Essay Three Part Two: Abstractionism -- Or, Science And Mathematics On The Cheap --

How This Actually Undermines Dialectical Materialism Itself

 

This Essay is currently undergoing a complete overhaul, re-edit and re-write, which should be finished by early 2025.

 

I am actively uploading the changes as they are being made.

 

~~~~~~~~oOo~~~~~~~~

 

Visitors are encouraged to read Part One of this Essay first, where much that is apparently taken for granted below has been fully substantiated.

 

Technical Preliminaries

 

Internet Explorer 11 will no longer play the videos I have embedded below. As far as I can tell, they play as intended in other browsers. However, if you have Privacy Badger [PB] installed, they won't play in Google Chrome unless you disable PB for this site.

 

[Having said that, I have just discovered that they will play in IE11 if you have upgraded to Windows 10. That is still the case with Windows 11, as far as I can determine. It looks like the problem was with Windows 7 and earlier versions of that operating system.]

 

If you are using Internet Explorer 10 (or later), you might find some of the links I have used won't work properly unless you switch to 'Compatibility View' (in the Tools Menu); for IE11 select 'Compatibility View Settings' and add this site (anti-dialectics.co.uk). Microsoft's browser, Edge, automatically renders these links compatible; Windows 10 and 11 do likewise.

 

However, if you are using Windows 10 and 11, IE11 and Edge unfortunately appear to colour these links somewhat erratically. They are meant to be mid-blue, but those two browsers render them intermittently light blue, yellow, purple and even red!

 

It looks like Firefox and Chrome reproduce them correctly.

 

Unfortunately, several browsers also underline these links erratically. Many are underscored boldly in black, others in light blue! They are all meant to be underlined in the same colour as the link itself.

 

Finally, if you're viewing this with Mozilla Firefox, you might not be able to read all the symbols I have used. Mozilla sometimes replaces them with an "º'.

 

There are no such problems with Chrome, Edge or Internet Explorer, as far as I can determine.

 

I don't know if that is the case with other browsers.

 

Preface

 

This Second Part of Essay Three has perhaps been written and re-written more times than any other at this site (in fact well over eighty times -- and that number is no exaggeration, either!). That is partly because several sections contained rather too many mixed metaphors and stylistic monstrosities, which approach was in turn adopted because I had wanted to experiment with new ways of covering two major topics in the History of Philosophy that have been analysed and debated countless times over the last 2400 years by Traditional Theorists: (i) The so-called 'Problem of Universals' and (ii) 'The process of abstraction'. As a result of those re-edits I have managed to eliminate or tone down most of the ornate rhetorical flourishes and mixed metaphors, but the material below still requires a several more revisions before I will be completely happy with the final version. Hence, the reader's patience is required here perhaps more than elsewhere at this site. Having said that, those familiar with the history of the above issues will perhaps find the novel approach adopted here rather refreshing -- and, with luck, illuminating.

 

Added on Edit: October 2024: I have just spent the last eight months completely re-structuring and re-writing this Essay (again(!)), which means I have eliminated even more of the stylistic monstrosities referred to earlier. I have also added a brief explanation why many of the remaining metaphors and other 'colourful images' were originally chosen and have been left in.

 

[DM = Dialectical Materialism/Materialist, depending on the context; HM = Historical Materialism/Materialist, again depending on the context.]

 

Some readers might wonder why I have quoted extensively from a wide variety of DM-sources in the Essays published at this site. In fact a good 10-20% of the material in many of them is comprised of just such quotations. Apologies are therefore owed the reader in advance for the length and extremely repetitive nature of most of these quoted passages. The reason for their inclusion is that long experience has taught me that Dialectical Marxists simply refuse to accept that their own classicists -- e.g., Engels, Plekhanov, Lenin, Trotsky and Mao -- alongside countless 'lesser' DM-theorists, actually said the things I have attributed to them. That is especially the case after they are confronted with the absurd consequences that flow from their words, and that remains so unless they are shown chapter and verse and in extensive detail. In debate, when I cite or quote only one or two passages in support of what I allege, they are simply brushed off as a "outliers" or as "untypical". Indeed, in the absence of dozens of proof texts drawn from many such sources (from across all areas of Dialectical Marxism) they tend to regard anything that a particular theorist had to say -- regardless of whether they were one of the aforementioned classicists -- as either "far too crude", "unrepresentative" or even(!) unreliable. Failing that, they often complain that any such quotes have been "taken out of context". Many in fact object since -- surprising and sad though this is to say --, they are largely ignorant of their own theory or they simply haven't read the DM-literature with due care, or at all! The only way to counter such attempts to deflect, reject and deny is to quote DM-material frequently and at length.

 

In addition, because of the highly sectarian and partisan nature of Dialectical Marxism, I also have to quote a wide range of DM-texts from across the entire spectrum. Trotskyists object if I quote Stalin or Mao; Maoists and Stalinists complain if I reference Trotsky -- or even if I cite "Brezhnev era revisionists". Non-Leninist Marxists will bemoan the fact that I haven't confined my remarks solely to what Marx or Hegel had to say, advising me to ignore the confused or even "simplistic" ideas expressed by Engels, Plekhanov, Lenin, Stalin, Mao and Trotsky! This often means I have to quote the lot!

 

That itself has had the (indirect) benefit of revealing how much and to what extent they (the classicists and subsequent epigones drawn from all areas of Dialectical Marxism) largely agree with each other (despite any sectarian rhetoric to the contrary) -- at least with respect to DM!

 

Several others have complained about the number of links I have added to these Essays, because they say it makes them very difficult to read. Of course, DM-supporters can hardly grumble about that since they believe everything is interconnected, which must surely apply to Essays that attempt to debunk that very idea. However, to those who find this does make these Essays difficult to read I say this: ignore the links(!) -- unless, of course, you want to access further supporting evidence and argument related to a particular point, or a specific topic fires your interest.

 

Still others wonder why I have linked to familiar subjects and topics that are part of common knowledge (such as the names of recent US Presidents, UK Prime Ministers, the names of rivers and mountains, the titles of popular films or the definition of certain words in common usage). I have done so for the following reason: my Essays are read all over the world and by people from all 'walks of life', so I can't assume that something which is part of common knowledge in 'the west' is equally well-known across the planet -- or, indeed, by those who haven't had the benefit of the sort of education that is generally available in the 'advanced economies', or any at all. Many of my readers aren't native English speakers, either, so any help I can give them I will continue to provide.

 

Finally on this specific topic, several of the aforementioned links connect to web-pages that regularly change their URLs, or which even vanish from the Internet altogether. While I try to update them when it becomes apparent that they have changed or have disappeared, I can't possibly keep on top of this all the time. I would greatly appreciate it, therefore, if readers informed me of any dead or incorrect links they happen to notice. In general, links to 'Haloscan' no longer seem to work, so readers needn't tell me about them! Links to RevForum, RevLeft, Socialist Unity and The North Star also appear to have died.

 

~~~~~~oOo~~~~~~

 

As is the case with all my Essays, nothing at this site should be read as an attack either on HM -- a scientific theory I fully accept --, or, indeed, on revolutionary socialism itself. I remain as committed to the self-emancipation of the working class and the dictatorship of the proletariat as I was when I first became a revolutionary over thirty-five years ago.

 

The difference between DM and HM, as I see it, is explained here.

 

It is also worth noting that phrases like "ruling-class theory", "ruling-class view of reality", "ruling-class thought-forms",  and "ruling-class ideology" (etc.), used at this site in connection with Traditional Philosophy and DM, aren't meant to suggest that all or even most members of various ruling-classes invented these ways of thinking or of seeing the world (although some of them did -- for example, Heraclitus, Plato, Cicero and Marcus Aurelius). They are intended to highlight theories (or "ruling ideas") that are conducive to, or which rationalise, the interests of the various ruling-classes history has inflicted on humanity, whoever invents them. Up until recently this dogmatic approach to 'knowledge' had almost invariably been promoted by thinkers who either relied on ruling-class patronage, or who, in one capacity or another, helped run the system for the elite.**

 

However, that will become the main topic of Parts Two and Three of Essay Twelve (when they are published); until then, readers are directed here, here and here for further details.

 

[**How and why this accusation applies to Dialectical Marxists and DM will, of course, be explained in the other Essays published at this site (especially here, here and here). In addition to the three links in the previous paragraph, I have summarised the argument in its support of that claim -- but in this instance with absolute beginners in mind --, here.]

 

It is also worth adding that at least one third of my case against DM in this Essay has been relegated to the End Notes and the Appendices. Indeed, much of the supporting evidence is to be found there. That approach has been adopted in order to allow the main body of the Essay to flow a little more smoothly. This means that readers who want fully to evaluate my case against DM should consult that material, too. In many cases, I have added numerous qualifications and considerably more supporting evidence to what I have argued in the main body. In addition, I have raised several objections (some obvious, many not -- and some that will doubtless have occurred to the reader) to my own arguments and accusations, which I have then answered.

 

[I have explained why I structured the material published at this site that way in Essay One.]

 

If readers skip this material, then my answers to any objections or qualms they might have will be missed, as will the extra supporting evidence and the numerous qualifications I have added. Since I have been debating this theory with comrades for well over thirty years, I have heard all the objections there are!

 

[Most of the on-line debates have been listed here. (Unfortunately, many of the links on that page have now died!)]

 

Two final points: First of all, readers will soon notice that in what follows the word "reality" has often been put in 'scare' quotes. That doesn't mean I think the world doesn't exist, or that everything is just an 'illusion', a 'simulation' or even that language actually constructs the world! I am in fact indirectly highlighting the fact that I object to the philosophical use of this word. I explain why that is so here and here -- but in more detail in Essay Twelve Part One.

 

Second, throughout this site I have employed the term "Dialectical Marxism" in order to distinguish Marxism from the 'dialectical aberration' that has completely dominated revolutionary socialism for over 150 years. So, the terms 'Dialectical Marxism' and 'Dialectical Marxist' are used to refer to the mainstream 'Marxist' tradition that, in one form or another, has accepted the validity of DM, and either applies it to all of 'reality', or restricts it to social development (i.e., it is confined solely to HM). However, I distance Marx himself from this toxic mutation; why that is so has been explained here and here. Furthermore, why this Hegelianised Hybrid (but not Marxism itself) has been an abject failure for well over a century is explained here and here. [That argument has been summarised here and here.]

