique can be used to create
embryonic-like stem cells from human
skin cells.
"Charles Vacanti,
a tissue engineer at Brigham and Women's
Hospital in Boston, Massachusetts, said
that the same team of researchers has
generated stem cells from human dermal
fibroblasts -- skin cells -- which came
from a commercial source of human
tissues sold for research purposes. 'The process was
very similar to the one we used on mouse
cells, but we used human dermal
fibroblasts that we purchased
commercially,' Dr Vacanti said. 'I can
confirm that stem cells were made when
we treated these human cells. They do
the same thing [as the mouse cells].
"'They revert back
to stem cells, and we believe the stem
cells are not a contamination in the
sample that we were inadvertently sent
by the company, but that they are being
made, although we still have to do the
final tests to prove this,' he added. 'We have strong
evidence that we have now made human
stem cells by the same technique used on
mouse cells and it suggests that there
is probably a parallel process going on.
I'm 98 per cent comfortable with the
results so far.'
"Detailed genetic
tests and further experiments will be
needed to prove beyond any doubt that
the cells are true stem cells, although
Dr Vacanti emphasised that he will not
be carrying out the same experiments on
the human stem cells that led to the
creation of mouse embryos from mouse
stem cells. 'My interest is
to demonstrate the biological process,
to grow your own perfect embryonic stem
cells in order to repair your own
damaged tissues -- but without making an
embryo,' Dr Vacanti said.
"'In order to
repair tissues you need embryonic stem
cells, but the irony is that in order to
show that you don't need an embryo you
have to sometimes create an embryo -- in
mice at least.' Asked whether it
would be possible in theory to follow on
from the mouse research to show that
skin cells could be turned into viable
human embryos -- effectively a clone of
the donor of the skin samples -- Dr
Vacanti said: 'This is an offshoot, an
unintended consequence, so the answer is
"yes".... This would be the natural
conclusion, but I won't be the one that
does it.'
"Robert Lanza, a stem cell expert at Advanced Cell Technology in Massachusetts, said that if the technique has been made to work on human cells as Dr Vacanti has described, then it could be a 'paradigm changer' in terms of using stem cells for therapeutic purposes. However, the development also raises serious questions about its possible unauthorised use for cloning babies.
"'Because of the ease of the methodology, this research could have serious ethical ramifications,' Dr Lanza said. 'If the cells are truly totipotent [able to develop into any cell type], then this technology could be used to clone organisms...and perhaps even humans.' Haruko Obokata, a young post-doctoral researcher now at the Riken Centre for Developmental Biology in Kobe, Japan, startled the world two weeks ago when she explained how she created embryonic stem cells from the blood of mice by simply bathing the murine blood cells in a weak solution of citric acid for half an hour.
"Dr Obokata began the research in 2008 in the United States after being recruited to work in the laboratory of Charles Vacanti, a colourful and engaging scientist at the Brigham and Women's Hospital in Boston, who first had the idea of creating stem cells from blood or skin cells by subjecting them to some kind of traumatic stress. Dr Vacanti, along with his pathologist brother Martin, had previously published studies indicating that stem cells are spontaneously created when ordinary tissue is stressed by either mechanical injury or by rising acidity.
"He believed this was the body's natural repair mechanism, when damaged adult cells revert to an embryonic state which we call 'stem cells'. His initial studies, published more than 10 years ago, were met with ridicule. On one occasion, Dr Vacanti was heckled at a scientific conference. 'People said we were nuts. They said it was heresy, that we should withdraw our scientific papers,' Dr Vacanti said.
"However, Dr Obokata's painstaking research, now published in the journal Nature after unusually severe scrutiny by peer reviewers, appears to have proved Dr Vacanti right. Making embryonic stem cells from human skin or blood could not be any easier." [Quoted from here; accessed 09/02/2014. Quotation marks altered to conform to the conventions adopted at this site. Several paragraphs merged.]
What could prove to be a game-changing advance in Xenotransplantation was announced in early January 2022:
"Man receives first successful transplant of a pig heart into human body
"The patient had previously been deemed ineligible for a traditional organ transplant
"In a first-of-its kind operation, surgeons successfully implanted the heart of a genetically modified pig into a human patient, saving his life after he'd previously been deemed ineligible for a traditional heart transplant. David Bennett Sr., of Maryland, was safely in recovery from the procedure on Monday, where his doctors from the University of Maryland Medical [UMD] center have been monitoring his condition.
"'It creates the pulse, it creates the pressure, it is his heart,' Dr Bartley Griffith, the director of the cardiac transplant program at the medical center, told The New York Times. 'It's working and it looks normal. We are thrilled, but we don't know what tomorrow will bring us. This has never been done before.' The procedure marks the first time a genetically modified animal heart has been transplanted into a human body without immediate rejection, according to UMD.
"'It was either die or do this transplant. I want to live. I know it's a shot in the dark, but it's my last choice,' Mr Bennett said of the procedure in a statement. 'I look forward to getting out of bed after I recover.' The 57-year-old had been in hospital for weeks with a life-threatening heart arrhythmia and only a heart-lung bypass machine was keeping him alive before the procedure. A previous surgery involved putting a pig valve into his heart, but his January operation would take things to a whole new level. The surgery, conducted on Friday with emergency authorisation from the Food and Drug Administration, could open the door for greater organ access, according to the doctor who performed it.
"'This was a breakthrough surgery and brings us one step closer to solving the organ shortage crisis. There are simply not enough donor human hearts available to meet the long list of potential recipients,' said Dr Bartley P Griffith in a statement. Roughly 110,00 people are waiting for organ transplants in the US, and more than 6,000 die each year before they can be matched with an organ donor and brought in for surgery. Doctors have attempted so-called 'xenotransplants' of animal organs into human bodies since the 1980s, but trials featuring entire have largely eased since the case of Stephanie Fae Beauclair, a baby who died a month after receiving a baboon heart to cure a fatal heart condition. Pig heart valves, similar to those in humans, have been used successfully for transplants.
"A regenerative medicine company called Revivicor supplied the pig heart for the procedure, using a combination of years of breeding and genetic editing to produce a suitable donor, a 240-pound male standard pig. The company edited out three genes in the pig's DNA that would've caused a human body to reject the organ, while adding in six human genes that would cause the heart to be accepted. Once the heart was harvested, it was kept in a special box that supplied it with nutrients and hormones. Researchers had previously tried using pig hearts in baboons, and were able to keep them alive for months on end, honing which genes played key roles in preventing bodies from rejecting organs. 'This is nothing short of a miracle,' David Bennett Jr told USA Today. 'That's what my dad needed, and that’s what I feel like he got.'" [Quoted from here; accessed 13/01/2022. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site; several paragraphs merged. Link in the original.]
These momentous break-throughs couldn't have been made by anyone who consistently accepts DL, since it is obvious from the above that it isn't its relation to the
whole that makes the part, but the ingenuity and expertise of the scientists
involved that does.
Are DM-fans prepared to warn these
scientists that they are actually wasting their time, since the "whole is greater than
the sum of the parts", and the "entire nature of the part is determined by
its relation to the whole"?
The fact
that dialecticians don't do this suggests that even they don't believe this
part of their own theory (no pun intended).
Either that, or they really haven't given it sufficient thought.
[Over the next few years,
in addition to the many instances quoted in the main body of this Essay (and in
the Endnotes), I will be adding further examples of non-Wholist science to
Appendix A.]
Admittedly,
Sean Sayers's point gains
whatever legitimacy it might seem to have from a consideration of organic wholes. If Wholism can
be shown to be defective there, DM-theorists would no longer have good reason
to advocate it anywhere else.
To that end -- and in addition to the examples given in
the previous section -- consider cases where organic compounds retain
their properties in new surroundings (or wholes): for instance, when blood and
bone are used as fertiliser. The only reason they would be used in these new
roles is because of the properties they already have. No one would use blood in such a
way if it ceased to possess all those properties when it had been put on the ground.
Similarly,
think of the way we use certain organic chemicals to fulfil different tasks --
for instance, the same type of plastic can be used to wrap things, isolate or
insulate them, burn or kill things. Other examples include artificial sources of insulin
(from
pigs,
bacteria or
yeast), hormones, clotting factors (the use of Chinese Hamster Ovaries (CHO),
for example), stem
cells, and
cell culture
in general to help treat human beings (or, indeed, certain animals).
The following
example (from 2008) of this use of medical technology only serves as a
reminder that this is an empirical, not a logical, issue: the growth of a
woman's
trachea from her own stem cells to replace a diseased wind pipe (obviating
the need to use tissue rejection medication).
~~~~~~oOo~~~~~~
Update
September 2023: It now transpires that the scientist at the centre of
the stem cell 'breakthrough' mentioned in the previous paragraph, Dr
Paolo Macchiarini,
was a total fraud (I have not deleted that material since it illustrates an
important point raised in Essay Eleven
Part One):
"Scientific pioneer, superstar surgeon, miracle
worker -- that's how Paolo Macchiarini was known for several years....
Macchiarini shot to prominence back in 2008, when he created a new airway for
Claudia Castillo, a young woman from Barcelona. He did this by chemically
stripping away the cells of a windpipe taken from a deceased donor; he then
seeded the bare scaffold with stem cells taken from Castillo's own bone marrow.
Castillo was soon back home, chasing after her kids. According to Macchiarini
and his colleagues, her artificial organ was well on the way to looking and
functioning liked a natural one. And because it was built from Castillo's own
cells, she didn’t need to be on any risky immunosuppressant drugs.
"This was Macchiarini's first big success. Countless
news stories declared it a medical breakthrough. A life-saver and a
game-changer. We now know that wasn't true. However, the serious complications
that Castillo suffered were, for a long time, kept very quiet. Meanwhile,
Macchiarini's career soared. By 2011, he was working in Sweden at one of the
world's most prestigious medical universities, the Karolinska Institute, whose
professors annually select the winner of the Nobel prize in physiology or
medicine. There he reinvented his technique. Instead of stripping the cells from
donor windpipes, Macchiarini had plastic scaffolds made to order. The first
person to receive one of these was Andemariam Beyene, an Eritrean doctoral
student in geology at the University of Iceland. His recovery put Macchiarini on
the front page of the New York Times.
"Macchiarini was turning the dream of regenerative
medicine into a reality. This is how NBC's Meredith Vieira put it in her documentary about
Macchiarini, appropriately called A Leap of Faith: 'Just imagine a world where
any injured or diseased organ or body part you have is simply replaced by a new
artificial one, literally manmade in the lab, just for you.' This marvellous
world was now within reach, thanks to Macchiarini. Last year, however, the dream
soured, exposing an ugly reality. Macchiarini gave his 'regenerating' windpipes
to 17
or more patients worldwide. Most, including Andemariam Beyene, are now dead.
Those few patients who are still alive -- including Castillo -- have survived in
spite of the artificial windpipes they received. In January 2016, Macchiarini
received an extraordinary double dose of bad press. The first was a Vanity
Fair article about his affair with Benita Alexander, an award-winning
producer for NBC News. She met Macchiarini while producing A Leap of Faith and
was soon breaking one of the cardinal rules of journalism: don't fall in love
with the subject of your story.
"By the time the program aired, in mid-2014, the
couple were planning their marriage. It would be a star-studded event.
Macchiarini had often boasted to Alexander of his famous friends. Now they were
on the wedding guest list: the Obamas, the Clintons, Vladimir Putin, Nicolas
Sarkozy and other world leaders. Andrea Bocelli was to sing at the ceremony.
None other than Pope Francis would officiate, and his papal palace in Castel
Gandolfo would serve as the venue. That's what Macchiarini told his fiancée. But
as the big day approached, Alexander saw these plans unravel, and finally
realised that her lover had lied about almost everything. The pope, the palace,
the world leaders, the famous tenor -- they were all fantasies. Likewise the
whole idea of a wedding: Macchiarini was still married to his wife of 30
years....
"Which left a big, burning question in the air: if
Macchiarini was a pathological liar in matters of love, what about his medical
research? Was he conning his patients, his colleagues and the scientific
community? The answer came only a couple of weeks later, when Swedish television
began broadcasting a three-part exposé of Macchiarini and his work. Called Experimenten
(The Experiments), it argued convincingly that Macchiarini's artificial
windpipes were not the life-saving wonders we'd all been led to believe. On the
contrary, they seemed to do more harm than good -- something that Macchiarini
had for years concealed or downplayed in his scientific articles, press releases
and interviews. Faced with this public relations disaster, the Karolinska
Institute immediately promised to investigate the allegations but then, within
days, suddenly announced that Macchiarini's contract would not be extended.
"Macchiarini’s fall was swift, but troubling
questions remain about why he was allowed to continue his experiments for so
long. Some answers have
emerged from the official
inquiries into the Karolinska Institute and the Karolinska University
hospital. They identified many problems with the way the twin organisations
handled him. Macchiarini's fame had won him well-placed backers. These included
Harriet Wallberg, who was the vice-chancellor of the Karolinska Institute in
2010, when Macchiarini was recruited. She pushed through his appointment despite
the fact that he had some very negative references and dubious
claims on his résumé....
"Support for Macchiarini remained strong, even as
his patients began to die. In part, this is because the field of windpipe repair
is a niche area.... Also, in such a highly competitive environment, people are
keen to show allegiance to their superiors and wary of criticising them. The
official report into the matter dubbed this the 'bandwagon effect'. With
Macchiarini's exploits endorsed by management and breathlessly reported in the
media, it was all too easy to jump on that bandwagon. And difficult to jump off.
In early 2014, four Karolinska doctors defied the reigning culture of silence by
complaining about Macchiarini. In their view, he was grossly misrepresenting his
results and the health of his patients. An independent investigator agreed.
But the vice-chancellor of Karolinska Institute, Anders Hamsten, wasn't bound by
this judgement. He officially cleared Macchiarini of scientific misconduct,
allowing merely that he'd sometimes acted 'without due care'....
"The Macchiarini scandal claimed many of his
powerful friends. The vice-chancellor, Anders Hamsten, resigned. So did
Karolinska's dean of research. Likewise the secretary-general of the Nobel
Committee. The university board was dismissed and even Harriet Wallberg, who'd
moved on to become the chancellor for all Swedish universities, lost her job....
If there is a moral to this tale, it's that we need to be wary of medical
messiahs with their promises of salvation." [Guardian
article, authors John Rasko and Carl Power, dated 01/09/2017, accessed
24/09/2023. Spelling modified to UK English; quotation marks altered to conform
with the conventions adopted at this site. Links in the original; several
paragraphs merged. June 2023: This con man has just been given a
two-and-a-half year
prison sentence for fraud. More details are set out
in this recent video.]
Some might
be tempted to view the above as a vindication of DM, but this fraud was exposed,
not by the use of 'dialectics', but by the diligent work of other scientists and
journalists. Had anyone simply appealed to DM, this con man would probably
still be in a job.
~~~~~~oOo~~~~~~
But, what about complex
organic entities that seem to preserve their identity and all their properties
in new surroundings, systems and contexts? For example, if an organ is kept alive outside the body (on a
machine, or in a refrigerator), not only is it still the same organ it can be
used as such in another body. So, skin remains skin when grafted onto a new area of
the same body, or onto the same or different area of a new body. It doesn't cease to be skin in between graftings.
Similarly, blood that is transfused still remains blood. Does anyone think
that when they donate a pint of blood it cease to be blood?22a
Moreover, if DM were true, we wouldn't see reports like this:
"Blind people could one day have their sight
restored thanks to a treatment that borrows a gene from an unlikely
source --
algae
-- and inserts it into the retina. The technique has succeeded in
restoring the ability to sense light and dark to blind mice, and
clinical trials in humans could begin in as little as two years.
'The idea is to develop a treatment for
blindness,' says
Alan Horsager, a neuroscientist at the
Institute of Genetic Medicine at the University of Southern
California, Los Angeles, who leads the research. 'We introduce a
gene that encodes a light-sensitive protein, and we target the
expression of that gene to a subset of retinal cells.'
"Horsager hopes his work will change that. His
team's approach is based on gene therapy, where a 'tame' virus is
harnessed to transfer a gene into target cells in the recipient. In
this case the gene of interest is one that makes
Channelrhodopsin-2
(ChR2), a photosensitive protein used by unicellular algae to help
them move towards light. The target cells are bipolar cells in the
retina. The retina contains three cellular layers
that work together to detect and transmit light signals to the
brain.... The first layer contains the photoreceptors -- the rods
and cones that detect light. The second layer is made of bipolar
cells that act as a conduit between the photoreceptor and the third
type of cell, the ganglion, which transmits the light signals to the
brain.
"In people with RP and AMD, the photoreceptors
have been damaged and lost, so the ganglion cells do not receive
signals and the brain cannot produce an image. The idea behind the
gene therapy is to make the bipolar cells function as photoreceptors
by producing ChR2. The modified bipolar cell would then be able to
sense light and transmit a signal to the ganglion.
"Horsager's team tested their technique using
three groups of mice: one with normal vision, and two groups of
mouse strains that naturally become blind with age in a similar way
to people with RP and AMD. One blind group was treated with the gene
therapy, while the other two groups were not. Treated mice received a sub-retinal injection
of the virus containing the algal gene. Ten weeks after the
injection, the team dissected some of the mice and used
immunolabelling to see whether ChR2 was being expressed in the
retina. They found that the protein was being made by the bipolar
cells.
"But the strongest evidence of the treatment's
success came when treated mice were put in the centre of a water
maze with six possible corridors, only one of which led to a ledge
that the mice could clamber out of the water onto. With a guiding
light shining at the end of the corridor which contained the ledge,
the gene-therapy mice were able to find the escape platform 2.5
times faster, on average, than the untreated blind mice. The work
will appear in Molecular Therapy.
"Repeating the test 10 months later, the team
found that the treated mice were still showing significant
improvements in vision compared with the untreated blind mice. 'Our
expectation is that this would be a one-time treatment that is
permanent or semi-permanent,' says Horsager. Concerns have been raised about the safety of
gene therapy in the past, not least about
links between the viruses used to transfer the genes and disease.
Horsager says the algal genes were only expressed in the target
cells, and that there is no evidence of an immune response in the
mice, suggesting that the transfer of the foreign gene has been
restricted to the bipolar cells.
"However, small amounts of ChR2 DNA were found
in other tissues. 'Regulatory agencies would be very concerned that
ChR2 DNA was found in tissues outside of the treated eye,' says
Robert Lanza, of Advanced Cell Technology
in Worcester, Massachusetts. Horsager's team believe the rogue DNA
is due to cross-contamination during the analysis process.
"'It's a good paper, and it's clear that they
are heading towards a clinical trial with the information they are
gathering,' says
Pete Coffey of the department of
ophthalmology at University College London. But he points out that
although there is a statistical difference between the performance
of the treated and untreated mice, that difference is small. Coffey also adds that, as Horsager and
colleagues admit, the mice seem to be seeing the difference between
light and dark, but not much more. Nevertheless, he thinks this sort
of technology will be seen in the clinic before a treatment based on
a stem cell replacement for photoreceptors. That's because stem
cells must be connected to existing neural networks -- something
that's not yet possible -- whereas gene therapy simply involves
making what is left in a diseased eye photosensitive.
"'The question,' says Coffey, 'is how good is
it going to be? Just light/dark or are people going to be able to
read large texts?' Horsager's team is trying to go beyond simple
light/dark discrimination by precisely activating particular cells
in the retinal system. However, the tests used so far don't say much
about visual acuity. 'If you can get acuity back it would be
phenomenal for anyone who's been blind,' says Coffey." [New
Scientist210, 2808, 16/04/2011, pp.10-11. The
on-line article is slightly different from the published copy.
Quotation marks altered to conform to the conventions adopted at
this site. Several paragraphs merged; some links
added.]
The above experiments would be non-starters
for logical reasons if DM were true and the entire nature of the part
were determined by its relation to the whole.
In this connection, an argument
George Moore
deployed against
Hegelian Holism a hundred years ago seems apt:
"…[I]f an arm be cut off from the human body,
we still call it an arm. Yet an arm, when it is a part of the body, undoubtedly
differs from a dead arm: and hence we may easily be led to say 'The arm which is
a part of the body would not be what it is, if it were not such a part'…. But,
in fact, the dead arm never was a part of the body; it is only partially
identical with the living arm. Those parts [i.e., properties] of it which are
identical with parts of the living arm are exactly the same, whether they belong
to the body or not…. On the other hand, those properties which are
possessed by the living, and not by the dead, arm, do not exist in a
changed form in the latter: they simply do not exist there at all. By
causal necessity their existence depends on their having that relation to the
other parts of the body which we express by saying that they form part of it.
Yet, most certainly, if they ever did not form part of the body, they
would be exactly what they are when they do." [Moore (1959), pp.34-35;
quoted in Hylton (1990), p.122.]
Hylton goes on to point out that:
"The implication of the last
sentence is that if, in violation of causal necessity, a living arm could
survive in isolation from the body, i.e., all its properties could continue to
exist…, then it would be, in isolation from the body, exactly what it was when
attached to the body. Causal dependence, Moore is saying, is not the sort of
constitutive relation which the Idealists had sought, yet causal dependence is
all we need in order to give an account of what the Idealists would have called
an organic unity. The analysis just quoted is,
it seems to me, by far the strongest argument that Moore has against internal
relations -- it enables him to claim that they are simply unnecessary to account
for the facts." [Hylton (1990), p.122. Paragraphs merged.]
This point can be developed further. Consider
again the facility we currently have for transplanting organs or re-attaching
limbs (etc.). In such cases, few would want to argue that a kidney belonging to,
say, donor NN, but now in recipient NM's body, was no longer a kidney,
or that it ceased to be one in the few hours it was outside either body (if stored,
for instance, in a refrigerator). However, when attached to the new body, a whole new range of
causal interactions kick in (many of which doctors not only now understand, but can
manipulate, prevent, speed up or slow down -- they could hardly do this if these
links were in some way logical or constitutive). So, if handled in the right
way, the new organ will function just like the old one for many years.
On the other hand, if the entire nature of the
part were determined by its "internal relation" to the whole,
medical staff would no longer need to go to the trouble of tissue-typing donors and
recipients. They would merely refer an anxious patient and his/her worried relatives
to textbooks devoted to DL,
throw in a couple of references to "internal relations", and they would soon
agree that the logical connection between their loved one's organs and the rest of his/her body -- as well as
the analogous relation that holds between a potential donor's organs and his/her
body -- which clearly meant that organ donation was a
non-starter (since kidney K in donor NN's body ceases to be a
kidney when removed and then transplanted into someone else's body), and let the poor sod
die.
[DL = Dialectical Logic.]
The fact that health workers don't
do this (and are right not to) shows that the connection between an
organism and its parts isn't logical
(in the DM-sense of this word), but causal, and that we all know this to
be so.23
Of
course, the case for DM-style Wholism hasn't been helped by the news that scientists feel they are now on the brink
of fitting whole artificial hearts into human chests. [On that, see
here.
Indeed, in 2011, a totally
artificial
heart was fitted to a UK man.]
Is such a heart a heart before or after it was fitted? Admittedly, this project
has still to be fully tested -- but
reports from 2021
suggest this is still a successful procedure. Scientists plainly wouldn't bother doing this if
there were
an 'internal' link between a heart and the body of its owner or its
recipient. They would simply ring up their local Hegelian Idealist (or, perhaps,
one of their bargain basement cousins, DM-fans) for advice, or simply give up.
Indeed, once DM-Wholism is examined
more closely its ridiculous consequences become all the more apparent. So, if it were
true that:
"…the entire nature of
the part is determined by its relationships with the other parts and so with the
whole. The part makes the whole, and the whole makes the parts" [Rees (1998), p.5. Emphasis
added.]
medical or biological intervention
would be viewed in a completely different light. For instance, if the "entire" nature of a bodily
part were determined by the "internal relations" it enjoyed with the other parts and with the whole of which
it is a part, then any alteration to one part of a given body would automatically
change all its other parts. There doesn't seem to be any other way of
interpreting the above passage that succeeds in avoiding such a crazy conclusion.
Does
this mean, for example, that whenever someone has a haircut -- or whenever they
trim their toenails -- their brain ceases to be a brain? But, that should
be the case if the "entire" nature of a brain were determined by its relation to each
and every other part of the body, including hairs on heads and nails on toes.
If, on the other hand, we admit that a brain remains a brain either side of a
trip to the barbers -- or a visit to the
Chiropodists -- then
the relation that organ has
to the hairs and the nails belonging to a given body determines
neither its "entire" nature, nor theirs.
[The "relatively important"
defence (should anyone attempt to use it) was defused
here.]
Of course, it could be
objected that this challenge to DM-Wholism relies on a caricature of that
theory, since no dialectician in her left mind would admit that minor
changes like this have such profound implications.
Maybe not, but in that
case, G1 will need to be abandoned or modified, since it clearly implies it.
G1: The
entire nature of a part is determined by its relation with the other
parts and with the whole.
And yet,
if we consider more significant changes, the same problems arise. In which case:
Does a brain cease to be a brain if a patient's leg is amputated?
What if a kidney is removed, or a patient is put on a dialysis machine? Does a
brain cease to be a brain if an artificial heart is fitted, or the same
unfortunate patient is put on a heart-lung machine for weeks or even months?
Now, these considerations don't present
problems for consistent materialists who reject Hegel's obscure "internal relations", but they
do for adherents of Dialectical Mysticism.
[LOI = Law of Identity;
LOC = Law of Non-Contradiction.]
We needn't labour the point; the problems we are continually facing with
respect to the attempts made by DM-theorists to
outline their theory have arisen from at least two sources:
(1) Their reliance on the
defective 'logic' Hegel inflicted on
humanity (upside down or 'the right way up'), and:
(2) A misconstrual of
the complex social rules we have for the use of certain words (i.e., those connected with the LOI,
motion, the LOC, and now here, the part/whole relation), as if they
expressed substantive truths about the world.24
As both Parts of Essay Eleven have shown, the "Totality" and the part/whole relation have yet to be given a
clear exposition by DM-theorists -- or, indeed, one that looks even vaguely coherent.
However, at the end of our journey through the wastelands of 'dialectical
thought', we know much about what the "Totality"
isn't, but
nothing about what it is. In that case, the allegation made at the beginning of
Part One of this Essay (that the
DM-"Totality" may be understood only by means of a
via
negativa) still looks sound. This isn't the least bit surprising given
the mystical origin of this way of viewing
nature.
Hence, as things now stand, the "Totality"
appears to be so 'contradictory', its 'border fence' so full of gaping holes, that it might include -- for all we know, or
for all that DM-theorists themselves know(!) -- the complete
Hindu pantheon,
all the
Norse gods, the departed spirits of the entire
Apache Nation, and possibly even the Evil
One 'Himself'.
Figure Four: Satan -- In Or
Out?
Why, it might even contain the 'real'
Hamlet...
Figure Five: DM --
Tragedy Into Farce?
There is something in this more than
natural, if philosophy could find it out. [Hamlet,
2. 2]
1.
This also appears to be what Marx was trying to say:
"A being which does not have its nature
outside itself is not a natural being and plays no part in the system of nature.
A being which has no object outside itself is not an objective being. A being
which is not itself an object for a third being has no being for its object,
i.e., it has no objective relationships and its existence is not objective. A
non-objective being is a non-being….
A being which is not the object of another
being therefore presupposes that no objective being exists." [Marx
(1975b),
p.390.
Paragraphs merged.]
Which is a rather more Hegelian way of making
largely the same point.
Incidentally, it is worth pointing out that Aristotle also accepted something
similar to this principle (that the whole isn't a mere sum of the parts):
"In the case of all things
which have several parts and in which the totality is not, as it were, a mere
heap, but the whole is something beside the parts...." [Aristotle (1984b), p.1650. I have used the on-line
version,
here.]
This gives the lie, I think, to comments like
this:
"According to formal
logic, the whole is equal to the sum of its parts." [Woods and Grant (1995),
p.57.]
Plainly, a "beside" isn't an "equal to".
Readers will note, too, that Woods and Grant
failed to cite a single logic text in support of their rather odd contention. Indeed, as we
will see in later re-writes of this Essay, Hegelian Wholism is itself partly dependant
on Aristotle's version.
Nevertheless, John Rees isn't the only
dialectician to advance similar comments. Here is his former UK-SWP
comrade, Ian Birchall:
"So,
rather than the whole being a simple sum of its parts, the parts can be
understood only in the context of the whole. As Lenin points out, a hand is only
really a hand if it is part of a body." [Birchall (1982), quoted from
here.]
Here,
too, are the thoughts of that card-carrying
Stalinist, Sheptulin:
"When we consider a
phenomenon from the point of view of its content it appears as a whole, as a
totality of all the elements and aspects that make it up and of all their
interactions. It is through this totality that content relates to form....
"[The content of a part],
however, is conditioned not only by their specific nature, but also by the
general nature of the whole. For this reason they play their specific roles not
by themselves but as parts of the whole. On the other hand, the general nature
of the whole...depends on the specific nature of the parts that make it up....
"The interconnection of the
whole and part, expressed in the dependence of the quality of the whole on the
specific nature of its component parts, on the one hand, and the qualities
of the parts on the specific nature of the whole, on the other, results from the
interconnection between parts within the whole, this interconnection
constituting the structure of the whole....
"...[T]he properties of the
elements depends on the structure of the whole they make up, whereas the
structure of the whole depends on its constituent elements, their nature and
quantity. In other words, the elements of an object and the structure of this
object (the manner of connection of the elements) are necessarily interdependent
and constitute a dialectical unity." [Sheptulin (1978), pp.227-31.]
And,
here, too, is Cornforth:
"The last dogmatic assumption
of [mechanical materialism] to be mentioned is that each of the things or
particles, whose interactions are said to make up the totality of events in the
universe, has its own fixed nature quite independent of everything else....
"Proceeding from this
assumption it follows that all relations between things are merely external
relations. That is to say, things enter into various relationships one with
another, but these relationships are accidental and make no difference to the
nature of the things related.
"And regarding each thing as
a separate unit entering into external relations with other things, it further
follows that [mechanical materialism] regards the whole as no more that
the sum of its separate parts....
"Not one of these assumptions
is correct. Nothing exists or can exist in splendid isolation, separate from its
conditions of existence, independent of its relationships with other things....
The very nature of a thing is modified and transformed by its relationships with
other things. When things enter into such relationships that they become parts
of a whole, the whole cannot be regarded as nothing more than the sum of the
parts.... [The] mutual relations which the parts enter into in constituting the
whole modify their own properties, so that while it might be said that the whole
is determined by the parts it may equally be said that the parts are determined
by the whole." [Cornforth (1976), pp.46-47.]
The fact that things in general exist in
wholes, of a loose, or even of a tightly organised, sort, in no way shows that there
are "internal relations" between them, or even that the phrases "internal
relation" and "external relation" make any sense at all (that is,
as DM-theorists seem to want to use them). Cornforth has
imported these concepts from Idealism and Traditional Philosophy, subjecting them to no sort of
interrogation, and has nevertheless imposed his own 'meaning' on them. [More on this later (and in
Essay Four Part Two).]
It is also worth pointing out here that while Cornforth takes a
dig at "mechanical materialism" for its dogmatism, he is quite happy to inflict
on reality a few dogmatic ideas of his own. So, for instance, how could he possibly
have known
the following for a fact?
"Nothing exists or can exist
in splendid isolation, separate from its conditions of existence, independent of
its relationships with other things.... The very nature of a thing is modified
and transformed by its relationships with other things." [Ibid.]
Of
course, and with considerably more justification, Cornforth could have argued that
up to now we have only ever encountered objects that fit this description
(plainly so, since it isn't easy to see how we could come to know about an
intrinsically isolated object), but he certainly can't dogmatically assert that nothing could so exist. Nor
could he legitimately conclude that any of these relations are necessarily
"internal", or that the nature of anything must be "transformed by its
relationships with other things". It might turn out that some of these relations are "external"
(i.e., causal and mechanical), and which induce no such radical changes on
those "other things" –- or, it might not. Either
way, this is surely an empirical issue not something we should accept on
the sole authority of that Christian Mystic, Hegel.
Here are Levins and Lewontin:
"In contrast, in the
dialectical world view, things are assumed from the beginning to be internally
heterogeneous at every level. And this heterogeneity does not mean that the
object or system is composed of fixed natural units. Rather the 'correct'
division of the whole into part varies, depending upon the particular aspect of
the whole that is in question.... It is a matter of simple logic that parts can
be parts only when there is a whole for them to be parts of. Part implies whole,
and whole implies part. Yet reductionist practice ignores this relationship,
isolating parts as pre-existing units of which wholes are then composed. In the
dialectical world the logical dialectical relation between part and whole is
taken seriously. Part makes whole, and whole makes part....
"The first principle of a
dialectical view, then, is that a whole is a relation of heterogeneous parts
that have no prior independent existence as parts. The second principle,
which flows from the first, is that, in general, the properties of parts have no
prior alienated existence but are acquired by being parts of a particular whole.
In the alienated world the intrinsic properties of alienated parts confer
properties on the whole, which may in addition take on new properties which are
not characteristic of the parts: the whole may be more than the sum of the
parts. But the ancient debate on emergence, whether indeed wholes may have
properties not intrinsic to the parts, is beside the point.
The fact is that the parts have properties that are characteristic of them only
as they are parts of wholes; the properties come into existence in the
interactions that makes the whole. A person cannot fly by flapping her arms
simultaneously. But people do fly, as a consequence of the social organisation
that has created airplanes, pilots and fuel. It is not that society flies,
however, but individuals in society, who have acquired a property they do not
have outside society. The limitations of individual physical beings are negated
by social interactions. The whole, thus, is not simply the object of interaction
of the parts but is the subject of action of the parts." [Levins and Lewontin
(1985), pp.272-73.]
But,
how could these two possibly know all this?
The fact that this allegedly follows from "simple logic" (if it
does) in no way justifies its
imposition onto nature. Ten Planet Earths added to twenty Planet Earths makes
thirty Planet Earths, but this tells us nothing about the number of Planet Earths there are
in the Solar System. These two authors plainly felt they could derive
substantive truths about nature from what they regarded as "simple logic",
but that can only mean they think
logic runs the
world. As we will see (in Essay Twelve (summary
here)), this idea itself implies that
'reality is rational', and hence is either 'Mind' or 'Mind-like'.
Comrades who have been seduced by the superficial appeal of
a prioriSupers-Science like thiswill find the above
counter-points not only
impossible to accept, but hard to grasp,
since this Super-Scientific approach to knowledge is the way that Philosophy has always been
practised. This age-old approach delineates what counts as 'acceptable' thought, just as it establishes the
only 'legitimate' endeavour to which Philosophers should rightly aspire.
In contrast, the method adopted at this site makes a radical break with this
tradition -- as one would expect
of an avowed radical.
[These comments follow from ideas
presented in EssaysTwo, Three Part One and
Twelve (summary here).
They will
be spelt out a little more concisely in Note 24,
below.]
Alexander Spirkin had this to say, in perhaps
one of the best dialectical summaries, even explanations, of these ideas I have so far encountered --
in which case, fellow Trotskyist should avert their since this part of the
"wooden and dogmatic" Stalinist 'dialectic' is
far clearer and comprehensive than anything Trotskyist-dialecticians
have so far managed to cobble together:
"Nothing in the world stands
by itself. Every object is a link in an endless chain and is thus connected with
all the other links. And this chain of the universe has never been broken; it
unites all objects and processes in a single whole and thus has a universal
character. We cannot move so much as our little finger without 'disturbing' the
whole universe. The life of the universe, its history lies in an infinite web of
connections....
"Connections exist not only
between objects within the framework of a given form of motion of matter, but
also between all its forms, woven together in a kind of infinitely huge skein.
Our consciousness can contain no idea that does not express either imagined or
real connections, and in its turn this idea must of necessity be a link in a
chain of other ideas and conceptions....
"A system is an internally
organised whole where elements are so intimately connected that they operate as
one in relation to external conditions and other systems. An element may be
defined as the minimal unit performing a definite function in the whole. Systems
may be either simple or complex. A complex system is one whose elements may also
be regarded as systems or subsystems.
"All things, properties and
relations that strike us as something independent are essentially parts of some
system, which in its turn is part of an even bigger system, and so on ad
infinitum. For example, the whole of world civilisation is no more than a large
and extremely complex self-developing system, which comprises other systems of
varying degrees of complexity.
"Every system is something
whole. So anything that corresponds to the demands of unity and stability -- an
atom, a molecule, a crystal, the solar system, the organism, society, a work of
art, a theory -- may be regarded as a system. Every system forms a whole, but not
every whole is a system.
"We usually call the parts of
a system its elements. If in investigating a system we wish to identify
its elements we should regard them as elementary objects in themselves. Once we
have established them as something relatively indivisible in one system,
elements may be regarded in their turn as systems (or subsystems), consisting of
elements of a different order, and so on.
"...Structure is the type of
connection between the elements of a whole. It has its own internal dialectic.
Wholeness must be composed in a certain way, its parts are always related to the
whole. It is not simply a whole but a whole with internal divisions. Structure
is a composite whole, or an internally organised content.
"But structure is not enough
to make a system. A system consists of something more than structure: it is a
structure with certain properties. When a structure is understood from the
standpoint of its properties, it is understood as a system. We speak of the
'solar system' and not the solar structure. Structure is an extremely abstract
and formal concept....
"We call something a whole
that embraces all its parts in such a way as to create a unity.
"The category of part
expresses the object not in itself but as something in relation to what it is a
part of, to that in which it realises its potentials and prospects. For example,
an organ is part of an organism taken as a whole. Consequently, the categories
of whole and part express a relationship between objects in which one object,
being a complex and integral whole, is a unity of other objects which form its
parts. A part is subject to the influence of the whole, which is present, as it
were, in all its parts. Every part feels the influence of the whole, which seems
to permeate the parts and exist in them. Thus, in a tragic context even a joke
becomes tragic; a free atom is distinctly different from an atom that forms part
of a molecule or a crystal; a word taken out of context loses much or all of its
meaning.
"At the same time the parts
have an influence on the whole. The organism is a whole and dysfunction of one
of its organs leads to disbalance of the whole. For example, against a
background of rational thinking an obsessive idea may sometimes have a very
substantial effect on the general condition of the individual.
"The categories of whole and
part are relative; they have meaning only in relation to each other. The whole
exists thanks to its parts and in them. The parts, in their turn, cannot exist
by themselves. No matter how small a particle we name, it is something whole and
at the same time a part of another whole. The largest whole that we can conceive
of is ultimately only a part of an infinitely greater whole. Everything in
nature is a part of the universe.
"Various systems are divided
into three basic types of wholeness. The simplest type is the unorganised or
summative whole, an unsystematic conglomeration of objects (a herd of cattle,
for example). This category also includes a mechanical grouping of heterogeneous
things, for example, rock consisting of pebbles, sand, gravel, boulders, and so
on.
"In such a whole the
connection between the parts is external and obeys no recognisable law. We
simply have a group of unsystematic formations of a purely summative character.
The properties of such a whole coincide with the sum of the properties of its
component parts. Moreover, when objects become part of an unorganised whole or
leave such a whole, they usually undergo no qualitative change. For this type of
whole the characteristic feature is the varying lifetime of its components.
"The second, more complex
type of whole is the organised whole, for example, the atom, the molecule, the
crystal. Such a whole may have varying degrees of organisation, depending on the
peculiar features of its parts and the character of the connection between them.
In an organised whole the composing elements are in a relatively stable and
law-governed interrelationship. Its properties cannot be reduced to the
mechanical sum of the properties of its parts. Rivers 'lose themselves' in the
sea, although they are in it and it would not exist without them. Water
possesses the property of being able to extinguish fire, but the parts of which
it is composed, taken separately, possess quite different properties: hydrogen
is itself flammable and oxygen maintains or boosts combustion. Zero in itself is
nothing, but in the composition of a number its role is highly significant, and
at times gigantically so, by increasing 100 into 1,000, for instance. A hydrogen
atom consists of a proton and an electron. But strictly speaking, this is not
true. The statement contains the same error as the phrase 'this house is built
of pine'. The mass of an atom of hydrogen is not equal to the total mass of the
proton and the electron. It is less than that mass because in combining into the
system of the hydrogen atom the proton and the electron lose something, which
escapes into space in the form of radiation.
"The third, highest and most
complex type of whole is the organic whole, for example, the organism, the
biological species, society, science, arts, language, and so on. The
characteristic feature of the organic whole is the self-development and
self-reproduction of its parts. The parts of an organism if separated from the
whole organism, not only lose some of their properties but cannot even exist in
the given quality that they have within the whole. The head is only a head
because it is capable of thinking. And it can only think as a part not only of
the organism, but also of society, history and culture.
"An organic whole is formed
not (as
Empedocles
assumed) by joining together ready-made parts, separate
organs flying around in the air, such as heads, eyes, ears, hands, legs, hair
and hearts. An organic whole arises, is born, and dies together with its parts.
It is an integral whole, with distinguishable parts. Sensations, perceptions,
representations, concepts, memory, attention do not exist in isolation; they
form the synthetic knot which we call consciousness. The elements that make up
the whole possess a certain individuality and at the same time they 'work for'
the whole. The whole is invisibly present, as it were, and guides the process of
'assembly' of its elements, that is to say, of its own self.
"The defining attribute of
harmony is a relationship between the elements of the whole in which the
development of one of them is a condition for the development of the others or
vice versa. In art, harmony may be understood as a form of relationship in which
each element, while retaining a relative independence, contributes greater
expressiveness to the whole and, at the same time and because of this, more
fully expresses its own essence. Beauty may be defined as harmony of all the
parts, united by that to which they belong in such a way that nothing can be
added or taken away or changed without detriment to the whole.
"The parts of a whole may
have varying degrees of relative independence. In a whole, there may be parts
whose excision will damage or even destroy the whole, but there may also be
parts whose loss causes no organic damage. For instance, the extremities or a
part of the stomach may be removed, but not the heart. The deeper and more
complex the relationship between the parts, the greater is the function of the
whole in relation to them and the less their relative independence.
"The various parts making up
a whole may occupy by no means equal positions. Some of them are less mobile,
relatively stable, others are more dynamic; some exist only for a time and are
doomed soon to disappear, others have the makings of something more progressive.
There are some parts without which the whole cannot be conceived and there are
others without which it can carry on quite well although with some loss to
itself....
"The highest form of organic
whole is society and the various social formations. The general laws of the
social whole determine the essence of any of its parts and the direction of its
development: the part behaves in accordance with the essence of the whole.
"For scientific analysis to
be able to move in the right direction, the object must constantly occupy our
consciousness as something whole. When we are investigating a whole, we break it
down into its parts and sort out the nature of the relation between them. We can
understand a system as a whole only by discovering the nature of its parts. It
is not enough to study the parts without studying the relationship between them
and the whole. A person who knows only the parts does not yet know the whole. A
single frame in a film can be understood only as a part of the film as a whole.
"An overabundance of
particulars may obscure the whole. This is a characteristic feature of
empiricism. Any singular object can be correctly understood only when it is
analysed, not separately, but in its relation to the whole. Each organ is
determined in its mode of operation not only by its internal structure but by
the nature of the organism to which it belongs. The importance of the heart can
be discovered only by considering it as part of the organism as a whole. The
methodological fault characteristic of mechanistic materialism is that it
understands the whole as nothing more than the sum of its parts." [Spirkin
(1983), pp.82,
97-103. Quotation marks altered to conform to the conventions adopted at
this site.]
We will have occasion to return to Spirkin's
discussion
later.
Here, once again, are Woods and Grant
(those who think 'Stalinist dialectics' as 'wooden and dogmatic' should compare
what follows with Spirkin's words, above):
"According to formal logic,
the whole is equal to the sum of its parts. On closer examination, however, this
is seen not to be true. In the case of living organisms it is manifestly not the
case. A rabbit cut up in a laboratory, and reduced to its constituent parts is
no longer a rabbit. This fact has been grasped by the advocates of chaos theory
and complexity. Whereas classical physics, with its linear systems, accepted
that the whole was precisely the sum of its parts, the non-linear logic of
complexity maintains the opposite proposition, in complete agreement with
dialectics....
"Modern atomic theory has
shown the incorrectness of this idea. While accepting that complex structures
must be explained in terms of aggregates of more elementary factors, it has
shown that the relations between these elements are not merely indifferent and
quantitative, but dynamic and dialectical. The elementary particles which make
up the atoms interact constantly, passing into each other. They are not fixed
constants but are at every moment both themselves and something else at the same
time. It is precisely this dynamic relationship which gives the resulting
molecules their particular nature, properties and specific identity.
"In this new combination the
atoms are and are not themselves. They combine in a dynamic way to produce an
entirely different entity, a different relationship, which, in turn, determines
the behaviour of its component parts. Thus, we are not dealing merely with a
lifeless 'juxtaposition,' a mechanical aggregate, but with a process. In order
to understand the nature of an entity it is therefore entirely insufficient to
reduce it to its individual atomic components. It is necessary to understand its
dynamic interrelations, that is, to arrive at a dialectical, not a formal,
analysis....
"Life is a complex system of
interactions, involving an immense number of chemical reactions which proceed
continuously and rapidly. Every reaction in the heart, blood, nervous system,
bones and brain interacts with every other part of the body. The workings of the
simplest living body are far more complicated than the most advanced computer,
permitting rapid movement, swift reactions to the slightest change in the
environment, constant adjustments to changing conditions, internal and external.
Here, most emphatically, the whole is more than the sum of the parts. Every part
of the body, every muscular and nervous reaction, depends upon all the rest.
Here we have a dynamic and complex, in other words, dialectical,
interrelationship which alone is capable of creating and sustaining the
phenomenon we know as life....
"It is necessary to acquire a
concrete understanding of the object as an integral system, not as isolated
fragments; with all its necessary interconnections, not torn out of context,
like a butterfly pinned to a collector's board; in its life and movement, not as
something lifeless and static. Such an approach is in open conflict with the
so-called 'laws' of formal logic, the most absolute expression of dogmatic
thought ever conceived, representing a kind of mental rigor mortis. But nature
lives and breathes, and stubbornly resists the embraces of formalistic thinking.
'A' is not equal to 'A.' Subatomic particles are and are not. Linear processes
end in chaos. The whole is greater than the sum of its parts. Quantity changes
into quality. Evolution itself is not a gradual process, but interrupted by
sudden leaps and catastrophes. What can we do about it? Facts are stubborn
things." [Woods and Grant (1995), pp.57-60,
82-83.]
Indeed, facts are
stubborn things. As we will see, they are about as unkind to DM-Wholism as the
class struggle has so far been to Dialectical Trotskyism, especially to the Woods-Grant
backwater.
"Indeed, when this
interpretation is extended to field theories, not only the inter-relationships
of the parts, but also their very existence is seen to flow out of the law of
the whole. There is therefore nothing left of the classical scheme, in which the
whole is derived from pre-existent parts related in predetermined ways. Rather,
what we have is reminiscent of the relationship of whole and parts in an
organism, in which each organ grows and sustains itself in a way that depends
crucially on the whole." [Bohm (1984), p.x.]
It is here, perhaps, that we can see the
baleful effects of far too much (or even just enough)
Hermetic Mysticism on the mind of a great scientist -- no
wonder he later went on to eulogise Uri
Geller!
However, we needn't labour the point; any
number of DM-texts could have been quoted (several more will be below) that
advance
similar dogmatic claims.
1a.
The idea seems to be that if the actual nature of something changes, this must
be because of factors that aren't
merely "external" to the object or process in question. So, for
example, it is hard to see how the mereagglomeration of objects can affect their "essential" nature or the
"essential" nature of the heap, pile or mound to which they might belong. In order to alter the
'logical' or "essential" properties of the objects or processes
involved, it
would seem that new
"internal" connections must be set up. But, how is that possible? What
is the 'logical' connection between, say, your appendix and your big toe? What
is the 'internal' connection between, for example, a rock and the mountain to
which is, or was, part? What is the 'logical' connection between, for instance, the
planets Venus, Mars and Jupiter? Once more we are left in the dark.
For instance, here is an example of the
'logical' sense of "internal", which soon slides over into the 'spatial' sense
of the word:
"...[C]ontrary to
metaphysics, not only are fundamental opposites involved in every
subject-matter, but these opposites mutually imply each other, are
inseparably connected together, and far from being exclusive, neither can
exist or can be understood except in relation to the other.
"This characteristic of
opposition is known as polarity: fundamental opposites are polar opposites. A
magnet, for example, has two poles, a north pole and a south pole. But these
poles, opposite and distinct, cannot exist in separation. If the magnet
is cut in two, there is not a north pole in one half and a south pole in the
other, but north and south poles recur in each half. The north pole exists only
as the opposite of the south, and vice versa; the one can only be defined as the
opposite of other." [Cornforth (1976), pp.66-67. Bold emphases added. Plenty
more examples have been posted
here. There is
another example of this equivocation on Cornforth's part,
here.]
The 'logical' sense plainly underlies
Cornforth's claim that one opposite "implies" the other, and that one can't be
"understood" without the other. So, the existence of the
proletariat implies the existence of the capitalist class; the one can't exist
(logically can't exist) without the other. The 'spatial' sense surfaces in Cornforth's
assertion that these opposites can't exist in "separation". But, if these items
are 'logically' connected (like father and son, say) then they can surely exist
in separation from one another; manifestly, the son remains a son even if his
father goes on a world cruise, hops on a rocket bound for Mars, or dies.
The magnet example isn't too clever either,
as we saw in Essay Eight Part
Two -- indeed, if the legendary
magnetic monopole is ever discovered (as it seems it
might have been; on that see
here and
here), this classic DM-example will plainly go the
same way as the
crystalline spheres and the
luminiferous ether. But,
even if this monopole remains undiscovered, the magnet example is rather
unique. What other examples are there from the natural (not the social)
world where these alleged opposites imply one another, or where
they can't exist apart? Other than electrical phenomena (which can
exist in glorious isolation -- so electrical phenomena don't qualify, either!),
there don't seem to be any other opposites that unambiguously exist in this way.
Not even
anabolic
processes (another popular DM-example) implycatabolic
processes. Whether one can exist without the other is somewhat dubious, too.
Quite apart from the fact that these processes operate largely on
different
molecules, they take place in
different parts of each cell. So, in vivo,
they are separated. [On this, see
here.]
An
electron,
too, can exist in splendid isolation from its alleged 'opposite' (as can
a proton and a
positron;
indeed, positrons and electrons have to be isolated since contact
would annihilate both, not turn either into its 'opposite' (as the
DM-classics tell us they must always do) -- in fact, the
situation is a little more complex than this; on that see
here), but even if an electron
couldn't so exist, what precisely is its opposite? Is it the positron or the
proton? [As we saw
here,
it has to have a single, unique opposite -- its "other", as Hegel and
Lenin both called 'it'.] But, that question alone gives the game away, since it
tells us that this connection can't be 'logical', since, if the one implied
the other, as we were told they should, we would already know the answer. Scientists
had to
discover the positron, and they did so long after they knew about
electrons. By way of contrast, the north and south pole of magnets were
discovered all in one go, as it were. The alleged logical connection between the
proletariat and the bourgeoisie wasn't discovered by observation, or experiment.
Just as soon as the one was defined, the other was automatically implied. Logical connections don't have to be
discovered. As soon as we know that a man is a father, we know that he has a
son or a daughter (even if they are dead); we don't have to wait for someone to
locate his progeny. As soon as we know that WW is a proletarian, we
automatically know she must work for a capitalist of some sort. Who on earth is going to try to find out
whether or not a vixen
really is a
female fox, or a cygnet is a baby swan?
Moreover, the atom is held together (largely) by the opposite charge of
elections and protons. Hence, it might seem that
we have here the opposites we seek. Of course, this would mean that the positron
can't be the 'logical' opposite of the electron. But, the electron
still doesn't imply the proton, either. They, too, were discovered at different
times, and they can exist without one another. [On that see
here
and here.]
Again, but perhaps more significantly,
since we have been told
by the DM-classics that
'dialectical opposites' "inevitably" turn into
one another, who has ever witnessed a father turning into his son? Or an
electron into a proton (or even a positron)? Or the proletariat into the
bourgeoisie, and vice versa? The medieval peasantry into the Feudal
Aristocracy,
and vice versa? The relations of production into the forces of
production?
[Added
on Edit, October 2021:There is another difficulty that is worth airing
at this point: 'dialectical opposites' it seems relate to each other
generically, not individually. So, it isn't an individual worker who is the
'dialectical opposite' of a single capitalist, or an individual electron that is
the 'opposite' of a proton, it is the proletariat that is the opposite of
the capitalist class, it is the electron that is the 'opposite' of
the proton. I have ignored this complexity in what I have so far said in
this Essay. I will, however, explore its consequences and ramifications in a
later re-write of this Essay. Having dais that, I suspect that when I
have worked out the details, it will mean this part of DM will look even more
shaky and absurd that it already is.]
Hence, as with
the vast majority of other examples
bandied about in this sub-branch of Dialectical Mickey
Mouse Science, Cornforth has plainly given this a priori, mystical
thesis insufficient thought.
And, as far as mysticism is concerned, compare
what Cornforth had to say (and what other DM-fans have to say) about opposites
with this passage from the Kybalion (one of the most important books in
the Hermetic cannon):
"CHAPTER X POLARITY
'Everything is dual; everything has poles; everything has its pair of opposites;
like and unlike are the same; opposites are identical in nature, but different
in degree; extremes meet; all truths are but half-truths; all paradoxes may be
reconciled.' -- The
Kybalion.
"The great Fourth Hermetic Principle
-- the
Principle of Polarity -- embodies the truth that all manifested things have 'two
sides'; 'two aspects'; 'two poles'; a 'pair of opposites,' with manifold degrees
between the two extremes. The old paradoxes, which have ever perplexed the mind
of men, are explained by an understanding of this Principle. Man has always
recognized something akin to this Principle, and has endeavoured to express it
by such sayings, maxims and aphorisms as the following: 'Everything is and
isn't, at the same time'; 'all truths are but half-truths'; 'every truth is
half-false'; 'there are two sides to everything'; 'there is a reverse side to
every shield,' etc., etc. The Hermetic Teachings are to the effect that the
difference between things seemingly diametrically opposed to each is merely a
matter of degree. It teaches that 'the pairs of opposites may be reconciled,'
and that 'thesis and antithesis are identical in nature, but different in
degree'; and that the ''universal reconciliation of opposites' is effected by a
recognition of this Principle of Polarity. The teachers claim that illustrations
of this Principle may be had on every hand, and from an examination into the
real nature of anything....
"Light and Darkness are poles of the same thing,
with many degrees between them. The musical scale is the same-starting with 'C'
you moved upward until you reach another 'C,' and so on, the differences between
the two ends of the board being the same, with many degrees between the two
extremes. The scale of colour is the same -- higher and lower vibrations being
the only difference between high violet and low red. Large and Small are
relative. So are Noise and Quiet; Hard and Soft follow the rule. Likewise Sharp
and Dull. Positive and Negative are two poles of the same thing, with countless
degrees between them...." [Anonymous (2005),
pp.59-62.
Spelling altered to conform to UK English. For more quotations from other mystical
systems along similar lines, see
here.]
Returning to the main feature, in the following
passage, Cornforth again confuses "internal" with
"spatially-internal":
"...[H]ow far is [change and
development] determined by the working out of the contradiction inherent in the
process itself, or by internal causes, and how far is it determined by external
or accidental causes? It is determined by both,
but in different ways. Both in nature and society
different things are always interacting and influencing each other. Hence
external causes must always play a part in the changes which happen to things.
At the same time, the character of the changes always depends on internal
causes.... Consider, for example, such
an event as the hatching of a chicken. The chicken does not develop inside the
egg unless heat is supplied from outside. But what develops in the egg, what
hatches out, depends on what is inside the egg...." [Cornforth (1976),
pp.99-100. Paragraphs merged.]
Here, "internal" is plainly a
'spatial', not a 'logical' notion. After all, is the inside of a chicken's egg a
logical space? Do the contents of an egg each imply one another?
Of course, this is where
Engels's Q«Q'Law' is supposed to come into play, since it is
apparently through the mere increase in the quantity of a certain item
that qualitative change and novelty are supposed to enter into the picture. Moreover,
one presumes this novelty can't be predicted solely from the nature of the elements concerned, which is
supposed to be what puts a block on "reductionism".
However, and once again, it
isn't easy to
see how an "external relation" -- which is what a quantitative increase or decrease
actually is
-- can
effect the required "internal", 'logical', or "essential"
development that an object or process
is supposed to undergo.
And, it is little use arguing
that while it might not be easy to see how this happens,
the plain fact is that it does. That is because, on the basis of
dialectical principles this shouldn't in fact be possible. If the (logical/"essential")
nature of each item in the "Totality" is determined by its relation to that
Whole, then its nature can only change when "internal"
relations with the Whole (to which it belongs) alter, or are initiated/created. Now,
that relation with the
Whole -- since it constitutes the logical/"essential" nature of each
part, so we are told -- can't result from of
its mere position or location within that Whole. It is still far from easy to see how 'logical' or
"essential" properties can be created by mere proximity.
But, what else is there in the dialectical box of tricks that is capable of
altering, or creating, such 'fundamental' properties, or effecting such changes? Indeed, how is it possible for
a mere change of place, an increase in number, or the amount of matter/energy input into a system to alter the
logical
link between opposites? If the items involved are internal oppositesalready, they must also be 'dialectical-logical' opposites, so that the object
or process in question can be described as a UO. That is, unless we are to
suppose that there are objects and processes that aren't UOs. But, if that
were the case, those objects and processes couldn't change (if we are to
believe the DM-classics)! If, in turn, that were so,
the mere addition of matter and/or energy couldn't change them qualitatively,
either. Furthermore, if that were
possible, an object could change its "essential" nature merely by moving, that is merely by a change in its external
relations. Does an individual become a son (in the biological sense) by
moving closer to an older male or an older female? Does another individual
become a worker by strolling about near factory? Do the individuals in a crowd
become proletarians merely by congregating in greater and greater numbers near
an oil refinery?
[UO = Unity of Opposites.]
Nor can it be the result of other such
"external" factors. That is, one presumes, why the 'logical' nature of each
part is determined by its "internal" relations with the Whole and with
other parts. And yet, these
"internal" relations can't themselves change. That is because, no matter what happens to an object, given these
dialectical constraints, its "internal" relations with the Whole must always
remain the same. Once more, separation distancecan't affect a logical relation.
The supposition that it might be able to do this can only have arisen because
of the
equivocation
mentioned earlier, whereby DM-theorists slide between a spatial and a
logical understanding of "internal". So, for example, the presumed logical
relation connoted by the word "son" isn't affected if the individual concerned moves to
the other side of the planet, or, indeed, is shot into space in a rocket.
If a capitalist goes on a world cruise, she remains a capitalist. If a daughter
moves closer to her mother, she doesn't become more of a daughter.
Furthermore, if
all objects and processes change because of a struggle between opposites (again, as the
dialectical classics tell us
they must),
and only because of this, then the mere addition or subtraction of matter and/or
energy can't effect a change in quality, anyway. That can only result from the
aforementioned 'dialectical' struggle. In which case, it looks like Engels's Second 'Law' ('the
interpenetration of opposites') is inconsistent with the First 'Law ('the change
of quantity into quality')!
Nevertheless, it is easy to
see why DM-fans, who interpret "internal" spatially, are more likely to conclude
that the mere proximity of certain objects is enough to create an
"internal", or 'logical', relation between them.