 

~~~~~~oOo~~~~~~

 

As of March 2024, this Essay was just over 124,500 words long; a much shorter summary of some of its main ideas can be accessed here.

 

The material presented below does not represent my final view of any of the issues raised; it is merely 'work in progress'.

 

[Latest Update: 14/08/2024.]

 

In fact, as noted at the top the page, this Essay is being updated continually.

 

Quick Links

 

Anyone using these links must remember that they will be skipping past supporting argument and evidence set out in earlier sections.

 

If your Firewall/Browser has a pop-up blocker, you will need to press the "Ctrl" key at the same time or these and the other links here won't work!

 

I have adjusted the font size used at this site to ensure that even those with impaired vision can read what I have to say. However, if the text is still either too big or too small for you, please adjust your browser settings!

 

(1) Introduction

 

(2) Dialectical Traditionalism

 

(3) The Traditional Approach To Abstract General Ideas -- Rationalism, Empiricism And 'Original Syntax'

 

(a) Rationalism Versus Empiricism

 

(4) Rationalism And 'The Problem Of Universals'

 

(a)  Traditional Theory

 

(b)   How Not To Solve A Philosophical Problem: Begin By Doubling It

 

(c)  Dialectical Materialists Agree With Idealists -- Matter Is An 'Abstraction'

 

(d)  'Self-Predication'

 

(e)  Descent Into A Metaphysical Abyss

 

(5) Empiricism And The 'Anthropomorphic Brain'

 

(a)  The Empiricist 'Mind' Hits A Brick Wall

 

(b)  Bourgeois Individualism

 

(c) How Not To Solve Philosophical 'Problems' 2.0

 

(d) Intelligent Ideas Versus A 'Little Man' In The Head

 

(i) Added On Edit, October 2024 -- Further Background

 

(ii) Yet More Problems

 

(6) Even More Headaches For Dialecticians

 

(a) Induction And The Social Nature Of Knowledge

 

(i)  Particular Problems With Abstractions

 

(ii) A New Approach Called For

 

(iii) 'Epistemological Thermidor'

 

(iv) The Anti-Democratic Decay Of Dialectical Marxism

 

(v)  Problems Continue To Multiply Like Japanese Knotweed

 

(b) Driven To Abstraction

 

(c) 'Reality': Abstract, Concrete -- Or Both?

 

(d) Collective Error Over General Terms

 

(7) Abstractionism: Have We Come To Bury It -- Or Praise It?

 

(a) You Have Nothing To Lose But Your Confusion

 

(b) Public Criteria Versus Private Gain

 

(c) Particular Problems With 'Dialectical Generality'

 

(8) Anti-Abstractionism

 

(a) 'Mental Strip-Tease'?

 

(b) Don't Scientists Employ Abstraction?

 

(c)  Are Abstractions 'Mentally' Processed?

 

(d) 'Mentally-Processed', According To Marx Himself

 

(e) Anti-Abstractionism

 

(i)   Berkeley And Frege

 

(ii)  The Young Marx And Engels

 

(9) 'Appearance' And 'Reality'

 

(a) The Underlying 'Essence' Of 'Being'

 

(b) Does 'Reality' Contradict 'Appearances'?

 

(i)    'Essence' And 'Appearance'

 

(a) Hegel

 

(b) Dialectical Marxists

 

(ii)   'Commonsense'

 

(iii)  Contradictions Supposedly Generated By Science

 

(iv)  The 'Contradiction' Between Science And 'Commonsense'

 

(v)   Does The Earth Move?

 

(c) Why Science Can't Undermine Common Sense

 

(i)   Ordinary Language Conflated With Common Sense

 

(ii)  Why Scientists Can't Afford To Undermine Common Sense

 

(iii) Can 'Appearances' Be Trusted?

 

(iv) Taking A Rise Out Of The Sun?

 

(v) 'Contradictory' Capitalism?

 

(d) Adrift In A Sea Of 'Appearances'

 

(i)   'Dialectical' Practice Can't Be 'Objective'

 

(ii)  Are All 'Appearances' False?

 

(iii) Dialectics Engages Auto-Destruct Mode

 

(10) Appendix One: Bertell Ollman's Traditionalism

 

(a) Initial Disappointment

 

(b) The Highly Secretive, Mysterious, Privatised 'Process Of Abstraction'

 

(i) Interlude One -- A Recent Failed Attempt To Prove There Actually Is A 'Process Of Abstraction' (Under Construction)

 

(c) Karl Marx -- A Magician?

 

(d) The Young Marx And Engels Torpedo 'Abstractionism'

 

(e) Ollman Misconstrues The Nature Of Change

 

(f) 'Internal Relations' To The Rescue?

 

(g) Welcome To The Desert Of The Reification

 

(h) Brain Scans Required?

 

(i) Ollman Versus The Critics

 

(11) Appendix Two: Plato And Aristotle

 

(a) The Link Between 'The Soul', 'Rationality' And A 'Well-Ordered' City

 

(b) Under Construction

 

(12) Appendix Three: John Rees Attempts To Rescue Lenin (Under Construction)

 

(a) Background Details

 

(b) Rees's Defence

 

(13) Appendix Four: Ernest Mandel On 'Essence', 'Appearance' And 'Abstraction' (Under Construction)

 

(14) Appendix Five: Sean Sayers And The Dialectics Of Confusion (Under Construction)

 

(15) Notes

 

(16) References

 

 

Summary Of My Main Objections To Dialectical Materialism

 

Abbreviations Used At This Site

 

Return To The Main Index Page

 

Contact Me

 

Introduction

 

Part Two of Essay Three continues where Part One left off, focusing on four inter-related topics:

 

(i) Traditional philosophical 'solutions' connected with the 'problem of generality', which involve, inter alia, the invention of 'Universals', 'Forms', 'Abstract Ideas', 'Categories', 'Concepts', 'Representations', and 'Essences' (etc.), many of which were also covered in Part One;

 

(ii) The so-called 'Process of Abstraction' that supposedly helped create or construct one of more of the above items;

 

(iii) The negative effect this has had on Dialectical Marxism;

 

(iv) The intimate connection that between the above three topics and the traditional distinction drawn between "appearance" and "essence"/"reality"; and,

 

(v) How the above are connected with theories concerning 'the rational order of reality'.

 

However, it is important to state up front that in what follows I am neither asserting nor denying there is a 'rational order to reality' (since both alternatives would be metaphysical -- a topic severely criticised at this site, summarised here and here). What is being questioned is the entire tradition in Metaphysics that attempted to explain the world along lines first promoted (in 'the west') by Ancient Greek theorists (principally, Plato and Aristotle) -- i.e., that there is a 'rational order to reality' which can be accounted for by an appeal to 'concepts' generated by what later came to be known as the 'Process of Abstraction'.

 

But first, several traditional attempts to explain the origin and nature of generality -- typically expressed by the use of common nouns and adjectives -- will be examined in detail.01

 

[Whether this also involves verbs and adverbs will be put to one side for now. Verbs were partially covered in Part One. Unfortunately, in this area of Traditional Philosophy and Logic it is all too easy to get lost in the weeds. On that, see Note 01 (link above).]

 

Dialectical Traditionalism

 

Part One of this Essay revealed that, beyond a handful of superficial differences, Dialectical Marxists have latched onto a thoroughly traditional interpretation of the nature and origin of 'abstract general ideas' (expressed by sub-categories of the aforementioned common nouns and adjectives). That Essay also showed how the 'philosophical problem' underlying this approach to 'knowledge' arose out of a series of ideologically-motivated, logical and grammatical moves (and logical blunders) committed by Ancient Greek, ruling-class theorists. This meant the common nouns, verbs and adjectives involved were transformed into the Proper Names of Abstract Particulars [APs], thus destroying their generality.

 

Unfortunately, that vitiated the entire project -- in which broken state it remains to this day.

 

Among other things, this Second Part of Essay Three will further underline how conservative and corrosive this approach to knowledge is, especially in the way it has negatively impacted on theories developed by Dialectical Marxists. Several other Essays at this site will further explore these (disastrous) implications.

 

The Traditional Approach -- Rationalism, Empiricism And 'Original Syntax'

 

Rationalism versus Empiricism

 

A comprehensive examination of the differences between Rationalist and Empiricist Epistemologies is way beyond the scope of this Essay, and this site. But, since DM-theorists share with both of these major strands in Traditional Thought much common ground concerning the connection that supposedly exists between the 'process of abstraction' and our knowledge of the world, a detailed analysis of how dialecticians have attempted to comprehend this 'process' and its (imagined) results is central to the criticisms of Dialectical Marxism advanced at this site.

 

[Also largely omitted from this Part of Essay Three will be an analysis of the difference between Realist and Conceptualist theories of the mode of signification (i.e., the semantic status and role) of general terms. That topic will be covered more extensively in Essay Twelve Part Four. Nominalism will be completely ignored -- mainly because it has had zero influence on Dialectical Marxism.]

 

In rather broad (and slightly misleading) terms, the main difference between these two main intellectual currents (in relation to the above remarks) is that (a) Rationalists tended to view the 'process of abstraction' in terms of recurrence, while, (b) Empiricists did so it in terms of resemblance. In addition, they both (c) Interpreted the 'process of abstraction' itself significantly differently. [More about that presently.]

 

To put this at its crudest, for something to recur it has to, (i) Exist or be present before it is cognised (Realism), or it has to be an (ii) Integral component in the cognitive process itself, such that the latter couldn't take place without it (Conceptualism). By way of contrast, since resemblance is relational (e.g., A resembles B in such and such a respect), for some sort of resemblance to be registered or recognised, (iii) The process itself creates, or constructs the said relation between the cognised relata. Plainly, this means the said resemblance typically doesn't need to exist prior to the relevant 'cognitive act'. [Or so an anti-Realist might claim. Realists and some Conceptualists will, of course, reject that conclusion.]

 

As noted above, these distinctions are rather crude, and as we will see throughout the history of Traditional Thought devoted to this question there has been much 'cross-pollination' between the above two main approaches. Roughly speaking Rationalists tend to adopt one or other of approaches (a)-(i) and (a)-(ii), while Empiricists opt for some form of (b)-(iii). But, as also noted earlier, this entire area of Traditional Thought is a veritable briar patch, so the material that follows in this Essay has had to be simplified considerably -- and that is partly because Dialectical Marxists themselves have adopted highly simplified theories in this area. [And resemblance itself is fraught with pitfalls and complexity. There are many ways in which objects, properties and processes are similar; on this, see Goodman (1970).]

 

[Having said that, this is only to be expected. Marxists in general have been more interested in changing the world than in disappearing down philosophical rabbit holes like this. Revolutionary theory isn't, nor should it be, the equivalent of a post-doctoral seminar on the scholastic distinctions that can be drawn in this area (some of which were briefly outlined in Note 01). or any other. The same is the case with the Essays published at this site -- except where lack of attention to detail has (demonstrably) led dialecticians astray. Whenever that happens it will be pointed out. On that see the next few paragraphs.]

 

As we will discover DM-theorists have by-and-large conflated approaches (a) and (b), which means they have ended up with a theory that is as muddled as it is unworkable -- at any level. But, they aren't alone in this, either; many Traditional Theorists have also conflate (a) and (b) to a greater or lesser extent. As with much else in Traditional Thought, systematic confusion like this has arisen directly out of a radically distorted use of language that was already vague and ambiguous before it was latched onto.

 

[Indeed, as Marx himself pointed out. Incidentally, the above remarks aren't meant to isn't to disparage ordinary language; as will be argued in Essay Twelve Part Seven, vagueness and ambiguity turn out to be two of the vernacular's many strengths. Failure to take this aspect of language into account had led Philosophers astray for well over two thousand years. One particularly notorious example of this -- the alleged 'contradictory nature of motion' -- has been examined in detail in Essay Five.] 

 

Also in what follows, Rationalist and Empiricist 'solutions' to this pseudoproblem have been painted in rather broad brushstrokes (since, once again, this Essay isn't meant to be an exhaustive study of this major wrong turn in the intellectual history of our species; it is merely a means to a specific end; the complete demolition of DM-Epistemology).

 

[Why this is a pseudoproblem was explained in Part One (on that, see for example Note 39 and Note 40), but it will be covered again from a different angle in what follows.] 

 

Rationalism And The 'Problem Of Universals'

 

Traditional Theory

 

As noted earlier, for ideological reasons (to be explored further below and in subsequent Essays), Ancient Greek Metaphysicians concluded that our ability to express generality in language represented a 'philosophical problem'. As a result, they initiated what can only be described as an interminable 'wild goose chase' that involved countless theorists across many centuries in a futile attempt to explain the origin, scope and nature of generality itself, which resulted in a distorted analysis of the mode of signification and use of common nouns and adjectives in indicative sentences. This entire topic was regarded as especially important in view of the key role these words occupied in the formation and growth of knowledge (both scientific and 'philosophical').

 

This pseudoproblem was subsequently given a grandiose title: 'The Problem of Universals'.1

 

As is the case with much of 'Western Philosophy', this 'problem' originated in Ancient Greece, in the work of Plato and Aristotle, and has dominated the last 2500 years of Traditional Thought:

 

"The essence of the theory of Ideas lay in the conscious recognition of the fact that there is a class of entities, for which the best name is probably 'universals', that are entirely different from sensible things. Any use of language involves the recognition, either conscious or unconscious, of the fact that there are such entities; for every word used, except proper names -- every abstract noun, every general noun, every adjective, every verb, even every pronoun and every preposition -- is a name for something of which there are or may be instances. The first step towards the conscious recognition of this class of entities was, if we may believe Aristotle, taken by Socrates when he concentrated on the search for definitions; to ask for the meaning of a general word was a step from the mere use of such a word towards the recognition of universals as a distinct class of entities. But Socrates seems to have been interested in the defining of one thing at a time, and not to have seen the general significance of what he was doing; Plato did see that what was common to all searches for definitions was the assumption that there are such things as universals. He saw, too, that the objective difference between universals and particulars answers to the subjective difference between science and sense-perception. The senses present to us a world of particular events in which qualities are present almost inextricably conjoined and confused; if we were left to the senses alone we should never be able to disentangle them and reach a clear understanding of the structure of the world. But in reason we have a faculty by which we can grasp universals in their pure form and to some extent see the relations that necessarily exist between them." [Ross (1961), p.225. Bold emphases added.]

 

"There have been periods when the problem of universals was the dominating theme of philosophical speculation. One such period was the medieval; another was that of Plato and Aristotle. A strong case might be made, too, for the view that the crux and testing-point of the empiricist argument in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries lay in its theory of universals and that Locke and Berkeley were well aware of this.... The problem of universals, rightly posed, is still fundamental and urgent; for to understand universals is to begin to understand thinking.... What we call conceptual thinking involves the use of general words and no explanation of the successful use of the general word is possible without facing and solving the problem of universals." [Aaron (1967), p.vii. Links added.]

 

Rationalist Philosophers tend to argue that general words/'concepts' (or what they supposedly refer to or reflect) were either anterior to experience or they were 'applied' to 'particulars' encountered in experience, which was itself based on, or was the result of, some form of 'rational cognition' or 'innate intuition' (what Lenin later would call a "law of cognition"). 'Particulars' encountered in experience (such a cat, a dog, a table, or another human being) were thus understood as individual objects of a certain kind (spoken about using so-called 'thing words' -- substantivals -- "cat", "dog", "table", or, before women's rights were even on the agenda, "man"), whose generality was either, (A) The product of 'pure thought', (B) Pre-installed in the 'mind', or (C) 'Apprehended' in some way during experience. [Something similar, but far less fundamental, for want of a better term, was the case with property words/adjectives (such as "red", "hard", or "hot"), and relational expressions (such as "taller", "slower", and "more than").] As such, 'cognitive acts' like these enabled, organised or made experience possible. The 'Concepts', 'Categories' and 'Ideas' implicated in this were supposed to 'represent', 'reflect' or even 'reveal' the 'formal', 'constitutive' or 'essential' properties belonging to each particular --, or they did so with respect to their more ordinary, 'inessential', properties and relations (also known as their 'accidents'). The former made each particular what it was and not something else. So, if some property, F, was viewed as 'essential', a particular, A, to which it belonged would not be the individual it actually was, but something essentially different. For instance, the 'essential' property of the (fictional) character' John we met in Part One was supposed to be his being a man.

 

[We will have good reason to question whether there are any such 'essential properties' in Essay Thirteen Part Two (to be published sometime in 2026). Until then, readers are directed to these comments in Essay Eight Part Two.]

 

So, depending on which Rationalist was telling the tale, particulars were either (1) Already categorised as such in 'external reality' (by 'God', or by some sort of 'collective intelligence' -- Realism, again), (2) Latterly categorised as such by 'the mind' as an integral component of 'cognition' (some forms of Conceptualism), or (3) An ad-mixture of both (Realist-Conceptualism).

 

Either way, a sub-set of these 'abstract general ideas' were held to be 'formal properties' that defined the particulars that instantiated them, while others perhaps occupied a less important role (as accidents). The former were 'apprehended' by 'rational thought', the latter often encountered in experience (but not based on experience). As noted earlier, depending on their precise nature and provenance, these 'abstractions' were variously characterised as "essential", "primary", or "secondary" qualities that individuals (i.e., particulars of a certain sort) either instantiated or in which they were said to "participate". So, 'universals' were either 'pure, rational concepts' or they were 'accidental'/'empirical'.

 

[Although I will later briefly consider questions concerning the possible existence of what came to be known as "bare particulars" -- i.e., particulars that supposedly have no (removable or un-removable) properties (actual or theoretical, essential or inessential), but which can and do somehow possess/'wear' them 'like clothing', and hence are 'bare' without them --, I don't propose to enter into this insoluble metaphysical 'problem' here. Any who would like to know more, and are thereby eager to develop yet another pointless headache, are encouraged to follow the above link and 'then check out Allaire (1963, 1965), Aune (1986), pp.46-54, Aune (2002), pp.132-36, Campbell (1981, 1990), Casullo (1988), Chappell (1964), Moore (1923), Sider (2006), Simons (1994), Stout (1923) (the last five links are to PDFs), and van Cleve (1985), for relatively recent traditional approaches to this 'problem'. A more recent survey of this tangled, briar-patch area of Traditional Metaphysics can be found in Orillia and Paoletti (2020). An 'un-removable property' would seem to be one that is a 'formal' or defining characteristic of an object, such as its number, or its spatio-temporal location, or even that it is a physical entity. They could also be what Traditional Theorists call their 'essential properties', such as the fact that an individual is a human being -- or, as we saw in Part One, the fact that John is a man, etc. Removable properties are then those we can imagine a particular lacking or losing without it fundamentally changing --, for instance, its colour or its size, although there might be 'problems' if some of these are changed too much. On this, see Mellor and Oliver (1997), and Orilia and Paoletti (2020). I briefly return to this topic again below, where I will suggest a way to dissolve this pseudoproblem. Much of what I will be arguing is based on detailed comments posted in Essay Four Part One, specifically here and Note 13 and Note 14.]

 

Here is the late Fraser Cowley on the origin of this approach to the understanding of general terms and the immediate problems it created (readers are encouraged to keep the last sentence of Fraser Cowley's remarks in mind as this Essay unfolds):

 

"The notion of a universal and with it the celebrated problem of universals was invented by Plato.... The distinction of particulars and universals is complemented in many doctrines since Plato with the distinction and division of labour between the senses and the reason or intellect, or understanding. According to these doctrines, what is given to the bodily senses is merely particular, and the understanding or reason alone apprehends, or constructs or derives, the universal. Many philosophers take the problem of universals to be that of the meaning of general terms without realising that what makes the meaning of general terms a problem is the very concept of a universal." [Cowley (1991), p.85. Spelling modified to agree with UK English. Bold emphases added.]

 