So, for instance, when an
electron enters an atom, it is supposed to assume an
"internal" relation with a proton. But, that will only happen because an
electron is what it is already -- it was negatively charged before
it entered that new whole (and it was negatively charged even before any atoms were
formed, if we are to
believe
what
physicists tell about "The Big Bang"). Its "essential nature" is thus given
independently of the sub-whole into which it enters. The electron doesn't become
negatively charged when it enters an atom; it has that charge wherever it goes.
But, its 'dialectical nature' is supposed to have been established logically,
not spatially; its nature is dependent on its logical relation to the entire
"Totally", the entire universe. [I am, of course, rehearsing (as best I can)
what I take to be the DM-view of things, not my own ideas!] The electron is what it is because
of its relation to the Whole, which is why it can be negatively charged
outside and inside the atom.
In that case, it would seem
that, despite what dialecticians tell us, nothing internal to the Whole can have its
'logical' or "essential" nature changed. As we have seen, these
dialectical-logical properties of bodies aren't sensitive to location. Hence, it
looks once more like a mere increaseor decrease in quantity, or the
simple concatenation of parts in close proximity, can't alter the "essential" nature of any object
or process inside the "Totality".
It
could be argued that when an individual becomes a capitalist, or even a worker,
his/her essential nature does change. So, the above argument is
misguided.
Maybe
so (although the above picture will be challenged in Essay Twelve Part Four),
but there is nothing in the DM-playbook that can account for this. As I
have noted in Essay Nine Part One in relation to this passage from Das
Kapital:
"A certain stage of
capitalist production necessitates that the capitalist be able to devote the
whole of the time during which he functions as a capitalist, i.e., as
personified capital, to the appropriation and therefore control of the labour of
others, and to the selling of the products of this labour. The guilds of the
middle ages therefore tried to prevent by force the transformation of the master
of a trade into a capitalist, by limiting the number of labourers that could be
employed by one master within a very small maximum. The possessor of money or
commodities actually turns into a capitalist in such cases only where the
minimum sum advanced for production greatly exceeds the maximum of the middle
ages. Here, as in natural science, is shown the correctness of the law
discovered by Hegel (in his 'Logic'), that merely quantitative differences
beyond a certain point pass into qualitative changes." [Marx (1996),
p.313. Bold emphasis added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the
conventions adopted at this site.]
Values (it is assumed that these are
"exchange values") don't become Capital by mere
quantitative increment. It requires the presence of a Capitalist Mode of Production
(and thus a change in the Relations of Production), or adifferent use of
that money, for this to
be so. The capitalists concerned have to do something with these
exchange values. So, the mere increase of exchange values doesn't automatically
"pass over" into a qualitative change and become Capital. These values have to be
invested (or put to some other specific productive use), and that too isn't automatic (in certain circumstances, they could be
consumed). So, what we have here is a change in quality passing over into
another change in quality! Quantity has nothing to do with it. The
same quantity of money could be used as Capital or fail to be so used.
It requires a change in its quality (its use, or its social context) to
effect such a development.
"[T]he International Monetary Fund has
pointed out that there is something like $76 trillion being held by financial
firms, such as private equity in different forms, waiting to be invested. There
is...something like $28 trillion that is held in the bank of New York Mellon
alone. The amount of money that cannot be profitably invested keeps going up....
It is a crazy situation when such enormous sums of money are being held and not
being invested -- a situation that has lasted almost a decade.
"In other words, there is a very large
proportion of surplus value that is not going into investment. And money that is
not invested is not capital: it is not being used to generate more surplus
value." [Quoted from
here; accessed 22/01/2016.]
Notice, "money that is not invested is not
capital...."
Over the last twenty-five years or so, in my
wander across the wastelands of the Dialectical Dustbowl, I have yet to encounter a single dialectician
who has pointed out that this application of Hegel's 'Law' by Marx contains a
serious error!
So desperate have DM-fans become (in their endeavour to find
support for their failed theory in what Marx wrote), every single one of them
seems to have forgotten,
or disregarded, basic principles of Historical Materialism
[HM]!
Hence, £x/$y (or their equivalent)
owned by a Medieval Lord in, say, Eleventh Century France, couldn't of its own become Capital
no matter how large this pot of money became (but see below), whereas £w/$z in Nineteenth
Century Manchester, even though that sum might be less than the £x/$y
held by the aforementioned Lord (allowing for inflation, etc.), would be Capital
if employed in
certain ways. It isn't
the quantity that is important here but the Mode of Production and the use to
which the money is put, that are.
Also worth
asking is the following question: How does this money actually "develop"? In what way can it
"develop"? Sure, money can be saved or accumulated, but how does a £1/$1 coin
"develop" if its owner saves or accumulates more of the same? Even if we redefine
"save" and "accumulate" to mean "develop" (protecting this 'law' by yet another
terminological dodge, thus imposing it on the facts), not all money will
"develop" in this way. What if the money was stolen or had been expropriated
from,
or even by, another non-capitalist? What if it had been obtained (all at
once) by selling land, slaves, works of art, political or other favours, etc?
Where is the "development" in such cases?
Notes and coins don't change, or become bigger, if they are accumulated. Money
in the bank doesn't "develop" either. Or are we to imagine that in the vaults,
of stored on disk somewhere, notes and coins grow and reproduce, or that all
those digital 'ones' and 'zeros' on that disk become more 'one'-, and
'zero'-like?
But, this money could still operate or serve as Capital, howsoever it had
been acquired, or where it had been stored, depending on
its use and the Mode of Production in which this takes place.
Of course, this isn't to
deny that there were Capitalists (or nascent Capitalists) in pre-Capitalist
Europe; but whatever money they had, its nature as Capital wasn't determined
by its quantity, no matter how large it became, but by the use to which it was put. This is also true
of
the period of transition between Feudalism and Capitalism (before the Capitalist Mode of
Production was apparent or dominant); again, it is the use to which money is put that decides whether or not
it is
Capital, not its quantity.
In which case, this represents an egregious
mis-application of Hegel's 'Law' -- by Marx himself! Now, either we
believe Marx was a complete imbecile (in that he committed this crass error, and
failed even to understand HM!), or we conclude he was still "coquetting" with
Hegelian jargon. [Again, these days we would use 'scare quotes' in such
circumstances, or we would simply refrain from employing such
language altogether.]
Compare the above with Marx's more considered
thoughts (where there is no hint of "coquetting"):
"Capital
consists of raw materials, instruments of labour, and means of subsistence of
all kinds, which are utilised in order to produce new raw materials, new
instruments of labour, and new means of subsistence. All these component parts
of capital are creations of labour, products of labour, accumulated labour.
Accumulated labour which serves as a means of new production is capital.
"So say the
economists.
"What is a
Negro slave? A man of the black race. The one explanation is as good as the
other.
"A Negro is a
Negro. He only becomes a slave in certain relations. A cotton-spinning machine
is a machine for spinning cotton. It becomes capital only in certain
relations. Torn from these relationships it is no more capital than gold in
itself is money, or sugar the price of sugar....
"Capital, also, is a social relation of production.
It is a bourgeois production relation, a production relation of
bourgeois society....
"How, then, does any amount of
commodities, of exchange values, become capital?
"By maintaining and multiplying
itself as an independent social power, that is as the power of a
portion of society, by means of its exchangefor direct, living labour
power. The existence of a class which possess nothing but the ability to
labour is a necessary prerequisite of capital.
"It is only the dominion of
accumulated, past, materialized labour over direct, living labour that turns
accumulated labour into capital.
"Capital does not consist in
accumulated labour serving living labour as a means for new production. It
consists in living labour serving accumulated labour as a means of maintaining
and multiplying the exchange value of the latter.
" [Marx
(1968a), pp.79-81. Italic emphases in the original; bold added. The on-line
version is slightly different to the published version I have used.]
We
also have this remark (unpublished by Marx) from Volume Three of Das
Kapital:
"Capital is not a thing,
but rather a
definite social production relation, belonging to a definite historical
formation of society...." [Marx
(1998), p.801. Bold added.]
In
which case, the mere accumulation of money, according to Marx himself, can't be, or become, capital if "certain relations" are absent.
Once again,
quantity has nothing to do with it.
So,
qualitative change arises not from mere quantitative increase, but from other
factors DM-fans refuse even to consider (I know, I have asked them and all they
do is change the subject, drift off into a dialectic sulk or become abusive). In which case, DM can't actually account for
qualitative change.
Engels's
Q«Q'Law' now seems incompatible
with the Part/Whole metaphysic, too! If the latter were correct, novelty
couldn't enter
into the universe. If Q«Q were
valid, then the nature of the part
can't be determined by the whole.
On the other hand, even
though objects
and processes plainly do change ('essentially'), given such dialectical
constraints
it is
difficult to see how they could do this.
[It is also plain that the
aforementioned equivocation allows DM-fans ignore or brush aside such 'pedantic'
quibbles. This particular objection will be
explored in more detail in Essays Three Part Three and Four Part Two. See also Note 2 and Note 3, below, and Essay Eight
Part One. We have
already
seen how DM can't cope with change, anyway. We also discovered that the
distinction between 'internal' and 'external' opposites, relations and
contradictions was
invented by STDs and MISTs in order to
rationalise
their attempt to 'justify' the doctrine of 'socialism in one country'. Added on Edit, October 2021: I have now published a much more
comprehensive discussion of this equivocation in Essay Seven
Part One.]
The distinction itself seems to be
unviable anyway (unless, that is, the meaning
of "contradiction" were to be altered so that it now failed to conform with the way Hegel,
Marx, Engels, and Lenin seem
to have understood it), despite the criticisms made of it above. That is
because, the classical DM-notion of a 'contradiction' (as the four aforementioned
theorists appear to have employed the term) is predicated on the internal
relation between dialectically-united opposites. If so, there could be no
such thing as an 'external contradiction'. There might be external relations,
and external causes (and possibly even external opposites and forces,
but even that isn't easy to square with what the
DM-classics tell us).
But
if "contradiction" is understood in the classical sense outlined above, "external
contradiction" would make about as much sense as "four-edged triangle", or
"proletarian monarch".
Of course, STDs and MISTs are free to use
words as they see fit (not that they need my permission or acquiescence!), but
"external contradiction" clashes with other things they say about "opposites".
Here are just a few quotations (taken from STD and MIST texts, since this
criticism only applies to their understanding of "external") that illustrate
what I mean:
"Opposites
are, then, the internal aspects, tendencies, forces of an object, which are
mutually exclusive but at the same time presuppose each other. The
inseverable interconnection of these aspects makes up the unity of opposites...[they]
are inconceivable one without the other." [Afanasyev (1968), pp.94-95.
Bold emphases alone added.]
"...[C]ontrary to
metaphysics, not only are fundamental opposites involved in every
subject-matter, but these opposites mutually imply each other, are
inseparably connected together, and far from being exclusive, neither can
exist or can be understood except in relation to the other." [Cornforth
(1976), pp.66-67. Bold emphases added.]
"Contradiction also expresses
this feature of the relation of opposition, i.e., the mutual exclusion and
mutual presupposing of its formative aspects. It can therefore be briefly
defined as the unity of opposites which mutually exclude one another and are in
struggle. The law of dialectics that demonstrates the driving force of
contradictions is formulated as the law of the unity and struggle of opposites."
[Kharin
(1981), p.125. Bold emphasis added.]
"The essence of the
dialectical contradiction may be defined as an interrelationship and
interconnection between opposites in which they mutually assert and deny each
other, and the struggle between them serves as the motive force, the
source of development. This is why the law in question is known as the law
of the unity and struggle of opposites." [Konstantinov,
et al (1974), pp.144-45. Bold
emphasis added.]
"Opposites are the inner
aspects, tendencies or forces of an object or phenomenon which rule each other
out [this probably should be "which are mutually exclusive" -- RL] while
simultaneously presupposing each other. The interconnection of opposites
constitutes a contradiction." [Krapivin (1985), p.161. Bold
emphasis added.]
"By a dialectical
contradiction Marxism understands the presence in a phenomenon or process of
opposite, mutually exclusive aspects which, at the same time, presuppose each
other and within the framework of a given phenomenon exist only in mutual
connection." [Kuusinen (1961), p.93. Bold emphasis added.]
"Though opposites have
different trends of functioning and development and different directions of
change, thereby excluding each other, they do not eliminate each other but
co-exist in an unbreakable unity and interdependence....
"The way in which
opposites presuppose each other and are inseparably interconnected is a
major form through which their unity manifests itself." [Sheptulin (1978),
p.260. Bold emphases added.]
"Analysis shows that
interaction is possible between objects or elements of objects that are not
identical to one another but different. Identity and difference have their
degrees. Difference, for example, can be inessential or essential. The
extreme case of difference is an opposite -- one of the mutually presupposed
sides of a contradiction. In relation to a developing object difference is
the initial stage of division of the object into opposites. When it comes into
interaction, an object seeks, as it were, a complement for itself in that with
which it is interacting. Where there is no stable interaction there is only a
more or less accidental external contact." [Spirkin (1983),
p.144. Bold emphasis added.]
"Identity,
unity, coincidence, interpenetration, interpermeation, interdependence (or
mutual dependence for existence), interconnection or mutual co-operation -- all
these different terms mean the same thingand refer to the following two
points: first, the existence of each of the two aspects of a contradiction in
the process of the development of a thing presupposes the existence of the other
aspect, and both aspects coexist in a single entity; second, in given
conditions, each of the two contradictory aspects transforms itself into its
opposite. This is the meaning of identity....
"The fact is
that no contradictory aspect can exist in isolation. Without its opposite
aspect, each loses the condition for its existence. Just think, can any one
contradictory aspect of a thing or of a concept in the human mind exist
independently? Without life, there would be no death; without death, there would
be no life. Without 'above', there would be no 'below'; without 'below', there
would be no 'above'. Without misfortune, there would be no good fortune; without
good fortune, these would be no misfortune. Without facility, there would be no
difficulty; without difficulty, there would be no facility. Without landlords,
there would be no tenant-peasants; without tenant-peasants, there would be no
landlords. Without the bourgeoisie, there would be no proletariat; without the
proletariat, there would be no bourgeoisie. Without imperialist oppression of
nations, there would be no colonies or semi-colonies; without colonies or
semicolonies, there would be no imperialist oppression of nations. It is so with
all opposites; in given conditions, on the one hand they are opposed to each
other, and on the other they are interconnected, interpenetrating,
interpermeating and interdependent, and this character is described as identity.
In given conditions, all contradictory aspects possess the character of
non-identity and hence are described as being in contradiction. But they also
possess the character of identity and hence are interconnected. This is what
Lenin means when he says that dialectics studies 'how opposites can be
and how they become identical'. How then can they be identical? Because each is the
condition for the other's existence. This is the first meaning of identity."
[Mao (1961b),
pp.337-38. Bold emphases added. Quotation
marks altered to conform to the conventions adopted at this site. Three minor
typos corrected; missing words "and how they become", found in the published
version, added. I have informed the editors over at the MIA of these errors.]
If the above theorists are correct, it
far from
easy to see how there could be any 'external contradictions'. If every
such
contradiction is a unity of opposites that imply or presuppose one another,
they should all be 'internal'. Indeed, Kuusinen more-or-less rules out any
other view of 'dialectical contradictions':
"By a dialectical
contradiction Marxism understands the presence in a phenomenon or process of
opposite, mutually exclusive aspects which, at the same time, presuppose each
other and within the framework of a given phenomenon exist only in mutual
connection." [Kuusinen (1961), p.93. Bold emphases added.]
If some contradictions aren't
'composed' in this way (i.e., if they are 'external', and in relation to which
their opposites do not "presuppose" one another, and for which each one
isn't the precondition for the existence of the other), then "contradiction"
must have two different meanings in DM -- the 'external' sort which can't be 'dialectical
contradictions' as such, and the 'internal', which are.
But, if 'external contradictions' aren't
'dialectical contradictions', what the hell are they?
Anyway, such a concession would fatally
compromise the dialectical theory of change since the interaction between
'externally-connected opposites' can't be law-governed, as we saw in an earlier
Essay. This would leave DM-theorists with no answer to Hume. [Since I have
covered this in detail in Essay Seven
Part Three, the
reader is directed there for more details.]
Finally, in Essay Eight
Part One, we saw that the
equivocation between the 'spatial' and the 'logical' sense of "internal"
(alongside the ill-defined notions, 'object', 'process', 'system', and 'whole',
as they feature in DM), means that 'external contradictions' might also
actually be 'internal' (but,
even then,
only 'spatially-internal'), if they are situated in a larger system/'Whole'. Confusingly,
too,
'logically-', or 'spatially-', 'internal contradictions' could be 'external' to
other objects and process within a larger or wider 'Whole'!
Consider
again, for example, the alleged 'contradiction' inside the atom -- presumably
between the negatively charged electrons and the positively charged protons --
which holds this micro-system together. While that 'contradiction' is 'internal'
to the atom, it is 'external' to each particle
involved,
if interpreted 'spatially'. On the other hand, if these two opposites
"presuppose" one another, this 'contradiction' would now be 'spatially
internal' to the atom and (in a 'logical' sense) 'internal' to each particle,
too. Moreover, this 'contradiction' would also be 'spatially internal' to any
molecule or wider natural sub-system to which it belongs -- at the same time -- even while it could be
logically 'external' to either of the latter!
Of course, several dialecticians acknowledge
this; for instance, here is Kharin:
"The existing boundary
between internal and external contradictions is not at the same time absolute.
The same contradiction may assume different qualities with regard to different
systems." [Kharin (1981), p.130.]
However, it isn't easy to see how
what Karin says could
be the case with respect to 'logically-internal contradictions'. Presumably the
alleged 'contradiction' between capital and labour is one of the latter sort.
But, how could this 'contradiction' ever become 'external', or change its
"qualities", as Kharin suggests?
Even supposing such 'contradictions' could
change in the above manner, it would seem that they could only do so because of their own internal
'contradictions' (again, if the
DM-classics
are to be believed -- which tell us that everything changes because of
its own 'internal contradictions')! So, if the working class becomes
the ruling-class one day, or it abolishes all classes, then this could only happen because
of 'contradictions' internal to the working class! If, on the other hand,
these
take place because of the 'contradiction' between the working class and the
capitalist class, then, since that 'contradiction' is itself external to
the working class (even if it is internal to capitalism), it can't change the
working class in the above manner, since only its own 'internal
contradictions' can do that!
We
can now, perhaps, see where this serial
DM-confusion is heading -- here is Afanasyev, confusing "internal" with "spatially
internal" in like manner:
"Both internal and external
contradictions are inherent in objects and phenomena of the material world, but
internal contradictions, those within the object itself, are the principal
contradictions that are decisive in development.... Internal contradictions are
the source of development because they determine the aspect or character of the
object itself. If it were not for its internal contradictions the object would
not be what it is.... All external influences
exerted on an object are always refracted through its inherent contradictions,
which is also a manifestation of the determining role of those contradictions in
development.... The source of social
development is also contained within society itself, in its inherent internal
contradictions...." [Afanasyev (1968), pp.98-99. Paragraphs merged.]
But,
this must mean that the
'contradictions' internal to capitalism are external to the working
class; in which case, on this view (as noted earlier), the working class can't change!
On the other hand, if the working class
does
change, then, according to the above, it can only do so as a result of its
own 'internal contradictions'. The class war, is, however, external to
the working class (in a spatial sense), given the above, and so can't affect the
development of history.
In which case, the motor of history isn't the
class war (as Marx supposed), but the internal strife in any given
class. Hence, if Afanasyev is to be believed, the struggle against the
capitalists won't actually change the working class into the new ruling-class; internecine
warfare inside the proletariat will do that!
Again, I trust we can all now appreciate where the equivocation between the two
senses of "internal" (coupled with ill-defined notions of objects, processes and
systems) has landed us. The fatal consequences this presents
HM -- i.e., if such
crazy ideas (upside
down or the 'right way up') were adopted -- should now be plain for all to see: on this view, the history of
all hitherto class societies isn't in fact the history of class struggle!
[Once
more the above aren't my views; I am merely exposing the absurd consequences of
this theory.]
It
could be objected that the contradiction between the working class (the
proletariat) and the capitalist class is internal to each class (in the
sense that it arises from their internal relation to one another). I have dealt
with the problems this creates for DM-theorists in Essay Seven
Part Three. Readers
are directed there for more details.
Independently of that, the above considerations affect
theories constructed by STDs and MISTs, but there is little room for Trotskyist
(or other Marxist) dialecticians to crow. As we discovered in Essay Eight
Part One, the introduction of
'external contradictions' at least had the merit of absolving Lenin of holding
manifestly absurd ideas about motion and change -- even if that
escape route itself finally proved to be a dead end.
However, without recourse to 'external
contradictions', Trotskyist-, or, indeed, other Marxist-dialecticians (who reject
'external contradictions') must face the
fact that the old anti-dialectical joke is in reality no joke at all:
Q: How many dialecticians
does it take to change a light bulb?
A: None at all, the light bulb
changes itself.
[Why this is a consequence of
appealing to 'internal contradictions' as the sole cause of change is explained
in detail in Essay Eight Part One (link above). Even so,
there are other serious problems that afflict the doctrine of 'external
contradictions' in addition to those mentioned in this Note -- problems
that threaten to undermine dialectics in its entirety. I have explained what
these are in Essay Seven
Parts One and
Three.]
2. As
noted above, in Note 1a (and in the main body of this Essay), DM-fans appeal to Engels's shaky Q«Q
'Law' here to account for the "emergence" of novelty.
But,
what precisely is part
and what is whole in relation to this 'law'? Indeed, what is quantity and what is quality? Is the quantity here the number, weight, size or age
of the parts --, the energy fed into them, or into the surrounding system? Or,
is energy itself one of the parts? [But, how could it be if
energy isn't
even a 'substance',
but merely a "capacity to do work"? Or, is it, as one physicist told
me recently, it is "The ability to turn into matter"? Is that what all
matter is made of, an 'ability to turn into matter'?] And, is the quality
here something that appertains to the whole, the parts -- or something else?
"Emergence" itself will
be discussed in detail in Essay Three Part Three -- however, this is what Woods
and Grant had to say:
"Life itself arises from a
qualitative leap from inorganic to organic matter. The explanation of the
processes by which this occurred constitutes one of the most important and
exciting problems of present-day science....
"...Moreover, the task of
deciphering the structure of a protein molecule itself was incredibly difficult.
The properties of each protein depends on its exact relation to each amino acid
on the molecular chain. Here too, quantity determines quality....
"The dialectical relationship between whole and
part manifests itself in the different levels of complexity in nature, reflected
in the different branches of science.
"a) Atomic interactions and the laws of chemistry
determine the laws of biochemistry, but life itself is qualitatively different.
"b) The laws of biochemistry 'explain' all the
processes of human interaction with the environment. And yet human activity and
thought are qualitatively different to the biological processes that constitute
them.
"c) Each individual person, in turn, is a product
of his or her physical and environmental development. Yet the complex
interactions of the sum total of individuals which make up a society are also
qualitatively different. In each of these cases the whole is greater than the
sum of the parts and obeys different laws.
"In the last analysis, all human existence and
activity is based on the laws of motion of atoms. We are part of a material
universe, which is a continuous whole, functioning according to its inherent
laws. And yet, when we pass from a) to c), we make a series of qualitative
leaps, and must operate with different laws at different 'levels'; c) is based
upon b) and b) is based upon a), but nobody in their right mind would seek to
explain the complex movements in human society in terms of atomic forces. For
the same reason, it is absolutely futile to reduce the problem of crime to the
laws of genetics." [Woods and Grant (1995), pp.59-60.]
But, what if it turns out that it is a property of the parts
that they interact this way when combined, allowing for the
reduction of certain properties of wholes to those of their parts? [On this, see the
electron example above.]
That
would make such parts more like pieces in a dynamic sort of jig-saw puzzle. On
their own, each piece would
carry
only a part of the overall picture, which may only be seen -- or which only becomes
apparent -- when combined with other parts. [This is a faint echo of the way
Leibniz, for example,
viewed
things.] In this way, the final result would arise from the
parts merely added together, with the new whole now a sum of such
parts, but no more. This would account for the phenomena just as well as
the 'theory' Woods and Grant tried to sell their readers, and it does so without an ounce
of mysticism -- i.e., in that it wouldn't now be a mystery where the final
picture or properties came from, as is the case with the 'theory' these two
have swallowed.
[I hasten to add that I am not advocating this theory (indeed, I
reject all philosophical theories as
non-sensical and incoherent), I am merely pointing out, once again, that Woods and Grant failed to
consider (fairly -- or at all!) any alternatives to their seriously blinkered view
of the world.]
This 'alternative' to Woods and Grant's
'theory' may or may not be correct --
as I noted above, I will pass no judgement on it --, but, the imposition of an a priori schema onto reality,
and one that is based on the mystical
musings of a Hermetic Idealist, backed up by an ill-defined and threadbare 'Law' (i.e.,
Q«Q),
sits rather badly with the constant refrain that this is something dialecticians
neverdo.
Attentive readers will no
doubt have noticed,
too,
how, in the last paragraph of the quoted passage above, the "quantities" to which Woods
and Grant refer have now morphed into "levels". This, of course, means that Engels
should have said:
"Qualitative changes
take place not just by the quantitative addition or subtraction of matter or motion (so-called
energy), but by going up or down one level, too. Hence it is possible to alter the quality of a body without
addition or subtraction of matter or motion." [Edited misquotation of
Engels (1954), p.63.]
Naturally, that makes this 'Law'
quintessentially Ideal, since the move between levels (resulting
in an alleged qualitative transformation) can't itself be consequent on a quantitative change
in matter or energy anywhere else in the system. Plainly,
magnification isn't an addition of energy, either. [There is more on this in Essay
Seven Part One.]
2a. I have quoted
(here)
several dozen passages from the DM-classics, along with several others from 'lesser'
DM-luminaries, that support this reading of the 'dialectical theory of change'.
Those tempted to respond that the
opposite of the "Totality" is "Nothing" (or even "nothing") should only be
allowed to get away with that Supers-Scientific, linguistic dodge when they
have explained clearly what the "Totality" actually is. As we saw in Essay Eleven
Part One, we have been left
totally the
dark on that score. [No pun intended.]
Anyway, as we will see in
Essay Twelve Parts Five and Six, "Nothing" (or, indeed, "nothing") can't act as
a name, let alone as the name of the 'opposite' of 'Everything'.
Of course, if the opposite of any
Tkis Nothing (or nothing), then that Tk
must change into Nothing (or nothing), and vice versa -- as
the DM-classics assure us that
everything must inevitably do.
If so, the world we see around us must be continually changing into Nothing (or nothing), and vice
versa -- but not
into the next Ti
in line (i.e., not into Tk+1)!
Moreover, if correct, the DM-theory of change (that everything must struggle
with and then change into that opposite) also predicts that this Nothing (or
nothing) must change back into T, again -- or, at least, into the next Ti
in line. [The theory is somewhat unclear on this!]
Has anyone noticed these remarkable
events?
Not only that, but the 'Totality' must struggle with its opposite, too. In which
case, it must struggle with nothing! But, how is that different from not
struggling at all?
Perhaps we just don't 'understand'
dialectics?
2b. Of course,
some dialecticians might agree with Engels:
"For that matter,
Herr Dühring will never succeed in conceiving real infinity without
contradiction. Infinity is a contradiction, and is full of
contradictions.From the outset it is a contradiction that an infinity is
composed of nothing but finites, and yet this is the case. The limitedness
of the material world leads no less to contradictions than its unlimitedness,
and every attempt to get over these contradictions leads, as we have seen, to
new and worse contradictions. It is just because infinity is a
contradiction that it is an infinite process, unrolling endlessly in time and in
space. The removal of the contradiction would be the end of infinity.
Hegel saw this quite correctly, and for that reason treated with well-merited
contempt the gentlemen who subtilised over this contradiction." [Engels (1976),
pp.63-64. Bold emphasis
added.]
But, over and above merely asserting
it, exactly why "infinity"
is contradictory Engels annoyingly kept to himself. Or, rather, why it is a contradiction
that an infinite 'collection' composed of 'finites' is contradictory. Of course,
it would be if it were the case that -- or, it had been defined that -- infinite
'collections' are composed only of further 'infinites', but who on earth would attempt
to do such an
odd thing? [Even then, this would merely be an inconsistency. (On the difference
between inconsistencies and contradictions, see
here and
here.)]
Unfortunately, however, beyond this
rather weak argument, Engels had nothing else to say in support of his claim that
infinity is 'contradictory'.
It could be argued that this
follows from one of the
Antinomies of
Pure Reason in
Kant's
Critique of Pure Reason, namely, the First Antinomy: The world had a
beginning in time, etc., but, then again, on the other hand, it had no such beginning. [Kant (1998),
pp.467-75;
517-30.] This 'contradiction' appears to be based on Kant's rejection
of
Baumgarten's definition (I am relying on the editorial comments in Kant
(1998), by Guyer and Wood for this information; cf., p.743 of the same), that is, that a magnitude
is infinite "if none greater than it...is possible" (p.472; A430/B458). Kant
argues that no such multiplicity could be the greatest, since units can always
be added to it. In that case, an infinite magnitude (and thus an infinite
world) is impossible. Kant thought he could derive a contradiction here since no
such infinite series is completable, hence time can't have stretched back to
infinity -- since, presumably, such an interval has actually been completed
(in the here and now).
On the other hand, time itself can't be bounded by a first moment
in time. In that case, there could be no beginning in time -- implying that time
stretches back to infinity. [I omit Kant's comments about space, and greatly
compress his argument here, of course;
pp.470-75.
Much of Kant's discussion
is intimately connected with his view of the nature of space and time as "forms"
of our ability to experience anything at all.]
I
don't want to get bogged
down in a detailed critique of Kant in this Essay; anyway, ideas about the
infinite have undergone
a
radical change
since the work of
Georg Cantor.
However, it is far from clear that contemporary theorists are at all clear
themselves what they mean by the new concepts these innovations introduced
into mathematics and philosophy. [On this see,
Moore (2001), and my comments here.
There is a useful discussion of Hegel's notion of the infinite in Houlgate
(2006), pp.394-435.]
However, it is plain that Kant
is operating with two different conceptions of the infinite (perhaps without realising
it), so no wonder he thinks he can derive a contradiction. He regards a set as
infinite if (a) No more units can be added to it -- but plainly, as he
acknowledges, they can be (hence, no magnitude could be the
greatest) -- and (b) A set is infinite if it isn't completable. Plainly, these two
aren't equivalent.
The set of Negative Integers is infinite, and yet, ordering it from
negative infinity, it is completed at -1 (a point made by Wittgenstein).
Of course, in
relation to (a), Kant might have had in mind an infinite set such as the
Rationals -- say, on the interval: <1,2>. It could be argued that no more can be added to this set. But how do we
know? It could be responded that it is obvious from the nature of the Rationals that no more can be added. Once again, how might this be verified? Do
we possess computers powerful enough to check this assumed fact; or, indeed, are
there human beings who might live
long enough to check it? So-called analytic proofs of this assume fact also depend for their cogency
on ignoring such questions (as subsequent and contemporary supporters of Kant's approach to
mathematics point out -- on this, see the next two paragraphs).
In addition, Kant failed to
distinguish
bounded from
unbounded
infinites. According to the prevailing view, the
Rationals
between one and two, for instance, can be put in an equivalence relation
with the
Natural Numbers, meaning this sub-set of the Rationals is infinite; but this
set is
bounded above and below. Of course, were Kant alive today, he would probably
have asked what the phrase "can be put" actually means in such
contexts, since this plainly can't be done even by super-fast computers many
hundreds of orders of magnitude quicker than any we have today. Indeed, as
noted above,
mathematicians who look to Kant
for inspiration
ask this very question, among others.
And, it isn't to the
point to argue that we can't write down the first number in the set of Negative
Integers, since this way of
looking at that set means they are completable. [The problem is
that the word "completable" is itself vague and ambiguous -- "completable" in what way,
and by whom? On this, see
Potter (2004) and Tiles (2004). See also the references listed
here.] Anyway, we can
write down the first and last members of the Rationals between one and two, but
few doubt it is infinite. [Even so, we can't write down the second
rational number in the interval <1,2>.]
Fortunately, we now have far more precise
ways of
defining infinite sets. Nevertheless, it is still far from clear whether we
understand this area of the Philosophy of Mathematics well enough to be able to
say with any confidence that 'The Infinite', so defined, is (or isn't) contradictory. However, in view
of the fact that any answer to this question -- or at least any attempt to
clarify it --, must be expressed in propositional form, it is reasonably clear
that any such answer will only ever be in the negative. That is because, if a
proposition were contradictory, it wouldn't
be a proposition with a clear sense, nor would it even count as a proposition,
to begin with. [Why that is so is explained
here.]
Despite this, as noted above, Engels's stated
reason for regarding the infinite as 'contradictory' is manifestly defective. [I
will say much more about that in Essay Twelve Part Five.]
To be sure, Engels examined several of
Dühring's (and Kant's) arguments, and concluded that one or more of them was "contradictory", but it is far from clear whether Engels
himself was asserting the things contained in the passage in question in
AD, or merely
rehearsing a few rhetorical
flourishes of his own. [Cf., Engels (1976), pp.57-69.]
3.It could be objected here that as T's
parts enter into new relationships
with one another, T wouldipsofacto alter, becoming a new
"Totality" --, say, T*.
This process could continue indefinitely as the "Totality" itself
developed. If
so, contrary to the claims made in the main body of this Essay, the parts of a "Totality"
would become more than they once were in a new,
perhaps
evolved, "Totality".
Or, so it could be argued...
However, that response is itself vacuous unless
and until DM-theorists tell us what
the "Totality" itself actually is. [This problem was discussed at
length in
Part One of this Essay, which has been summarised
here.]
Nevertheless, and independently of the above, this volunteered DM-reply is difficult to
square with G1:
G1: The entire nature of a part is
determined by its relation with the other parts and with the whole.
If the entire nature of a part is
indeed so determined, then it isn't easy to see how it could change, or enter into new
relations with other parts and with the whole -- all of which are likewise so
constrained.
If any part, say,
pi, is locked
in place by its relation with all the other parts,
Pn (where
Pn
is the set of all the parts of Tnot including
pi),
and with T -- hence, presumably, with itself --, and the latter are equally
so constrained, change would appear to be impossible. There doesn't seem to be
any way that novelty could emerge.
[In
Note 1a andNote
Two above, we have already seen that an appeal to Engels's Q«Q
'Law' would be to no avail in this respect.]
Even if novelty were to 'emerge' this way -- somehow -- in line
with this 'Law', then the
entire nature of any new part couldn't after all be determined by its relation with other
parts and with the whole -- that is, not unless there were a law of some sort that
caused or initiated such novelty. But, in that case, such a 'law' would allow for a reduction of these
new properties to the properties of the
assembled parts, undermining the resistance DM-theorists have always
shown toward reductionism.
[This argument will be more fully developed in Essay Three Part Three.]
Hence, it seems that if change is to be
accommodated within DM, G1 will need to be modified or abandoned. In either event,
classical DM-Wholism would be untenable.
It could be objected here that the above
is misguided since it is quite clear that dialecticians believe the nature
of any part is determined by a changing, developing "Totality". That
means
the nature of each and every part, even if entirely so constituted, must change
accordingly.
But, if
that were so, then any change to parts couldn't be internally-driven (as
we have been led to believe), and if in turn that is so, another core DM-thesis will have been fatally-wounded. [On
this, see Essay Eight Part One.] Moreover, the proffered response
(given above) fails to deal with the fundamental
objections raised against this way of seeing things outlined in Note 1a, above.
We will also see
herethat the
DM-reply in the last but one paragraph only works if (i) The "Totality" incorporates the non-existent
past -- which, paradoxically would also prevent change from taking place(!) --,
or (ii) Recourse is made to events and processes that either don't exist or which are outside the
"Totality" in order to account for things inside the "Totality", vitiating the explanatory
role that this obscure entity (i.e., the "Totality") was supposed to
occupy in the first place.
[This
is quite apart from the difficulties noted
here and
here --
i.e., in relation to the confusion in DM-circles about whatexactly causes change.]
It could also be
argued that even if the entire nature of each part is determined by its
relation to other parts and to the whole, that doesn't mean that all such
influences are of equal significance. In which case, parts that are
separated by billions of light years, say -- or which aren't relevantly
related to each other -- would have vanishingly small effects on one another.
In which case,
they may safely be ignored. For instance, in relation to changes on this planet, objects on the outer
fringes of the visible universe can, for all intents and purposes, be
disregarded. Or, to take another example,
minor changes to certain parts of an organism (such
as those affecting its hair or its toe-nails) will have no
effect on the rest of
that organism -- which clearly defuses several of the objections
advanced
here.
Now, this would be an effective response
had it been made by anyone other than a DM-fan. As we saw in Note 1a, that is because
many of them believe these
'influences' aren't in fact external or causal, but are "internal" and
'dialectical-logical'. Remoteness has no effect on this type of
inter-relation as it operates between part and part, whole and part, or whole and whole.
[Exactly
why those DM-fans who reject this 'Hegelian' view of reality (a view that
Lenin, for example, endorsed) are making a rod for their own backs is
explained here.]
To see this, consider an analogy: suppose that NN (who lives in New York) has a
husband who unfortunately dies. This would have an immediate effect on the
logical/legal status of NN whether her late partner was in New York,
California, or Tokyo at the time of his demise. Distance is irrelevant in this
regard.
To be sure, the news of the bereavement might take longer to reach the widow if,
say, her partner had passed away in East Asia, but that has nothing to do with
the logical/legal point being made. Plainly, separation-distance doesn't mean that
widowhood is governed by some sortof
inverse square law,
so that if the said partner were twice as far
away when he died, NN would now only be one quarter of the widow she would have been had he passed away
in her arms.
Consider another example: suppose that the
committee which controls the standards encapsulated in
SI
units
were to alter the definition of a metre from 100 to 120 centimetres. In that
eventuality, the length of a metre in distant galaxies, billions of light years
away, would immediately change. There is no inverse square law at work here,
either; so the length of this (new) metre plainly wouldn't
change with the square of the distance.
Hence, the system-wide
implications of the adoption of "internal relations" (which makes some
sort of crazy sense in Hegel's Mystical System), can't be defused by pretending that
they are really external relations in disguise, subject to inverse square laws, and
the like -- and thus are sensitive to separation distances.
To be sure, and as noted
above, there are
DM-theorists (these are mainly
STDs and
MISTs) who don't think
these relations are all "internal", but we have
already seen that they equivocate
between a 'spatial' and a 'logical' sense of "internal". However, if relations
are to be classified as "internal" or "external", depending on whether they are on the
inside or the outside of the object or process in question and not on the basis
of their
'dialectical-logical' relations, the
unity and interdependence of the "Totality" will plainly be called into
question. It isn't easy to see how everything can be interconnected, or how the entire
nature of the part might depend on the nature of the whole, if the relation between
part and whole is "external" in the 'spatial' sense of that word.
If STDs and MISTs want to hang on to
the doctrine of interconnectedness as well as the part-whole relation, then it seems they will have to
accept that objects and processes that are spatially separated must be
internally-related (in the 'dialectical-logical' sense). If so, then
remoteness can't affect these inter-relations, and the above points still stand.
On the other hand, if they want to maintain a commitment to 'external
relations', and thus to 'external contradictions', then much of DM will fall apart. But,
because 'external contradictions' were invented for political reasons
connected with the attempt to 'justify' the doctrine of 'socialism in one
country', it is
pretty clear which option they will choose. However, since history has shown
that Lenin and Trotsky were right (when they argued that socialism can't be
built in one country), the political reason for holding on to 'external
contradictions' was roundly refuted by subsequent events. [On this, see Essay Nine Part
Two, here
and here.]
It could be objected that
dialecticians have built "relative interconnectedness" into their theory, which shows
that the above comments are misguided.
Sure, they might very well say that this is what they have done, but until they can show
how a logical link is capable of varying -- or decreasing with
distance -- their protestations will remain ineffective.
Once more, but with
respect to a different example: consider the
Prime Meridian
that passes through Greenwich in South East London; all other lines of
longitude are unquestionably 'internally'-related to this Meridian
(however, I should prefer to express this point differently; I have only adopted
this way of characterising this set of links in order to help strangle it). But, no one supposes that
longitude 180o West, say,
is slightly less of a longitude than 179o
West, or that 5o East is
more of a longitude than 10o
East -- nor even 'relatively' more.
Furthermore,
consider an
'internal relation' that DM-fans themselves acknowledge: suppose that capitalist, C1,
goes on a trip across the globe, all the while remaining the owner of her
company back in, say, Paris, France. In that case, would she be any less of a
capitalist with each mile she travelled away from her home country? Are the relations
of production and ownership sensitive toseparation-distance? Would
any of her employees be less
proletarian as a result?
Of course, no one
imagines that class or economic relations can be reduced to the links between
their 'parts' taken severally (that is, if we are ever told by DM-fans what these
'dialectical parts' are!), but
it is nevertheless the case that C1
will rightly be classified as a capitalist because of legal, or ownership, relations that are interconnected
by the relations of production. In
that case, distance won't affect these relations -- nor her, nor her employees,
in these respects. Taken severally or collectively, such things aren't governed by inverse square laws.
It could be objected that
as a matter of fact inverse square laws do operate in nature, and because
of that the force of gravity operating between, for example, stars separated by
millions of light years is
negligible.
But, the "internal
relations" in DM aren't like gravity -- which is manifestly an
external cause --, so this particular force can't be used in such an "internalist" way.
[Of course, this is all the more so now that gravity is no longer viewed as a force. On that, see
Essay Eight Part Two.]
Once more, it could be argued that "internal
relations" are unlike the logical relations outlined above (concerning the
goings-on between married partners, the metric system, or peripatetic
capitalists); so, the above
comments are misguided.
Admittedly, the nature of the interconnections
postulated by dialecticians is impenetrably obscure (as we discovered in
Part Oneof this
Essay, and as we will also see in Essay Four Part Two), but that is precisely the
problem. Until we are told what the nature of a single one of these mysterious
'dialectical interconnections' is, not even DM-fans will know if
--
or even how -- their commitment to "internal relations" affects these alleged drop-off
rates.
Again, as pointed out in Note 1a, the above proffered DM-responses were
prompted by the dialectical equivocation originally
mentioned
here. This involves one minute interpreting "internal" in 'spatial' terms
(thus confusing "internal relation" with "external relation"), the next in
'dialectical-logical' terms. This also
allows DM-theorists to slip effortlessly back-and-forth between these two interpretations, describing a relation,
or a 'contradiction', as "internal" from one point of view, and then "external"
from another.
Finally, it could be objected that
DM-theorists do not claim that everything in the universe is
internally-related.
Unfortunately, that seems to fly in the face of what Lenin
had to say:
"Hegel brilliantly divined the
dialectics of things (phenomena, the world, nature) in the dialectics of
concepts…. This aphorism should be expressed more popularly, without the word
dialectics: approximately as follows: In the alternation, reciprocal dependence
of all notions, in the identity of their opposites, in the
transitions of one notion into another, in the eternal change, movement of
notions, Hegel brilliantly divined precisely this relation of things to
nature…. [W]hat constitutes dialectics?…. [M]utual dependence of notions
all without exception…. Every notion occurs in a certain relation, in
a certain connection with all the others." [Lenin (1961), pp.196-97.
Bold emphasis alone added.]
That seems reasonably clear --, and
Hegel very helpfully 'divined' these 'internal relations' for us.
One thing is for
sure:
bemused readers
will search long and hard through the highly repetitive writings of
dialecticians (for example, here),
and to no avail, but
they will find not one single comment
devoted to this problem. Now, this long-term silence is itselfinternally-connected
with the profound
obscurity of the concepts DM-fans have appropriated from Hegel. And that internal
confusion will itself dissipate only when those Mystical Musings have
themselves been ditched.
4.One
way to avoid this conclusion might be to argue that G1 doesn't carry the
implications that have been imputed to it in this Essay:
G1: The
entire nature of a part is determined by its relation with the other parts
and with the whole.
Hence, it could be maintained that whatever G1 says, DM itself isn't committed to the idea that
the entire nature of a whole is determined by any of its parts, nor
vice versa. In that case,
both whole and part can be compared each side of the amalgamation of one or more
extra parts in order to decide if one or both had in fact changed. Of course,
that wouldn't be something we could
establish in advance. This modified view might imply the following:
G1a: The
nature of a part is determined by its relation with the other parts and with the
whole, and vice versa.
Nevertheless, this 'modified view' would be worse than useless since it would be
unclear to what extent part and whole influenced each other. If some aspect of
a part wasn't constrained by its
relations with other parts, then that particular aspect could, for all intents and
purposes, exist in splendid isolation (at least as far as its interconnections were
concerned).
To that end, let us suppose that there exists aspect,
A1, of part, P1,
the nature of which isn't affected by the other sub-parts of P1,
or by anything else. It would seem therefore that in this respect at least
A1
must be isolated, or sealed off from the rest of nature. Are DM-theorists
prepared to go down that route to bail out their theory? But, if we
allow one exception to G1, why not two..., why not billions? And then what is
to stop this option collapsing into CAR?
All
this is quite apart from the fact that wholes don't exist except they are made of their parts. So, it isn't too clear from where
this additional source of novelty is supposed originate.
Just
as it is inconsistent with the following
declarations of Lenin's:
"[T]he individual exists only in the connection
that leads to the universal. The universal exists only in the individual and
through the individual. Every individual is (in one way or another) a universal.
Every universal is (a fragment, or an aspect, or the essence of) an individual.
Every universal only approximately embraces all the individual objects. Every
individual enters incompletely into the universal, etc., etc. Every individual
is connected by thousands of transitions with other kinds of individuals
(things, phenomena, processes), etc. Here already we have the elements,
the germs of the concept of necessity, of objective connection in nature,
etc. Here already we have the contingent and the necessary, the phenomenon and
the essence; for when we say John is a man…we disregard a number of attributes
as contingent; we separate the essence from the appearance, and
counterpose the one to the other…." [Lenin (1961), p.359. Emphases in the
original.]
"[Among the elements of dialectics are the
following:] [I]nternally contradictory tendencies…in [a thing]…as the sum
and unity of opposites…. [E]ach thing (phenomenon, process, etc.)…is
connected with every other…." [Ibid.,
p.221. Bold emphases
alone added.]
"In our times, the idea of
development, of evolution, has almost completely penetrated social
consciousness, only in other ways, and not through Hegelian philosophy. Still,
this idea, as formulated by Marx and Engels on the basis of Hegel's philosophy,
is far more comprehensive and far richer in content than the current idea of
evolution is. A development that repeats, as it were, stages that have already
been passed, but repeats them in a different way, on a higher basis ('the
negation of the negation'), a development, so to speak, that proceeds in
spirals, not in a straight line; a development by leaps, catastrophes, and
revolutions; 'breaks in continuity'; the transformation of quantity into
quality; inner impulses towards development, imparted by the contradiction and
conflict of the various forces and tendencies acting on a given body, or within
a given phenomenon, or within a given society; the interdependence and the
closest and indissoluble connection between all aspects of any
phenomenon (history constantly revealing ever new aspects), a connection
that provides a uniform, and universal process of motion, one that follows
definite laws -- these are some of the features of dialectics as a doctrine of
development that is richer than the conventional
one." [Lenin (1914),
pp.12-13. Bold emphasis
alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform to the conventions adopted at
this site.]
"A
tumbler is assuredly both a glass cylinder and a drinking vessel. But there are
more than these two properties and qualities or facets to it; there are an
infinite number of them, an infinite number of 'mediacies' and
inter-relationships with the rest of the world….
"[I]f
we are to have true knowledge of an object we must look at and examine
all its facets, its connections and 'mediacies'. That is something we
cannot ever hope to achieve completely, but the rule of comprehensiveness is
a safeguard against mistakes and rigidity…." [Lenin (1921), pp.92-93. Bold
emphases added. Quotation marks altered to
conform to the conventions adopted at this site.]
These look pretty maximalist.
[That descriptor was explained here.
See also,
below.]
Moreover, and in relation to this, we have
seen (in Note 1a and Note
2)
that Engels's rickety
Q«Q
'Law' isn't much help, either. But, even
if it were,
the alleged 'emergent' novelty in this case would clearly have been caused by the parts so
assembled; it wouldn't 'drop in from the skies', as it were. Hence, even if Q«Q
were a
reliable 'Law', and even though dialecticians might claim to be able to use it to show how
certain aspects of a whole had in fact been determined by its parts (but not the
entire nature of that whole), it still wouldn't be possible for them to show that
the whole was more than the sum of the assembled parts -- or even that
the qualities they claim had mysteriously 'emerged' as a result weren't reducible to
those parts. [On that, see below.]
Some might want to argue
here that this entire line-of-thought is thoroughly misconceived, since
dialecticians hold that, as things develop, there is a "Unity in Difference", or
an "Identity in Difference" [IED], at work in
such changes.
This means that although an object might change, there would be a clear line of continuity
between its different stages so that it could be identified as
the 'same object' either side of any such alteration --, which object would
itself have been transformed as a result.
Unfortunately, this runs
foul of many other things that DM-classicists also have to say.
"Dialectics…prevails throughout nature….
[T]he motion through opposites which asserts itself everywhere in nature,
and which by the continual conflict of the opposites…determines the life of
nature." [Engels (1954),
p.211. Bold emphases added.]
"[Among the elements of dialectics are the
following:]…internally contradictory tendencies…in this [totality]…and
unity of opposites…. [E]ach thing…is connected with every other…[this
involves] not only the unity of opposites, but the transitions of
everydetermination, quality, feature, side, property into
every other ….
"In brief, dialectics can be
defined as the doctrine of the unity of opposites. This embodies the essence of
dialectics….
"The splitting of the whole and the cognition
of its contradictory parts…is the essence (one of the 'essentials', one
of the principal, if not the principal, characteristic features) of dialectics….
"The identity of opposites…is the
recognition…of the contradictory, mutually exclusive, opposite tendencies
in all phenomena and processes of nature…. Development is the 'struggle'
of opposites.
"…The unity…of opposites is
conditional, temporary, transitory, relative. The struggle of mutually exclusive
opposites is absolute, just as development and motion are absolute." [Lenin
(1961),
pp.221-22;
357-58. Emphases in the original.]
"According to Hegel,
dialectics is the
principle of all life…. [M]an has two qualities: first being alive, and
secondly of also being mortal. But on closer examination it turns out that
life itself bears in itself the germ of death, and that in general
any phenomenonis contradictory, in the sense that it develops
out of itself the elements which, sooner or later, will put an end to its
existence and will transform it into its opposite. Everything
flows, everything changes; and there is no force capable of holding
back this constant flux, or arresting its eternal movement. There is
no force capable of resisting the dialectics of phenomena….
"At a particular moment a moving body is at a
particular spot, but at the same time it is outside it as well because, if it
were only in that spot, it would, at least for that moment, become motionless.
Everymotion is a dialectical process, a living contradiction, and
as there is not a single phenomenon of nature in explaining which we do
not have in the long run to appeal to motion, we have to agree with Hegel,
who said that dialectics is the soul of any scientific cognition. And
this applies not only to cognition of nature….
"And so every phenomenon, by
the action of those same forces which condition its existence, sooner or later,
but inevitably, is transformed into its own opposite….
"When you apply the dialectical method to the
study of phenomena, you need to remember that
forms change eternally
in consequence of the 'higher development of their content'….
"In the words of Engels, Hegel's merit
consists in the fact that he was the first to regard all phenomena from
the point of view of their development, from the point of view of their origin
and destruction…." [Plekhanov (1956), pp.74-77, 88,
163. Bold emphases alone
added.]
"'All is flux, nothing is
stationary,' said the ancient thinker from Ephesus. The combinations we call
objects are in a state of constant and more or less rapid change….
"…[M]otion does not only make objects…, it
is constantly changing them. It is for this reason that the logic
of motion (the 'logic of contradiction') never relinquishes its
rights over the objects created by motion….
"With Hegel, thinking progresses in
consequence of the uncovering and resolution of the contradictions
inclosed (sic) in concepts. According to our doctrine…the contradictions
embodied in concepts are merely reflections, translations into the language
of thought, of those contradictions that are embodied in phenomena
owing to the contradictory nature of their common basis, i.e., motion….
"…[T]he overwhelming majority of phenomena
that come within the compass of the natural and the social sciences are among
'objects' of this kind…[:ones in which there is a coincidence of opposites].
Diametrically opposite phenomena are united in the simplest globule of
protoplasm, and the life of the most undeveloped society…." [Plekhanov (1908),
pp.93-96. Bold emphases alone added.]
"There are two possible ways of regarding
everything in nature and in society; in the eyes of some everything is
constantly at rest, immutable…. To others, however, it appears that there is
nothingunchanging in nature or in society…. This second point of
view is called the dynamic point of view…; the former point of view is
called static. Which is the correct position?... Even a hasty glance
at nature will at once convince us that there is nothingimmutable
about it….
"Evidently…there is nothing
immutableand rigid in theuniverse…. Matter in motion: such
is the stuff of this world…. This dynamic point of view is also called the
dialectic (sic) point of view….
"The world being in constant
motion, we must consider phenomena in their mutual relations, and not as
isolated cases. All portions of the universe are actually related to each
other and exert an influence on each other…. All things in the universe are
connected with an indissoluble bond; nothing exists as an isolated object,
independent of its surroundings….
"In the first place, therefore, the
dialectic (sic) method of interpretation demands that all phenomena be
considered in their indissoluble relations; in the second place, that they be
considered in their state of motion….
"Since everything in the world is in a
state of change, and indissolubly connected with everything else, we
must draw the necessary conclusions for the social sciences….
"The basis of all things is therefore
the law of change, the law of constant motion. Two philosophers
particularly (the ancient Heraclitus and the modern Hegel…) formulated this law
of change, but they did not stop there. They also set up the question of the
manner in which the process operates. The answer they discovered was that
changes are produced by constant internal contradictions, internal struggle.
Thus, Heraclitus declared: 'Conflict is the mother of all happenings,' while
Hegel said: 'Contradiction is the power that moves things.'
"There is no doubt of the correctness of this
law. A moment's thought will convince the reader. For, if there were no
conflict, no clash of forces, the world would be in a condition of unchanging
stable equilibrium, i.e., complete and absolute permanence, a state of rest
precluding all motion…. As we alreadyknow that all things change, all
things are 'in flux', it is certain that such an absolute state of rest
cannot possibly exist. We must therefore reject a condition in which
there is no 'contradiction between opposing and colliding forces' no disturbance
of equilibrium, but only an absolute immutability….
"In other words, theworld consists
of forces, acting many ways, opposing each other. These forces are balanced
for a moment in exceptional cases only. We then have a state of 'rest', i.e.,
their actual 'conflict' is concealed. But if we change only one of these forces,
immediately the 'internal contradictions' will be revealed, equilibrium
will be disturbed, and if a new equilibrium is again established, it will be on
a new basis, i.e., with a new combination of forces, etc. It follows that the 'conflict,'
the 'contradiction,' i.e., the antagonism of forces acting in various
directions, determines the motion of the system…." [Bukharin (1925),
pp.63-67,
72-74. Bold emphases added.]
"[A]ll bodies change uninterruptedly in
size, weight, colour, etc. They are never equal to themselves…. [E]verything
is always changing." [Trotsky (1971), pp.64-65. Bold emphases added.]
As we saw in Essay Eleven Part One, these
comments appear to endorse a maximalist view
of change. If everything, and every property, is in constant flux
-- and that in turn is the result of the countless UOs at work everywhere -- and if everything is "never equal to
itself", the IED ploy can gain no grip. Indeed,
there would seem to be no point in DM-apologists appealing to
Heraclitus's
thesis that it is impossible to step into the same river twice, and that "everything
flows", if some things don't "flow". On this view,
at no time would an
object be equal to itself so that it could truly be said that is was "the same and not
the same". If nothing is ever equal to itself, then concerning any object or process,
it would only ever be true that it was "not the same and not the same". On the
other hand, if it were the case that an object or process was "the same and not
the same", then it wouldn't be true
that it
was "never equal to itself".
In short: it can never truly be said
that anything is a UO in constant flux.
[UO = Unity of Opposites;
IED = Identity in Difference (i.e., 'Improvised Explanatory Device').]
In Essay Six, I argued as follows:
Nevertheless, let us suppose that an object,
B, has the following properties, qualities or relations: B1,
B2,
B3,...,
Bn.
According to several of the above
dialectical worthies, all of these properties, qualities and relations must change
all the time (into what they do not say, but presumably it is into
their 'opposites',
not (B1,
B2,
B3,...,
Bn)
-- or perhaps it is (B1*,
B2*,
B3*,...,
Bn*).
[However that possibility is closed off in
Essays
Seven and Eleven
Part One.]
Nevertheless, even as
B changes it is still
identical with itself. In order to see this, let us suppose that when each
property, Bi,
changes, it becomes Bi*,
in the first instance, and then Bi**
in the next, and so on. But at any moment, B's identity will be given by its
set of properties, qualities or relations (if we must view identity
traditionally). So, in the first case, for example, B will have changed into {B1*,
B2*,
B3*,...,
Bn*}.
But, even though B has changed, it retains its changed identity. Hence, as
long as B exists it is identical to itself (albeit, its changed self). So,
when
viewed this way, identity is no enemy of change.
[Dialecticians often appeal to the existence
of
UOs to defuse this sort of objection;
this topic examined in Essays
Seven and
Eight Parts
One and
Two.]
Of course, the above scenario (which is
called Maximal Heracliteanism (or MAH) in Essay Eleven -- link below)
might not be the option that most dialecticians would want to adopt (even though
the DM-classicists quoted above seem to be sold on it). If so, they should pause
for thought before finally deciding. That is because, if just one of the properties, qualities or relations
B enjoys -- say, Bk --
remains the same even for a few
nanoseconds
then the
LOI must apply to it, and the dialectical game is up -- for here we would have something that remained the
same, and was identical to itself, even if only momentarily.
In contrast, the maximalist option (i.e.,
MAH -- this is explained at the following link) has far worse consequences for DM; these will be spelt-out in detail in Essay Eleven
Part One).
Either way,
Heraclitus is no friend of DM --
or, if he is, he is also its enemy....
Moreover, if everything in the "Totality"
-- or,
indeed,
in each sub-"Totality" -- is what it is because of the "internal relations" it
has with everything else, and which characterise it completely and
essentially, so that
the "entire nature of the part is determined by its relation to other parts and
to the whole", then, if those relations change as it enters a new Sub-"Totality",
or sub-whole, it can't fail to alter. Moreover, the latter aren't minor,
superficial features of no account; they represent
significant and 'essential' changes.
[This might seem to contradict the
conclusions reached in Note 1a
above, but that isn't so. There, the implications of one strand of DM-Wholism
were explored (i.e., those connected with the 'emergence' of novelty) based on
the idea that 'internal' relations remain fixed. Here, the implications of
relaxing that assumption are being examined.]
Hence, if everything is a UO, and isn't
therefore self-identical from moment to moment (if we are to believe the above
DM-theorists), and if the entire nature of every object
or process is altered upon entering a new whole, there doesn't seem to be anything for the IED ploy to latch onto.
[Anyway, DM-theorists might have to abandon
the IED for other reasons; on that,
see here.]
On the other hand, if the IED
ploy
is to gain any sort of grip, several core DM-theses (like those mentioned in the
above quotations) must be defective. Either way, dialectics takes another body blow.
Exception might be taken to this entire way of viewing things, in that it is
manifestly absurd to suppose that wholes don't change when they incorporate new parts.
That is undeniable, but then it just shows how useless this dialectical 'thesis' really is; it
contradicts not just common sense, but other DM-theses. It is a pity, therefore, that DM-theorists reject
common sense, too -- or, at least, beyond everyday "banalities", hold it in
considerable doubt.