"The dispute between rationalism and empiricism concerns the extent to which we are dependent upon sense experience in our effort to gain knowledge. Rationalists claim that there are significant ways in which our concepts and knowledge are gained independently of sense experience.... Rationalists generally develop their view in two ways. First, they argue that there are cases where the content of our concepts or knowledge outstrips the information that sense experience can provide. Second, they construct accounts of how reason in some form or other provides that additional information about the world." [Markie (2021). Paragraphs merged. Bold emphases added.]

 

[As Cowley suggests and as I have explained below how this family of theories -- which I will hereinafter call 'Abstractionism' (i.e., the overall idea that later morphed into a doctrine that there is a 'process of abstraction' we are all supposed to be capable of accessing or utilising (either consciously or unconsciously), which results in the creation, or the production, of 'abstract general terms') -- in the end turns out to be, or was meant to be, a Theory of Meaning. This isn't just an academic point; it is central to understanding how and why DM-theorists have constructed an unworkable, if not incoherent, theory in this respect. As such, this is therefore connected with the contribution DM has itself made to the long-term failure of Dialectical Marxism. (Note, once again, I am not claiming Marxism has been a failure, just its 'dialectical' aberration!)]

 

For Rationalists in general, 'genuine' or 'reliable knowledge' was deemed to be in some way, or in some respect, "in-born", a consequence of 'concepts' or 'faculties' that were themselves "innate", or were in the end based on cognitive processes and structures created and underwritten by 'God' -- or which enabled, or was enabled by, the very possibility of there being such a thing as knowledge. [In support of theories like this several so-called 'Transcendental Arguments' were invented as required.]

 

Here is Descartes (expressing ideas that were typical of this sub-branch of ruling-class ideology):

 

"For since God has endowed each of us with some light of reason by which to distinguish truth from error, I could not have believed that I ought for a single moment to rest satisfied with the opinions of another, unless I had resolved to exercise my own judgment in examining these whenever I should be duly qualified for the task...." [Descartes (1997b), Part 3, p.88. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"The most important point is that I find in myself countless ideas of things that can’t be called nothing, even if they don’t exist anywhere outside me. For although I am free to think of these ideas or not, as I choose, I didn’t invent them: they have their own true and immutable natures, which are not under my control. Even if there are not and never were any triangles outside my thought, still, when I imagine a triangle I am constrained in how I do this, because there is a determinate nature or essence or form of triangle that is eternal, unchanging, and independent of my mind. Consider the things that I can prove about the triangle – that its three angles equal two right angles, that its longest side is opposite its greatest angle, and so on. I am forced to agree that the triangle has these properties, even if I didn’t give them a thought when the triangle first came into my mind. So they can’t have been invented by me." [Descartes (1997c), Fifth Meditation,  pp.170-71. (This links to a different translation.) Bold emphases alone added. The clear implication is that 'God' not only invented these 'ideas', they were implanted by 'Him'. That is certainly how Descartes argues throughout his work.]

 

"The mathematical truths which you call eternal have been laid down by God and depend on him entirely no less than the rest of his creatures. Indeed to say that these truths are independent of God is to talk of him as if he were Jupiter or Saturn and to subject him to the Styx and the Fates. Please do not hesitate to assert and proclaim everywhere that it is God who has laid down these laws in nature just as a king lays down laws in his kingdom." [Descartes (1991), p.23. Letter to Mersenne, 15/04/1630, in Bennett (2019), p.14. (This links to a PDF.) Bold emphases added.]

 

"As for the eternal truths, I say once more that they are true or possible only because God knows them as true or possible. They are not known as true by God in any way which would imply that they are true independently of him. If men really understood the sense of their words they could never say without blasphemy that the truth of anything is prior to the knowledge which God has of it. In God willing and knowing are a single thing in such a way that by the very fact of willing something he knows it and it is only for this reason that such a thing is true. So we must not say that if God did not exist nevertheless these truths would be true; for the existence of God is the first and the most eternal of all possible truths and the one from which alone all others proceed." [Ibid., p.24. Letter to Mersenne, 06/05/1630, in Bennett (2019), p.16. (This links to a PDF.) Bold emphasis added.]

 

Naturally, this means that for such thinkers objects and events in the physical universe were somehow 'less real' than the abstractions that supposedly lent them both their substantiality and their 'essence' -- or, indeed, which allowed them even to be experienced. This 'hidden world of abstractions' and 'essences' was therefore more 'real' than the world we see around us.

 

[In Part One we saw theorists like Engels and Lenin echo these sentiments; here in Part Two we will witness DM-theorists in general further promote these anti-materialist sentiments.]

 

Partly because of this, in the Rationalist Tradition the general, the 'rational' came to dominate over the particular, the 'accidental' and the 'irrational'; the Ideal and the 'necessary' were given precedence over the physical and the contingent. Hence, as noted above, invisible and in principle undetectable 'essences' were regarded as more real than the individual objects and events we encounter in everyday life. Here is Plato giving birth to this idea:

 

"If mind and true opinion are two distinct classes, then I say that there certainly are these self-existent ideas unperceived by sense, and apprehended only by the mind; if, however, as some say, true opinion differs in no respect from mind, then everything that we perceive through the body is to be regarded as most real and certain. But we must affirm that to be distinct, for they have a distinct origin and are of a different nature; the one is implanted in us by instruction, the other by persuasion; the one is always accompanied by true reason, the other is without reason; the one cannot be overcome by persuasion, but the other can: and lastly, every man may be said to share in true opinion, but mind is the attribute of the gods and of very few men. Wherefore also we must acknowledge that there is one kind of being which is always the same, uncreated and indestructible, never receiving anything into itself from without, nor itself going out to any other, but invisible and imperceptible by any sense, and of which the contemplation is granted to intelligence only." [Plato (1997c), 51e-52a, pp.1254-55. I have used the on-line version here. Bold emphases added. The published edition translates the third set of highlighted words as follows: "It is indivisible -- it cannot be perceived by the senses at all -- and it is the role of the understanding to study it." Cornford renders it: "[It is] invisible and otherwise imperceptible; that, in fact, which thinking has for its object." (Cornford (1997), p.192.)]

 

Furthermore, concerning the Rationalist Philosophers who directly influenced the DM-classicists we read the following:

 

"Already with Fichte the idea of the unity of the sciences, of system, was connected with that of finding a reliable starting-point in certainty on which knowledge could be based. Thinkers from Kant onwards were quite convinced that the kind of knowledge which came from experience was not reliable. Empirical knowledge could be subject to error, incomplete, or superseded by further observation or experiment. It would be foolish, therefore, to base the whole of knowledge on something which had been established only empirically. The kind of knowledge which Kant and his followers believed to be the most secure was a priori knowledge, the kind embodied in the laws of Nature. These had been formulated without every occurrence of the Natural phenomenon in question being observed, so they did not summarise empirical information, and yet they held good by necessity for every case; these laws were truly universal in their application." [White (1996a), p.29. Bold emphasis added.]

 

As we have just seen this approach originated with Plato. On that, see Appendix 2b.

 

And here is Hegel echoing and amplifying these idea, but adding to it an overtly theological emphasis:

 

"The view that the objects of immediate consciousness, which constitute the body of experience, are mere appearances (phenomena) was another important result of the Kantian philosophy. Common Sense, that mixture of sense and understanding, believes the objects of which it has knowledge to be severally independent and self-supporting; and when it becomes evident that they tend towards and limit one another, the interdependence of one upon another is reckoned something foreign to them and to their true nature. The very opposite is the truth. The things immediately known are mere appearances -- in other words, the ground of their being is not in themselves but in something else. But then comes the important step of defining what this something else is. According to Kant, the things that we know about are to us appearances only, and we can never know their essential nature, which belongs to another world we cannot approach. Plain minds have not unreasonably taken exception to this subjective idealism, with its reduction of the facts of consciousness to a purely personal world, created by ourselves alone. For the true statement of the case is rather as follows. The things of which we have direct consciousness are mere phenomena, not for us only, but in their own nature; and the true and proper case of these things, finite as they are, is to have their existence founded not in themselves but in the universal divine Idea. This view of things, it is true, is as idealist as Kant's; but in contradistinction to the subjective idealism of the Critical philosophy should be termed absolute idealism. Absolute idealism, however, though it is far in advance of vulgar realism, is by no means merely restricted to philosophy. It lies at the root of all religion; for religion too believes the actual world we see, the sum total of existence, to be created and governed by God." [Hegel (1975, §45, p.73. Links in the original. Bold emphases added; paragraphs merged.]

 

"[O]nly...God is actual... He is the supreme actuality, that He alone is truly actual; but also, as regards the logical bearings of the question, that existence is in part mere appearance, and only in part actuality." [Ibid., p.9, §6; bold emphasis added.]

 

Allen Wood neatly summarised Hegel's entire approach in the following terms:

 

"Hegel sees reality as structured organically and developmentally. Things display their essential natures when they are seen as organized wholes or systems, and as elements of larger wholes or systems. These systems are characterized by tendencies not only to self-harmony and self-maintenance, but also to development, both temporally and hierarchically. Things which exist through time have essential tendencies to develop, to unfold their natures by continually changing or revolutionizing their organic structures. Organic structures themselves display a hierarchy, developing or unfolding a certain abstract essence or basic principle toward its full concreteness. A theory which captures the structure of reality must conceive things as organized totalities. It must attend to their essential tendencies to temporal development, and it must analyze their organic structure through a hierarchy of concepts of or viewpoints on a whole which reveal all the levels or stages belonging to its nature. Hegel is sure reality has this structure on purely metaphysical grounds. Hegel believes that absolute reality is self-positing spirit. The marks of thought and its creative self-expression are organic interconnection and development. Consequently, whatever appears or is actual must be an expression or manifestation of spirit, and must display the marks of its spiritual origin. Further, the creative activity of thought is simultaneously the activity of God's original creation; the activity of human thought which apprehends the inherent structure of thinking thus brings God's thoughts to self-consciousness. Since the dialectical structure of thinking is apprehended not by the senses but by reason, our key to the structure of reality is not casual sense observations but the necessary movement of thought, which philosophers can produce out of their own minds. The task of philosophy is to penetrate these observations and 'give to their contents the essential shape of thoughts freedom (the a priori)'." [Wood (2004), pp.215-16. Bold emphasis alone added; paragraphs merged. Wood is (partially) quoting Hegel (1975), p.18, §12.]

 

And here is Mega-DM enthusiast, George Novack, underlining how far dialecticians like him are prepared to bend over to accommodate the mystical ideas they imported from Hegel:

 

"We have already seen what great measure of truth there is in the proposition that the real is rational. We have ascertained that all things come into existence and endure in a lawful and necessary way. But this is not the whole and final truth about things. It is one-sided, relative, and a passing truth. The real truth about things is that they not only exist, persist, but they also develop and pass away. This passing away of things, eventuating in death, is expressed in logical terminology by the term 'negation.' The whole truth about things can be expressed only if we take into account this opposite and negative aspect. In other words, unless we introduce the negation of our first affirmation, we shall obtain only a superficial and abstract inspection of reality.

 

"All things are limited and changing. They not only force their way and are forced into existence and maintain themselves there. They also develop, disintegrate and are pushed out of existence and eventually disappear. In logical terms, they not only affirm themselves. They likewise negate themselves and are negated by other things. By coming into existence, they say: 'Yes! Here I am!' to reality and to thought engaged in understanding reality. By developing and eventually going out of existence, they say on the contrary: 'No, I no longer am; I cannot stay real.' If everything that comes into existence must pass out of existence, as all of reality pounds constantly into our brains, then every affirmation must inexorably express its negation in logical thought. Such a movement of things and of thought is called a dialectical movement.

 

'All things...meet their doom; and in saying so, we have a perception that Dialectic is the universal and irresistible power, before which nothing can stay, however secure and stable it may deem itself,' writes Hegel. (Shorter Logic, p.128.) [I.e., Hegel (1975), p.118, §81 -- RL.]

 

"There is a fable in The Arabian Nights about an Oriental monarch who, early in life, asked his wise men for the sum and substance of all learning, for the truth that would apply to everything at all times and under all conditions, a truth which would be as absolutely sovereign as he thought himself to be. Finally, over the king's deathbed, his wise men supplied the following answer: 'Oh, mighty king, this one truth will always apply to all things: "And this too shall pass away".' If justice prevailed, the king should have bequeathed a rich reward to his wise men, for they had disclosed to him the secret of the dialectic. This is the power, the omnipotence of the negative side of existence, which is forever emerging from, annihilating and transcending the affirmative aspect of things. This 'powerful unrest,' as Leibnitz (sic) called it, this quickening force and destructive action of life -- the negative -- is everywhere at work: in the movement of things, in the growth of living beings, in the transformations of substances, in the evolution of society, and in the human mind which reflects all these objective processes.

 

"From this dialectical essence of reality Hegel drew the conclusion that constitutes an indispensable part of his famous aphorism: All that is rational is real. But for Hegel all that is real is not without exception and qualification worthy of existence. 'Existence is in part mere appearance, and only in part reality.' (Introduction to the Shorter Logic, §6.)  [I.e., Hegel (1975), p.9, §6 -- RL.] Existence elementally and necessarily divides itself, and the investigating mind finds it to be so divided, into opposing aspects of appearance and essence. This disjunction between appearance and essence is no more mysterious than the disjunction between the inside and outside of an object. What distinguishes essence or essential reality from mere appearance? A thing is truly real if it is necessary, if its appearance truly corresponds to its essence, and only so long as it proves itself to be necessary. Hegel, being the most consistent idealist, sought the source of this necessity in the movement of the universal mind, in the Absolute Idea. Materialists, on the other hand, locate the roots of necessity in the objective world, in the material conditions and conflicting forces which create, sustain and destroy all things. But, from the purely logical standpoint, both schools of philosophy agree in connecting reality with necessity. Something acquires reality because the necessary conditions for its production and reproduction are objectively present and operative. It becomes more or less real in accordance with the changes in the external and internal circumstances of its development. It remains truly real only so long and insofar as it is necessary under the given conditions. Then, as conditions change, it loses its necessity and its reality and dissolves into mere appearance.

 

"Let us consider a few illustrations of this process, this contradiction between essence and appearance, resulting from the different forms assumed by matter in its motion. In the production of the plant, seed, bud, flower and fruit are all equally necessary phases or forms of its existence. Taken separately, each by itself, they are all equally real, equally necessary, equally rational phases of the plant's development. Yet each in turn becomes supplanted by the other and thereby becomes no less unnecessary and non-real. Each phase of the plant's manifestation appears as a reality and then is transformed in the course of development into an unreality or an appearance. This movement, triadic in this particular case, from unreality into reality and then back again to unreality, constitutes the essence, the inner movement behind all appearance. Appearance cannot be understood without an understanding of this process. It is this that determines whether any appearance in nature, society or in the mind is rational or non-rational. Yet each in turn becomes supplanted by the other and thereby becomes no less unnecessary and non-real. Each phase of the plant's manifestation appears as a reality and then is transformed in the course of development into an unreality or an appearance. This movement, triadic in this particular case, from unreality into reality and then back again to unreality, constitutes the essence, the inner movement behind all appearance. Appearance cannot be understood without an understanding of this process. It is this that determines whether any appearance in nature, society or in the mind is rational or non-rational." [Novack (1971), pp.84-87. Several paragraphs merged; quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. I have reproduced the version of Hegel's work used by the editor of Novack's on-line text, Andy Blunden, not the one that appears here. Links and bold emphases added.]

 

[I have subjected Novack's remarks to detailed criticism in Note 29b.]

 

According to the above, whatever isn't 'rational' can't therefore be 'real'. So, if objects (like plants, for instance) are to be counted as even temporarily real, that would only be because of the (undetectable) 'rational principles' they supposedly instantiate.

 

But, where exactly are these 'rational principles', these 'abstractions', to be found? In the world or just in each head?

 

As we discovered in Part One (Sections Two and Three), the answer to that question is neither -- 'dialectical abstractions' are nowhere to be found in the physical universe! Even so, they are supposed to be 'more real' than the objects and events that instantiate them. Go figure...

 

This from a materialist!

 

That helps explain why DM-fans find it impossibly difficult to tell the rest of us (or even each other, for goodness sake!) exactly with what in 'extra-mental reality' their 'abstractions' actually correspond. [Here is a just recent example of the corner into which they have painted themselves.] If there were anything in the physical universe for these 'abstractions', these 'rational principles', to correspond with, that would clearly imply nature is 'Mind' or the product of 'Mind'. How else could such thoroughly 'mental entities' exist in the physical universe if the latter wasn't 'Mind' or the product of 'Mind'? If they actually exist in 'extra-mental reality', 'mind must precede matter', and if, as we will see later, matter itself is also regarded as an 'abstraction' by DM-enthusiasts, 'reality' must ultimately be 'Mind' or 'Mind-like', all the way down. On the other hand, if there isn't anything in nature or society with which these 'mental entities' correspond, what possible use are they? Have they simply been invented to help boost the morale of DM-theorists? Or perhaps give them something over which they can endlessly bicker, thus allowing them to accuse each other, or the rest of us, of 'not understanding dialectics'?

 

[Of course, the answer often given is that 'abstractions' help scientists and philosophers 'understand/manipulate reality', but as we are about to find out, not even that is true.]

 

As the Book of Genesis would have us believe, it takes the 'Word of God' (or something analogous to it) to give life and form to matter, creating 'everything out of nothing'. Without that, the universe would have remained lifeless, chaotic and might even cease to exist --, or, indeed, might never have begun to exist:

 

"And the earth was without form, and void; and darkness was upon the face of the deep. And the Spirit of God moved upon the face of the waters. And God said, Let there be light: and there was light.... And God said, Let there be a firmament in the midst of the waters, and let it divide the waters from the waters. And God called the firmament Heaven.... And God said, Let the waters under the heaven be gathered together unto one place, and let the dry land appear: and it was so. And God called the dry land Earth; and the gathering together of the waters called he Seas: and God saw that it was good. And God said, Let the earth bring forth grass, the herb yielding seed, and the fruit tree yielding fruit after his kind, whose seed is in itself, upon the earth: and it was so...." [Genesis, Chapter One, verses 2-11. Bold emphases added.]

 

"In the beginning was the Word [λόγος -- logos], and the Word was with God, and the Word was God. He was with God in the beginning. Through him all things were made; without him nothing was made that has been madeIn him was life, and that life was the light of all mankind." [John 1:1-4. Bold emphasis added.]

 

'Abstractions' were likewise conjured into existence in a similar, but less overtly religious, way. They are and have always been Ideal 'objects of thought' -- that is, they either represent a given philosopher's 'Ideas' or they are integral to the 'thoughts' attributed to one or more of the many 'deities' humans have dreamt up throughout history -- and that includes Hegel's 'Absolute'. As we will see, every single DM-theorist calls the 'abstractions they have conjured into existence, 'mental entities'. [On that, see Sections 8c and 8d, below.]

 

This is the ideological cess pit out of which DM-theorists hauled their theory!

 

As I also noted in Part One:

 

Philosophy was now viewed as a unique and special source of Super-Knowledge -- knowledge that is not just anterior to, it is even more fundamental than, anything the sciences could possibly deliver. It is "Superscientific" because its theories reveal Super-Necessities that underpin 'Being' itself, knowledge of which is only attainable by the application of 'reason'. As Immanuel Kant noted:

 

"First, concerning the sources of metaphysical cognition, it already lies in the concept of metaphysics that they cannot be empirical. The principles of such cognition (which include not only its fundamental propositions or basic principles, but also its fundamental concepts) must therefore never be taken from experience; for the cognition is supposed to be not physical but metaphysical, i.e., lying beyond experience. Therefore it will be based upon neither outer experience, which constitutes the source of physics proper, nor inner, which provides the foundation of empirical psychology. It is therefore cognition a priori, or from pure understanding and pure reason.... Metaphysical cognition must contain nothing but judgments a priori, as required by the distinguishing feature of its sources." [Kant (1953), pp.15-16. (This links to a PDF.) I have quoted the on-line version which is a different translation to the one I have referenced. Bold emphases and link added; paragraphs merged.]

 

"Lying beyond experience", of course, implies philosophical knowledge is superior to anything science has to offer.

 

As we also saw in Part One, in the end these 'objects of thought' turned out to be Abstract Particulars (or the Proper Names thereof). This meant that for Rationalists, while 'reality itself' was held to be essentially Ideal, the physical universe was in effect a Shadow World, not fully 'real', since it was where contingency, brute facts, 'appearances', finitude and uncertainty reigned supreme. But, as Plato and Hegel argued, the 'rational structure' that supposedly lay 'behind appearances' was the really real world. Indeed, as we saw, for Hegel only 'God' was "truly actual", fully 'real'. In that case, the invisible world that supposedly underpins the material universe, which is home to humanity's countless deities and 'abstractions', may only be accessed by non-physical means -- via 'thought alone'. But, this had to be 'thought' of a rather  special kind, belonging to a select group of socially privileged thinkers'/'ideologues' -- "prize-fighters" of the ruling elite.

 

And now, DM-fans.

 

[A brute fact is one for which no other fact is necessary in order to 'explain' it. So, if an object falls to the earth, that fact needs further facts about gravity to explain what happened or even why it did. But what then explains gravity? Well, there may be something that explains gravity. But, at some point we are going to hit a brick wall where we have to say, "Well, that's just how nature works!" That would be a brute fact. Of course, exactly when and where we hit this brick wall will change over time, but even if we hit an 'ultimate fact' -- maybe as part of a Grand Unified Theory, a GUT (which was all the rage twenty or so years ago), which supposedly explained everything -- the next question will be "Ok, so what explains that?" Even an appal to 'god' won't prevent this slide, since any question about what explains why 'god' did what 'he' did will hit the "It's all a mystery!" brick wall -- leaving us with a 'mysterious brute fact' -- 'god'. Which is. of course, where all 'proofs' for the existence of this imaginary 'being' end -- 'mysterious brute facts'. On this, see also here.]

 

If general terms -- e.g., common nouns, such as "cat", "table", "human", "money", "value", "population", or adjectives such as "red", "cold" or "heavy", etc., etc. -- were in some way capable of reflecting the 'essence' of material bodies (and/or their 'accidental properties' and inter-relationships, if we also include the use of verbs and adverbs), then, according to this approach to theory that would be because of the Abstract Particulars [AP] to which they supposedly refer or which they instantiate. [For example, these APs might be 'The Form of the Cat', 'The Concept, Table', 'The Population', 'Redness', 'Sameness', etc., etc.] Hence, APs must be 'ontologically'-, and even 'epistemologically'-, anterior to the objects to which we supposedly refer by our use of such words. So, for Rationalists, APs exist (in some form or other) prior to, or in conjunction with, the objects they instantiate. This means APs underpin the latter's limited, temporary, or 'apparent', actuality. For other Rationalists they were merely 'mental constructs' to which reference must be made in order to understand 'extra-mental reality'.1a

 

We will see Engels, Lenin and other DM-theorists reach similar conclusions, arguing that the 'concrete' only succeeds in being concrete (or is only concrete) because of the abstractions to which we have to appeal in order for them even to be concrete in the first place. That clearly implies there are no concrete objects and processes until they have been so processed! Oddly enough for those who at least claim to be materialists, this led them into believing matter is also an abstraction! In which case, these self-proclaimed, 'hard-headed materialists' found themselves tail-ending Idealist Philosophers by their adoption of at least four core principles of Rationalism (not that these are its only defining characteristics):

 

(i) Abstract knowledge is not only superior to empirical knowledge, it is its necessary pre-requisite;

 

(ii) Matter is fundamentally abstract;

 

(iii) There is an 'underlying rational order to reality', accessible to thought alone; and,

 

(iv) 'Appearances' are 'deceptive'!

 

It is here where we witness (yet again) the conflation of 'talk about talk' with 'talk about the world' -- i.e., an approach that confuses linguistic and logical categories with reality itself; a profound muddle analysed in Part One. We met it, for example, when we examined the ideas of theorists who interpreted predicates as:

 

(a) The referents of general terms (i.e., the objects or sets of objects in the world supposedly designated or named by predicate expressions) -- which often also supposedly stood for the properties of objects and events; and,

 

(b) Linguistic expressions in their own right.

 

Hence, for such theorists, predicates were both linguistic and extra-linguistic at the same time!

 

A semantic slide like this definitely confused Hegel; it prompted him into imagining that what went on in his head (as he juggled with certain words/'concepts') reflected, if not constituted, objects and events in the 'external' world. Hence, he thereby thought he was free to project the contents of his head onto 'external reality'. As should seem obvious, that is as egregious a case of Epistemological Megalomania as one could wish to find. A sort of cosmic version of disturbed individuals who think they are Napoleon, The 'Messiah', or even 'God'.

 

 

Figure One: Megalomania Clearly Isn't Confined To German Mystics

Who Also Talk Boll*cks

 

While Descartes imagined there were two substances -- 'Mind' and 'Matter' --, it soon became apparent (in the work of Spinoza, and in a somewhat different form in Leibniz's work, and later still in Hegel's 'theory' -- but now on steroids) that there is only one 'rational', 'actual' or 'real' substance: 'Mind'. Everything else is an 'appearance', or even an 'emanation', and as such is 'accidental', 'ephemeral', transient, contingent.

 

[Readers might now like to go back and re-check Novak's comments to see to what extent ideas like these have been thoroughly internalised by DM-theorists. He is typical of the genre.]

 

The traditional approach, which particularises common nouns and adjectives and nominalises verbs, has, in one form or another, dominated Western Thought -- and, currently, DM -- for the best part of 2500 years. Its 'logical apex' (if that is the right tem) was reached in the metaphysical systems constructed by Leibniz and Hegel, and only serves to underline the claim advanced in these Essays that all ancient, medieval, early modern and contemporary versions of Rationalist Philosophy are simply different forms of Idealism (and that includes DM -- as we saw in Essays Twelve Part One and Thirteen Part One). As we will also see, this approach to generality (and the meaning of general terms) has filtered into every subsequent metaphysical system, and to such an extent that it is now abundantly clear that all forms of Traditional Philosophy -- Rationalist, Nominalist, Realist, Monist, Dualist, Empiricist and Positivist -- are just different forms of Idealism.

 

Which is one of the few things Hegel managed to get right:

 

"Every philosophy is essentially an idealism or at least has idealism for its principle, and the question then is only how far this principle is carried out." [Hegel (1999), pp.154-55; §316. Bold emphasis added.]

 

[Why that seemingly controversial remark also applies to Empiricism, Nominalism and Positivism will be entered into presently. Follow the above links for an explanation of what is meant by "particularises" and "nominalises".]

 

These "ruling ideas" -- originally concocted in 'the West' by Ancient Greek Philosophers -- have now found a home in contemporary bourgeois thought, albeit with brand new content mirroring the novel social and economic conditions in which they were conceived and now flourish.

 

Even when this 'theory' is flipped "right-side up" (or "put back on its feet" -- supposedly by dialecticians), material reality is still regarded as secondary, derivative, dependent, not fully real. Once again, witness where we are told by erstwhile materialists that matter is an abstraction. The material world, according to DM-theorists, requires the 'rational principles' encapsulated in DL to give it life and form. After all, 'underlying essence contradicts appearances', and in that 'philosophical wrestling match', it is "essence" that always ends on top.1aa

 

Here, for example, is Lenin:

 

"Logical concepts are subjective so long as they remain 'abstract,' in their abstract form, but at the same time they express the Thing-in-themselves. Nature is both concrete and abstract, both phenomenon and essence, both moment and relation." [Lenin (1961), p.208. Italic emphases in the original.]

 

"Thought proceeding from the concrete to the abstract -- provided it is correct (NB)… -- does not get away from the truth but comes closer to it. The abstraction of matter, the law of nature, the abstraction of value, etc., in short all scientific (correct, serious, not absurd) abstractions reflect nature more deeply, truly and completely." [Ibid., p.171. Italic emphases in the original.]

 

Notice that it is abstraction that drives thought closer to the truth. Moreover, as we saw in Part One, according to Engels and Lenin, the concrete only emerges (or can only be appreciated as concrete) at the end of an infinite process. In that case, nothing could ever rightly be said to be concrete until that endless task had been completed, which is clearly impossible. [We will also see later that Lenin is even less ambiguous concerning several other things he had to say about the mysterious 'process of abstraction' (here and here).]

 

In like manner, again according to DM-theorists, the 'Dialectical Logos' (i.e., 'Logic') is required, not just to add form to formless matter, but to call it into existence, give it life, make it move, and for all of this literally to have emerged out of 'Nothing'. Creation ex nihilo isn't just a Christian doctrine, it is also a DM-dogma, courtesy of Hegel's 'derivation' of everything from 'Being' and 'Nothing' -- via 'Becoming'.

 

Here is what I have written elsewhere about this 'derivation' by Hegel (slightly edited):

 

One particular 'argument' is of special interest here; it crops up in different forms in several places in Hegel's work, and attempts to connect "Being" with "Nothing" and then both with "Becoming", by magically 'deriving' all three from the verb "to be"....

 

Amazingly, this 'argument' was praised by Lenin and Trotsky....

 

Rees summarised thus 'argument' in the following way:

 

"The 'Science of Logic' begins with the most abstract of all human ideas, Being. This is the bare notion of existence shorn of any colour, size, shape, taste or smell. This first concept is also, in its way, a totality. Although Being reveals no characteristics or distinguishing marks, it does, nevertheless, include everything. After all, everything must exist before it can take on any particular characteristics. Being is therefore a quality that is shared by everything that exists; it is the most common of all human ideas. Every time we say, 'This is --,' even before we say what it is, we acknowledge the idea of pure Being…. But Being also contains its opposite, Nothing. The reason is that Being has no qualities and no features that define it. If we try to think about pure Being…we are forced to the opposite conclusion, Being equals Nothing.

 

"But even Nothing is more than it seems. If we are asked to define Nothing, we are forced to admit that it has at least one property -– the lack or absence of any qualities…. This presents us with a strange dilemma: being is Nothing and yet Nothing is something. Hegel, however, is not so stupid as to think that there is no difference between being and Nothing, even though this is what our logical enquiry seems to suggest. All that this contradiction means is that we must search for a new term that…can explain how Being and Nothing can be both equal and separate (or an 'identity of opposites'…). Hegel's solution is the concept of Becoming." [Rees (1998), pp.49-50. Spelling adjusted in line with UK English; quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

But, there is no way that these concepts ("Being", "Nothing" and "Becoming") could have been derived from "careful empirical work", nor can they be "tested in practice" -- let alone abstracted from anything that is recognisably material.

 

In the end, the fact that erstwhile materialists (like Lenin and Trotsky -- or even Rees, since he nowhere criticises this 'argument') praised this prime example of linguistic mystification isn't the least bit surprising -- when their own ideas are viewed against the class-compromised background of Traditional Thought.

 

This is how Trotsky characterised it:

 

"The identity of Being (Sein) and Nothingness (Nichts), like the contradictoriness of the concept of the Beginning, in which Nichts and Sein are united, seems at first glance a subtle and fruitless play of ideas. In fact, this 'game' brilliantly exposes the failure of static thinking, which at first splits the world into motionless elements, and then seeks truth by way of a limitless expansion [of the process]." [Trotsky (1986), p.103.]

 

Whereas Lenin thought it was:

 

"Shrewd and clever! Hegel analyses concepts that usually appear dead and shows that there is movement in them." [Lenin (1961), p.110.]

 

However, at no point do Rees and other DM-fans repudiate this style of reasoning, only some of its 'Ideal' implications -- which, coupled with the praise Lenin and Trotsky heaped upon it, indicates that, for dialecticians, the rejection of Hegelian Absolute Idealism is purely formal, and clearly superficial. By no stretch of the imagination have any of the above conclusions been drawn from "an analysis of real material forces", or anything even remotely like one. The fact that leading DM-classicists could claim to learn anything about the nature of "static thinking" from such woefully defective 'logic' reveals how superficial their frequent and vociferous rejection of Absolute Idealism really is. The 'logic' of this passage is entirely bogus and thoroughly Idealist, again, as George Novack noted:

 

"A consistent materialism cannot proceed from principles which are validated by appeal to abstract reason, intuition, self-evidence or some other subjective or purely theoretical source. Idealisms may do this. But the materialist philosophy has to be based upon evidence taken from objective material sources and verified by demonstration in practice...." [Novack (1965), p.17. Bold emphasis added.]

 

The concepts Hegel employed are the result of grossly exaggerated abstractions, tortured 'logic' and terminally dubious assertions....

 

In fact, this Hegelian 'derivation' has set a new gold standard for all forms of LIE, for from it everything in existence -- every object, thought and process -- can be 'derived' miraculously from the verb "to be"!

 

[LIE = Linguistic Idealism; follow that link for an explanation.]

 

So, even for dialecticians, matter isn't sufficient to itself -- indeed, as we have seen, it is an 'abstraction'. Which is, of course, why Hegel and Dialectical Marxists found they had to appeal to a linguistic form -- i.e., to 'contradiction' -- to set things in motion, keep them moving and give them life. Uncoincidentally, as we also saw earlier, according to the Bible, the universe, life and movement were created by, and are now sustained via, language and 'logic' (i.e., the Logos, again). In DM, these ideas are mirrored by the above linguistic forms, which have been projected onto reality, but in a secular form. That should surprise no one given the fact that Hegel was a Christian Mystic:

 

"Contradiction is the root of all movement and life, and it is only in so far as it contains a contradiction that anything moves and has impulse and activity." [Hegel (1999), p.439, §956. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"So long as we consider things at rest and lifeless, each one by itself…we do not run up against any contradictions in them…. But the position is quite different as soon as we consider things in their motion, their change, their life, their reciprocal influence. Then we immediately become involved in contradictions. Motion itself is a contradiction…. [T]here is a contradiction objectively present in things and processes themselves, a contradiction is moreover an actual force...." [Engels (1976), pp.152-53. Bold emphases added.]

 

"Dialectics…prevails throughout nature…. [T]he motion through opposites which asserts itself everywhere in nature, and which by the continual conflict of the opposites…determines the life of nature." [Engels (1954), p.211. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"The identity of opposites…is the recognition…of the contradictory, mutually exclusive, opposite tendencies in all phenomena and processes of nature…. The condition for the knowledge of all processes of the world in their 'self-movement,' in their spontaneous development, in their real life, is the knowledge of them as a unity of opposites. Development is the 'struggle' of opposites. The two basic (or two possible? or two historically observable?) conceptions of development (evolution) are: development as decrease and increase, as repetition, and development as a unity of opposites (the division of a unity into mutually exclusive opposites and their reciprocal relation).

 

"In the first conception of motion, self-movement, its driving force, its source, its motive, remains in the shade (or this source is made external -- God, subject, etc.). In the second conception the chief attention is directed precisely to knowledge of the source of 'self'-movement. The first conception is lifeless, pale and dry. The second is living. The second alone furnishes the key to the 'self-movement' of everything existing; it alone furnishes the key to the 'leaps,' to the 'break in continuity,' to the 'transformation into the opposite,' to the destruction of the old and the emergence of the new. The unity (coincidence, identity, equal action) of opposites is conditional, temporary, transitory, relative. The struggle of mutually exclusive opposites is absolute, just as development and motion are absolute." [Lenin (1961), pp.357-58. Bold emphases alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Several paragraphs merged.]

 

"The law of contradiction in things, that is, the law of the unity of opposites, is the basic law of materialist dialectics.... As opposed to the metaphysical world outlook, the world outlook of materialist dialectics holds that in order to understand the development of a thing we should study it internally and in its relations with other things; in other words, the development of things should be seen as their internal and necessary self-movement, while each thing in its movement is interrelated with and interacts on the things around it. The fundamental cause of the development of a thing is not external but internal; it lies in the contradictoriness within the thing. There is internal contradiction in every single thing, hence its motion and development....

 

"The universality or absoluteness of contradiction has a twofold meaning. One is that contradiction exists in the process of development of all things, and the other is that in the process of development of each thing a movement of opposites exists from beginning to end....There is nothing that does not contain contradictions; without contradiction nothing would exist.... Thus it is already clear that contradiction exists universally and is in all processes, whether in the simple or in the complex forms of motion, whether in objective phenomena or ideological phenomena.... Contradiction is universal and absolute, it is present in the process of the development of all things and permeates every process from beginning to end...." [Mao (1937), pp.311-18. Bold emphases added; several paragraphs merged.]

 

Because of this, it isn't possible to find -- nor even to suggest there might be -- a single physical correlate in nature or society for the 'abstractions' dialecticians have dreamt up (or, to be more honest, imported from Hegel and other ruling-class ideologues) to correspond with. But, since they form the 'essential nature' of material objects and processes, this can only mean that, for DM-fans, they must be Ideal, too.

 