5.Some might be tempted to appeal to the process of abstraction
here to neutralise this objection. That would be an unwise move for
reasons explored in Essay Three Parts One and
Two.
The problem is, of course, that if it
isn't
easy to identify (or even distinguish) DM-parts and DM-wholes as they
appear in
'reality', a retreat into the abstract
would be a backward step. That is because abstract parts and abstract wholes are even more
difficult to identify, or distinguish.
Of course, this depends on what is meant by
"abstract" (and by "abstraction"), but we have already seen
that traditional and DM-theorists are
decidedly unclear in this respect. If they both mean by this term something
like a 'mental
construct' (or, 'a concept constructed in the mind'), then the above comment applies all the more.
For example, there would be no way of
deciding whether or not Abstractor, A, had constructed, formed or identified, say, abstract part 3,000,001 in the same way
that
Abstractor, B, had constructed, formed or identified abstract part
3,000,001 -- or if either one or both had confused it with,
say, abstract part 3,000,002, or with something else entirely. Of course, in everyday life such confusions
over the identity of objects can be cleared up relatively easily -- because this
would be done in the open, in a public
domain --, but if all this
philosophical chicanery takes place 'in the
mind', in a hidden, abstract world, where
would one even begin?
The same goes for Wholes, too; how could
Abstractor, A, confirm that he/she had constructed, formed or identified abstract Whole, W,
correctly from
moment to moment (especially in the face of the ever-present Heraclitean Flux
--
which, so we are told, also works on brains, just as it must screw around
with memories, too). Indeed, how could Abstractor, A,
be sure he/she had included, or had left out, the same elements as Abstractor,
B, and had mentally arranged them in the same way? Indeed, how would
they know if they were aiming at the same, or even the 'right', target? In fact, in
such cases, the word "right" could gain no grip. Once more, in the real
world we typically manage to agree over our use of words (having been
socialised to do so when young), but in
the obscure world of 'inner abstractions' and 'representations', how would this be even possible?
Guesswork? Brain probes? 'Mind readers'?
[This, of course, assumes that it makes sense
to 'abstract', say, a Whole into existence to begin with. Since this topic has
been dealt with extensively in
Essay Three Parts One and
Two, the reader is directed there
for more details.
In addition, the idea that there are such things as 'inner representations' was put under
severe pressure in Essay Thirteen Part
Three.]
It could be argued that
these 'difficulties'
aren't fatal to DM. Admittedly, this
'problem' seems paradoxical or contradictory to our ordinary ways of
thinking (in that it requires us to identify parts independently of wholes when
the theory says this can't be done). If part and whole depend so intimately on
each other, we would have to know both before we knew either -- neither of which
would be achievable in advance of the other. But, this simply underlines the
limitations of 'commonsense' and ordinary thought. That is, of
course, why we need the "dialectical method" to advance knowledge, since it isn't stymied by ordinary ways of thinking
about, or looking at, reality.
Or, so a response might
proceed...
At this point,
DM-theorists might be tempted to reach for a useful formula that informs them that dialectics allows such contradictions (or
paradoxes) to be
"grasped" -- which means that both 'contradictory' alternatives can be
accepted as 'correct', or, true,, the conflict mysteriously "resolved" somehow,
by the simple expedient of labelling it 'contradictory'. But, this handy escape route would in this case involve the
idea that DM-Wholism depends on an acceptance of the fact that (i) There is complete inter-determinism between part
and whole and that (ii) Neither part nor whole can be known until
both have been. As we shall see many times over at this site, whenever
dialecticians encounter a 'contradiction' in their own theory, it is casually
'solved' (i.e., waved aside) by the use of the handy "grasp" ploy, or its equivalent -- which
often involves little more than asserting that anyone who rejects this logical
chicanery doesn't "understand" dialectics.
In effect, this means that to "understand" dialectics amounts to
turning a blind eye to contradictions and confusions like these -- or, at least, it
saves dialecticians from having to worry about such
annoying, 'pedantic' details. This is a novel and innovative use of the verb "to understand".
Clearly, human knowledge wouldn't have advanced much beyond the Iron Age had
this strategy been adopted in the past. Consider a few examples: had early
modern astronomers been dialecticians they would presumably have grasped the two
halves of the following 'contradiction', and have accepted them both as true:
the planets move in their orbits attached to crystalline spheres, and they don't.
No one would have taken an astronomer seriously who argued that way, who
"grasped" both of
these as true. Would we lionise Darwin quite so much had he been a DM-fan and
had argued that every species had evolved from a common
ancestor by natural selection even though some of them hadn't? Indeed,
had Marx argued that in Capitalism there is and there isn't a conflict between
the forces and relations of production, would we just shrug our shoulders and
simply "grasp" that conundrum?
In like manner, should we be inclined to try to "understand" a theory whose
supporters argue that the nature of any part can only be comprehended when the
whole of which it is a part
has been understood -- but which
happy day will never actually come to pass
--
while at the same time maintaining
that at least this example of partial knowledge can be trusted, even
though the
whole of which it is allegedly a part remains shrouded in an impenetrably dense
fog (always supposing we could assert that much with any
confidence)?
Nixon
was able to get away with an analogously similar con-trick for a few years (i.e., alleging he had a
'solution' to the Vietnam War, when he hadn't); dialecticians can't expect to be
granted the same latitude. [Follow
this link for an
explanation of the point of that remark.]
[This
topic was discussed in more detail in Essay
Seven
and Part One
of this Essay, where it is connected with what I have called "The Dialecticians'
Dilemma". Some might object that the above is just another caricature of the nature of
'dialectical contradictions', but since DM-fans studiously refuse to tell us
with any clarity what a 'dialectical contradiction' actually is, it will have to
do until they get their act together. I have dealt with that topic at great
length in Essays Eight Parts One,
Two and
Three, and Eleven Part
One; readers
are directed there for more details.]
Even
so, the "grasp" ploy can't work in this case, for no matter how strong their metaphorical
grip happens to be, 'grasping dialecticians' [GDs,
for short] would still be in no position to
specify parts and wholes without at the same time rejecting their own theory -- for to
itemise any part in advance of knowing the whole would be tantamount to
admitting that the entire nature of the part isn't determined by
its relation to the whole. And since knowledge of each part is itself
a part of the whole, the entire nature of any one individual's knowledge of a
given part
should likewise be determined by the whole, and by their knowledge of that
whole. Furthermore, since an infinite amount of knowledge separates humanity
from the hypothesised epistemological end-state --
when alone knowledge of wholes may be expected to emerge -- then, at any point in history, humanity
will be
infinitely ignorant of one or both.
[On this,
see here, where this topic is linked
to something I have called HEX, or "Hegelian Expansionism", the opposite of
"Cartesian Reductionism", CAR.]
This point
was well-made by Michael
Rosen, where he referred to something he called the "post festum
paradox":
"If truth requires a system,
then it only properly exists at the point of completion of the system: what
precedes it is only partial, but not adequate. As critics, however, what should
interest us is how that point of completion is obtained, and whether we
have arrived at it legitimately or not. But, on one obvious interpretation of
the quotations above [see
below, RL], what they say is that, except as we attain
this point of completion, we are not at the standpoint of truth, and that,
therefore, we are not in a position fully to comprehend (and hence to justify or
criticise) the method by which it was reached. In this way we have the paradox:
to criticise Hegel is to claim that the system does not attain validly its point
of completion. But to criticise from any point other than the point of
completion violates crucial presuppositions of the system itself, namely, that
only someone who has really attained its final point can perceive the
rationality of its attainment." [Rosen (1982), pp.23-24. Italic emphasis
in the original.]
Of course, Rosen uses this argument to show
that Marxist critics of Hegel are in a bind; they can't invert his system (so
that it is now set 'the right way up') until the entire process
has reached its final
denouement, for to do so would be to adopt a partial stance
toward it, i.e., an irrational stance. This, Rosen claims, is why Marxists from time to
time are attracted to irrational schemes of thought (in the way that leading
Bolsheviks, say, thought highly of
Nietzsche, among others). [Cf., Rosen (1982)
p.24.] On this, also see
Rosenthal (1997, 2002).
More recently,
dialecticians of various stripes have gone even further;
David Bohm, for instance, was an admirer
of Eastern religion (and
of Uri Geller, as well as much
else besides), and more recently still,
the late
Roy Bhaskar
drifted off into
open mysticism (on this see Bhaskar (2002a, 2002b, 2002c) --, to mention
just a few cases in point. [These examples are, of course, mine, not Rosen's. I
have said more about this in Essays Thirteen
Part Three
and Three Part Two. A detailed
survey of the close link there exists between Daoism and Maoist 'Dialectics' can
now be accessed here.]
Here,
for instance,
is a lay-dialectician who thinks highly of
Daoism (and he
isn't the only one),
although it seems not to have minimised his fondness for scatological language.
Expert logician and fan of 'dialectical logic', Graham Priest, is also a fan of
eastern mysticism (here
is video of him lecturing on the relation between Buddhism and science). This is
another:
Video One: Graham Priest -- This Is
Where An Acceptance Of
Hegelianism Finally Led Him
Here is another nature mystic, who is also a keen DM-fan (an affliction that
seems to affect many Greens and other assorted New Age fans, especially
those influenced by
Michael Kosok,
Murray
Bookchin or
Frijtof
Capra, although none of the latter is a Marxist) -- Bookchin (1996), Capra (1997,
1999, 2003), Kosok (2004). [For a timely corrective, Stenger (1995) is worth
consulting, as is
Stenger's
web page. See also
here.]
Naturally, this also helps account for the
mystical predilections of those whom Lenin criticised in MEC for suspect
intellectual moves like these.
[There is
more on this in Essay Nine Part Two, where
the class origin of the DM-classicists, and the current class position of
'fans-of-the-dialectic', will be exposed as the real reason for this
continual slide into mysticism -- as opposed to their incomplete understanding
of Hegel, that is, of course, because it isn't possible to understand Hegel's Hermetic
and
incoherent non-sense, even partially.]
[MEC = Materialism and
Empirio-Criticism, i.e., Lenin (1972).]
Be this as it may, we can surely go further
ourselves; consider then the following quotation from Hegel (this was one of the
passages to which Rosen was referring
above):
"The truth is the whole.
The whole, however, is merely the essential nature reaching its completeness
through the process of its own development. Of the Absolute it must be said
that it is essentially a result, that only at the end is it what it is in very
truth; and just in that consists its nature, which is to be actual, subject, or
self-becoming, self-development. Should it appear contradictory to say
that the Absolute has to be conceived essentially as a result, a little
consideration will set this appearance of contradiction in its true light. The
beginning, the principle, or the Absolute, as at first or immediately expressed,
is merely the universal. If we say 'all animals', that does not pass for
zoology; for the same reason we see at once that the words absolute, divine,
eternal, and so on do not express what is implied in them; and only mere words
like these, in point of fact, express intuition as the immediate. Whatever is
more than a word like that, even the mere transition to a proposition, is a form
of mediation, contains a process towards another state from which we must return
once more. It is this process of mediation, however, that is rejected with
horror, as if absolute knowledge were being surrendered when more is made of
mediation than merely the assertion that it is nothing absolute, and does not
exist in the Absolute." [Hegel (1977),
p.11; section 20. Bold emphases added. Quotation marks
altered to conform to the conventions adopted at this site.]
Hegel himself half spotted the problem here, but
he simply
brushed it aside as an apparent contradiction. However, if what he
said were true, he himself would require access to the finished system to be able
to advocate it as true. Hence, the truth even
of his claim that what he says
looks contradictory would itself need a completed system to substantiate it.
Short of that, it can't be true -- or, rather, he can't assert its truth.
Indeed, it could be completely false. In fact, given that what it says contradicts its own
content, it can't be true.
Now, anyone who objects to that
comment, or any other, while also accepting this Hegelian formula (i.e.,
that 'the truth is the whole', upside down or the
'right way up') will, of
course, need to climb into a working time machine, fast forward to the end of existence,
and access for us the complete system that confirms that recklessly bold
objection.
It could be argued that Hegel's claims
might be 'partially' true, or 'relatively' true --, but, once more, if these
meta-claims(i.e., that these are indeed 'relative' or 'partial
truths'), are themselves true, we would also need to be standing at the end of
time, on the sunlit uplands of Epistemological Judgement Day, even to be
able to agree with this minimal assertion. In that case -- unless this response has itself been beamed in from the
far distant future
-- it can
safely be ignored.
Of course,
Engels himself had already made a somewhat similar point (in unpublished
preparatory material for Anti-Dühring):
"Systematics impossible after
Hegel. The world clearly constitutes a single system, i.e., a coherent whole,
but the knowledge of this system presupposes a knowledge of all of nature
and history, which man will never attain. Hence he who makes systems must fill
in the countless gaps with figments of his own imagination, i.e., engage
in irrational fancies, ideologise." [Marx and Engels (1987), p.597. Italic
emphases in the original.]
It is a pity, therefore, that Engels didn't
call this to mind when he too began to speculate and fill his work with
"figments" of his own (or rather, Hegel's) imagination. [Many of these
"figments" were exposed in Essays Seven Part One
and Eight Part Three.]
Finally, Rosen himself considers a number of
replies to this paradox that could be advanced (and readers are directed to his book
for more details: Rosen (1982), p.23, et seq.), but we needn't trouble
ourselves with them for long, for if it were possible to find some way of
resolving this 'difficulty', and hence arrive at a true account of Hegel's
thought -- one that rescued it
from self-imposed oblivion --, then, consistent with Hegel's own precepts (not mine),
only
The Elect among
Hegelians, congregated at the end of time, when The Absolute has finally got its
Cosmic Act together, will have access to it.
6. Again, it could be argued that
Rees is merely adverting to our altered view
of reality if and when we adopt this DM-Wholist stance.
Perhaps so,
but if the entire nature of a part is 'determined' by the Whole and by
its relationship with other parts -- which would include, one presumes, any
sub-grouping of matter comprising the base on which the thoughts of anyone who
disagreed was founded, and out of which that disagreement had "emerged"
in the same way
--,
then, paradoxically, the opposite conclusion would also follow. The opposite thought -- that reality isn't
interconnected and the part isn't 'determined' by the Whole in the way DM-theorists allege -- would be equally well-founded.
That is because this contrary idea is also part of the Whole, and so
it must be 'determined' by it, if DM-Wholism is correct. What is more, in like
manner, the opposite of any and all DM-theses would also be determined and
true. Hence, the DM-Whole confirms the valid status
of any and all
refutations of this wacky 'theory'!
And, it is little point objecting that the
Whole can't determine two incompatible conclusions since it would be
contradictory so to do. Clearly, that is because we should expect the contradictory
DM-Whole to do precisely that!
On the other hand, if nature
isn't in fact interconnected, the above contrary view would be correct, anyway.
So, either way: the
idea that nature isn't interconnected (etc.) would have the edge over its
DM-alternative, since it would be
correct under both eventualities: that is, it would be correct when it wasn't
and when it was!
Perhaps this is one paradox DM-theorists might not want to
"grasp" too enthusiastically. Indeed, this is an especially annoying
conundrum in that
it undermines dialecticians' own ability to grasp paradoxes! Continuing the "Nixon"
theme, we might want to say that GDs here have been "Deep Throated".
[Readers who know
the details of the
Watergate
affair will understand that allusion.]
An appeal to
human freedom would be of little help, either; if novelty can enter the picture
here, then the entire nature of the part can't be determined
by the other parts or by the whole. [On that, see Note 1a and Note 3, above.]
7.
I return to this theme in Essay Thirteen
Part One where I
present a much more detailed argument aimed at showing that DM implies human
thought does indeed determine 'Being' -- in order to highlight further the
Idealist implications of DM-interconnectedness. That argument will show that the
'materialist flip' dialecticians say they have inflicted on Hegel's system
did work --
but, alas, it did so far better than even they had imagined,since it
succeeded in flipping his ideas through
a full 360◦, not
the touted 180◦.
8.
And these comments don't just apply to Rees's formulation; they compromise the
ideas of anyone who believes that (a) everything in the "Totality" is
interconnected, and that (ii) the parts determine the whole and the whole determines the
part because of their "internal relations".
This is surely no surprise since it is a
direct consequence of importing concepts from Hegel's Idealist Holism, where
'truth is the whole', etc. Now, in that system, this
Idealist Dogma makes some sort of crazy sense -- these connections and inter-relationships
only seem to 'work' because they are situated in a Mega-Mystical Whole, inter-linked by the 'Mega-Thought'
that develops
because of, and through, them.
However, as should seem plain, we
can see
here yet
again another disastrous consequence of trying on the one hand to 'invert'
Hegel's Mystical System while on the other thinking that its Wholist/Idealist
implications were somehow edited out of the picture.
"One
important point to note, about this approach is that it is by its very nature,
opposed to reductionism. It does not abolish the role of the individual in
favour of the whole….
"The
principle of contradiction is a barrier to reductionism, where linear notions of
causality are not, because two elements that are in contradiction cannot be
dissolved into one another but only overcome by the creation of a synthesis that
is not reducible to either of its constituent elements.
"Furthermore, a dialectical approach is
radically opposed to any form of reductionism because it presupposes that parts
and whole are not reducible to each other. The parts and the whole mutually
condition, or mediate, each other. And a mediated totality cannot form
part of a reductionist philosophy, because by definition, reductionism collapses
one element of a totality into another without taking account of its specific
characteristics." [Rees (1998), pp.5-8.]
This
passage will be examined in more detail in Essay Three Part Three -- where DM-anti-reductionist arguments will be
reduced to their own incoherent parts.
[It
is important to add that this doesn't
commit the present author to any form of reductionism. Both of these options (i.e., DM-'Wholism' and
scientistic-reductionism) are metaphysical theories and as such they are
non-sensical and incoherent. My reasons for asserting this can be found in Essay Twelve
Part One.]
10.
The only way that human beings would be "more" than they used to be would
appear
to be as a group. Hence, it could be maintained that as a group humanity
now has a property that it once lacked -- flight. Of course, human beings as
a group, or as individuals, still can't
fly; clearly, it is the machines they build that do this!
So, humanity itself
still lacks this 'property'.
If it is argued in response that humans can
now do something they couldn't do before (namely, fly through space),
even this isn't entirely correct. Since we now know that the earth rotates on
its axis as it orbits the Sun humanity has in fact been travelling through space for hundreds of
thousands of years. Which means we have been flying for many hundreds of
thousands of years!
Again, it could be maintained that it is only
since the invention of
dirigibles,
balloons and aeroplanes that human beings can do things
at will that in earlier generations they couldn't: i.e., leave the surface of the earth whenever they wanted,
and move about
the planet, sometimes at great speeds, flying to destinations that would have been
unimaginable, say, 500 years ago.
But,
not even this is correct. Human beings have been hurtling off cliffs and tall
buildings for thousands of years. To be sure, the vast majority don't live to
tell the tale, but for a few seconds they manifestly possess the property of
flight (in the sense described above).
Once more,
it could be replied that it is only in aeroplanes (etc.) that they can
leave the surface of the earth at will. Nevertheless, it still seems that
it isn't humanity that has this novel property, but these new artefacts which
have.
Moreover, the properties of these machines are reducible to their parts.
Try taking off without engines made of heat resistant materials;
a chocolate jet engine won't get you very far--
nor will wings made of
butter or cheese.
So, in this case, human beings just hitch a ride, as it were.
If
so, precisely whatis the new property
humanity is supposed to have gained? The ability to hitch new sorts of rides?
Or, the capacity to form queues at check-in desks?
11. When
powered flight was finally achieved by the
Wright
Brothers in December 1903 (or, earlier, by means of the
steam/hot
air
powered machines or balloons of the 1800s -- or even by means of the
gliders and kites mentioned in Note 10,
above), the question is: which novel parts or wholes
emerged as a result? To be sure,
there was a new 'whole' comprising the Kitty Hawk (the name of the
Wright Brothers' flying machine) and its pilot, but it isn't easy to see how the entire
nature of Orville Wright, say, was determined by this new Orville/Kitty Hawk 'whole', or that
the entire nature of the Kitty Hawk was determined by its 'internal relation'
to Orville.
Moreover, when the
first
commercial flights began a few years later, what new wholes or parts
came into existence then? To be sure, new capitalist ventures were set up, but which
is whole and which is part even here?Was this 'capitalist-venture-whole' the workers and the bosses, or the buildings and the legal
documents -- or maybe the lawyers who drafted the contracts, the energy fed in from the outside
that powered the lighting or the heating systems, the
roof on the office building, the waste paper
basket in the corner of the room, the
air circulating in and through the building, the natural 'forces' holding
everything together...?
And, are any of these items
also parts? Or,
are the parts the
passengers, the freight, the paint on the aeroplane's fuselage, the rubber
molecules in its tyres, the fuel in its tanks, the countless billions of dead
sea creatures that went into forming that fuel millions of years ago...?
So many questions, so few answers...
In fact, and in general, as we have repeatedly
seen, the precise nature of
DM-wholes and DM-parts is terminally obscure. Consider several possible alternatives:
(1) Dialecticians
sometimes offer molecules as examples of wholes (see below, as well as
Woods and Grant (1995), p.7), but no single molecule is an isolated unit in
nature (as DM-fans are themselves quick to remind us). They all share energy and 'particles' with one another, all the time (so
we are told). If so, what is the whole
here?
One molecule, two, ten million? And what, for
that matter, is a part? [No pun intended.] The sub-atomic particles or the
probability waves/perturbations in 'the field' (which Physicists tell us is what
these 'particles'/'non-particles' really are), or a combination of one or more of
these factors? But, these 'particles' are notorious for not staying put, continually interacting and merging with one another. And, according to DM-fans, all of these are interconnected with everything else
in the entire universe (and, also according to many of them, this isn't an accidental connection, either -- all
are inter-linked by those mysterious "internal
relations"), or, at the very least, they are interconnected with other
'particles' in the vicinity (if we concentrate, say, on those no-less
obscure "external relations" for the moment). What then is the boundary between
part and part, whole and whole, part and whole, in this dialectical menagerie? If there isn't
one, can they be counted as physical
parts and
wholes, in the first place?
To be sure, there are
many different
types of parts
--, for example, part of a play, part of a song, part of a cake, part of a problem, part of a
fight, part of a plan, part of an animal, part of a criminal conspiracy, part of
a strike, part of a dossier that told lies about WMD [Weapons of Mass
Destruction] in Iraq, and so on. These aren't all physically comparable; but, in the material
world it must be possible to discriminate among parts to be able to say that
they are indeed parts, in order to identify them over time, or even count them.
On the other hand, if it isn't possible to
do this, even in thought -- as seems to be the case in this part of DM
(no pun intended, again) --, then key elements
in this theory become far too vague and obscure to be of any use.
Admittedly, we have already seen one or two DM-theorists tell us something like
the following:
"The categories of whole and
part are relative; they have meaning only in relation to each other. The whole
exists thanks to its parts and in them. The parts, in their turn, cannot exist
by themselves. No matter how small a particle we name, it is something whole and
at the same time a part of another whole. The largest whole that we can conceive
of is ultimately only a part of an infinitely greater whole. Everything in
nature is a part of the universe." [Spirkin (1983),
pp.99-100.]
However, we have also seen that this sort of response only succeeds in
sinking this part of DM even further in the mire (no pun intended, again). We have
already had occasion to examine Hegel's odd idea that 'the truth is the whole':
"The truth is the whole.
The whole, however, is merely the essential nature reaching its completeness
through the process of its own development. Of the Absolute it must be said
that it is essentially a result, that only at the end is it what it is in very
truth; and just in that consists its nature, which is to be actual, subject, or
self-becoming, self-development. Should it appear contradictory to say
that the Absolute has to be conceived essentially as a result, a little
consideration will set this appearance of contradiction in its true light. The
beginning, the principle, or the Absolute, as at first or immediately expressed,
is merely the universal. If we say 'all animals', that does not pass for
zoology; for the same reason we see at once that the words absolute, divine,
eternal, and so on do not express what is implied in them; and only mere words
like these, in point of fact, express intuition as the immediate. Whatever is
more than a word like that, even the mere transition to a proposition, is a form
of mediation, contains a process towards another state from which we must return
once more. It is this process of mediation, however, that is rejected with
horror, as if absolute knowledge were being surrendered when more is made of
mediation than merely the assertion that it is nothing absolute, and does not
exist in the Absolute." [Hegel (1977),
p.11; section 20. Bold emphases added. Quotation marks
altered to conform to the conventions adopted at this site.]
The implications of this for DM are quite
disastrous, since this dogma implies that we will only know what constitutes
part, or what constitutes whole, when the Mega-Whole is finally known, and that
will only take place at the end of an infinite asymptotic DM-meander:
"'Fundamentally, we can know only the
infinite.' In fact all real exhaustive knowledge consists solely in raising
the individual thing in thought from individuality into particularity and from
this into universality, in seeking and establishing the infinite in the finite,
the eternal in the transitory…. All true knowledge of nature is knowledge of the
eternal, the infinite, and essentially absolute…. The cognition of the
infinite…can only take place in an infinite asymptotic progress." [Engels
(1954),
pp.234-35.
Italic emphasis in the original; bold emphasis added;
paragraphs merged.]
"Cognition is the eternal, endless approximation
of thought to the object." [Lenin (1961),
p.195.]
"A tumbler is assuredly both a glass cylinder and
a drinking vessel. But there are more than these two properties and qualities or
facets to it; there are an infinite number of them, an infinite number of
'mediacies' and inter-relationships with the rest of the world." [Lenin
(1921),
pp.92-93.]
"Dialectics requires an all-round
consideration of relationships in their concrete development…. Dialectical logic
demands that we go further…. [It] requires that an object should
be taken in development, in 'self-movement' (as Hegel sometimes puts it)…."
[Ibid., p.90. Bold emphases
alone added.]
This view wasn't just limited to the DM-classicists,
either; here,
for example, is Henri
Wald:
"A 'concrete' truth is a logical system of
abstractions multilaterally reflecting the real concrete. One truth is more
concrete than another to the extent to which it reflects more essential traits
of the investigated object. Concrete truth like absolute truth,
can only be reached asymptotically ad infinitum." [Wald (1975), p.35.
Quotation marks altered to conform to the conventions adopted at this site.
Italic emphases in the original.]
If this is indeed the case, it means that at any point in human
history, the gap between each and every DM-assertion, proposition or thesis is
infinitely large, meaning that there is an infinite probability that they are
all
false -- or, alternatively, there is a vanishingly small probability they are true.
And that includes the assertion that "the
categories of whole and part are relative." Moreover, incipient DM-scepticism**
like this threatens to spill over into our ability to tell part from part, and
part from whole, which in turn means that it will only be possible to decide which is
part and which is whole when humanity reaches Epistemological Valhalla
infinitely far in the future.
[**As was
shown
in Essay Ten Part
One, DM-Wholism soon collapses into extreme scepticism.]
A
couple of points made earlier are worth repeating (slightly edited):
Now, anyone who objects to
these
comments, or to any other, while also accepting this Hegelian formula (i.e.,
that 'the truth is the whole', upside down or the
'right way up') will, of
course, need to climb into a working time machine, fast forward to the end of existence,
and access for us the complete system that confirms that recklessly bold
response.
It could be argued that Hegel's claims
might be 'partially' true, or 'relatively' true --, but, once more, if these
meta-claims are themselves true, we would also need to be standing at the end of
time, on the sunlit uplands of Epistemological Judgement Day, even to be able to agree with
this minimal assertion. In that case -- unless this response has itself been beamed in from the distant future
-- it can
be safely ignored.
(2)
Other
DM-theorists
refer us to organisms as excellent examples of part/whole ensembles. But, once
more, what is part and what is whole here? [On that see, the previous point.]
Again, as dialecticians are
quick to remind us, nothing in reality stands in splendid isolation. Now, if that
is true, it is difficult to see how it would be possible to identify, or
even distinguish,
the alleged members of
either category. For example, is a whole an identifiable organism
--, say, a cat --, or is it something else? But cats are continually exchanging matter
and energy with their environment. Only if we freeze frame a targeted
moggie would it be possible to stop annoying seepage like this at its recklessly
porous feline boundary. But, such an un-dialectical mammal, it seems,
would be of
little use to dialectical Whole-Seekers. So, this can't be the Cat-Whole we seek.
But then, what is it?
Does this cat -- which is, according to Physicists, a four-dimensional manifold, a
sort of furry, mathematical 'sausage' stretched out in
4-space -- comprise all its temporal
parts (even if we could identify them), or only those freeze-framed at some
arbitrary point in time?
Do DM-objects (parts
and/or wholes)
endure in
time, or do they simply
perdure?
[Readers
keen to find out more about the arcane intricacies of this branch of modern
Ontology
can download this
PDF to find out more (this article is in fact Hales and Johnson (2003).)
See also Sider (2001), Hawley (2004), and
Hawley (2015).
While I reject this entire approach to Philosophy (for reasons explored in Essay Twelve
Part One), it is incomparably
clearer and vastly superior to the trivial, confused and superficial ramblings one finds in
books and articles that try to sell us DM-Wholism -- Spirkin's book (partially)
excepted -- as if it were cutting edge science.]
Of course, the same problems afflict that hapless cat's parts, too. In which
case, a cat's tail, for instance, is not only extended in
3-space,
it is also a manifold of a 'tail' in 4-space (intermixed and intermingled with other manifolds --
e.g., of mice, birds, balls of fur, the contents of tins of
cat food, and the like -- intersecting with its 'world
line'), if modern Physics is to be believed. This non-dialectical,
ontologically-complex set of moggie parts is, one suspects, no friend of DM. Indeed, we saw
in Part One
of this Essay (and in Essay Seven Parts
Oneand
Three) how this quintessentially reactionary mammal has helped demolish several
long-cherished DM-theses
all on its own. A catabolic
process if ever there was one.
Dialecticians who
might be tempted to respond
impatiently to all this along the lines that the above aren't legitimate
objections to their theory in view of the fact they themselves admit the
existence of just such dynamic and interconnected parts and wholes (for example,
cats in relation to their environment), should themselves pause for a moment
before pushing that point too far. Unless they are careful, and agree to
freeze-frame things once more, this unfortunate cat might wind up being a
part that is, say, several miles wide as it dynamically interacts with its environment over several years.
And if we change the example, we could easily end up
with, for instance, 'whale parts' that are tens of thousands of miles across,
and many hundreds of metres deep, as they patrol, say,
the Pacific Ocean. That is to say nothing of the real
size of this dialectical whale-whole if we throw in the motion of the Earth
around the Sun, and then its transit through the Galaxy.
Figure Seven: Only A Tiny Part Of This
Whale-Part?
Or, Is It The Whole
Whale?
In fact,
and worse still, it isn't easy to see how dialecticians can prevent this
(or the earlier furry) mammal expanding catastrophically (and about as quickly
as
HEX did)
to encompass the entire universe, if this
'part'
is allowed to include all that it interacts with and all to
which it is
"internally related". This
Cheshire Cat In Reverse
is, indeed,
a sort of metaphysical time bomb purring away at the centre of this ramshackle
'theory'.
(3)
Now the whole point of
DM-Holism (no pun intended, once more) was to provide an account of capitalism so
it might be replaced by socialism. To that end, for example, dialecticians view capitalism as a
whole, and various classes as sub-wholes, too -- or even as parts.
But, once more, what is
whole and what is
part, here? Even if we were to wave aside the insurmountable 4-space
difficulties noted above (when DM is confronted with modern Physics), as well as
the 'asymptotic black hole' we discovered in point (1)
above, this isn't an easy question to answer. So, is the entire capitalist class
a whole, or a part --, or is it part part, or part whole? Is a
single proletarian a part, a whole, or wholly part or partly whole?
Anyone who
rashly thinks that my highlighting these
'difficulties' will
make the slightest impression on the adamantine skulls of the DM-fraternity (even if
the latter could be bothered to read any of this!) knows
nothing of their capacity to develop
hysterical blindness when it
suits them. [In fact, in Essay Nine Part Two,
it will be shown that this neat DM-trick is just another form of "cognitive dissonance".]
Determined as they are to remain super-glued to these obscure, pre-scientific, mystical
nostrums
-- come
what may --, DM-fans soon reach for the "pedantry"
button, and press it maniacally, backed up, or not, by a liberal use of the 'sophistry'
raspberry, and the 'special-pleading' smoke bomb -- along the lines, perhaps, that
dialectics is "different", and so it can't be expected to be judged by the normal
cannons of scientific reasoning, a ploy genuine 'god'-botherers are also rather
fond of using -- on that, see here.
Clearly, benighted DM-critics (like yours truly, RL) have failed to notice that when
Lenin said that no science is complete or un-revisable, he meant to exclude
DM.
"Dialectical materialism
insists on the approximate, relative character of every scientific theory of the
structure of matter and its properties...". [Lenin (1972),
p.312.]
Which idea was underlined by Engels himself:
"Just as the bourgeoisie by large-scale industry,
competition, and the world market dissolves in practice all stable time-honoured
institutions, so this dialectical philosophy dissolves all conceptions of
final, absolute truth and of absolute states of humanity corresponding to it.
For it [dialectical philosophy], nothing is final, absolute, sacred. It reveals
the transitory character of everything and in everything; nothing can endure
before it except the uninterrupted process of becoming and of passing away, of
endless ascendancy from the lower to the higher. And dialectical philosophy
itself is nothing more than the mere reflection of this process in the thinking
brain. It has, of course, also a conservative side; it recognizes that definite
stages of knowledge and society are justified for their time and circumstances;
but only so far. The conservatism of this mode of outlook is relative; its
revolutionary character is absolute -- the only absolute dialectical philosophy
admits." [Engels (1888),
p.588. Bold emphasis added; spelling modified to conform with UK English.]
Except that, even though "dialectical philosophy dissolves all conceptions of
final, absolute truth...", it is nevertheless absolute truth itself
since its supporters will brook no criticism of it, howsoever mild that is, or
howsoever nuanced it happens to be.
Now
that this has been made clear, we will surely witness DM-fans in thrall
to these mystical mantras, secure in the belief that no advance in human
knowledge can, or will ever, disturb their dogmatic slumber.
However, Trotsky torpedoed that theological approach to knowledge:
"Dialectic materialism is not of course an eternal
and immutable philosophy. To think otherwise is to contradict the spirit of the
dialectic." [Trotsky (1971),
pp.96-97. Bold emphasis added.]
Nevertheless,
as we have also seen
"dialectical philosophy [doesn't in fact] dissolve all conceptions of final,
absolute truth...", after all, and stands in permanent proof of it own
fallibility as a result!
Yet another ironic dialectical inversion
for readers to ponder.
12.
It could be argued that these objections
ignore the distinctions dialecticians make between different kinds of parts and
different kinds of wholes.
On this, see Note 14, below, and Note 11 above.
13.This entire topic
raises issues connected with the nature of 'part properties' that are dependent
on, or arise out of 'whole properties'. Plainly, I can't
enter into the finer details of this topic here. Fans of this branch of
Ontology (i.e.,
Mereology) might like to consult Goodman (1966),
Casati
(2016), Casati and Varzi (1999), and Simons (1987) -- or the more introductory,
Hoffman and Rosenkrantz (1997), pp.43-149, for more details. In such work,
admixed with some rather annoying and unnecessary Metaphysics, there is much
valuable logical insight; that is especially true of Simons (1987).
It could be objected that the points made in
this Essay are entirely bogus because they ignore the different types of
wholes and parts envisaged by DM-theorists. We might call this "Spirkin's Defence" [henceforth SD], after the analysis given in Spirkin
(1983), quoted earlier.
Spirkin argues as follows:
"A system is an internally
organised whole where elements are so intimately connected that they operate as
one in relation to external conditions and other systems. An element may be
defined as the minimal unit performing a definite function in the whole. Systems
may be either simple or complex. A complex system is one whose elements may also
be regarded as systems or subsystems....
"The categories of whole and
part are relative; they have meaning only in relation to each other. The whole
exists thanks to its parts and in them. The parts, in their turn, cannot exist
by themselves. No matter how small a particle we name, it is something whole and
at the same time a part of another whole. The largest whole that we can conceive
of is ultimately only a part of an infinitely greater whole. Everything in
nature is a part of the universe.
"Various systems are divided
into three basic types of wholeness. The simplest type is the unorganised or
summative whole, an unsystematic conglomeration of objects (a herd of cattle,
for example). This category also includes a mechanical grouping of heterogeneous
things, for example, rock consisting of pebbles, sand, gravel, boulders, and so
on.
"In such a whole the
connection between the parts is external and obeys no recognisable law. We
simply have a group of unsystematic formations of a purely summative character.
The properties of such a whole coincide with the sum of the properties of its
component parts. Moreover, when objects become part of an unorganised whole or
leave such a whole, they usually undergo no qualitative change. For this type of
whole the characteristic feature is the varying lifetime of its components.
"The second, more complex
type of whole is the organised whole, for example, the atom, the molecule, the
crystal. Such a whole may have varying degrees of organisation, depending on the
peculiar features of its parts and the character of the connection between them.
In an organised whole the composing elements are in a relatively stable and
law-governed interrelationship. Its properties cannot be reduced to the
mechanical sum of the properties of its parts. Rivers 'lose themselves' in the
sea, although they are in it and it would not exist without them. Water
possesses the property of being able to extinguish fire, but the parts of which
it is composed, taken separately, possess quite different properties: hydrogen
is itself flammable and oxygen maintains or boosts combustion. Zero in itself is
nothing, but in the composition of a number its role is highly significant, and
at times gigantically so, by increasing 100 into 1,000, for instance. A hydrogen
atom consists of a proton and an electron. But strictly speaking, this is not
true. The statement contains the same error as the phrase 'this house is built
of pine'. The mass of an atom of hydrogen is not equal to the total mass of the
proton and the electron. It is less than that mass because in combining into the
system of the hydrogen atom the proton and the electron lose something, which
escapes into space in the form of radiation.
"The third, highest and most
complex type of whole is the organic whole, for example, the organism, the
biological species, society, science, arts, language, and so on. The
characteristic feature of the organic whole is the self-development and
self-reproduction of its parts. The parts of an organism if separated from the
whole organism, not only lose some of their properties but cannot even exist in
the given quality that they have within the whole. The head is only a head
because it is capable of thinking. And it can only think as a part not only of
the organism, but also of society, history and culture.
"An organic whole is formed
not (as
Empedocles
assumed) by joining together ready-made parts, separate
organs flying around in the air, such as heads, eyes, ears, hands, legs, hair
and hearts. An organic whole arises, is born, and dies together with its parts.
It is an integral whole, with distinguishable parts. Sensations, perceptions,
representations, concepts, memory, attention do not exist in isolation; they
form the synthetic knot which we call consciousness. The elements that make up
the whole possess a certain individuality and at the same time they 'work for'
the whole. The whole is invisibly present, as it were, and guides the process of
'assembly' of its elements, that is to say, of its own self....
"The parts of a whole may
have varying degrees of relative independence. In a whole, there may be parts
whose excision will damage or even destroy the whole, but there may also be
parts whose loss causes no organic damage. For instance, the extremities or a
part of the stomach may be removed, but not the heart. The deeper and more
complex the relationship between the parts, the greater is the function of the
whole in relation to them and the less their relative independence....
"The highest form of organic
whole is society and the various social formations. The general laws of the
social whole determine the essence of any of its parts and the direction of its
development: the part behaves in accordance with the essence of the whole."
[Spirkin (1983), pp.97-102.]
There are a number important points that
can be distilled from the above analysis:
(1) Systems are organised
entities. They are distinct from their environment, and are minimal units
capable of performing definite functions inside the wider whole. What may be
whole from one point of view, is part from another, and vice versa.
(2) The universe is the
largest whole and contains every system.
(3) There are three types of
system:
(a) The first sort includes summative and
unorganised systems; for example a herd of cattle, a rock, a pile of sand, etc. In such
systems, the connection between the parts is external and obeys no set law. The
whole here is merely a sum of its parts. Objects do not change qualitatively if
they either leave or join such systems.
(b)
The second comprises what seem to be minimally organised wholes (e.g., atoms, molecules or crystals). Here, not only are the elements related to
one another in a law-like manner, the whole is more than the sum of the parts.
Moreover, as parts of the whole:
(i) the elements gain properties, or,
(ii) the whole
severally or collectively acquires them.
These
are properties that one or both wouldn't have had on their own. So, for example, Hydrogen and Oxygen can't put fires out, but combined
to form water they can.
(c) The third type
includes the most complex
systems, organic wholes (examples include the wolf, the genus Canis,
society, language, etc.). Elements of these systems lose some of their
properties when separated from the whole, and can't exist apart from that whole. This type
of whole
is more than the sum of its parts, too. However, some parts can enjoy relative separation from
the whole, but this isn't true of all. Capitalism, it seems, is just such a whole.
Hence, it could be argued that the
analysis presented in this Essay has recklessly conflated these three distinct types of system,
which means it is entirely misconceived.
In response it is worth underlining several points
(in addition to those that have already been made):
(1)
The distinction between these three types of system isn't as clear-cut as Spirkin would have us believe.
Even in a heap of sand there are forces at
work that are law-governed (or, which we can certainly depict that way, at least), and even in an organism there are parts that are
heterogeneous (think of bacteria in the gut, hair on a body, dead skin cells the
surface, etc.), which an organism can lose without it itself altering as a
result, and which parts don't alter when they are lost, either.
Furthermore, it is worth asking
the following question: Is a heap of sand still a
heap if it loses all (or even the vast majority of) its parts? In that case, these parts and that whole
are
intimately linked. And heaps of sand (on beaches or in deserts) don't
accumulate without cause. There are
physical forces at work which explain (or can be used to explain) why they are where they are,
and why they take the shape they have. In addition, ants, termites, bees,
wasps, bats, birds, cattle, bison and other
herbivores congregate in colonies, shoals, flocks, swarms and
herds for
well-known evolutionary
reasons; so they aren't 'accidental' conglomerations, either. [On this, see for example, Williams (1966).
For other collective nouns, see
here.]
Moreover, the 'internal
relations' to which DM-theorists also appeal imply that everything in
reality is part of One Big Whole. Naturally, this doesn't just
blur the distinctions Spirkin tries to draw, it obliterates them -- or, it will
do so
unless and until DM-theorists themselves decide what they mean by these
'internal relations' and those 'interconnections'. [On this, see Note 1a.]
Of course, it could be argued alongside
Spirkin that in loose conglomerates (like heaps, swarms and herds), elements
are only externally-related. But what makes a herd a herd, or a cow in a herd a
cow in a herd, aren't external relations, whatever else they happen to be.
A herd of cows wouldn't be a herd of cows if there were no cows in it, or if
they had all been replaced by antelopes. Moreover, given
the truth of DM, what makes a grain of sand what it is (that is, whatever it is
that 'determines' its nature and properties), is "internally-connected" to
something or other, for if that weren't so,
sand wouldn't be sand and it couldn't change -- if, that is, change is
motivated by
dialectical "internal relations" between an object or process and its
dialectical "other" (as
Hegel puts it). [On that, see
here.]
Again, it could be countered that even if this were so, the grains in a heap
aren't "internally-linked" to one another.
But, how are we to account for each individual grain changing from being an
isolated grain to being a gregarious grain in a heap? If Hegel is correct, and things
change only because of their "internally-linked" 'others', then whatever
produces a heap of sand must be governed by the 'Laws' of dialectics. But, until this heap changes
into --, one presumes --, "not a heap" (its 'other'?), it must be in dialectical
tension with that 'other' now (or maybe this is some other 'other'?), or it, too, will
never change.
After all, there is only one DM-principle available to dialecticians that
'enables'
them to explain change -- these 'others' and their inter-relation.
This means that if (in a heap) a
particular grain (say, Gi)
is resting next to at least one other grain (say, Gk),
and it remains next to it, then it must be in dialectical tension with this other
'other', which, in this case, must be "not-next-to-Gk"
(and thus "not-not-next-to-Gk")
--,
one supposes, again --,
so that one day it might indeed change into not being next to Gk
-- otherwise, that specific change won't have been be 'internally'-generated, as had been
claimed). In short, each DM-grain must be implicated in some sort of "internal
relation" with each local grain (or is it with each not-local grain?); by a suitable induction,
it must be implicated in some sort of "internal relation" with all the
grains in that heap. Hence, there would be a set of "internal relations" even in
a heap -- that is, if they change
in the way DM-theorists suppose.
And what goes for heaps, goes for herds,
swarms, shoals, flocks and colonies, too.
Naturally, the above observations can be
neutralised quite easily by
abandoning Hegel's whacky 'theory' of change -- upside down or 'the right way
up'.
But in that case, dialecticians would, of
course, be
left with no theory of change.
(2)
Although Spirkin sort of half concedes that the picture he drew isn't as clear-cut as he would like, he
failed to notice that this 'semi-admission' (if such it be) seriously affects the status of many of the
examples he considered.
Consider a species like
Canis lupus(The Grey Wolf);
not only would the genus to which it belongs (Canis)
not be affected if this species died out, the family Canidae
wouldn't, either -- nor would the species
itself be affected if several wolves died. And more-or-less the same can be said
of other social wholes -- animal or human. Hence, human society isn't really affected if, say, few individuals
went off to live
on the Moon. Nor are astronauts altered as human beings when they blast
off into space,
either.
(3) Concerning the most plausible example
Spirkin
cites (that of an organism), as we have seen above
and will see
later, things aren't quite so
straight-forward, even here. Hearts remain hearts while they are being
transplanted, as do other organs, and so do blood and skin. In fact, there
doesn't to seem to be a single part of a human body -- except perhaps the
CNS, but even that
might not always be so -- about which this isn't true. Even
something as significant as a
head
can exist on its own for some time away from its original torso, given the right
technological support.
As we
will see, such wholes aren't as they were
imagined to be by the
Natürphilosophers (from whom Hegel and Spirkin pinched these ideas), or even as
they had been conceived by ancient mystics (from whom all three lifted these
Wholist nostrums).
Body parts (etc.) are
causally linked to one another -- which explains why they can be
separated and can be maintained alive if the right causal substitutes are
found for the relevant inputs. Hence, as such, these connections aren't an expression
of "internal relations"
(a notion which is, as we shall see in Essay Four Part Two, another Idealist
fantasy). If they were, there would be no such thing as transplant
surgery, blood transfusions or cloning.
Indeed, in January 2007, we
read this from the
BBC:
"UK scientists planning to
mix human and animal cells in order to research cures for degenerative diseases
fear their work will be halted....
Ministers proposed outlawing such work after unfavourable
public opinion. PM Tony Blair said any new law would have 'flexibility'
to support scientific research that helped people. He said there were 'difficult' issues surrounding
creating the embryos, which are more than 99% human but have a small animal
component....The creation of hybrid human-animal embryos was first
suggested as a way of addressing the shortage of human eggs available for
research." [Quoted from
here.
Quotation marks altered to conform to the conventions adopted at this site;
paragraphs merged.]
Naturally, had
Tony Blair stopped and asked DM-fans for
advice, he could have ruled this project out much earlier -- and on sound
DL-lines, too
-- as a
non-starter, thus saving much time and money as a result.
Nevertheless, as will soon become apparent, the postulation of "internal
relations" is little more than a 'God
of the Gaps' approach to biological science, and as such
supervenes on our
ignorance of the entire set of material causes operating in nature. In that case,
that postulate is
dependent on our not knowing allthe material causes at work in, or
operating on,
organisms. DM-fans have simply re-labelled these gaps in our knowledge
"internal relations" (and as a result have introduced the difficulties
noted earlier). Hence, it is no surprise to find that this mystical concept has gone the same way as
its analogous exemplar from theology -- the genuine "God of the Gaps". Because of scientific advance, we are now able to
view such wholes in an entirely new and more consistently materialist
light. [On this, also see points (4), (5) and (7), below.]
Artificial limbs, replacement hearts,
pacemakers, skin and corneal grafts, dialysis, blood and bone marrow
transfusions, wigs, hearing aids, glasses, and the like, would all be non-starters
otherwise.
"The
essential conflict between essentialism and reductive materialism is between
their respective ontologies. Reductive materialism believes in an ontology of
simples, of basic building-blocks lacking complexity, and further believes
everything else is reducible to them. Essentialism, on the other hand, admits
into its ontology what I have referred to up to now as 'organic wholes' or
'entities', and does not consider them to be reducible but rather irreducible."
[Meikle (1985), p.154.]
[I will examine Meikle's
theory in a later re-write of this Essay. Anyway, it is merely a variant of
other theories I have already examined.]
[Cf., Behe (2004, 2006), Behe's book, by the way,
is taken apart in
Orr (1997),
and
Shanks (2004); see also
here. Cf., Brockman (2006), Dembski and Ruse (2004), Forrest and Gross (2004), Foster,
Clark and York (2008), Pennock (2000, 2001),
Sober
(1999) (this links to a PDF), and Young and Edis (2006). However, for a
corrective view, parts of which are more in line with the argument
developed in Essay Thirteen Parts Two and
Three, see Fuller (2008). Be this
as it may, in what follows, I am not adopting a view of the alleged parallels
between ID and DM, since DM is far to vague to for such an opinion to feel
secure,
as the Essays published at this site clearly demonstrate. Nevertheless, in order
for them to 'work' both systems of thought (and,
surprisingly, several interpretations of modern science, too) rely on a systematic anthropomorphisation of
nature. Those serious allegations will be
substantiated in Essays Thirteen Parts
One, Two and
Three.]
According to ID-ers, aspects of
organic wholes are so constituted that they can't be reduced to their
parts without fundamental features of their 'design' being lost or destroyed --
for instance, the flagellum
of certain bacteria, the human eye, and blood clotting factors -- just to take three of their favourite examples.
As noted above, they call this "irreducible complexity", which has been characterised
by Behe in the following way:
"The main difficulty for
Darwinian mechanisms...that many systems in the cell are what I termed
'irreducibly complex.' I defined an irreducibly complex system as: a single
system that is necessarily composed of several well-matched, interacting parts
that contribute to the basic function, and where the removal of any one of the
parts causes the system to effectively cease functioning." [Behe (2004), p.353.
Quotation marks altered to conform to the conventions adopted at this site.]
Which
view is virtually
indistinguishable from this comment of Spirkin's:
"A system is an
internally organised whole where elements are so intimately connected that they
operate as one in relation to external conditions and other systems. An element
may be defined as the minimal unit performing a definite function in the
whole....
"The third, highest and most
complex type of whole is the organic whole, for example, the organism, the
biological species, society, science, arts, language, and so on. The
characteristic feature of the organic whole is the self-development and
self-reproduction of its parts. The parts of an organism if separated from the
whole organism, not only lose some of their properties but cannot even exist in
the given quality that they have within the whole...." [Spirkin (1983), pp.97,
101. Bold emphasis added.]
However, this
is a 'wedge
strategy' [Forrest and Gross (2004)] directed
against Darwinism and in favour of belief in "God" (although, for legal reasons
connected with the US constitution, ID-ers don't use that particular description). So,
the idea is that organisms are "irreducibly complex" and therefore can't have evolved by
a process of random variation, gene mutation and natural selection -- even
though, as
some of them concede, these natural processes might induce
micro-evolutionary change.
Consequently,
opponents of ID have targeted
"irreducible complexity" for concerted criticism, and in so doing they have
(inadvertently)
undermined many of the points upon which Spirkin and other DM-Wholists rely;
indeed, it isn't easy to see how
DM-theorists can
account for evolution with the sort of analysis they peddle.
As far as I know, Inconsistent Dialecticians
(who, quite fortuitously, can also be labelled ID-ers) haven't
considered this fatal defect in their theory. That is possibly because ID (the
quasi-theological version, not the dialectical mutant, which I will henceforth
label ID(T) to save confusion) is a relatively new phenomenon. Even so,
ID(T)
is based on the now defunct 'Design
Argument' for the existence of 'God', invented thousands of years ago, which
in turn depends on ideas that share uncomfortably close similarities with
DM-Wholism. Hence, the novelty of ID(T) isn't in fact a good explanation of why Inconsistent Dialecticians
[henceforth ID(D)-ers] have ignored these compromising implications of their theory. As was pointed out
here, this
is probably because ID(D)-ers devote little (original) thought to DM; and that
in turn is because (a) DM works
primarily as a test of orthodoxy, and, like other dogmas, it can't be
altered, elaborated upon or even clarified,
without (b) Anyone foolish enough even attempting to do so being called a
"Revisionist!" and cast into outer darkness (or worse) as a result).
[On the ancient,
mystical origins of the 'Design Argument', see Sedley (2007), and Sorabji
(1983).]
Nevertheless, the kind of analysis Spirkin and other DM-theorists have concocted
(or, rather, have imported from German Mysticism) has only succeeded in
re-introducing teleology into science, which undoes much of what
many thought Darwin had achieved -- i.e., ridding science of teleology.
Naturally, these are highly controversial
allegations, since dialecticians, following Marx and Engels, hold
Darwin's theory in such high esteem, and clearly to think that DM is a logical
extension to Darwin's theory. [However, it is worth adding that Marx and Engels
held serious reservations about
Darwinism. On that, see Essay Thirteen
Part Three.]
But, it is difficult to detect much
difference between the ID(T)-idea that there are 'irreducible' complexities in
nature and the ID(D)-claim that there are "emergent
properties" that aren't reducible to their parts. [On this, see below.]
(5) Dialecticians appeal to the sorts of points
advanced by Spirkin in their argument against "reductionism", referring to
"emergent properties" that are unique to wholes, and which can't be derived
from their parts. As we will see in Essay Three Part Three, this is another
seriously
flawed doctrine. Suffice it to say here that this is a secular version
of the "God of the Gaps" argument; in the
present case, we might call it the "Totality of the
Gaps" argument [or TOGA].
Hence, the assumed fact (if
it is one) that we can't
at present reduce
DM-wholes to their parts is then used to argue that it is logically
impossible to do so.
Hence,
from scientific ignorance we somehow get DM-necessity.
In that case, a gap in our knowledge is all that
underpins already shaky TOGA.
But, what if such parts have among their
as-yet-to-be-discovered properties just those qualities Holists now deny them on
an a
priori basis? What if, say, it is a property of Hydrogen and a property of
Oxygen that when combined they form water, which is liquid at certain
temperatures, and can put fires out because of the properties inherent in the
parts? In that case, the whole would be a sum of the parts, and no more.
These two elements certainly combine
according to what scientists call a "law"; no one supposes this 'law' is
accidental or capricious, or that the new set of properties which arise
isn't a consequence of the properties inherent in these two elements.
Even DM-fans would be reluctant to conclude that this 'law', or these properties, 'descend from the skies',
as it were.
No one supposes that the properties of water are simply 'sports of nature',
which aren't related to the properties of their constituent atoms in a 'law'-like
manner, and thus aren't connected with the atomic structure of Oxygen and
Hydrogen.
After all, if this weren't the case, any two elements would do just as well! On this
(presumed) view, CO2
and NH3
(Carbon Dioxide and Ammonia)
would behave exactly like water!
So,
if these 'emergent' properties aren't to be regarded
as merely coincidental by-products of these two elements, as 'caprices of
nature', which just so happen to arise 'out of the blue' when combined, as it
were, then scientists will rightly look for 'laws'
that account for the 'higher order' qualities of water, or whatever, which explain how they
can
be derived from the properties of their parts.
Now,
as I noted earlier, I take no view on this matter
(especially given my other comments about the status of 'natural laws' found
elsewhere at this site, which explains the 'sacre quotes' used above), but one certainly can't impose a priori TOGA-type restrictions on science
-- as
dialecticians attempt to do, and as Spirkin does --, simply in order to protect
Mystical Hegelian Holism.
It
might, indeed, be the case that the above reduction can't be pushed through --
but then again, it might not. However, this is an empirical matter,
not one over which contemporary Hermetic Philosophers
(i.e., DM-fans) should pontificate, as if they were born
again ID(T)-ers.
[Some
might object that this isn't simply an empirical issue, it is also ideological
and political -- in
the sense that reductionism is
a feature of modern bourgeois science. This topic will be dealt
with in Essay Three Part Three. Suffice it to say here that the threat of
reductionism in the social sciences (where it does become openly ideological)
can be neutralised on far more effective lines than has hitherto been the case
-- if we abandon other covertly ideological ideas and theories imported
from ancient, or even contemporaneous, ruling-class views of reality (found, for
example, in Hegel's work, as well as in 'rotated Hegelianism' -- i.e., DM). Metaphysical Wholism is
just as much a ruling-class form-of-thought as is Metaphysical Reductionism;
both are the result of the imposition onto reality of an
a priori scheme.]
Indeed, the strategy adopted by anti-ID(T and D)-ers (see
above -- as well as
here
and here)
has been aimed at showing that structures, processes and organs (such as the human
eye,
bacterial flagella and the clotting of blood, for instance), could have arisen
from small changes, accumulated over time, and thus that their 'complexity' can
be reduced to the parts so assembled by
natural forces.
(6)
The above analogy with evolution is worth pursuing a little further. As we know,
one of the more invidious problems facing those who believe they can see
purposeful design in nature is that they have ignored the results of a long and
drawn-out process of historical development, whereby natural events have built
up complexity from the available 'simpler' parts over vast expanses of time. So, to use a
hackneyed example, the
human eye
didn't spring forth in all its glory overnight; it took hundreds of millions
of years to develop, and it now has the properties it has because natural selection
shaped the properties of the parts made available to it by variation and
mutation, and which properties helped ensure the reproductive success and
survival of the populations of organisms involved -- and this was achieved with
no overall plan, or aim behind it (since, clearly, nature isn't 'Mind', nor is
it guided by 'Mind').
[The
employment of obvious metaphors here has been analysed in more detail in Essay
Thirteen Part Three.]
So,
what appear to ID(T)-ers andID(D)-ers to be
irreducibly complex functioning wholes and/or organisms are
in fact the products of a lengthy process whereby such parts were slowly put into
causal or structural relationship (but not into some sort of mysterious
"internal-relation") with one another, and were thus built into the
complex structures we see today.
Hence,
ID(D)-ers make the
same sort of mistake as creationists: they look at
fully-formed organisms and see 'logical connections' (or, in fact, Ideal links) where there
are only causal relations, assembled over time. Again, this isn't the
least bit surprising,
since ID(D)-ers lifted their ideas from Hegel, who in turn borrowed them from
earlier Mystics -- indeed, the same tradition from which ID(T) itself emerged!
Moreover, as we saw in Part One
of this Essay, these ID(T)-obscurantists think that the world is the product of the
Divine Logos, by means
of which all things are logically inter-linked in a mysterious
"Totality"/"Cosmos"/"Creation".
To be
sure, DM-fans don't copy all the mistakes of the ID(T)-ers and Creationists
by joining them in the denial of descent through
modification, etc. However, they do appeal to Engels's shaky first 'Law' to try
to explain how novelty has arisen (or has 'emerged') over time. But, just like
the 'miraculous' acts of 'God' (which can't be explained), exactly how
Engels's 'Law' can account for
novelty remains no less of a mystery; it just seems to 'happen'. According to
DM-theorists, novelty just 'emerges', almost like magic, from certain states of
matter. In like manner, for Christian Fundamentalists, design just 'emerged' from the
'Mind of God', in an equally obscure way. [As we will see later, this helps explain why DM-fans like to toy
around with
Lamarckism (and, indeed,
Lysenkoism),
and other 'scientific' oddities.]
Of
course, it could be argued that ID(D)-ers
can't in any meaningful sense be compared with ID(T)-ers since they are quite clear that nature, not 'God', assembled the parts of organisms over time.