And, in a nutshell, that is why Dialectical Marxists think matter is an 'abstraction', and hence why the aforementioned "flip" they allegedly performed on Hegel's system was actually through the full 360º, not the 180º they now try to claim for it. Nor is it at all surprising to find that they have had to denigrate, or at least depreciate, ordinary language and with it the lives and experience of ordinary workers -- accusing them of being trapped by 'commonsense', 'formal thinking' and 'false consciousness' (thus reprising a rhetorical flourish perfected by countless generations of ruling-class hacks), in order to 'justify' and rationalise the importation of Hegelian concepts into the workers' movement.

 

[The above accusations will be substantiated in Essay Twelve (summary here). They have already been covered from a different angle in Essay Nine Parts One and Two, where the underlying motives driving DM-advocates in this direction were exposed.]

 

As we will discover throughout the rest of this site, because of their reliance on the traditional thought-forms, which they have imported into revolutionary socialism, dialecticians have only succeeded in saddling themselves and our movement with a set of insoluble 'philosophical problems'. This also helps explain why every single dialectician slips into a priori, dogmatic mode at the drop of a copula --, and why they all fail to notice they have done so even after it has been pointed out to them!

 

[The point of the copula remark will be clear to anyone who has read Part One of this Essay.]

 

Moreover, as indicated earlier, this version of 'rotated Idealism' [i.e., DM] pictures the material world as less 'real' than the Ideal world which lends it its substance, its 'essence', and which in the end determines what its theorists finally regard as "concrete".

 

And we can now see why that is so: for dialecticians, material objects are only "concrete" in the Ideal Limit, at the end of an 'infinite journey'. But, since that limit is forever unattainable, it means that, for them, there are in effect no concrete objects or processes whatsoever!

 

How Not To Solve A Problem: Begin By Doubling It

 

Almost as if to spoil the metaphysical fun, Aristotle pointed out in reference to Plato's Theory of Forms and the so-called "Third Man Argument" that it is a bad idea when trying to solve a problem to begin by doubling it.

 

[Although the "Third Man Argument' first saw light of day in Plato (1997d), p.366, 132a-132b. (Yes, I am aware that several commentators have tried to argue that Plato abandoned the Theory of Forms in that dialogue, but I don't want to become sidetracked into a lengthy discussion of what is currently an unanswerable question (viz.: "Did Plato abandon his Theory of Forms?"). I will, however, assume along with other Plato scholars that he still retained a commitment to this theory. On that see, for example, Meinwald (1990, 1992).)]

 

By this Aristotle meant that if there is a 'difficulty' explaining the similarities that exist between particulars given in experience (which 'problem' gave birth the idea there must be 'Abstract Universals', or 'Forms', that accounted for these similarities, and hence for generality itself), there must surely be a similar 'difficulty' accounting for those that exist between the particulars themselves and the 'Forms' they supposedly instantiate.

 

So, where previously there was only one 'problem', now there are two.

 

The problem Plato's theory faced is explained rather well by Hilary Staniland:

 

"[W]hen Plato tells us that men are men in virtue of their relation to the Form of Man, or that beautiful things are beautiful in virtue of their relation to the Form of Beauty, he definitely does claim to be telling us something new. And the puzzle is to understand what this new information can possibly be. What on earth is 'imitating' or 'participating' in the Form of Beauty, if it is not the same thing as just being beautiful? Plato himself was seriously concerned about this problem. In one of his later dialogues, the Parmenides, he advances arguments attacking his own theory at precisely this point, and it has even been maintained by some commentators that toward the end of his life he abandoned the Theory of Forms because of these very difficulties. The two most important arguments in the Parmenides are directed against the metaphors of 'imitation' and 'participation' respectively. The argument against the metaphor of 'imitation' is as follows. According to the 'imitation' version of the Theory of Forms, the resemblance between particular beautiful things, in virtue of which we call them all 'beautiful,' can be made intelligible only by postulating a Form of Beauty which all the particular beautiful things resemble. But if the first resemblance really stands in need of an explanation of this kind, surely the second resemblance does too. So in order to make the resemblance between particular beautiful things and the Form of Beauty intelligible, we shall have to postulate a second Form which all the particular beautiful things and the Form of Beauty resemble, and so on ad infinitum. At each stage we still have an unexplained resemblance on our hands, and so the explanation can never be completed. This sort of difficulty is inevitable if we assume on the one hand that resemblances, as such, stand in need of explanation, and on the other that they can be explained only in terms of further resemblances. (Plato himself does not use the example of the Form of Beauty, but simply states the argument in general terms. Later, the Form of Man came to be the standard example, and the argument is therefore traditionally known as the 'Third Man Argument.')

 

"The kind of difficulties Plato found himself in with the alternative metaphor of 'participation' may be brought out as follows. The idea here is that the Form is somehow shared in by the particulars. Each beautiful thing has a share of Beauty, each human being a share of Humanity, and so on. The difficulty here is as follows. Are we to think of the particulars as sharing in the Form in the way that several people might share a cake? Then the Form will be divided into separate parts belonging to different particulars. But then we have to explain how it is that all these separate parts nevertheless constitute one thing. So we have merely replaced the problem of explaining why this beautiful thing and that may both be called by the same name by the problem of explaining why the beauty of this thing and the beauty of that thing may both be called parts of the same Form, which is hardly an advance. Should we say, then, that the whole Form is present in each of the particulars? Then we shall have to say that the Form is in many separate places at the same time. And even if we do not disallow this as absurd, we shall still have to explain how 'Beauty' can be the name both of what is to be found in this thing and of what is to be found in that thing. So again, we have only replaced one problem by another." [Staniland (1973), pp.22-24. Several paragraphs merged; italic emphases in the original. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. We will have occasion to return to this specific topic later, where it will soon become clear that the DM-theory of 'abstraction' faces similar problems.]

 

Worse still, if the solution to this ancient conundrum implied there is a link of some sort between particulars and a 'we-know-not-what' (i.e., a 'Form' or a 'Universal'), located 'we-know-not-where', in a mysterious world anterior to experience, or even apprehended in experience, but accessible to thought alone), it would be a 'solution' in name alone.

 

Hence, if an abstract term is required to account for the similarities that exist between particulars (for instance, between each man), a third term would clearly be required to account for the similarity between that abstraction and those particulars themselves (which is what generates the need for a 'third man' to account for that similarity). Otherwise, the supposed connection wouldn't be rational, merely fortuitous or accidental, undermining the whole point of the exercise.

 

As we saw in Part One, that helps explain why the Medieval, 'Identity Theory of Predication' (this links directly to a downloadable .doc file), was invented by Roman Catholic theologians and was subsequently adopted by Hegel -- i.e., in order to re-establish the necessary connection that was supposed to between a subject and its predicates, or between an object and its properties. Here is Hegel scholar, Katharina Dulckeit (summarising this aspect of Hegel's theory and why he argued in its favour):

 

"[It] must be remembered that [Hegel's] analysis of the forms of judgment in the Logic is motivated by his interest in essential judgement. There are two conditions for such judgements. To begin with, a judgement is an essential judgement only if P tells us precisely and exclusively what S is; no less and no more. But merely predicating universals of particulars is insufficient for this, unless the term in the predicate position at once expresses the essential nature of the subject. This, in turn, argues Hegel, is possible only if the 'is' expresses some identity between S and P. For if essential determination were possible exclusively via predication, the subject and the predicate would remain separate and the relation between them expressed by the copula would remain external. As a consequence, S would refer to one thing, namely an individual, while P would designate something distinct from S, namely a universal. But the truth of sense-certainty in the Phenomenology has already been shown that qua individual, an individual is grasped only through the mediation of universals. It follows that divorced from these, it would then have to be an individual without a universal nature, i.e., a bare individual.... Thus, if S and P are utterly distinct they must be mutually exclusive, which means that S will necessarily be bare, and P necessarily abstract.... Clearly then, where judgements of essence are concerned, the 'is' of predication will not do because it entails the distinction between S and P which would commit us to a metaphysical thesis already overcome in the Phenomenology." [Dulckeit (1989), pp.115-16. Bold emphases alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site; links added. I have subjected passages like this to sustained criticism in Appendix D of Part One. The letter "S" has been capitalised; it is in small case in the original. Here "P" clearly stands for "predicate" and "S" for "subject". As we saw earlier, a "bare particular" is a particular that has no properties, or to which no predicates apply -- which is clearly impossible. More about that later and in Essay Twelve Part Six.]

 

As we have also seen, the introduction of a third term (such as, in this case, "Identity" -- but any 'Universal' will do) simply reproduces the original problem. That is because questions would now arise over the link between this new term and the rest -- i.e., between each particular and this hypothetical 'Universal' -- which had originally been invented in order to explain the original connection between particulars! But, for those who dote on this way of talking, any attempt to undermine the 'necessary connection' that Plato sought here would introduce contingency into nature, which would undermine belief in 'God' and imply some form of atheism. Medieval theologians saw this only too clearly, which is why they invented the 'Identity Theory of Predication', which Hegel readily appropriated. [I enter into this topic in more detail in several places below, particularly here.]

 

While 'Abstract Universals' like this 'exist' in an 'Ideal World' anterior to the world we see around us, they also supposedly enjoy 'connections of some sort' with particulars in this world, connections that are of a different order/kind to those that material particulars presumably experience among themselves. That would have to be the case if these 'abstractions' don't actually exist in the material world themselves. Unfortunately, this leaves the 'abstract', other-worldly side of this family of proposed 'solutions' (and the connections they allegedly have with material particulars) forever shrouded in mystery, and with no hope of resolution, either. [Which is where this 'problem' remains to this day with all the 'solutions' offered by Traditional Philosophers and DM-theorists.]

 

Hence, if the introduction of a Universal, Concept, Idea or 'abstraction' -- call it/them, "C1" -- is required in order to account for the common features/properties shared, for instance, by objects A and B, then a new Universal, Concept, Idea or 'abstraction' -- call it/them, "C2" (a third term) -- will be required to account for the commonality between C1 and A, and between C1 and B, and so on. As noted above, the whole exercise thus threatens to generate an infinite regress, as similar questions will now be asked about the relation between C1 and C2, thus requiring the introduction of a fourth term, "C3", and so on, leaving nothing explained. [On this topic, see Passmore (1970), Chapter 2. This age-old conundrum is also connected with the so-called 'Problem of Self-Predication', which I have dealt with briefly below. On this, see Allen (1960). (This links to a PDF.)]

 

Donald Davidson put this point rather well, too:

 

"In one dialogue or another Plato tells us that the forms are not perceived by the senses, but are objects of the mind; that they are imperishable; that they are indivisible; that they are superior to material objects; that they are norms by which we judge material things; that they have a certain creative power (the form of wisdom 'makes' Socrates wise). Material objects participate in, resemble, copy, or are modelled by the forms. Problems arise because some of these characteristics of the forms turn out to clash with others. If material things resemble the forms they instantiate to various degrees, then material things have something in common with any form they resemble. If a well-drawn circle resembles the form of circularity, it must be because both the particular drawn circle and the form of circularity share the property of circularity; but then what the particular and the property share must be still another form. Scholars of Plato have puzzled over this problem, the problem of the 'third man,' because it seems to lead to an infinite regress." [Davidson (2005), pp.78-79. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Bold emphases added.]

 

Of course, Davidson goes on to argue that Plato appears to have 'solved' this problem by claiming that it is a mistake to think that shapes also have a shape (i.e., that the 'Form of Shape' itself has a shape) or that Socrates resembles the concept of a man, thus ruling out what has come to be known as 'self-predication', mentioned above.

 

In some instances that might well be the case, but it isn't easy to see how the Forms could be exemplars of the particulars they supposedly instantiate if they share nothing with them. Indeed, why call something the 'Form of Circularity' if there is nothing circular about it? Or if there is nothing in common between this Form and circles that have been drawn, or could be drawn, in this world? Otherwise why would circles not exemplify the 'Form of Squareness' or of 'Triangularity', with which they also share nothing? There has to be some reason why the 'Form of Circularity' expresses what all circles have in common that prevents the 'Form of Squareness', 'Triangularity', or even 'Happiness', from doing this. But, just as soon as it is acknowledged there is something unique held in common between a given Form and the particulars that supposedly fall under it (and which thereby rules out the applicability of any other Form in that respect to those specific particulars), the 'Third Man Argument' will simply reassert itself.

 

Of course, exemplary rules (if that is what the Forms are supposed to express or exemplify) in no obvious way resemble the objects to which they are, or can be, applied, but there is little in Plato to suggest he regarded his Forms as rules. Moreover, if the Forms are supposed to be exemplars, there would have to be a rule of some sort that informed those who use them or their linguistic counterparts (as exemplars) how to apply them, and how to do so correctly. But, there are no such rules, or none that Plato mentioned. An object, a Form, can't tell anyone how to use or apply it, let alone how to do so correctly. An interpreted rule can and does. [Exactly how such interpretations take place will be covered in Essay Twelve Part Seven.] A chess piece, for example, can't tell a novice chess player how it should be moved; the rules of chess, once understood, typically serve in that capacity. But it takes a human being to do this. In which case, the Forms without rules that show how they apply or are to be used (correctly) as exemplars would be inert (for want of a better term), and therefore useless. But no rule is self-interpreting. Again a human being is required, and human beings are social agents. Considerations like this (which, once more will be expanded on in Essay Twelve) bring this entire topic down to earth and situate it in the open, on home turf for the left, in the public domain.

 

[The significance of those comments shouldn't be lost on fellow Marxists. It should become even more so as this Essay and others at this site unfold. Wittgenstein made a similar point about 'signs' and 'mental images'; on that see Note 40a, below. There is a sophisticated defence of Plato in Meinwald (1990, 1992). The reader will have to decide for herself whether or not it is successful. However, as we will see, this pseudo-problem is easily resolved, as this Essay, in tandem with Part One, will demonstrate. Having said that, the case against DM-Epistemology is in no way affected if Plato's theory survives the 'Third Man Argument' or crashes and burns as a result.]

 

Well, this might be to misinterpret the nature of Plato's Forms, perhaps even anachronistically. In fact, Plato talks as if we just 'see' or 'remember' the Forms (on that, see Note 6a), and that that is all there is to it. But, once more, if we are to recognise the 'Form of Circularity' and distinguish it from, say, the 'Form of Squareness', there must be something about the former that isn't the case with the latter, which the former shares with examples of circularity we encounter in this world that it doesn't share with squareness. But, what could that be? A name or label of some sort? But, names don't seem to resemble other names, nor can they express a rule. That is also the case with labels. Of course, we already know what circularity is so our understanding has already been biased in that direction (so to speak), but just looking at the alleged 'Form of Circularity' in Platonic Heaven before we were born (which is how Plato apparently conceived of this pre-natal, Cosmic Drama), without knowing what it represents or how to apply it would tell us nothing. Maybe, in our 'pre-existent state', we were all given a guided tour or presented with an 'Empyrean Form-User's Handbook' of some description? If so, that would make this a social theory of knowledge and all the problems Plato associated with banausic theories like that would now surely apply to each and every 'heavenly' version of the same.

 

What, for example, would be common to 'The Form of Dog', or the 'Forms of Cat, Lion, Horse, Rat and Crocodile' that would make them all partake in the 'Form of Vertebrate', 'Form of Animal' and 'Form of Living Organism'? Any answer to such questions would once again re-introduce the 'Third Man Argument/Objection', only now applied to the Forms themselves!

 

Maybe Platonic Heaven works in 'mysterious ways', and 'Cosmic Knowledge' is different from ordinary, boring, earthy knowledge? But, that is precisely the point at issue, for Plato's theory kicks this 'problem' off into the 'ethereal long grass', a fundamentally mysterious world which is (currently) accessible to no one.

 

Similar 'difficulties' subsequently resurfaced in Hegel's theory, but in a different form (no pun intended), since he had no way of knowing whether or not his apprehension of the concepts that were of interest to him were genuine copies of those processed by 'the Absolute Itself' --, or, for that matter, whether or not they were the same as anyone else's 'concepts'. He certainly imagined he was investigating the 'nature of thought itself', and that peremptory presupposition -- in what was supposed to be a presuppositionless enquiry! -- 'allowed' him to credit everyone else with the content of his thoughts, as though we need a Christian Mystic to tell us what we are all (really) thinking if we but knew it. And, of course, if we all prevented ordinary 'understanding' from getting in the way! But, as we are about to see, there is good reason -- beyond the ridiculous implausibility of any such presupposition -- to question Hegel's confidence in this matter. [To put this at its mildest!] In fact, he would have no way of knowing whether or not he had interpreted these 'concepts' correctly, or had even grasped what they 'really meant'. Having the name of a concept (such as "Being") would be of no more use to Hegel than seeing the 'Form of Circularity' would be to our 'pre-existent selves' in Platonic Heaven. The name of a concept provides no clue as to how it should be applied -- or even what it means -- certainly no more than 'the word' "Meskonation" would help you, dear reader, if you simply stared at it or thought about it for weeks on end.

 

[Don't bother to look that 'word' up! I invented it, just like Philosophers invented "Being".]

 

Of course, it could be argued that Hegel inherited a range of concepts from previous generations of philosophers (such as, "Being", "Nothing", "Form" -- or even "Concept" itself), which isn't the case with "Meskonation". That is undeniable, but it misses the point. Hegel could stare at the word "Being" all day long and that would still fail to tell him that what he meant by that word was the same as, or was different from, what previous thinkers had meant by it -- or, indeed, that the meaning of any of the words they had used in their explanation of what they thought they meant by "Being" were the same as, or were different from, what he now meant by those words -- without a social theory or social explanation of meaning to assist him, or them. The fact that Hegel processed these ideas 'in the privacy of his head' undermines any attempt on his part to formulate just such a social theory/explanation. And it is little use, either, pointing to his copious writings, or even those of previous thinkers on whom he relied, as a way of extricating Hegel from this impasse. That is because those ideas, expressed in print, are neither locked inside Hegel's skull nor theirs. Those writings merely record (on paper) the results of their private musings, they don't in any way alter their provenance or meaning (that is, if they ever had any!), still less do they establish their legitimacy.

 