However, as noted above, they do argue that because of the 'Law' of the
transformation of quantity into quality new properties simply 'emerged' as a result. Quite apart from the
fact that this 'Law' is the next best thing to a
joke, it
plainly appeals to the same sort or
'emergent' properties that aren't reducible to their parts, an idea that ID(T)-ers try to sell us. While ID(T)-ers appeal to myth and miracle,
ID(D)-ers appeal to 'emergence', and hence mysticism.
There
is an excellent summary of the two main avenues theists have taken in
their attempt to conceive of the
relationship between 'God' and 'His' creation in Osler (2004), pp.15-35. [Not
unexpectedly, these
neatly mirror the tensions that plague the DM-account of nature, too.]
Here
follows a summary of the relevant parts of Osler's thesis (with a few additional comments of
my own thrown in for good measure):
Traditionally, there were two ways of
conceiving 'God's' relation to material reality:
(a) 'He' is related to it by necessity, as an
expression of 'His' nature; or,
(b) 'He' is related to it contingently,
as an expression of 'His' 'free will'.
If (a) were the case,
there would be a logical connection between the properties of created
beings and their 'essence' -- i.e., the logical core of each being, which is either an
expression of its unique nature, or of the 'kind' to which it belongs. In turn, this
would be a consequence of the logical or conceptual links that exist between
'creation' and 'God's Nature'. If that weren't the case, it would introduce radical
contingency into creation, undermining 'God's Nature' and 'His'
control of 'Creation'. As a result language and logic must constitute
reality (why that is so is outlined
here).
[Also worth pointing out is the fact that Super-Truths like this
-- about
fundamental aspects of 'reality' -- may only be accessed
by means of speculative thought.]
This means that all
that exists is either:
(i) An expression of the logical properties inherent in 'God';
or,
(ii) An emanation from 'God'.
That is, material reality
must be logically 'emergent' from, and hence connected with, the 'Deity'.
So, the universe 'issues' forth from 'His'
nature 'eternally' and a-temporally, outside of time, since that is where 'He exists'. Everything
must therefore be inter-linked by 'internal', or 'necessary', relations, all of
which were derived from, and constituted by, 'concepts' implicit in 'God',
which are also mirrored in fundamental aspects of
creation. This idea is prominent in
Plotinus and
subsequent
Neo-Platonists, like Hegel.
Given this approach,
it is clear that the vast majority of 'ordinary' human beings are incapable of accessing,
nor can they even comprehend, this 'rational' view of 'reality'. Their
lack of knowledge, education and 'divine
illumination' means that, at best, they
misperceive these 'logical properties' as contingentqualities. Hence, for them,
appearances fail to match underlying "essence". Naturally, this
implies that "commonsense" and ordinary language are fundamentally unreliable.
Now, where have we heard all that before?
Email me if you know.
Option (b), on
the other hand, implied that 'God' acted freely when 'He' created the world.
So, if 'He' wasn't acting under any form of 'compulsion', logical or conceptual --
i.e., 'He' wasn't acting on the basis of the logical properties
inherent in 'His' nature -- then there
will be no logical or necessary connection between 'The Creator' and 'His Creation'.
Nor,
indeed, would there be such between each created being. Every object and process in reality
would therefore be genuinelycontingent, and appearances will no
longer be 'deceptive', since they can't mask the hidden, esoteric 'essences'
mentioned above -- for there are none. That being the case, there are no
synthetic a priori truths (as these later came to be known)
ascertainable by thought alone. The only path to knowledge was through observation,
experiment,
and a careful study of the 'Book
of Nature'. It is no coincidence then that the foundations of modern science were laid
in the Middle Ages largely by theorists who adopted this view of 'God' --
for example,
Jean
Buridan.
[On this, see also: Copleston (2003c), pp.153-67, Crombie (1970, 1979),
Grant (1996), Hannam (2009), Lindberg (2007).]
In post-Renaissance thought, the 'necessitarian' tradition re-surfaced in the work
of Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, Wolff, and Hegel; the 'voluntarist'
tradition saw the light of day in an attenuated form in the work of Newton, the Empiricists, and the so-called "mechanists".
They all tended to stress the connection between 'God's'
free will and contingency in nature, alongside the primacy of empirical
over a priori knowledge and the superiority of observation and
experiment over speculation and abstract theory.
[Admittedly, the above classification is rather crude -- for example, Descartes was a
mechanist, but his theory put him on the same side of the fence as Spinoza and
Leibniz, whereas
Gassendi
was also a mechanist, but his ideas aligned him with the voluntarists. On this,
see Copleston (2003d).]
So, when, for example, Fundamentalist Christians look at nature and see design everywhere, they
also claim to see
'irreducible complexity' -- the handiwork of 'God' -- and they either put this
down to 'His' free creation, or they see it as an expression of logical
properties imposed on nature by the Logos (depending, of course, on how they view the
nature of 'The Creator' and 'His' relation to the world).
Christian mechanists saw design in nature, too, but their
theories became
increasingly
deistic, and later openly atheistic. The admission of a contingent link between
'God' and nature severed the logical connection that earlier theorists had
postulated, making "the God hypothesis" seem increasingly redundant. [Laplace
-- "I
have no need of that hypothesis".]
[On this,
see
Lovejoy (1964).
[This links to a PDF.] There is also an excellent account of these developments in
Redwood (1976). See also, Dillenberger (1988). A classic expression of these developments
can be found in the debate between
Leibniz and Clarke. Cf., Alexander (1956), and Vailati (1997).]
Much of this controversy had been motivated much
earlier by the work of
the
Medieval Nominalists, whose theories also sundered the logical link between a
substance and its properties as part of a reaction to the tradition begun by
Avicenna (IbnSīnā, with his separation of 'essence' and 'existence' in created
beings), Averroës (Ibn Rushd), and the so-called "Latin Averroists" (e.g.,
Siger of
Brabant). The latter argued strongly in favour of Aristotle's doctrine of
natural necessity, thus undermining 'God's' free will -- at least, so far as the Roman
Catholic Church
saw things. This reaction was also prompted by philosophical worries about the
nature of
transubstantiation and the relation between the 'essence' of the
emblems (the bread and the wine in the
Eucharist)
and their 'accidents' (their apparent properties). Here 'appearances'
most definitely couldn't reflect 'essence' otherwise the bread would look like
human flesh and the wine would smell of blood!
The aforementioned reaction
was occasioned by the 'Condemnations
of 1277', whereby the Bishop of Paris, Étienne
Tempier,
condemned 219 propositions, among which was the Averroist interpretation of
Aristotle -- particularly the idea that the created order was governed by
logical necessity. The most important response to these condemnations appeared
in the work of
the Nominalist,
William of
Ockham, who, as a result, stressed 'the free will of God' and thus the
contingent nature of the world. For Ockham, this meant that there were no 'essences' in
nature, nor were the apparent properties of bodies (their 'accidents', again) logically
connected with their 'nominal essence' (as this later came to be called by
Locke).
In
the 18th century,
a resurgence of the
'necessitarian' tradition motivated, among other things, the "re-enchantment" of nature in
the theories concocted by the
Natürphilosophers and Hegel -- and later still in those invented by Marxist Dialecticians.
[On this, see Harrington (1996),
Lenoir (1982),
Richards (2002),
and Essay Fourteen Parts One and Two, when they are published. More details can be found in Foster (1934), Hooykaas (1973),
Lindberg (2007), and Osler (2004).
For the Hermetic background to all this, see
Magee (2008). Cf., also Essay Twelve (summary
here). At a later
date I will publish an essay on Leibniz I wrote as an undergraduate, which
anticipated some of the ideas in Osler's book, for example.]
So,
where Christians see design, DM-fans see "internal relations". Same
problematic, same tainted source, same bogus 'solution' to this set of pseudo-problems.
I will say much more about this in
Essay Three Parts
Two and Five, where I will link the above considerations to Traditional
Theories of Mind, Will, Freedom, Necessity, and Determinism -- as well as with
the aforementioned re-enchantment of
nature apparent in Dialectical Marxism (in Essay Fourteen
Parts One and Two (summary
here)).
(7) Finally, and once more, in DM (and
despite what Spirkin says) it isn't too clear
which is part and which is whole -- indeed, as we have seen in
Part One of this Essay, it isn't at all clear what a DM-Whole itself is -- so that internal relations
could be
set up between any supposed 'parts'. [On this, see
Note 15 below, and Note 11 above.]
15. For example, is the part here a single human organism? It
looks like it must
be if the example from DB
is to work. Plainly, a human being is a whole of sorts.
If so, is the part here a human organ? Again, it must be this if another
example (concerning the
heart) is to work. But, each organ is a whole, too. Perhaps, the part here is a
cell? But, a cell is also a whole. Maybe then it is a molecule, an atom, a
proton…? All are wholes in their own right. It seems that the only genuine
part here is an 'elementary particle' (but then again, maybe not -- even they might be
wholes!). However, few DM-theorists are prepared to admit that such elementary parts exist.
But, even if they were to acknowledge their possible/actual existence, these awkward material
'objects' would be inimical
to DM-Wholism, anyway. That is because, as we saw in Essay Eight
Part
One, simple parts like this can't interact, and so can't change.
Perhaps then, parts can
be wholes and wholes can be parts? As we have seen, Spirkin admitted as much:
"The categories of whole and
part are relative; they have meaning only in relation to each other. The whole
exists thanks to its parts and in them. The parts, in their turn, cannot exist
by themselves. No matter how small a particle we name, it is something whole and
at the same time a part of another whole. The largest whole that we can conceive
of is ultimately only a part of an infinitely greater whole. Everything in
nature is a part of the universe. [Spirkin (1983), pp.99-100.]
If so, how is the entire nature of the
part/whole relation to be spelt out? Which parts determine which whole, and
which whole determines which parts? And how does a larger whole determine a
lesser whole of which it is a part? The way Spirkin depicts things, the whole idea
(no pun intended) seems subjective in the extreme.
However, we met this problem in Essay Eight Parts
One and
Two, where we found it was impossible
to decide what, if anything, DM-theorists mean by an
object, or a system, what 'internal
contradictions' are, and what an 'intrinsic' or an
'extrinsic' property is -- or even
what is
meant by "internal". [See also
Note 1a, above.] In addition, we discovered in Part One of this Essay that the
DM-"Totality" is impossible to define, hence the overall
motivating factor for DM-Wholism seems to be about as real as a $7 note.
Indeed, anyone who described this
theory "hopelessly vague and confused" would be praising it far too
highly!
16. It
is worth recalling that a cat eating a mouse is just as 'natural' a process as
grain turning into barley.
17.A de dicto necessity
is one that simply follows from the way we use
words -- for example, the following are de dicto necessities: "A regicide is a king killer",
"A cygnet is
a
baby swan", and "A vixen is
a female fox", since that is how such words are employed. De
re necessities, on the other hand, are supposed to operate in
nature (or society; they are in general held to be independent of our use of language (although,
they
might influence how we use language to depict them). These are often called also
"natural necessities", and are generally connected with
natural laws of
some sort. In
Essay Twelve Part One, I explain
why philosophical theses (to the effect that there are such necessities in nature
and society) are
non-sensical and incoherent.
Ian Hunt [in Hunt (1993)] has developed a strong case for
Dialectical Wholism (even though much of what he says is susceptible to many of
the arguments and objections presented in other Essays at this site; for example,
these). I will be
devoting an Additional Essay to Hunt's book at a later stage. [Update: It
has already been started here.]
Suffice it to say that Hunt's study revolves around wholes taken from human society, an application which isn't being questioned here (even
if the Traditional/Hegelian concepts employed to that end are).
There
are forceful arguments to a similar end in Robinson (2003), and Redding (2007)
--, based partly on Aristotle's work.
[I will add several comments
on this topic in a later re-write of this Essay.]
However, the line I
will take can be seen
from the approach I have adopted
here.
18.Although, it isn't easy to see how G9 could
fail to involve temporal
considerations -- otherwise it would be a lifeless abstraction of no use to dialecticians.
"A
sophist will respond that a pound of sugar is equal to itself at 'any given
moment'…. How should we really conceive the word 'moment'? If it is an
infinitesimal interval of time, then a pound of sugar is subjected during the
course of that 'moment' to inevitable changes. Or is the 'moment' a purely
mathematical abstraction, that is, a zero of time? But everything exists in
time; and existence itself is an uninterrupted process of transformation; time
is consequently a fundamental element of existence. Thus the axiom 'A' is equal
to 'A' signifies that a thing is equal to itself if it does not change, that is
if it does not exist." [Trotsky (1971), pp.63-64.]
This
seems to commit Trotsky to objects (and processes?) that only exist in the present (otherwise his
comment about transformation wouldn't seem to make much sense), but since time
is a feature of four-dimensional reality (in Relativity Theory), this might suggest
that things in the past can
change, too!
It
would, however, be unfair to attribute such views to Trotsky on the basis of
this brief and badly thought-out passage. [Having said that, as far as can be
ascertained, none of his epigones
have yet commented on whether (or even how) this passage could be made consistent with Relativity Theory.]
Incidentally,
on this theme,
Jean van Heijenoort recorded
Trotsky saying of Einstein, "He is essentially a mathematician" --, and he
then added
this aside:
"This, of course, was not
correct, for Einstein's cast of mind was entirely that of a physicist....
Trotsky's remark was an echo of the discussions that had taken place in Russia
around 1922, when an attempt had been made to show that Einstein's theories were
in no way a threat to Marxist materialism because they were somehow mathematical
fictions." [Van Heijenoort (1978), p.145.]
Those familiar with the development of
thought in the USSR (after, say, 1918) will know that Soviet theorists
(following
the lead given by Lenin in
MEC) remained
either sceptical of, or hostile toward, the Idealism they perceived in some
interpretations of Relativity Theory (and, indeed, in other areas of modern Physics). [On
this, see Graham (1971, 1987, 1993), Joravsky (1961), Josephson (1991), Vucinich
(1980, 2001), and Wetter (1958).]
Now, compare that with the radical change of heart
recorded in, say, Omelyanovsky (1979), pp.123-30, where Einstein is said to have
resolved certain 'contradictions' "dialectically" in order to present an "objective" view
of reality --, and then further contrast it with what
Bukharin, for example, was arguing a few generations earlier (i.e., circa 1937, just before
he was executed):
"The development of
theoretical physics and chemistry over the past two or three decades, the
creation of a new physics and microphysics, has thus confirmed the teachings of
dialectical materialism. Dialectical materialism is not in the least afraid of
the...idealist interpretation of
Heisenberg's principle, and the similar
interpretation of Einstein's theory of relativity. These are ugly
ideological growths on the body of science; they have to be exposed and
denounced. But they no longer have long to live.
"Lenin was therefore correct
in his dispute with the 'idealist physics'...." [Bukharin (2005), p.205.
Italic emphases added.]
Hop, skip from Idealism to 'objectivity' within 40
years!
However, Bukharin later spoke of the
"genius" of Einstein (p.228) -- so it seems clear that although he
disapproved of certain "idealist" interpretations imposed on Relativity Theory, he
regarded it as the work of "genius", and perhaps, like Trotsky, he viewed it
merely as a "mathematical fiction" -- a bit like the way that, say, the
Roman
Catholic Church initially received the work of Copernicus, thanks largely to
Osiander's
introduction to De Revolutionibus.
Of late, however, it seems that some Trotskyists have
finally come to terms with (certain parts of) Relativity Theory --, cf., Woods and Grant (1995), pp.141-74,
even though it is also clear from what these two say that they haven't quite
twigged the fact that this theory implies that change isn't an 'objective'
feature of reality! [However, it is worth noting the exceptions to this interpretation, and
the changes made in the second edition of
RIRE, outlined in
Mason (2012).]
Contrast this with the much more favourable comments
advanced by
Paul McGarr (which is probably
because he has a PhD in Physics):
"This revolution arose from a profound crisis in
science. By the time of Engels' death there were a series of glaring
contradictions between different branches of physics. Theories which
successfully explained different physical phenomena contradicted each other in
fundamental ways. It was out of the attempt to resolve these contradictions that
the new scientific revolution was born....
"Relativity theory was developed by Einstein
between 1905 and 1915. The first step, known as 'special relativity', was born
of a contradiction between theories of motion, dynamics, on the one hand, and
theories of electromagnetism -- phenomena such as radio and light waves as well as
electric and magnetic forces -- on the other. In dynamics, Newton's laws of motion
had stood the test of over two centuries. Then in the 1860s
James Clerk Maxwell
had put the understanding of electromagnetism on a similar footing by describing
all electromagnetic phenomena in terms of a series of simple and beautiful laws.
Maxwell's equations were a huge breakthrough, they enabled the prediction of
radio waves and led to a host of other developments, and they remain today a key
element of modern science....
"A series of consequences follow from Einstein's
arguments which seem to challenge commonsense notions of time and space. These
new notions have since been tested and confirmed in countless experiments....
"Einstein later extended his theory to provide a
new explanation of gravity, which had not been incorporated into his earlier
theory of 'special relativity'. 'General relativity' starts from a simple fact.
In Newton's theory mass appears, but there are two different masses -- what are
known as the
gravitational and inertial masses. One is the mass which is the
source of the force of gravity, the other is the measure of a body's resistance
to change of motion. In fact the two, though in Newtonian physics quite distinct
aspects of matter, are always found to be the same. Weightlessness in a falling
lift is one example. Einstein's theory is an attempt to explain facts like this.
It attempts to incorporate gravity into the new relativistic dynamics.
"General relativity is not, as often presented,
simply an exotic tool for speculation about the universe -- though it can help
in that too. Something as straightforward as the
orbit of the planet Mercury
around the sun was never fully explained by Newton's laws -- despite the best
efforts of generations of brilliant physicists, astronomers and mathematicians.
General relativity now makes it possible to explain it. Again the theory was
spectacularly confirmed in 1919 when its novel prediction that
light from stars
should bend
when it passed close to the sun was shown to be correct....
"...Despite the difficulties however, the final
form of the theory is the most beautiful and elegant in modern physics. And the
key notion in the theory is not so difficult. It is simply that the old notion
of matter which exists in a passive, unaffected background of space will not do.
Rather matter and the space it exists in are connected and influence each other
in fundamental ways. The geometry of space and the distribution of matter
mutually determine each other.
"Neither special nor general relativity are in
any way a challenge to materialism. By the turn of the century existing
scientific theories simply could not explain a growing number of observed facts
of nature and, moreover, the theories that explained different facets of nature
contradicted each other. The new theories resolved those contradictions,
explained the unexplained, and showed both why the old theories had worked
within limits and why they broke down beyond those limits...." [McGarr (1994),
pp.159-61.]
As we will see in Essay Thirteen Part Two, McGarr's
interpretation of the history of science, and what motivates scientific change,
is about as accurate as pre-Copernican Physics.
Nevertheless, there is no hint here that
McGarr is aware of the fact that, if correct, this glitzy new theory (i.e,
Relativity) means that
change can't happen -- or that, at best, it is merely a 'subjective' aspect of
our perception of the world.
[I
am, of course, being ironic here! Whether or not Einstein's theory challenges
'commonsense' will be discussed in Essay Thirteen Part Two. However, the
line I will take can be seen from the comments I have included in Essay Three
Part Two.]
Of
course, the point of the dialectical emphasis on the holistic nature of
organisms isn't merely academic, it is aimed
at providing an analogy with class society, but more specifically with
Capitalism.
However, since that topic will take us too far into HM, little more will be said about
it here.
Suffice it to say that the alleged 'logical' link between capitalists and
workers (where one is said to imply, or to depend on the other) is in fact
merely verbal. [In other words it is a de
dicto link. I will say more about this in a later Essay; in the meantime,
readers are re-directed
here
for more details.]
To give an analogy: if say, a limited
resource, like a cake, is to be shared out between NN and MM, and
NN is to receive more than half,
then that will imply MM is to receive less than half. Based on what we mean by
these words, we can make the required inferences in advance of sharing that
cake, but nature (or even society considered as an object (or a set of
relations) in it own right for the moment) can't do this. So, if a capitalist
wants to set up a company, he/she will need to initiate certain causal chains
that bring it about that he/she hires some workers. There is no logical link
here, since robots will do. Of course, it could be argued that the entire
capitalist class can't do this or there would no one to whom they could sell
their products, but that, too, would be a causal consequence of a collective set
of decisions. Moreover, based on what we mean by these words, we may make these
inferences in advance of this taking place, but those inferences themselves do
not take place in the outside world, as an expression
of a 'logical' link between the items involved. To think otherwise would be to
assume social reality was 'mind-like'.
It could be argued that these are causally
"necessary" connections. I will say more about that in a later Essay
(in the meantime, see
here).
It could be objected that the relation
between the capitalist and working classes can't be compared to the sharing of a
cake! However, the point of that analogy was to show that what might at first
sight look like a logical connection is in fact verbal and causal. [On this, see
Hacker (2007), pp.57-89.]
[HM = Historical
Materialism.]
21a.
And it won't do to argue that the
Sun, for example, is part of a developmental process that formed the Solar
System or the rest of the Galaxy, and hence that this process is the
whole in question. That is because 99.999999999%
of this process no longer exists. In that case, this 'whole' would be a phantom
totality, at
best.
Furthermore, this is quite apart from the fact that being merely a part of
something doesn't establish the
'logical' or 'internal' links DM-fans require. There are no logical links
connecting the origin of the Solar System with the formation of the Galaxy, or
the Sun to the formation of the Solar System -- that is over and above the
gravitational field produced by both. But, even then, the influence of this
field is causal not logical. If there is such a 'dialectical-logical' link here,
we are still waiting for the proof. Assertion isn't proof. [On this, see Note1a, above.]
"The next step in this process brings us to
the argument from design. You all know the argument from design: everything in
the world is made just so that we can manage to live in the world, and if the
world was ever so little different we could not manage to live in it. That is
the argument from design. It sometimes takes a rather curious form; for
instance, it is argued that rabbits have white tails in order to be easy to
shoot. I do not know how rabbits would view that application. It is an easy
argument to parody. You all know
Voltaire's
remark, that obviously the nose was designed to be such as to fit spectacles."
[Russell, Why I Am Not A Christian, quoted from
here.
Accessed 26/10/2017; link added.]
We saw (here)
that 'dialectical teleology' was one consequence of the DM-thesis that wholes
can't be reduced to
their parts -- and that this idea doesn't distinguish DM from ID(T).
[ID(T) =
Intelligent Design
(Theological) --
as opposed to ID(D), Intelligent Design (Dialectical); follow the above link for
more details.]
Moreover, it is worth asking whether the fan
belt in the above example was in fact a fan belt before it was made. On
this 'new' interpretation, it seems it would be an intended design that
turns a fan
belt into a car part of a certain sort. But, the car in question might not have been made when
the intention to make that belt was formed. Of course, that would make this car
an intentionalwhole since, manifestly, it doesn't yet exist. In such
an eventuality, we would perhaps have to declare that these intentional items
related to one another as 'ghostly' parts to 'spooky' wholes -- but then it might
prove impossible to say which was the greater: this 'phantom' part or that 'spectral'
whole?
Of course, if the manufacture of this 'intentional car' was itself cancelled,
the 'intentional fan belt' would thereby cease even to be a 'ghostly fan belt';
it would, in effect, have been
exorcised by whomever it was in the nether world
that had deleted its apparitional identity.
"There needs no
ghost, my lord, come from the grave
To tell us this." [Hamlet 1.5.]
[The
reason for the many Hamlet references scattered throughout this Essay will be plain to
anyone who has read Part One.]
Among the many other questions worth asking
are the following: Is the part (in this intentional whole) the fan belt after it
had been made, so that it would then relate (i) to cars that might or might not
have been assembled, or (ii) to cars (any cars) that have lost, or which have
damaged, fan belts? Or, does a fan belt, as a part, relate to the entire set of
(possible, intentional) cars it was designed to fit? This would, of course, mean that the
whole (in this part/whole relation) was one of potential (not
actual) set inclusion. In that case, the part would be the entire set of made and
eventually-to-be-made fan belts designed to fit a whole that would itself
comprise the entire set of cars (made and yet-to-be-made) designed (or one day
to-be-designed) to have these potential fan belts fit them!
Again: is the part here
the original design for the fan belt, and is the whole the corresponding design
of all the cars intended to accommodate these potential fan belts? Or something
else?
Consider the other example mentioned earlier
--, that cake. Are the raisins in a cake still raisins even though they are no longer in the
packet, but now in the cake? Are all the ingredients of a cake "more" than they
were before they were mixed into that cake? Indeed, are raisins actually raisins
even when they were in the packet? But, if we are to be consistent
intentional-Wholists,
raisins are surely only raisins when on a tree, before they became
raisins, just as the above fan belts were only fan belts before they were made,
when they were queuing up in 'intentional space' ready to be put into 'intentional/cars'.
22a. It could be objected that it
was argued earlier that a heart that had
been removed from a body isn't the same as it had been when inside that body. But
here the
opposite is claimed. Which is it to be?
Unlike DM-fans, I won't employ
the
Nixon defence
at this point (by claiming that this apparent contradiction should
merely be "grasped", and then quietly swept under the carpet), since the earlier argument was
aimed at putting pressure on dialecticians to say what they mean by "part"
and
"whole", as well as underline the fact that they have continue to rely on seriously
impoverished conceptual tools when formulating their ideas in this area (and
others), as a result of which they will always struggle to say precisely what DM actually commits them to.
In
this part of the Essay, I am merely appealing to an everyday use of the word "same" (alongside
related terms), not to the sort of obscure jargon employed by Hegel and his
latter day groupies, to make a point that parts and wholes aren't related in the way DM-apologists
suppose.
Now,
the only use of these notions to which I myself am committed is their employment
in everyday contexts. My use of traditional
jargon is merely ad hominem.
[Note
that the Wikipedia article about the so-called Ad Hominem Fallacy (to
which i have linked to above) brands it a logical
fallacy when it is
in fact merely an informal fallacy, and then only so sometimes.
When used to expose the inconsistencies in another's beliefs (as is the case in
this Essay), it forms part of a legitimate argumentative strategy. On this, see
my Quora article.]
23.It seems that when we use tools we tend
to regard them as extensions to our bodies --
or so
scientists tell us. The question then is: How could we do this if tools
aren't in fact body parts, and plainly aren't organically linked to our bodies? Is a hammer
more-of-a-hammer when we use it to bang in a few nails? Maybe these scientists
need to be told of the error of their ways and then encouraged to read Hegel's Logic,
which will soon put their minds right.
At this
point, it needs underlining that the analysis
offered in the main body of this Essay is aimed at defusing the
metaphysical one-liner -- expressed in G3 --, it isn't
directed against the
many and varied physical or causal connections that plainly exist between human
organs and human bodies, which are easily expressible in the vernacular (when
augmented with and by medical/physiological language,
of course).
The nature of the errors DM-advocates continually make is easily illustrated by
(i) A consideration of the manner in which DM-theses like these were
'discovered', and (ii) Their subsequent, miraculously acquired 'necessary'
status.
DM-'laws' are generally cobbled-together in
one or more of the following ways:
(1) Dialecticians will often attempt
to construct a superficial (but
idiosyncratic) grammatical and/or 'logical' analysis of a limited range of
exemplary 'propositions' or 'concepts', almost invariably copied off one another from generation to
generation (but
originally from Hegel and his mystical forebears).
From these they 'derive' what look like 'Super-Empirical
Truths' (i.e., theories which apply to all of
reality, for all of time), subsequently imposed on nature on the
pretence that they haven't been. The former include
(a) Lenin's
attempt to show that everything in existence is a
UO based his
'in-depth' one line 'analysis' of the sentence "John
is a man",
along with (b) Trotsky's conclusions about 'identity'
derived from a brief
examination of few schematic letter "A"s and an imaginary bag
of sugar!
(2) DM-theorists will sometimes attempt
to obtain analogous 'Super-Empirical Truths' from, or base them upon, a handful
of rudimentary 'thought experiments' or superficially analysed anecdotal examples -- for
instance, the oft-repeated discussion of
motion
(cats moving about on mats, etc.), the transformation of 'quantity into quality' (heads
becoming bald, water boiling, the inconsistent fighting ability of the
Mamelukes when
faced with
varying numbers of French soldiers, etc.), the
negation of the negation (seeds germinating, cells
dying, etc.) and
a smattering of
UOs (e.g., fathers and sons -- although, significantly,
not
mothers and daughters, or fathers and daughters, or even mothers and sons --
life and death,
magnets, etc.).
(3) DM-apologists often try
to insert into all of this a little elementary 'conceptual analysis' -- for instance, Engels's
discussions of motion, his analysis of the metaphysical implications of
subject-predicate sentences (a gambit Lenin also used), Trotsky's 'analysis' of
identity, Lenin's comments on the nature of matter and motion, and even TAR's
own attempt to analyse "parts and wholes", "facts", and "friendship".
[Rees (1998), pp.5, 77, 109-10, 131.]
All of these
have been discussed in detail in
various Essays at this site (follow the above links). [Rees's 'analysis' of "friendship" will be examined
in Essay Three Part Four.]
One
further characteristic of
remarkably
easilydiscovered universal truths like these (conveniently 'hidden', for
example, in the meanings of a few words or in the structure of
subject-predicate propositions) is the fact that they aren'tbasedon any evidence -- notwithstanding the subsequent and feeble attempts sometimes made
by DM-apologists to produce a few supporting facts in an effort to substantiate
these a
priori theses (which facts actually tell a different story when examined a
little more carefully than DM-fans heave hitherto managed). Rather, these 'universal verities'
were invariably derived from brief,
superficial or limited analyses of a few carefully selected words, concepts or
examples, compounded by a hasty projection onto the world of the misapplied
rules for the use of the terms employed in each case, in the fond belief that
substantive truths can be effortlessly concocted this way. [These somewhat controversial claims
are defended at length in Essays Two
and Twelve Part One.]
This
DM-segue from specially-selected and
suitably-doctored
words to universal truths about the world invariably goes unnoticed, certainly un-remarked,
in DM-circles. In fact,
this conceptual sleight-of-hand is so
easy missed that dialecticians imagine the opposite is in fact the case: that their examples actually address 'objective' features of
reality, and that their theses have been read from nature rather than
having been derived from a determination to use words in rather odd ways, and
then imposed on nature. Indeed, it is virtually
impossible for those who indulge in this 'logo-magic' to recognise
when they are doing it -- even after it has been pointed outto them.