Someone might object that if the aforementioned writings were examined in detail, it would be possible to ascertain their meaning by the way each author used such words. But, if the one reading those writings only has available to them their own private meanings of words -- like "meaning", "word" and "use", never mind "same" -- they would still fail to ascertain what any given author meant by their words. Even worse, the same would apply to their own use of words; they would have no way of knowing, from moment-to-moment, what their own words meant. Nor is it any use appealing to memory here since that word attracts the very same problems, as do any 'internal ideas' they supposedly represent. As argued in Note 40a, 'internal' signs/ideas can no more tell us what they mean than external ones are able. Social agents are required to establish meaning, and that is actioned in the open, in a social context. Indeed, as we have seen (in Part One), and will see throughout the rest of this Essay (and this site -- especially Essay Thirteen Part Three), it isn't possible to build a social theory of language, meaning or even knowledge if one starts with privately processed 'abstractions', 'ideas' or 'concepts' -- no matter how carefully that is done or the supposed 'genius' of the one doing it.

 

[And that is especially the case with theories constructed by those -- like Hegel and DM-theorists -- who also believe in the Heraclitean Flux. Why that is so is explained below.]

 

That is precisely where Hegel's non-social theory of knowledge -- i.e., his bourgeois individualism (for that is what this is an example of; once again, Hegel worked all this out, individualistically, in the 'privacy of his head') -- landed his theory of 'conceptual development'. Simply grafting a temporal component onto Plato's Theory of Forms (even if they are given an Aristotelian veneer) is no solution. Time can't add a dimension of meaning where there was none to begin with. [I have said more about this here and here.]

 

Any who doubt this need only ask themselves in, say, a few months' time if "Meskonation" now means something to them (i.e., if they constantly mull it over 'in their heads' in the meantime), and then whether or not it means the same to anyone else as it does to them. Then ask the same question in, say, twenty years time.

 

[There is more about this below, too -- here and here.]

 

Hegel could assert and insist all he liked -- and could do so until his face turned blue (as, indeed, can any of his epigones) -- that the results he had achieved were 'objective' and delineate how 'all thought actually proceeds', if carried out in the way he (sort of) described, but that would simply be the philosophical equivalent of thumping the table. And thumping the table carries no force philosophically, no matter how much better it might make any given table-thumper feel. But, because Hegel began by using the traditional concepts and methods he inherited from previous generations of mystical day-dreamers (albeit adapted and transformed to suit his own ends), and he did all this 'in his head', there is no way out of the 'subjective hole' he had dug for himself -- as the above remarks, the rest of this Essay and much of Essay Twelve and Thirteen Part Three will substantiate.

 

And the same applies to anyone foolish enough to adapt or employ his method.

 

Be this as it may, Davidson makes the point that even if Plato had managed to circumvent these 'difficulties', his theory falls foul of another, even more intractable infinite regress: one involving the 'problem of predication' and the 'unity of the proposition' -- covered in extensive detail in Part One of this Essay.

 

Dialectical Materialists Agree With Idealists -- Matter Is An 'Abstraction'

 

Plato's theory demotes the status of the 'evidence' that sense experience presents to each 'knowing subject', rendering it of secondary importance (or even of no importance) compared to whatever is contributed by 'reason', 'thought', or 'tradition' -- as Plato's Allegory of the Cave amply confirms. [On that, see Appendix B of Essay Eight Part Two. Having said that, there are passages in Plato's dialogues which seem to contradict such a sweepingly negative interpretation of his theory, but they certainly aren't decisive, and they run against the grain of his Aristocratic contempt for anything ordinary. On that, see Silverman (2014).]

 

[Indeed, we will soon see this Platonic, anti-scientific attitude re-surface in the ideas promoted by several DM-theorists, who argue that facts are not only an impediment, they are entirely misleading! After all, facts/'appearances' 'contradict essence', according to them. In Essay Two, we have already seen CLR James arguing along similar lines.]

 

This Aristocratic depreciation of the material world, with its 'irrational contingency', accompanied by an all-too-familiar and arrogant denigration of the thought, lives and experience of ordinary human beings spilled over into subsequent Platonic and Neoplatonic revivals, core ideas from both of which find clear echo in Hegel's work, and hence in DM.

 

[On that, see O'Regan (1994). In fact, Hegel himself devoted an entire book (all of 452 pages!) to Plato and the Platonists; i.e., Hegel (1995b), and clearly saw that ancient class warrior as his intellectual mentor. On this aspect of Plato, his trenchant opposition to democracy, see De Ste. Croix (1981), pp.70-71, 284, 411-12. For a revisionist view of Plato and his anti-democratic prejudices, see Monoson (2000). For a critique of the latter, see Miller (2003), Schaeffer and Nichols (2003), and Arnhart (2001). Of course, the classic work in this area is Popper (1966), which pushed this criticism of Plato to the extreme, accusing Plato of supporting or promoting totalitarianism (something that would actually have been physically impossible in Ancient Greece), and since Popper also traduces Marx (in Volume Two of the same work) along similar lines, it can hardly be recommended by the present author. This theme will be explored at greater detail in Essay Twelve Parts Two, Three and Seven, as well as Essay Fourteen Part One (summaries here and here).]

 

In which case, if "What is rational is real, and what is real is rational" [Hegel (2005), p.xix] actually were the case, both the 'real' and the 'rational' would remain forever inaccessible to the senses (and would thereby conveniently lie beyond easy refutation), which means the outward appearance of objects and processes will (always) fail to match their 'real form'/'essence'. That is because only 'the Mind' is 'rational', and since material things aren't 'Mind', they can't be 'rational'. In that case, material bodies have be 'governed' by 'rational principles' in order to have life, move or even exist. Or so this Mystical Tradition, and Dialectical Marxists, would have us believe:

 

"Matter is not the Ground of Form, but the unity of Ground and Grounded. Matter is the passive, Form is the active." [Lenin (1961), p.145. Bold emphasis alone added. Lenin is here paraphrasing Hegel.]

 

[The various responses that could be made to the seemingly dogmatic assertions (in the previous paragraph) will be considered in Essay Twelve Part Four. I have already covered some of the issues involved in Essay Thirteen Part Three, here, here and here.]

 

Or, perhaps better: given the above aristocratic approach, the 'problem' of the relation between matter and 'mind' may only be resolved if the material world is re-interpreted as an aspect of 'Mind', an "abstraction" of some sort, or even an Ideal Entity in its own right. Hence, the logical conclusion of this way of regarding 'knowledge', as indeed Hegel seemed to believe, is that, despite appearances to the contrary, everything must be 'Mind', an aspect of 'Mind' or a reflection/expression of 'Mind' in 'self-development'.

 

That helps explain why Hegel thought every philosophy was in effect a different form of Idealism (quoted earlier):

 

"Every philosophy is essentially an idealism or at least has idealism for its principle, and the question then is only how far this principle is carried out." [Hegel (1999), pp.154-55; §316. Bold emphasis added.]

 

Here, too, is Hegel on why everything material is (really) an 'abstraction' (and hence in some way, fundamentally 'mental'/'mind'):

 

"If abstraction is made from every determination, from all form of anything, what is left over is indeterminate matter. Matter is a sheer abstraction. (Matter cannot be seen, felt, and so on -- what is seen, felt, is a determinate matter, that is, a unity of matter and form). This abstraction from which matter proceeds is, however, not merely an external removal and sublating of form, rather does form, as we have seen, spontaneously reduce itself to this simple identity." [Hegel (1999), pp.450-51, §979. Bold emphasis alone added. (Typos in the on-line version have been corrected.)]

 

Here is Engels faithfully parroting the above:

 

"Matter as such is a pure creation of thought and an abstraction. We leave out of account the qualitative differences of things in lumping them together as corporeally existing things under the concept matter. Hence matter as such, as distinct from definite existing pieces of matter, is not anything sensuously existing." [Engels (1954), p.255. Bold emphases added. I have dealt with this issue in much more detail, here.]

 

Puzzled readers who (naively) imagined Engels was a materialist might well ask: what on earth is an avowed materialist doing repeating such garbage!?

 

Not to be outdone, here is Lenin, quoting Hegel (again!) approvingly:

 

"'If abstraction is made from every determination and Form of a Something, indeterminate Matter remains. Matter is a pure abstract. (-- Matter cannot be seen or felt, etc. -- what is seen or felt is a determinate Matter, that is, a unity of Matter and Form)." [Lenin (1961), pp.144-45. Bold emphasis alone added. The original passage Lenin is here quoting has been reposted in Note 57 of Essay Thirteen Part One. In the same Essay, I have also quoted several other DM-fans who say much the same as Hegel, Engels and Lenin; see also Note 54a, Note 56a and Note 65a of that Essay for just such DM-theorists, those who also claim matter is an 'abstraction'!]

 

It is worth recalling that according to DM-theorists 'abstractions' are 'creations of the mind', which, once more, can only mean that, for them, matter is, too!

 

While it might be expected that an Absolute Idealist like Hegel (or a Subjective Idealist, like George Berkeley) would consign matter to a waste bin labelled "Put Your Trash In Here Please!", it is quite shocking to see erstwhile materialists in effect agreeing with him/them!

 

Indeed, we read this about Berkeley:

 

"In the Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous [i.e., Berkeley (2016) -- RL], George Berkeley argues that physical matter, external to our minds, does not exist. The objects that we perceive are physical objects, insofar as we perceive them, but they do not exist in the absence of perception. Physical objects are only intricate ideas of perception; i.e., they are not actual objects of matter, the way we ordinarily think of them." [Welsh (2000), p.93. Quoted from here. Bold emphasis and link added; italics in the original. Minor typo corrected. See also Downing (2011).]

 

The reader might now perhaps be able to appreciate the pernicious influence Hegel's ideas have exercised on Dialectical Marxism; the adoption of his method (upside down or 'the right way up') has created generations of 'materialists' who think matter is an abstraction, a 'creation of the mind'!

 

At best, this means that, for DM-fans, 'appearances' must in some way be misleading or are to some extent 'untrustworthy'. At worst, it suggests 'appearances' are 'contradicted' by underlying 'essence'. Hence, in any such 'clash' between the 'evidence' the senses supposedly deliver and the rational principles upon which 'the Mind' allegedly relies, Traditional Theorists have always privileged the latter over the former, as the following authors point out:

 

"Empirical, contingent truths have always struck philosophers as being, in some sense, ultimately unintelligible. It is not that none can be known with certainty…; nor is it that some cannot be explained…. Rather is it that all explanation of empirical truths rests ultimately on brute contingency -- that is how the world is! Where science comes to rest in explaining empirical facts varies from epoch to epoch, but it is in the nature of empirical explanation that it will hit the bedrock of contingency somewhere, e.g., in atomic theory in the nineteenth century or in quantum mechanics today. One feature that explains philosophers' fascination with truths of Reason is that they seem, in a deep sense, to be fully intelligible. To understand a necessary proposition is to see why things must be so, it is to gain an insight into the nature of things and to apprehend not only how things are, but also why they cannot be otherwise. It is striking how pervasive visual metaphors are in philosophical discussions of these issues. We see the universal in the particular (by Aristotelian intuitive induction); by the Light of Reason we see the essential relations of Simple Natures; mathematical truths are apprehended by Intellectual Intuition, or by a priori insight. Yet instead of examining the use of these arresting pictures or metaphors to determine their aptness as pictures, we build upon them mythological structures.

 

"We think of necessary propositions as being true or false, as objective and independent of our minds or will. We conceive of them as being about various entities, about numbers even about extraordinary numbers that the mind seems barely able to grasp…, or about universals, such as colours, shapes, tones; or about logical entities, such as the truth-functions or (in Frege's case) the truth-values. We naturally think of necessary propositions as describing the features of these entities, their essential characteristics. So we take mathematical propositions to describe mathematical objects…. Hence investigation into the domain of necessary propositions is conceived as a process of discovery. Empirical scientists make discoveries about the empirical domain, uncovering contingent truths; metaphysicians, logicians and mathematicians appear to make discoveries of necessary truths about a supra-empirical domain (a 'third realm'). Mathematics seems to be the 'natural history of mathematical objects' [Wittgenstein (1978), p.137], 'the physics of numbers' [Wittgenstein (1976), p.138; however these authors record this erroneously as p.139 -- RL] or the 'mineralogy of numbers' [Wittgenstein (1978), p.229]. The mathematician, e.g., Pascal, admires the beauty of a theorem as though it were a kind of crystal. Numbers seem to him to have wonderful properties; it is as if he were confronting a beautiful natural phenomenon [Wittgenstein (1998), p.47; again, these authors have recorded this erroneously as p.41 -- RL]. Logic seems to investigate the laws governing logical objects…. Metaphysics looks as if it is a description of the essential structure of the world. Hence we think that a reality corresponds to our (true) necessary propositions. Our logic is correct because it corresponds to the laws of logic….

 

"In our eagerness to ensure the objectivity of truths of reason, their sempiternality and mind-independence, we slowly but surely transform them into truths that are no less 'brutish' than empirical, contingent truths. Why must red exclude being green? To be told that this is the essential nature of red and green merely reiterates the brutish necessity. A proof in arithmetic or geometry seems to provide an explanation, but ultimately the structure of proofs rests on axioms. Their truth is held to be self-evident, something we apprehend by means of our faculty of intuition; we must simply see that they are necessarily true…. We may analyse such ultimate truths into their constituent 'indefinables'. Yet if 'the discussion of indefinables…is the endeavour to see clearly, and to make others see clearly, the entities concerned, in order that the mind may have that kind of acquaintance with them which it has with redness or the taste of a pineapple' [Russell (1937), p.xv (this links to a PDF); again these authors record this erroneously as p.v; although in the edition to which I have linked, it is p.xliii -- RL], then the mere intellectual vision does not penetrate the logical or metaphysical that to the why or wherefore…. For if we construe necessary propositions as truths about logical, mathematical or metaphysical entities which describe their essential properties, then, of course, the final products of our analyses will be as impenetrable to reason as the final products of physical theorising, such as Planck's constant." [Baker and Hacker (1988), pp.273-75. Referencing conventions in the original have been altered to conform with those adopted at this site. Italic emphases in the original; links added.]

 

"Already with Fichte the idea of the unity of the sciences, of system, was connected with that of finding a reliable starting-point in certainty on which knowledge could be based. Thinkers from Kant onwards were quite convinced that the kind of knowledge which came from experience was not reliable. Empirical knowledge could be subject to error, incomplete, or superseded by further observation or experiment. It would be foolish, therefore, to base the whole of knowledge on something which had been established only empirically. The kind of knowledge which Kant and his followers believed to be the most secure was a priori knowledge, the kind embodied in the laws of Nature. These had been formulated without every occurrence of the Natural phenomenon in question being observed, so they did not summarise empirical information, and yet they held good by necessity for every case; these laws were truly universal in their application." [White (1996a), p.29. Links added.]

 

But, as we will see (in Essays Ten Part One and Twelve Part One), not only is the search for a priori 'knowledge' a pipe dream (in that it can't deliver what had been advertised for it), it destroys the capacity we have for articulating anything at all!

 

[Why that is so was explained in Part One.]

 

The same is largely the case with Dialectical Marxists. Perhaps even worse, they have from the beginning shown they are only too willing to appropriate this anti-materialist, ruling-class 'view of reality'. The 'ruling ideas' that Marx spoke about now proudly rule what were supposed to be radical minds. The sad truth is that this 'approach to knowledge' ironically has had the opposite effect: it delivers no knowledge at all.

 

In fact, if, per impossible, DM were 'true', it would completely undermine science.

 

This means that while DM-theorists have hocked the 'materialist cow', they haven't even received a handful of beans in return:

 

 

Figure Two: Jack Negotiates A Far Superior Deal

 

[This also helps explain why DM readily collapses into incoherence -- as the next ten Essays at this site will amply demonstrate.]

 

Davidson (from earlier) then turned our attention to Aristotle's non-solution (and since Hegel adopted/adapted Aristotle's theory -- albeit buried under several tons of gobbledygook --, the following remarks also apply to his version):

 

"Aristotle again and again reverts to the claim that if the forms are to serve as universals, then they cannot be separate from the entities of which they are properties. Aristotle agrees with Plato that universals, like the forms, are the objects of scientific study.... Where Aristotle differs from Plato was in holding that universals are not identical with the things of which they are properties, they exist only by virtue of the existence of the things of which they are properties. If universals existed independently, they would take their place alongside the things that instantiate them. Separate existence is just what would make universals like other particulars and thus no longer universal. But doesn't this argument show Aristotle to be confused? If universals can be talked about, they can be referred to. Yet whatever can be referred to is a particular. Confusion seems to have set in: universals are both particulars and at the same time necessarily distinct from particulars." [Davidson (2005), pp.89-90. Bold emphases added; paragraphs merged.]

 

The 'necessary' connection that was supposed to exist between these 'forms' and the particulars they exemplified ends up reducing them to the level of particularity, too, thus vitiating the whole exercise. That is because these moves destroy generality, the very thing the 'forms' had originally been introduced to explain.

 

On the other hand, if that isn't done (i.e., if the above 'necessary connection' is sundered by rejecting the Identity Theory of Predication), rationality will be threatened, since necessity is an integral factor, as we saw earlier. That would introduce contingency into nature and society by making the connection between a particular and all its properties (even those deemed 'essential') accidental or fortuitous, which would, of course, threaten the (assumed) legitimacy of the status quo. [I explain in more detail why that is so below, and even more fully here and in Essay Twelve Part Two). But as we will see, this (traditional) approach to knowledge either collapses into incoherence or it only succeeds in undermining itself.

 

Alternatively, if C1 (from earlier) can't connect A and B directly on its own, what then is the point of introducing it?

 

Of course, it could be argued that C1 belongs to a different category to A and B, so the above criticisms are misconceived.

 

Well, they would be if 'Universals' hadn't already been transformed into Abstract Particulars -- or, rather, into the Proper Names thereof -- as a result of the syntactical segue exposed in Part One (also alluded to by Davidson, above). But, because Traditional Theorists have been doing precisely this -- at least since the heyday of the Presocratics -- Aristotle's 'Third Man Argument' (suitably adapted in each case) applies to every known version of this theory. In which case, it turns out that all such 'Universals', 'Concepts', 'Ideas', 'Categories' and 'Abstractions' (as they are employed in Traditional Thought and, alas, in DM, too), can't be general. They are just particulars of a rather peculiar, rather grandiose kind, ashamed, perhaps in many cases, to come out of the Idealist Closet.

 

The 'philosophical' question therefore remains: Is there a general term, or any term, that is capable of connecting ordinary objects and events/processes given in experience with the Abstract Particulars of Traditional Lore, in the manner imagined? Is there any way of avoiding the catastrophic consequences that were fully exposed in Part One? That is just one of the reasons why this 'problem' is being addressed the way it is in all Parts of Essay Three. The aim is both to explain and expose the bogus syntactic and semantic moves that originally motivated this ancient conundrum -- i.e., how generality can be accounted for by reference to what turn out to be (invisible) Abstract Particulars, where predicate expressions have been transformed into the Proper Names thereof. As we have seen, Aristotle himself half recognised this 'problem', but the logic he (single-handedly) invented wasn't sophisticated enough to account for it, which is one of the reasons why he was incapable of resolving it. That meant he ended up promoting an early version of this logical and grammatical error -- i.e., in relation to what turned out to be a precursor of the Identity Theory of Predication, discussed in Part One. [On that, see Geach (1972b).]

 