[Here
is a recent example.]
This is partly
because the supposedly 'necessary truths' that emerge at the end of this process
look like genuine philosophical gems. Clearly, it is the metaphysical
sparkle that distracts the incautious eye.
Hence, what diverts attention in the present
case is the production of a motley collection of "emergent" or "supervenient" properties out of the
dialectical conjurer's metaphysical hat, as it were -- to change the image. [On this, see Essay Three Part Three,
when it is published.]
As is the case with genuine conjuring tricks, the audience
is mystified. Nevertheless, in this case -- unlike stage magic -- even the
metaphysical magician him/herself is baffled. That is because it is unclear to audience and trickster alike
where such properties could possibly have come from, how they got here or how they are related
to the metaphysical hat from which they had been so unceremoniously wrenched.
Connected with these examples of DM-legerdemain
is
the accompanying claim that these "emergent" properties "can't be
reduced to the parts" upon which they had supposedly been "based". We are never
told why these novel properties can't be so reduced -- only that they
can't. So, perhaps we would be wise not to ask. [That's another problem "Nixoned"!]
The accuracy of the above allegations (at
least, with respect to the DM-analysis of parts and
wholes) can be judged from a consideration of the only possible response
a DM-fan could make to anyone who denied, for example, that the whole is
greater than the sum of the parts -- or, indeed, to anyone who rejected the idea
that there were such things as "emergent" properties and "internal
relations", to begin with. Such a response would soon
involve the DM-apologist pointing out that the aforementioned sceptic was ignoring what
words like "part", "whole", "heart", "organism", and
other
associated terms, really meant. The
argument would then rapidly become embroiled in a dispute about the meaning of
certain words.
[MEC = Materialism and
Empirio-Criticism; i.e., Lenin (1972).]
It
could be objected that this isn't so.
Indeed, it could be argued that this entire issue revolves around a dispute about objectivereality
itself. [This is precisely the line Lenin took in MEC -- more on that in Essay
Thirteen Part One.] However, anyone tempted to
reach for that response would have to ignore
their own reaction when challenged in the above manner: in order to correct
those of us who question homely 'truths' like G3, it would be no use trying to get
a single one of us to look harder, or consider more evidence. The
problem wouldn't be one of eyesight, but of one of understanding.
Which is why DM-fans often resort to the "He/she just doesn't 'understand'
dialectics" defence. So, when pressed, DM-theorists soon find they have to appeal to the supposed meanings
of words, and to "understanding", in order to substantiate or defend their
theory. That alone shows this isn't a matter of evidence but one of comprehension.
G3: The whole is more than the sum of
its parts.
This also explains why DM-theorists are so
confident about the universal and eternal applicability of their theses -- when
in fact the latter were only ever based on a superficial analysis of a
limited range of examples, anecdotes, thought experiments and seriously over-worked DM-clichés.
Hence, if DM-principles actually follow from
what certain wordsaretaken
to mean, their universal applicability is a function of
linguistic usage, too -- but not of 'objective reality'.
[The
idea that DM
'reflects' reality has been batted out of the park
here. It will
be given even more detailed consideration In Essay Twelve Part Four.]
In
that case, the truth of DM-theses isn't dependent
on evidential support (even if there were much to speak of). And, because this fact is all
too easily missed (for reasons that are examined in Essay Nine
Parts One and
Two, and in several Parts of Essay Twelve
(for example, here)), DM-theorists find it
impossible to spot the rather oversized beam in their own eye when they
complain about the relatively microscopic mote in that of their critics.
Indeed, that is why the counter-examples
advanced in this Essay can only be neutralised by a more careful use of
language,
or by the advocacy of other linguistic principles or conventions (such as those
governing the use of words for identity, parts, wholes and change, etc.).
As we have seen, the interpretation of the hackneyed examples DM-theorists constantly
employ depends on a specific, often idiosyncratic, use of
language -- which use generally contains hidden ambiguities and
equivocations that the
counter-examples advanced in this and other Essays force to the surface.
In fact, as social beings themselves,
DM-theorists could find no way out of this circle other than by an appeal
to the use of language -- that is, if they hope to make themselves comprehensible to
others, let alone to one another.
The failure to take into account the
socially-sanctioned rules we
already have for the use of words connected with parts, wholes, identity,
and movement (etc.) helps explain why so many DM-theses readily collapse into
incoherence even upon superficial examination. Since language itself is a sort of
interconnected (if constantly growing and changing) 'totality', when its
rules are ignored or flouted, it soon becomes impossible to say anything at
all without surreptitiously trying to re-deploy -- i.e., misuse or distort -- them
in a belated attempt to minimise the resulting incoherence. We saw this with
respect to
Trotsky's attempt to attack the
LOI by means of a
back-door use of that very
same 'law', Engels's analysis of motion and now in the discussion of the
part/whole relation.
As Marx noted:
"We have shown that thoughts and ideas acquire an
independent existence in consequence of the personal circumstances and relations
of individuals acquiring independent existence. We have shown that exclusive,
systematic occupation with these thoughts on the part of ideologists and
philosophers, and hence the systematisation of these thoughts, is a consequence
of division of labour, and that, in particular, German philosophy is a
consequence of German petty-bourgeois conditions. The philosophers have only
to dissolve their language into the ordinary language, from which it is
abstracted, in order to recognise it, as the distorted language of the actual
world, and to realise that neither thoughts nor language in themselves form a
realm of their own, that they are only manifestations of actual life." [Marx
and Engels (1970), p.118. Bold emphases added.]
To be sure,
it is arguable that Marx was talking about
German Idealists, but his comments certainly apply in equal measure
to the work of all traditional theorists, especially when he
also said similar things about philosophers in general. [There is more on this in Essay Twelve
Part One.]
That
is why the present study focuses on the use of language so much -- to make this point obvious, to expose latent
DM-non-sense and
incoherence as patent DM-non-sense and incoherence.
This means,
therefore, that the part/whole metaphysic depends on misconstrued rules for the use
of a handful of words, and not on fundamental aspects of reality.
Finally, it is worth re-iterating the point that none of the theses mentioned above
concerning the part/whole relation are being asserted or denied in this Essay.
Since the distinction itself (and the relation between parts and wholes) is a
grammatical feature of our socially-sanctioned use of certain words, and not a
fundamental truth about the world
(even if it enables us to state such truths), the supposition that these words
express substantive theses about 'reality' is non-sensical itself. And, as has been pointed out
elsewhere, the sentential negation of
non-sense is also non-sense.
These and other similarly controversial claims will be
defended in Essay Twelve, as well as in several others to be published in the Additional
Essays section at a later date.
Over the next few years I
will post
a series of examples of scientific progress that further underline the
non-Wholist nature of much of science -- and, indeed, the world.
Almost as if to show that the "whole makes
the part" mantra is false, scientists have now manufactured synthetic
chromosomes, which feat would, of course, be impossible if Wholism were
true. That is because, if the "whole made the part" (etc.), a set of molecules
would only constitute a chromosome if they had been formed naturally as part of
the metabolic processes inside a given organism, and not otherwise. [This is
just a variation on
the
car parts example we met earlier.]
"Scientists hail
synthetic chromosome advance
"David Shukman
27 March 2014
"Scientists have
created the first synthetic
chromosome
for
yeast
in a landmark for biological
engineering. Previously
synthetic DNA
has been designed and made
for simpler organisms such as bacteria. As a
form of life whose cells contain a nucleus,
yeast is related to plants and animals and
shares 2,000 genes with us. So the creation
of the first of yeast's 16 chromosomes has
been hailed as 'a massive deal' in the
emerging science of synthetic biology. The
genes in the original chromosome were
replaced with synthetic versions and the
finished manmade chromosome was then
successfully integrated into a yeast cell.
"The new cell was then
observed to reproduce, passing a key test of
viability. Yeast is a favoured target for
this research because of its
well-established use in key industries such
as brewing and baking and its potential for
future industrial applications. One company
in California has already used synthetic
biology to create a strain of yeast that can
produce
artemisinin, an ingredient for an
anti-malarial drug. The synthesis of
chromosome III in yeast was undertaken by an
international team and the findings are
published in the journal Science
(yeast chromosomes are normally designated
by Roman numerals).
"Chucking the
junk
"Dr Jef Boeke of the
Langone Medical Centre at New York
University, who led the team, described the
achievement as 'moving the needle in
synthetic biology from theory to reality'. In an interview with
BBC News, he said: 'What's really exciting
about it is the extent to which we have
changed the sequence and still come out with
a happy healthy yeast at the end.'
"The new chromosome,
known as SynIII, involved designing and
creating 273,871
base pairs of DNA
-- fewer than the
316,667 pairs in the original chromosome.
The researchers removed repeated sections in
the original DNA and so-called
'junk' DNA
known not to code for any
proteins -- and they then added 'tags' to
the chromosome. Dr Boeke said that
despite making more than 50,000 changes to
the DNA code in the chromosome, the yeast
was not only 'hardy' but had also gained new
functions. 'We have taught it a few tricks
by inserting some special widgets into its
chromosome.'
"One new function is a
chemical switch that allows researcher to
'scramble' the chromosome into thousands of
different variants making genetic
manipulations far easier. The hope is that
the ability to create synthetic strains of
yeast will allow these organisms to be
harnessed for a wide range of uses including
the manufacture of vaccines or more
sustainable forms of biofuel.
"While
genetic
modification
involves
transferring
genes
from one
organism
to
another,
synthetic
biology
goes far
further
by
designing
and then
constructing
entirely
new
genetic
material.
Opponents
of the
field
argue
that
scientists
are 'playing
God'
by
designing
new
forms of
life
with the
danger
of
unexpected
consequences.
A report
for the
Lloyds
insurance
market
in 2009
warned
that the
new
technology
could
pose
unforeseen
risks.
"The
synthesis
of
chromosome
III is
the
first
stage of
an
international
project
to
synthesise
yeast's
entire
genome
over the
next few
years. A
team at
Imperial
College
London
is
tackling
chromosome
XI, one
of the
largest
with
670,000
base
pairs,
using a
similar
technique
of
creating
'chunks'
of bases
to
insert
into the
yeast's
genome.
"New
tricks
"Dr Tom
Ellis,
who is
leading
the
work,
described
the
creation
of the
first
synthetic
chromosome
for a
eukaryotic
organism
-- the
branch
of life
including
plants,
animals
and
fungi --
as a
'massive
deal.
Yeast is
the king
of
biotech
-- and
it's
great to
use
synthetic
biology
to add
in new
functions.
The
fitness
of the
chromosome
is in
line
with the
natural
one.
Making
all
these
design
changes
has not
caused
any
major
issues
-- it
behaves
as it
should
-- and
it's
great to
see that
others
can do
it.'
"The
Imperial
scientists
have so
far
synthesised
about
one
third of
the DNA
for
their
chromosome
XI with
about
5-10%
inserted.
Their
research
includes
developing
synthetic
genes
for
yeast
that
would
allow it
to
produce
antibiotics
and to
turn
agricultural
waste
into
biofuel.
With
critics
arguing
that
synthetic
biology
involves
meddling
in
Nature
with
unknown
effects,
Dr Ellis
and
others
stress
that the
new
organisms
are
designed
with
in-built
restrictions.
"The
strains
of yeast
containing
synthetic
genetic
material
can only
survive
in a lab
environment
with
specialist
support.
To
highlight
the
benefits
of the
work, Dr
Boeke
stresses
the
importance
of yeast
throughout
human
history
and its
potential
for the
future.
'Yeast
has an
ancient
industrial
relationship
with Man
-- the
baking
of bread
and the
brewing
of
alcoholic
beverages
dates
back
[to] the
Fertile
Crescent
and
today
the
industrial
relationship
goes far
beyond
that
because
we're
making
medicines,
vaccines
and
biofuels
using
yeast.'
"The
paper
describing
the
first
synthetic
chromosome
concludes
with a
far-reaching
vision
looking
beyond
yeast to
more
sophisticated
organisms,
saying:
'it will
soon
become
feasible
to
synthesise
eukaryotic
genomes,
including
plant
and
animal
genomes'. In his
interview,
Dr Boeke
explained
that
this
will not
be
immediate
but is
getting
closer.
'It's
still
aways
off in
the
future
to do
entire
chromosomes
for
those
organisms
but
certainly
mini
chromosomes
containing
tens or
even
hundreds
of genes
are
definitely
within
the
foreseeable
future,'
he said.
"It was
only in
2010
that the
scientific
world
was
stunned
when Dr
Craig
Venter
unveiled
the
first
synthetic
genome
for
bacteria.
So this
new
science
is
gathering
pace and
growing
in
ambition."
[Quoted
from
here;
accessed
27/03/2014.
Links
added;
several
paragraphs
merged.
Quotation
marks
altered
to
conform
to the
conventions
adopted
at this
site;
emphases
added.
See also
here.]
Will we now see DM-fans object that scientists are 'playing
Hegel' by designing new forms of non-Wholist life? Only non-dialectical time
will tell.
"A kidney 'grown' in
the laboratory has been transplanted into
animals where it started to produce urine,
US scientists say. Similar techniques to
make simple body parts have already been
used in patients, but the kidney is one of
the most complicated organs made so far. A study,
in the journal Nature Medicine,
showed the engineered kidneys were less
effective than natural ones. But
regenerative medicine researchers said the
field had huge promise. Kidneys filter the
blood to remove waste and excess water. They
are also the most in-demand organ for
transplant, with long waiting lists.
"The researchers'
vision is to take an old kidney and strip it
of all its old cells to leave a
honeycomb-like scaffold. The kidney would
then be rebuilt with cells taken from the
patient. This would have two major
advantages over current organ transplants.
The tissue would
match the patient, so they would not need a
lifetime of drugs to suppress the immune
system to prevent rejection. It would also
vastly increase the number of organs
available for transplant. Most organs which
are offered are rejected, but they could be
used as templates for new ones.
"Researchers at Massachusetts General
Hospital have taken the first steps towards
creating usable engineered kidneys. They
took a rat kidney and used a detergent to
wash away the old cells. The remaining web
of proteins, or scaffold, looks just like a
kidney, including an intricate network of
blood vessels and drainage pipes. This protein plumbing
was used to pump the right cells to the
right part of the kidney, where they joined
with the scaffold to rebuild the organ. It
was kept in a special oven to mimic the
conditions in a rat's body for the next 12
days.
"When the kidneys were
tested in the laboratory, urine production
reached 23% of natural ones. The team then
tried transplanting an organ into a rat.
Once inside the body, the kidney's
effectiveness fell to 5%. Yet the lead
researcher, Dr Harald Ott, told the BBC that
restoring a small fraction of normal
function could be enough: 'If you're on
haemodialysis then kidney function of 10% to
15% would already make you independent of
haemodialysis. It's not that we have to go
all the way.' He said the potential was
huge: 'If you think about the United States
alone, there's 100,000 patients currently
waiting for kidney transplants and there's
only around 18,000 transplants done a year.
I think the potential clinical impact of a
successful treatment would be enormous.'
"There is a huge amount of further research
that would be needed before this is even
considered in people. The technique needs to
be more efficient so a greater level of
kidney function is restored. Researchers
also need to prove that the kidney will
continue to function for a long time. There
will also be challenges with the sheer size
of a human kidney. It is harder to get the
cells in the right place in a larger organ.
"Prof Martin Birchall,
a surgeon at University College London, has
been involved in windpipe transplants
produced from scaffolds. He said: 'It's
extremely interesting. It is really
impressive. They've addressed some of the
main technical barriers to making it
possible to use regenerative medicine to
address a really important medical need.'
"He said that being
able to do this for people needing an organ
transplant could revolutionise medicine:
'It's almost the nirvana of regenerative
medicine, certainly from a surgical point of
view, that you could meet the biggest need
for transplant organs in the world -- the
kidney.'" [Quoted from
here; quotation marks altered to conform
to the conventions adopted at this site.
Several paragraphs merged.
Accessed 11/04/2014. See also
here, and
here.]
DM-fans are encouraged to write to these
scientists and tell them to stop wasting time and money on this futile project since
they (DM-fans) have a 200-year old book devoted to extolling Christian Mysticism that tells them this sort
of thing is impossible.
'Reactionary' science,
it seems, is gaining
momentum:
"Doctors implant
lab-grown vagina
"By James
Gallagher -- 11/04/2014
"Four women have had
new vaginas grown in the laboratory and
implanted by doctors in the US. A tissue
sample and a biodegradable scaffold were
used to grow vaginas in the right size and
shape for each woman as well as being a
tissue match. They all reported normal
levels of desire, arousal, lubrication,
orgasm, satisfaction; and painless
intercourse. Experts said the
study, published in the Lancet, was the
latest example of the power of regenerative
medicine. In each woman the vagina did not
form properly while they were still inside
their mother's womb, a condition known as
vaginal aplasia. Current treatments can
involve surgically creating a cavity, which
is then lined with skin grafts or parts of
the intestine.
"Doctors at Wake
Forest Baptist Medical Centre in North
Carolina used pioneering technology to build
vaginas for the four women who were all in
their teenage years at the time. Scans of
the pelvic region were used to design a
tube-like 3D-scaffold for each patient. A
small tissue biopsy was taken from the
poorly developed vulva and grown to create a
large batch of cells in the laboratory.
"Muscle cells were
attached to the outside of the scaffold and
vaginal-lining cells to the inside. The
vaginas were carefully grown in a bioreactor
until they were suitable to be surgically
implanted into the patients. One of the
women with an implanted vagina, who wished
to keep her name anonymous, said: 'I believe
in the beginning when you find out you feel
different. I mean while you are living the
process, you are seeing the possibilities
you have and all the changes you'll go
through. Truly I feel very fortunate because
I have a normal life, completely normal.'
"All the women
reported normal sexual function. Vaginal
aplasia can lead to other abnormalities in
the reproductive organs, but in two of the
women the vagina was connected to the
uterus. There have been no pregnancies, but
for those women it is theoretically
possible. Dr Anthony Atala,
director of the Institute for Regenerative
Medicine at Wake Forest, told the BBC News
website: 'Really for the first time we've
created a whole organ that was never there
to start with, it was a challenge.' He said
a functioning vagina was a 'very important
thing' for these women's lives and
witnessing the difference it made to them
'was very rewarding to see'. This is the
first time the results have been reported.
However, the first implants took place eight
years ago.
"Meanwhile,
researchers at the University of Basel in
Switzerland have used similar techniques to
reconstruct the noses of patients after skin
cancer. It could replace the need to take
cartilage from the ribs or ears in order to
rebuild the damage caused by cutting the
cancer away.
Prof Martin Birchall,
who has worked on lab-grown windpipes,
commented: 'These authors have not only
successfully treated several patients with a
difficult clinical problem, but addressed
some of the most important questions facing
translation of tissue engineering
technologies. The steps between
first-in-human experiences such as those
reported here and their use in routine
clinical care remain many, including larger
trials with long-term follow-up, the
development of clinical grade processing,
scale-out, and commercialisation.'" [Quoted
from
here; quotation marks altered to conform
to the conventions adopted at this site.
Several paragraphs merged.
Accessed 11/04/2014.]
None
of this would be possible if DM-Wholism
were true.
"Cartilage growing to
rebuild body parts 'within three years'
"BBC News 29/12/15
"Patients needing surgery to
reconstruct body parts such as noses and ears could soon have treatment using
cartilage which has been grown in a lab. The process involves growing someone's
cells in an incubator and then mixing them with a liquid which is 3D printed
into the jelly-like shape needed. It is then put back in an incubator to grow
again until it is ready. Researchers in Swansea hope to be among the first in
the world to start using it on humans within three years.
"'In simple terms, we're trying to
grow new tissue using human cells,' said Prof Iain Whitaker, consultant plastic
surgeon at the Welsh Centre for Burns and Plastic Surgery at Morriston Hospital.
'We're trialling using 3D printing which is a very exciting potential modality
to make these relatively complex structures. Most people have heard a lot about
3D printing and that started with 3D printing using plastics and metals. That
has now developed so we can consider printing biological tissue using
bio-printing, which is very different. We're trying to print biological
structures using human cells, and provide the right environment and the right
timing so it can grow into tissue that we can eventually put into a human. It
would be to reconstruct lost body parts such as part of the nose or the ear and
ultimately large body parts including bone, muscle and vessels.'
"The team of surgeons are working with
scientists and engineers who have built a 3D printer specifically for this work.
Prof Whittaker, who is also the chairman of plastic and reconstructive surgery
at Swansea University's medical school, said the project started in 2012 but
research in the field has been going on for more than 20 years. He said the work
would have to be tested on animals and go though an ethics process [but not a
'dialectical logic' test -- RL] before being used on humans. 'The good news in the future is, if
our research is successful, within two months you'd be able to recreate a body
part which was not there without having to resort to taking it from another part
of the body which would cause another defect or scar elsewhere, ' he added.
"How The Process Works
"1) Cells are taken from a tiny sample
of cartilage during the initial operation and grown in an incubator over several
weeks.
"2) The shape of the missing body part
is scanned and fed into a computer.
"3) It is then 3D printed using a
special liquid formula combined with the live cells for form the jelly-like
structure.
"4) Reagents are then added to
strengthen the structure.
"5) It is put into an incubator with a
flow of nutrients to supply the cells with food so they can grow and produce
their own cartilage.
"6) The structure will then be tested
to see if it is string enough to be eventually implanted into patients."
[Quoted from
here. Accessed 24/04/2016. Paragraphs merged; quotation marks
and formatting altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]
Again, this would be impossible if DM-Wholism
were true.
Capra, F. (1997), The Web Of Life. A New
Synthesis Of Life And Matter (Harper Collins).
--------, (1999), The Tao Of Physics.
An Exploration Of The Parallels Between Modern Physics And Eastern Mysticism (Shambhala Publications, 3rd ed.).
--------, (2003), The Hidden Connections
(Flamingo).
Casati, R., and Varzi, A. (1999), Parts And Places. The
Structures Of Spatial Representation (MIT Press).
Casati, R. (2016), 'Mereology', Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta (Spring 2019 Edition).
Copleston, F. (2003a), A History Of
Philosophy, Volume Two: Medieval Philosophy (Continuum Books).
--------, (2003b), A History Of
Philosophy, Volume Three: Late Medieval And Renaissance Philosophy (Continuum Books).
--------, (2003c), A History Of
Philosophy, Volume Four: The Rationalists, Descartes To Leibniz (Continuum Books).
--------, (2003d), A History Of
Philosophy, Volume Five: British Philosophy, Hobbes To Hume (Continuum Books).
Cornforth, F. (1976), Materialism And The
Dialectical Method (Lawrence & Wishart, 5th ed.).
[A copy of the 1968 edition is available
here.]
Crombie, A. (1970), Robert Grosseteste And
The Origins Of Experimental Science 1100-1700 (Oxford University Press,
Corrected Edition).
--------, (1979), Augustine To Galileo: Science In The Middle Ages; Science
In The Later Middle Ages And Early Modern Times, Two Volumes in One
(Heinemann, 3rd
ed.).
Dembski, W., and Ruse, M. (2006) (eds.),
Debating Design. From Darwin To DNA (Cambridge University Press).
Dillenberger, J. (1988), Protestant
Thought And Natural Science (University of Notre Dame Press).
--------, (1976), Anti-Dühring(Foreign
Languages Press).
Fuller, S. (2008), Dissent Over Descent. Intelligent Design's
Challenge To Darwinism (Icon Books).
Forrest, B., and Gross, P. (2004),
Creationism's Trojan Horse. The Wedge Of Intelligent Design (Oxford
University Press).
Foster, J., Clark, B., and York, R. (2008),
Critique Of Intelligent Design. Materialism Versus Creationism From Antiquity
To The Present (Monthly Review Press).
Foster, M. (1934), 'The Christian Doctrine Of
Creation And The Rise Of Modern Natural Science', Mind43,
pp.446-68; reprinted in Russell (1973), pp.294-315.
Goodman, N. (1966), The Structure Of
Appearance (Bobbs-Merrill).
Graham, L. (1971), Science And Philosophy
In The Soviet Union (Allen Lane).
--------, (1987), Science, Philosophy, And
Human Behaviour In The Soviet Union (Columbia University Press).
--------, (1993), Science In Russia And
The Soviet Union: A Short History (Cambridge University Press).
Grant, E. (1996), The Foundations Of
Modern Science In The Middle Ages (Cambridge University Press).
Hacker, P. (2007), Human Nature: The
Categorical Framework (Blackwell).
Hales, S., and Johnson, T. (2003),
'Endurantism, Perdurantism And Special Relativity', Philosophical Quarterly,
53, pp.524-39, available
here as a PDF.
Hannam, J. (2009), God's Philosophers. How
The Medieval World Laid The Foundations Of Modern Science (Icon Books).
Harrington, A. (1996), Reenchanted
Science: Holism In German Culture From Wilhelm II To Hitler (Princeton
University Press).
Hawley, K. (2004), How Things Persist
(Oxford University Press).
--------, (2015), 'Temporal
Parts', Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta (Spring 2018 Edition).
Hegel, G. (1977), Phenomenology Of Spirit,
translated by A V Miller
(Oxford University Press).
Hoffman, J., and Rosenkrantz, G. (1997),
Substance (Routledge).
Hooykaas, R. (1973), Religion And The Rise
Of Modern Science (Scottish Academic Press).
Houlgate, S. (2006), The Opening Of
Hegel's Logic (Purdue University Press).
Hunt, I. (1993), Analytical And
Dialectical Marxism (Ashgate Publishing).
Hylton, P. (1990), Russell, Idealism And
The Emergence Of Analytic Philosophy (Oxford University Press).
Joravsky, D. (1961), Soviet Marxism And
Natural Science 1917-1932 (Routledge).
Josephson, P. (1991), Physics And Politics
In Revolutionary Russia (University of California Press).
Kant, I. (1998), Critique Of Pure Reason
(Cambridge University Press). [The on-line version is a different translation.]
Kharin, Y. (1981), Fundamentals Of
Dialectics (Progress Publishers).
Konstantinov, F., et al (1974),
The Fundamentals Of Marxist-Leninist Philosophy (Progress Publishers, 2nd ed.).
Kosok, M. (2004), The Singularity Of
Awareness. From Mystical Theology Through Contemporary Cosmology (Author
House).
Krapivin, V. (1985),
ABC Of Social And Political Knowledge: What Is Dialectical Materialism?(Progress Publishers).
Kuusinen, O. (1961) (ed.), Fundamentals Of Marxism-Leninism
(Lawrence & Wishart).
Lenin, V. (1914), 'Karl
Marx', reprinted in Lenin (1970), pp.1-18.
--------, (1980), On The Question Of Dialectics (Progress
Publishers).
Lenoir, T. (1982), The Strategy Of Life.
Teleology And Mechanics In Nineteenth-Century Biology (University of Chicago
Press).
Levins, R., and Lewontin, R. (1985), The
Dialectical Biologist (Harvard University Press).
Lindberg, D. (2007), The Beginnings Of
Western Science. The European Scientific Tradition In Philosophical, Religious,
And Institutional Context, 600 BC To AD 1450 (University of Chicago Press,
2nd
ed.).
Marx, K., and Engels, F. (1968), Selected Works In One Volume
(Lawrence & Wishart).
--------, (1970), The German Ideology,
Students Edition, edited by Chris Arthur (Lawrence
& Wishart).
--------, (1987), MECW
Volume 25 (Lawrence & Wishart).
[Unfortunately, the passage from this Volume, quoted in Note 5, has not yet
been reproduced at the Marxist Internet Archive.]
Osler, M. (2004), Divine Will And The
Mechanical Philosophy. Gassendi And Descartes On Contingency And Necessity In
The Created World (Cambridge University Press).
Pennock, R. (2000), Tower Of Babel. The
Evidence Against The New Creationism (MIT Press).
--------, (2001) (ed.), Intelligent Design
Creationism And Its Critics (MIT Press).
Plekhanov, G. (1908), Fundamental Problems Of Marxism
(Lawrence & Wishart). [The Appendix to this work -- which in fact
formed part of Plekhanov's Introduction to Engels (1888) -- can be found
here, under the title 'Dialectic And Logic'. It can also be found in
Plekhanov (1976), pp.73-82.]
Richards, R. (2002), The Romantic
Conception Of Life. Science And Philosophy In The Age Of Goethe (University
of Chicago Press).
Robinson, G. (2003), Philosophy And
Mystification. A Reflection On Nonsense And Clarity (Fordham University
Press).
Rosen, M. (1982), Hegel's Dialectic And
Its Criticism (Cambridge University Press).
Rosenthal, B. (1997) (ed.), The Occult In
Russian And Soviet Culture (Cornell University Press).
--------, (2002), New Myth, New World.
From Nietzsche To Stalinism (Penn State University Press).
Russell, C. (1973) (ed.), Science And
Religious Belief. A Selection Of Recent Historical Studies (Open University
Press).
Sayers, S. (1996), 'Engels And Materialism',
in Arthur (1996), pp.153-72.
Sedley, D, (2007), Creationism And Its Critics In Antiquity
(University of California Press).
Shanks, N. (2004), God, The Devil, And
Darwin. A Critique Of Intelligent Design Theory (Oxford University Press).
Sheptulin, A. (1978), Marxist-Leninist
Philosophy (Progress Publishers).
Sider, T. (2001), Four Dimensionalism. An
Ontology Of Persistence And Time (Oxford University Press).
Simons, P. (1987), Parts: A Study In
Ontology (Oxford University Press).
Sober, E. (1999),
'How Not To Detect Design. A Review Of William A. Dembski's The Design
Inference -- Eliminating Chance Through Small Probabilities', available
here.
[This links to a PDF.]
Sorabji, R. (1983), Time, Creation And The
Continuum (Duckworth).