On the other hand, if the aforementioned "third term" (i.e., C2, also from earlier) is superfluous, if a new general term like this isn't needed (in order to connect an 'abstraction' to each material particular -- even of only 'in the mind'), then it is difficult to see why particulars themselves need a second term (i.e., C1) to link them, in the first place. The resolution of this quandary becomes even more pressing if it turns out that this 'general term' (C1, again) is incapable of doing the job imagined for it -- once more, because it has been transmogrified into an Abstract Particular itself, or the Proper Name thereof!

 

Proper Nouns aren't general nouns, and no amount of spin, or Hegelian jargon, can turn the former into the latter.

 

But, if it is possible to inter-relate objects in the world without an entire hierarchy of 'abstract intermediaries' (which appear to be the metaphysical equivalent of the Epicycles of Ptolemaic Astronomy) -- or, perhaps better, if speakers manage to use general terms day of the week without all this fuss --, what need is there for a single 'philosophical abstraction', to begin with?1bb

 

Alternatively, if the relation between Universals and Particulars isn't one of resemblance (i.e., if C1 itself fails to resemble A or B, also from earlier) -- or of recurrence --  then the relation between each particular and its (invisible, Ideal) 'exemplar' -- i.e., a 'Universal'/'abstraction' --, must remain mysterious. If Universals and Particulars don't resemble one another (and if each of the former can't recur over and over again -- since they have all lost their generality!), in what way can Universals and Particulars possibly be connected? How could any one of the factors we have so far met connect the other two if they share nothing in common? Or, if these so-called Universals are no longer even that -- i.e., universal?

 

Indeed, it is far from clear what a Universal could possibly lend a particular that our use of general words doesn't already provide. And that worry isn't lessened when it is recalled that, in Traditional Thought, Universals were pictured in ways that deprived them of the capacity to fulfil the very role that had originally been assigned to them -- accounting for generality.1b

 

'Self-Predication'

 

[The following material is a continuation of remarks made earlier.]

 

For many logicians and Plato scholars there seems to be a much more important logical principle tucked away behind the Third Man Argument: the 'problem of self-predication' (which some commentators and critics have tried to saddle Plato with). This 'problem' arises when it is asked whether, say, the 'Form of the Small' is itself small, or the 'Form of the Heavy' is itself heavy.1bc

 

As Richard Allen explains:

 

"Briefly, the problem is this: the dialogues often use language which suggests that the Form is a universal which has itself as an attribute and is thus a member of its own class, and, by implication, that it is the one perfect member of that class. The language suggests that the Form has what it is: it is self-referential, self-predicable. Now such a view is, to say the least, peculiar. Proper universals are not instantiations of themselves, perfect or otherwise. Oddness is not odd; Justice is not just; Equality is equal to nothing at all. No one can curl up for a nap in the Divine Bedsteadity; not even God can scratch Doghood behind the Ears. The view is more than peculiar; it is absurd. As Plato knew, it implies an infinite regress, one which he doubtless regarded as vicious. Indeed, if a recent critic, Professor Gregory Vlastos, has analyzed the Third Man correctly, it implies still more. We must suppose that Plato could swallow, without gagging, a flat self-contradiction; that the reason for this, presumably, was that the author of the Third Man -- one of the more brilliant of philosophical demonstrations -- lacked the wit, or perhaps the diligence, to identify the premises of his argument; that the man who first explicitly distinguished between universals and particulars confused them; and, finally, that a central thesis of his ontology, the doctrine of degrees of being and reality, rests on this elementary mistake. Such thorough confusion is not lightly to be imputed to any man, let alone to Plato." [Allen (1960), pp.147-48. Paragraphs merged; link added. Allen is here referencing Vlastos (1954).]

 

The above two examples (of mine) are hereby translated into quasi-Plato-speak:

 

P1: Small is small.

 

P2: Heavy is heavy.

 

P1a: The Form of The Small is small.

 

P2a: The Form of The Heavy is heavy.

 

It has been argued that in P1, for example, the predicate, "small", is predicated of the other predicate term, "Small" (now misleadingly operating as a subject term), which results in what is now called "the problem of self-predication". But, this is just another pseudo-problem. That is because the first "small" in P1 is no longer a predicate; it now functions as the Proper Name of the abstract particular, 'Small' (again, as we saw in Part One). Of course, what we actually have here is a predicate expression, "ξ is small", attached to a subject term, "Small" (the reference of which is now entirely mysterious).

 

[Academic articles on this topic -- especially those devoted to the supposed origin of this idea in Plato's dialogue, Parmenides (i.e., Plato (1997d); on this, see Rickless (2020) and Section 3 of Silverman (2014)) -- often go astray right from the start when they try to analyse the 'logic' of such sentences using schemas like the following: "F is F", or "The F is F", where "F" stands for any relevant predicate expression, such as "small". But this ignores the fact that predicate expressions are incomplete (i.e., they require subject terms to complete them!). At this site, that feature has regularly been highlighted by the use of schematic stencils, like the following: "ξ is small", or more generally, "ζ is F" or even, "ή is φ" Plainly, predicate expressions can't work as subject terms for that very reason. For 'self-predication' to work (at least 'in theory'), we would have to have something like the following: "ξ is small is small" or even "ζ is F is F", and "ή is φ is φ", where an actual predicative expression completes another incomplete expression (using the same gap-marking letter)! The result is just plain gibberish. As we also saw in Part One, calling "small" (or even "...small") a predicate, as opposed to using "ξ is small" as a predicative expression, creates the sort of confusion that plagued Traditional Philosophy for over two thousand years, no less so here. This use of neo-Fregean symbols makes that impossible (which is just one more reason it is to be preferred). Unfortunately, the aforementioned academic studies seem intent on keeping those confusions alive for another couple of thousand! Readers are referred back to Note 15a of Part One for more details, a topic also briefly covered again below. (The use of Greek letters like those above, and why a predicable (so used) is the linguistic expression of a rule, were explained in Part One of this Essay, here and here, where the rationale for this way of analysing such sentences was more fully explained.) On this in general, see Long (1969, 1976, 1982, 1984). Long's articles aren't an easy read, but they merit close attention. My approach to topics in this area have been heavily influenced by them. That isn't to suggest Long would agree with the way I have used/adapted some of his ideas! Far from it.]

 

Well, this would be a 'more important logical principle' if it hadn't been based on the transformation of predicate expressions into singular terms, which in the end means that nothing has actually been 'self-predicated', nor could it be! This ancient pseudoproblem was conjured into existence by spurious linguistic moves like this, and nothing more. That is because, in P1 and P2, there has been no predication applied to a predicate expression, and that means there has been no 'self-predication' for a single logician to worry about. What has happened is that a predicate expression has been attached to a singular term that is typographically identical to part of that predicate expression itself.

 

P1: Small is small.

 

P2: Heavy is heavy.

 

In which case, this confusion arose largely because of two inter-related considerations:

 

(i) Those who commit this error focus on superficial linguistic factors -- i.e., if something looks like a predicate expression, it must be a predicate expression --, instead of examining the logical role certain phrases occupy in indicative sentences; and,

 

(ii) The adoption of an Ancient Greek interpretation of predicate expressions (again, covered in Part One of this Essay).

 

If you regard a predicate expression (for example, "heavy" or "small", expressed in traditional terms) as an inscription of some sort, and not the linguistic expression of a rule (for example, "ξ is heavy", or "ξ is small", expressed in contemporary terms), then it will seem completely legitimate to swap their roles in indicative sentences, inserting them into a space validly (and rightly) occupied by a subject term. That done, putting "heavy" and "small" at the beginning of P1 and P2, for instance, will seem perfectly acceptable, when all that that will have achieved is to change what had been a general noun into a singular term, meaning it can no longer operate as a predicate expression, and, as such, it is no longer general. So, in P1, for example, the word "small" at the beginning ceases to be a predicate expression; it is now a singular term, a Proper Noun (which 'names' a mythical Abstract Particular/Form, 'Small').

 

Hence, this means that self-predication is in fact impossible.

 

[The word "inscription" used above applies to physical marks (on a page, screen, poster, billboard, blackboard, whitescreen, cavewall...) that aren't considered random or accidental, but are held to be the product of intentionality, part of a natural-, or even a formal-language -- or perhaps even a work of art, no matter how 'primitive'.]

 

On the other hand, as noted earlier, if the above were still to be regarded as examples of 'self-predication', we would have to have something like the following:

 

P1b: ξ is small is small (sic).

 

P2b: ζ is heavy is heavy (sic).

 

In P1b and P2b we now have two instances of attempted 'self-predication', but all they manage to do is expose the hidden nonsense at work here, revealing it as obvious nonsense.

 

And that is why I haven't considered this 'important logical principle' in any of my criticisms of Plato.

 

Like so much else in Traditional Thought, 'self-predication' is a pseudoproblem.

 

Mystery solved! Nothing to see here...

 

[That isn't to suggest this specific 'problem' is quite so easily disposed of -- especially in the extremely brief manner attempted above. But, any further detour in that direction would catapult this Essay into a lengthy consideration of this 'conundrum', which would then lead us too far away from the main aim of this Essay. If this Essay were devoted specifically to the Philosophy of Logic, I would say much more, expanding on ideas aired by Peter Geach, among several others.]

 

Descent Into A Metaphysical Abyss

 

Unfortunately, this ancient syntactical error has been passed down the centuries to later generations of Traditional Theorists, a fall from linguistic grace that has traduced the entire family of flawed 'solutions' descending from it with modification by unnatural selection -- including the 'poor cousin' we find in DM.

 

[Apologies are owed the reader for those mixed metaphors!]

 

Empiricism And The 'Anthropomorphic Brain'

 

The Empiricist 'Mind' Hits A Brick Wall

 

Philosophers of a, shall we say, more practical, maybe even a more worldly, Empiricist frame-of-mind, approached this 'problem' from what seemed to be an entirely different angle. They held that general terms (and their meanings) were 'constructions' of some sort, cobbled together (somehow) by 'the mind'.

 

It is worth noting at this point that in general, just like the Rationalists, Empiricists' approach to the origin and status of 'philosophical' and scientific knowledge meant that the 'mental' side of the equation took precedence, even though philosophers in this tradition appealed to experience far more than the Rationalists. But, in this case, it is experience processed by 'the mind' that held primacy -- that is, this tradition focused on what an individual 'mind' was capable of making of experience. In fact, for both traditions, each individual 'mind' in the end is the sole arbiter, not the world -- which was, at best, either a 'mental-construct' or the 'product of mind' (i.e., the product of 'God's mind' or each 'human mind'). The deciding factor in such circumstances certainly isn't how we collectively use words in everyday life, nor is it based on any idea that language and knowledge are social products (which is how Dialectical Marxists say they view discourse, at least in their saner moments).

 

The difference between the above two traditions (largely) lies in:

 

(a) The means by which each 'mind' supposedly arrives any such conclusions;

 

(b) The emphasis placed on (i) experience or (ii) 'reason', as a sole/final arbiter; and on,

 

(c) What assumptions a given theorist begins with and subsequently employs. [More about that later.]

 

[The difference between diverse traditions within Empiricism itself on this specific topic revolved (and to a large extent still revolve) around whether the 'process of abstraction' involved 'the mind' refining inputs directly from experience or whether this was done indirectly, via 'content already present' (howsoever it got there -- or even what exactly was mean by "content"). It will take us too far away from the aims of this Essay and this site to enter into the weeds on this topic (specifically in relation to the difference between Locke, Berkeley and Hume's approach to this question -- or, indeed, the theories promoted by contemporary Empiricists) -- even so, a few words will be called for.]

 

Nevertheless, the 'high road' (Rationalism) and the 'low road' (Empiricism) both channelled Traditional Theorists in the direction of one or other form of Idealism -- indeed, as we saw Hegel himself point out. That is largely because, to a greater or lesser extent, post-Renaissance Philosophers were consciously working within the confines set by the Cartesian Paradigm (itself an extension of the Platonic/Christian Paradigm). Its basis was never fundamentally questioned --, or, at least, not for several more centuries. In fact, its first major challenge had to wait well into the 20th century (among professional philosophers influenced by Wittgenstein):

 

"...[V]irtually no philosopher doubted, from the time of Locke until roughly 1914, that, whatever concepts and ideas were, they were clearly mental objects of some kind. And no large-scale and comprehensive demolition job was done against this particularly wide-spread and influential philosophical misconception until Wittgenstein produced his Philosophical Investigations...." [Putnam (1975b), p.7. Bold emphasis added. I return to this again below, but in much more detail in Essay Thirteen Part Three.]

 

So, the core Cartesian belief that knowledge begins with, and is confirmed/ratified by, each individual 'mind' -- as it 'processes' its 'contents', using 'principles' that seem self-evidence to that individual -- has overshadowed 'western thought' for the best part of four centuries. (Earlier theorists conceptualised knowledge differently, deferential to authority and tradition and as more of a collective enterprise; Descartes broke with this -- or so he imagined (more about that later) -- and completely flipped this from the community to the individual.) As noted above, the method of justification and background assumptions were in the end what largely distinguished between the two main camps (i.e., whether reliance was placed solely on experience or uniquely on 'rational principles'). It was no accident, therefore, that this re-orientation of both traditions was in early modern Europe and coincided with the rise of the Capitalist Mode of Production and the parallel ascendancy of the Bourgeois Individual. As we will see, contemporary 'cognitive theory' still remains locked in this Paradigm -- even though a tiny minority of contemporary philosophers have been brave enough to challenge it. [On that, see Bennett and Hacker (2008, 2022), Hacker (1996) and Kenny (1992). See also, Hanfling (2001). On Descartes break with the past, see Copleston (2003d), pp.67-89, Roberts (1991), and Williams (1990), Chapter Two.]

 

The Bourgeois Individual was now inducted into, and proceeded to take over and dominate, Traditional Philosophy.

 

While the three leading theorists in the Early Modern Empiricist tradition (i.e., Locke, Berkeley and Hume) differed among themselves over the precise details, they all held that 'the mind' was somehow capable of  to 'apprehending' the 'common' features supposedly shared in, or exhibited by, particulars given in experience. The 'mental capacity' that managed to do all this manifested itself internally, in the production, or the 'processing', of "ideas", "images", "impressions", and/or "representations". More recently, other artificial terms have been called in off the bench and sent into play, so now we have "sense data" and even more recently, "qualia", "tropes", "data inputs" or even "bits".

 

In this tradition, the above 'psychological conjuring trick' (i.e., 'the process of abstraction') was somehow achieved by one or more of the following:

 

(i) A recognition of certain 'resemblances' that supposedly exist between particulars, or their 'impressions', 'images', etc., etc.;

 

(ii) A process of 'mental subtraction' (of the kind also accepted and promoted by several DM-theorists, for example this one); in tandem with,

 

(iii) Some form of behavioural or psychological 'habituation' (described below).

 

[Having said that, some philosophers have mysteriously, and confusingly, attempted to distinguish between 'thought' and 'mind' (I won't enter into the byzantine reasoning offered in support; readers can check that for themselves by following the reference I am about to give), but this has meant their ideas rapidly collapse into a tangled mess as a result -- as we see, for example, in Ruben (1979), pp.64-66, which book is otherwise a thoughtful and careful consideration of several aspects of DM-Epistemology. There are far better ways of distinguishing among the factors upon which Ruben, for instance, focused his attention. This can be achieved by a detailed consideration of how we use ordinary language in this area (as Marx himself suggested) -- to be covered in more detail Essay Three Part Six, where Ruben's ideas will be examined at greater length. (That has also been effected in broader terms in Essay Thirteen Part Three.) Suffice it to say that much of Ruben's book is ruined as much by his failure to follow Marx's advice (about returning to the use of ordinary language) as it is by his failure to learn anything substantive from Wittgenstein. In what follows I won't be drawing the above distinction (between 'thought' and 'mind'), nor will I try to show how confused it is (on that, check out the references listed in Note 86 of Essay Thirteen Part Three), even if I end up referring to it from time to time. Another dialectician who tries to defend Lenin is Sean Sayers; I have relegated several criticisms of his book -- Sayers (1985) -- to Appendix Five, but in more detail in Part Six of Essay Three. Criticism of Ruben (1979) and Althusser (2001) -- the latter of whom also tries to defend (a version of) Lenin's theory of knowledge --, have also been postponed to Part Six. Both have been relegated in that way because this Essay is already far too long!]

 

Theorists working in the Empiricist Tradition tended to disagree over whether 'Universals' were genuine features of 'reality' (i.e., whether or not they were 'extra-mental' -- this view tending to shade off into various forms of 'Philosophical Realism') or were simply a by-product of an overactive imagination (which is one way of characterising Conceptualism) --, or, indeed, whether they were, according to the Nominalists, just 'empty terms' (flatus vocis -- "mere breath"), perhaps even "useful fictions" (an interpretation that dominated the Positivist wing of this particular current). [On that in general, see Eklund (2024).]

 

As soon became obvious, such seemingly profound differences mattered little in the end. Given this overall approach, general words (common nouns/adjectives, or even verbs and adverbs) were once again demoted, having now been transformed into the Proper Names of 'mental particulars' of one sort or another -- i.e., they were now the Proper Names of the 'ideas', 'representations', or 'concepts' lodged in each head, or they were the Proper Names of something-we-know-not-what out there in 'extra-mental reality'). Even though Berkeley, for example, saw the importance of escaping the confines of this theoretical cul-de-sac, with its obscure 'abstractions', his 'solution' only succeeded in sinking the Empiricist Tradition even deeper in the same Idealist quick sands.

 

Unfortunately, there were additional problems over and above those bequeathed to Empiricist Philosophers as a result of the syntactical sins of their theoretical forebears (covered in Part One), which 'errors' also (but, as we will see, not uncoincidentally) bedevilled Rationalism. That is, the 'general' ideas 'processed' by each lone abstractor were particular to that individual 'mind', and that had to be the case in both traditions. That is because (obviously!) no two individuals (whether they were both died-in-the-wool Empiricists or card-carrying Rationalists) share the 'same mind', experience the same sensory inputs or even draw the same conclusions from them. And that included the same idea about 'same'! In that case, any ideas that emerged as a result couldn't be general across an entire population, not just in fact but in theory, too! This clearly meant that every 'general idea' was exclusive to each individual. But, as Bertell Ollman correctly pointed out, this approach to 'abstraction' only succeeded in creating a private language, unique to each lone abstractor. That unfortunately implied inter-subjective communication was impossible, which in turn meant that the status and validity of scientific knowledge itself was now fatally undermined.

 

The 'process of abstraction' (as it had been conceived by Empiricist Philosophers) had simply created Empiricist Abstract Particulars --, or the Proper Names thereof --, just as earlier versions of the 'same process' had manufactured Rationalist Abstract Particulars. Different input -- same output. But, those working in the Empiricist Tradition seemed perfectly happy to accept, and even elaborate upon, these (Ancient Greek) false moves. In fact, they were equally happy to promote the Epistemological Individualism this implied. This particular set of "ruling ideas" (i.e., a commitment to 'abstractionism' alongside the existence of 'abstractions' generated by 'individual minds') thus succeeded in colonising a new batch of compliant 'intellects' -- those belonging to early modern, petty-bourgeois philosophers. This antiquated ideology had now found a fresh home -- where it largely remains to this day.

 

Indeed, this novel turn later coalesced around Classical and Neo-Classical criticisms of Marx's economic theory (briefly mentioned elsewhere at this site), and later still formed a basis for what came to be known as 'Methodological Individualism'.

 

However, the problems these moves generated only succeeded in threatening their legitimacy from the start -- since they were analogous those that had confronted Rationalist Metaphysics for nigh on two millennia.

 

To see this, assume thinker, T1, has formed the 'general idea', G1, of whatever it supposedly 'represents' or 'reflects' (in the head, in the world, or wherever) -- call the latter, "g1" --; and thinker, T2, forms the 'same general idea', G2, of supposedly the 'same property, object or process' in 'reality' -- i.e., this is g1, again. Hence, G1 supposedly 'represents' or 'reflects' g1, which is also supposedly 'represented' or 'reflected' by G2. Now, in order to be able to say of these two 'general ideas' (G1 and G2) that they are ideas of the 'same thing' (or are even the 'same general idea'), a third term will be required to connect them. That is because, in this case, G1 and G2 would both presumably be exemplars of the same general, general idea (that isn't a typo!), G, -- so that it could truly be said that G1 and G2 were instances of the same 'concept', 'idea' or 'abstraction' (in this case were both instances of G). Of course, as noted above, if that weren't the case (if there were no 'general, general term', G, that linked G1 and G2), communication would be impossible. That is because there would be no way for T1 to determine whether or not she meant the same by her use of G1 that T2 meant by his use of G2. Without G itself, that would be impossible. But, if there actually is a G that manages to do all this connecting, it would now threaten to spiral off into infinity, just like the 'The Man Argument' did. So, if G is required to connect G1 and G2, what connects G with G1? Or with G2? Given this theory, yet another linking term, G', would be required, and then G'', and then G'''..., and so on ad infinitem...

 

[There is more on this below. It might be objected that neither T1 nor T2 need be aware of G in order to communicate; they could simply use the same words -- for instance, "cat" or "table". But, given this individualistic theory, these two abstractors wouldn't mean the same by their use of these words, and hence would fail to communicate. It might even be pointed out that human beings typically fail to communicate, but the heavens don't fall as a result. I have dealt with that rather common objection below. Finally, it might now argued that communication could easily be secured as reference is made to that actual objects themselves -- for instance pointing to a cat or a table. Quite apart from the fact that not all such 'objects' can be pointed at -- for example, trying pointing at Mt Everest when in the USA; a picture won't do, since that would mean the word "Mt Everest" stood for the picture not the mountain -- pointing gestures are ambiguous. When NN points at a cat, is she trying to explain the meaning of "animal", "mammal", "vertebrate", "one", "hairy object", "quadruped", or what? And it is no good using other words to help clarify NN's meaning since they, too, are subject to the same sceptical questions about common meaning. On this see, Cowie (2002), pp.1-68, and Baker and Hacker (2005), pp.7-9, 81-106.]

 

Hence, and to be a little more 'concrete', if intrepid Abstractor A, forms what she takes to be 'the general idea of green1', encountered in experience -- call the idea/'representation' she forms as a result, "Green1" -- and based on her perception of a series of 'green1 objects', and Abstractor B, forms what he takes to be 'the general idea of green2', also met in experience -- call the idea/'representation' he forms as a result, "Green2" --, then in order to determine that these are in fact two ideas/'representations' of 'green itself' (or 'the same idea/'representation' of green', whatever that means!) -- so that Green1 and Green2 could both be said to 'reflect' the same Universal, Concept or Abstraction (or even were the same abstraction) --, a new term would be needed to connect them, namely "Green Itself" (or, 'Green'/'Greenness'). Without this third term there would be no way of determining whether or not A and B had formed a common/shared idea/'representation' of green, but had instead formed two different ideas/'representations' of 'green'. Worse still, if there were no third connecting term, there would be no way of deciding they had any idea/'representation' at all of green (in any shape or form), or even if there were two or more occurrences of what might be taken to be green1, by A herself. [Recall there would have to be more than one occurrence, instantiation or example of green1 (registered in or by experience) for it to be counted by A as having been 'reflected' by the general term "Green1", to begin with, and for A even to be able to call it to mind, or 'think it'.] That is, these would have to be actual occurrences of green1, as opposed to 'something entirely different' (otherwise A would be 'naming the wrong thing').

 

As should now seem clear: the same problem confronts each lone abstractor, even with respect to their own ideas (never mind what other abstractors might have 'in their heads'!), since they would now need a linking term connecting the idea they had of 'green' yesterday with the one they entertained today -- call them "GreenY" and "GreenT", respectively -- or even ideas from a few seconds earlier! And that would also apply to any memories they had of the 'Greens' so far mentioned and not yet mentioned -- i.e., Green1, Green2, Green3,..., Greeni,..., Greenn-2, Greenn-1, and Greenn. But, without this third term (and all the rest to infinity!) no statement based on the 'memory' of any of these 'Greens'/'greens' could truthfully be asserted.

 

[Henceforth, to save on needless and irritating repetition, I will simply refer to the ideas formed, not the ideas/'representations' -- but the latter should be taken to be what is intended, unless it is stated to the contrary. In addition, I have drawn a distinction between the ideas an abstractor might form (e.g., Green1) and the 'extra-mental' objects or properties they supposedly 'reflect' (e.g., green1). Nevertheless, it is my contention that no such distinction can legitimately be drawn by Empiricists (or even by Rationalists!). The rest of this Essay will try to explain why that is so, but in the meantime I am simply assuming it can be drawn in order to put pressure on the 'strongest version' of this theoretical current in post-Renaissance Epistemology.]

 

So, without this third term -- and all the rest to infinity(!) -- no 'process of abstraction' can even begin!

 

In other words, each abstractor must have 'a concept of green already installed', or have access to an 'infinite set of such linking terms'. Since the latter is impossible, this means that each one would already have to have some a grasp of the general terms involved, otherwise the 'process of abstraction' (always assuming there is such a 'process'!) couldn't even get off the ground.

 

But, if each prospective abstractor already understands these general terms -- if each one already has a grasp of green, for example -- what need is there for abstraction, in the first place?

 

[For those who think colour terms and other 'secondary properties'/'qualities' are subjective and don't actually exist in the 'outside world', just replace "Green1" and "Green2" (etc.) with "Table1" and "Table2", or "Flat surface1" and "Flat surface2", in the above. In order to connect them (even in the memory) there would have to be a third term, such as "table itself", "tabularity", "Tableness" -- or, "flat surface itself" and even "Flat-Surfaceness"(!). The rest follows as before. (However, I have dealt with the confused idea that colours exist 'only in the mind' in Essay Thirteen Part One, here. In the meantime, readers are directed to Hacker (1987), Bennett and Hacker (2022), pp.140-46, and Stroud (2000). To those who think we never really communicate, anyway, I say this: "I'm sorry, are you trying to communicate something?" I have said much more about that oft-repeated objection in Essay Thirteen Part Three, here.]

 

So, for this family of theories to work, a third linking term and all the rest 'to infinity' are required; but, given the tenets of Empiricism, where such terms might come from is a mystery best passed over in silence (since it can't have come 'from experience' -- or, it can't without the very same problems arising, and so on...).

 

[This unanswerable question has prompted several contemporary philosophers (many of whom have been influenced by the neo-Rationalist theories developed by Chomsky; I have examined the ideas of two such theorists -- Laurence and Margolis -- in Interlude One, and Chomsky's theories themselves in Essay Thirteen Part Three) to argue that all such ideas and concepts are 'innate'. That is, of course, what Rationalists have always maintained. I will say much more about this bogus solution throughout the rest of this Part of Essay Three, as well as other subsequent Parts; see also Essay Thirteen Part Three (link above). 

 

Plainly, as we have just seen, each 'new term' is susceptible to Aristotle's objection, which means that every single 'solution' concocted by those working in the Empiricist Tradition suffered from the same fatal defects that had blighted those dreamt up by the Rationalists. Without these 'new linking terms' (which, once more, can't have come from experience), all communication would cease. But, since we actually do manage to communicate nearly every day of our lives, this approach isn't even plausible -- never mind its other fatal defects.

 

As we will see, this not only makes it impossible for Traditional Theorists -- those drawn from right across the philosophical spectrum -- to account for inter-communication, representation and learning, it also empties generality of all content, thus vitiating the whole exercise.

 

[Exactly how this approach to knowledge would make communication (etc.) impossible will be re-examined below, and in even more detail in Essay Thirteen Part Three. But the basic argument was set out earlier.]

 

Of course, it could be objected that such ideas had intentional generality built into them --, whereby their inventors intended they should refer to general features of reality. But, as should seem obvious, 'intentional generality' is similarly trapped in this closed, solipsistic universe, since it itself is the Proper Name of yet another particular, 'Intentional Generality'.

 

[To see this, just replace "G1" with "intentionally general idea, G1" in the above argument; the rest follows. The fact that this approach to knowledge leads to solipsism was established in Essays Ten Part One and Thirteen Part One, but it will be dealt with more fully in Essay Three Part Four. {Spoiler: If all that a 'knowing subject' has available to them are these individually-formed or generated ideas/concepts, and that 'subject' has no way of checking that any they possessed, even a moment earlier, were of the same general type, all they can possibly 'know' is the immediate present (and their own experience of 'it'), but with no way of determining if such ideas represent anything in the 'outside world' -- not least because the phrase "outside world" is subject to the same epistemological constraints. This theory therefore traps each 'knowing subject' in their own private, solipsistic universe, with no way out.}]

 

Clearly, this is just another way of saying that intentions can't create generality any more than wishes can improve a beggar's prospective quadrupedally-enabled travel plans.

 

Indeed, simply gluing the word "general" onto the word "concept" (perhaps as part of an 'intention' to refer to a "general concept") would merely saddle each prospective user of that phrase with a term born of the same defective logic, for the phrase "general concept" is the Proper Name of a yet another particular.

 

[To see this, just replace "G1" with "general concept, G1" in the above argument; the rest follows.]

 

In fact, given this entire 'family of theories', any attempt to derive generality from the atomised conceptual fragments that float (aimlessly) into each individual head (via the senses, or which are somehow cobbled-together in, or by, 'the mind') will always hit the same brick wall: abstraction only ever succeeds in generating the Proper Names of abstract particulars --, whoever indulges in it, whenever they so indulge and with whatever 'noble philosophical intentions' they might come up with to rationalise their persistent endeavours.

 

Fortunately, for genuine materialists the logic of predication (as it shapes our use of such terms in ordinary discourse) has already loaded the dice and fixed the result in our favour --, and there is no leave to appeal its uncompromising verdict. Generality is a feature of the way we use words, not a property of those words themselves -- nor, indeed, is it a property of the 'images', 'ideas', 'impressions', 'representations', or 'signs' that supposedly underpin, or are reflected by, them. Human beings decide what is to be counted as general by their social, not their individual, (verbal and practical) behaviour, and words aren't human beings.

 

[That 'surprising conclusion' was established in Part One of this Essay.]

 

It could be countered that inter-communication isn't threatened by empiricist versions of abstraction, since communication with others is not only possible, it is actual. Manifestly, people share their thoughts and ideas.

 

But, quite apart from the above response assuming what was to be proved, it runs aground almost immediately. That is because it reproduces Aristotle's original problem -- only now greatly magnified. It is an even worse idea to multiply one's difficulties by a factor of several billion -- right across the entire human race -- in an attempt to account for generality by appealing to the abstractions supposedly engineered by, and now trapped in, each socially-isolated skull. [On that, see the next sub-section.]

 

[To see this, just replace the "G1" or "G2" with "G3 to Gn", where "n" can take any value from one to seven billion, or more, in the above argument, and the rest will still follow.]

 

In that case, we wouldn't just have the two theorists mentioned above -- A and B, or even P1 and P2 (where the latter stand for two randomly-selected Philosophers) --, each with their individually-formed 'general' ideas of 'green' ('table' or 'flat surface'), we would have billions of 'minds' with countless individual ideas of 'green' ('table' or 'flat surface') to interconnect. [I.e., "G3 to Gn", above.]

 

And the same difficulties confront anyone who tries to find a general solution to this spurious problem. Attempts along such lines are doomed to fail because any explanation of how the particular ideas of general terms located in each individual head actually resemble the same general features of reality they supposedly express, reflect or mirror -- or even the same particular ideas of these (allegedly) general terms located in anyone else's head --, would require its own linking term along lines explored earlier. Accounting for them would, of course, make squaring the circle look like child's play in comparison. That pointless task would simply create yet more abstract particulars locked in the individual mind of anyone foolish enough to wander down that blind alley.

 

Struggling to escape these 'metaphysical quicksands' will only sink the trapped Philosopher ever deeper. Given the traditional approach, Abstract Particulars are required at every turn, as yet more of them are required to account for the last batch that had just been pulled out of a given philosopher's hat. Since none of them are capable of developing into a higher general form by their own efforts, this approach to knowledge simply creates an endlessly ascending hierarchy of Abstract Particulars, each even more obscure than the one below.

 

[Apologies are once again owed the reader for those mixed metaphors!]

 

Bourgeois Individualism

 

Just as Rationalist ideas originally grew out of, and were inspired by, aristocratic imperatives promoted and then rationalised by Ancient Greek Philosophers -- somewhat similar developments were taking place 'in the East', to be covered in Essay Twelve Parts Two and Three --, concerning the 'divine' order that supposedly underpinned the Universe, and motivated by a pressing need to 'justify' ruling-class power, social stratification, exploitation, oppression and inequality, so the origin of more recent Empiricist theories of 'Universals' was itself connected with the novel ideological landscape that was taking shape in early modern, bourgeois society with its emphasis on "possessive individualism". [On that, see Note 2.]

 

If this new social and political order was (in the end) meant to be 'democratic' (but only "within certain limits"), founded on the presumed psychology and self-serving 'rationality' of the fabled, 'Bourgeois Individual', then private ownership in the means of 'mental production' began to make perfectly good sense.

 

The social, economic and political fragmentation introduced into society by the break-up of Feudal Relations of Production (as a result of the rise of Capitalism) mirrored an analogous splintering of Aristotelian 'Universals' (as the old Aristocratic-Slave society itself gave way to Feudalism). In this new ideological terrain, 'Universals' were rebranded as just so many 'ideas' scattered across countless epistemologically-isolated, bourgeois heads. Out of the window went the 'necessary' connection presumed to exist between an object and its properties, or between a subject and its predicates -- a doctrine that was considered unquestionably true by influential Ancient Greek and Medieval Rationalists. Out with that went the conceptual link that was thought to exist between a general term and what it supposedly represented or reflected in 'reality' (or even what it tokened in 'the mind'). For many theorists, moves like these seemed to threaten the 'rationality of the universe', raising the spectre of Atomism, and with that Republicanism, early forms of Communism and Atheism. [More on that presently.]

 

 

Figure Three: Traditional Theorists React To Atomism

And Contingency

 

If the connection between an object and its properties turns out to be merely adventitious or accidental, then, at its deepest level, 'reality' can't be 'rational' and that in turn implies 'God Himself' can't be 'rational', either. 'Dangerous' ideas like these began to threaten the 'legitimacy' of Kings and Queens, and, along with that, aristocratic and priestly authority. The rapidly eroding hierarchy that had dominated Europe for countless centuries had always depended -- at least ideologically -- on its 'divine origin', which in turn was based on the presumed 'rationality of reality', with everything in its assigned place in the 'Cosmic Pecking-Order'. If legitimacy was to be restored, the 'necessary connections' that had just been sundered had to be re-instated -- and as a matter of some urgency, too. Revolution was now in the air in Europe (and not just in the air, on the ground, too  -- on that, see Rees (2016, 2024)). A spectre was beginning to stalk Europe, which meant a 'favourable' ideological re-alignment now became essential. [More on that presently.]

 

 

Figure Four: Medieval Hierarchy -- 'Guaranteed' By Metaphysics

 

[I have said more about this metaphysical aspect of Christian Theology and its political implications, below.]

 

Once again, this helps explain why Hegel adopted the 'Identity Theory of Predication' (mentioned earlier), since that theory sought to re-establish the aforementioned 'necessary connection' between an object and its properties (or, at least, some of them). This then served as a core component of Hegel's response to Hume's sceptical criticism of rationalist theories of causation, the latter of which had attempted to dissolve all such 'mysterious necessary connections'.

 

Just as capitalism increasingly 'freed' workers from the land and from feudal ties to Lords and Ladies, so Empiricism 'freed' bourgeois ideas from 'oppressive', aristocratic, Platonic 'Forms' and Aristotelian 'Universals'. The old ontological pecking-order began to fall apart as new market conditions and ideological priorities swept all before them.

 

"The bourgeoisie, wherever it has got the upper hand, has put an end to all feudal, patriarchal, idyllic relations. It has pitilessly torn asunder the motley feudal ties that bound man to his 'natural superiors', and has left remaining no other nexus between man and man than naked self-interest, than callous 'cash payment'. It has drowned the most heavenly ecstasies of religious fervour, of chivalrous enthusiasm, of philistine sentimentalism, in the icy water of egotistical calculation. It has resolved personal worth into exchange value, and in place of the numberless indefeasible chartered freedoms, has set up that single, unconscionable freedom -- Free Trade. In one word, for exploitation, veiled by religious and political illusions, it has substituted naked, shameless, direct, brutal exploitation.... The bourgeoisie cannot exist without constantly revolutionising the instruments of production, and thereby the relations of production, and with them the whole relations of society. Conservation of the old modes of production in unaltered form, was, on the contrary, the first condition of existence for all earlier industrial classes. Constant revolutionising of production, uninterrupted disturbance of all social conditions, everlasting uncertainty and agitation distinguish the bourgeois epoch from all earlier ones. All fixed, fast-frozen relations, with their train of ancient and venerable prejudices and opinions, are swept away, all new-formed ones become antiquated before they can ossify. All that is solid melts into air, all that is holy is profaned, and man is at last compelled to face with sober senses his real conditions of life, and his relations with his kind.... But not only has the bourgeoisie forged the weapons that bring death to itself; it has also called into existence the men who are to wield those weapons -- the modern working class -- the proletarians." [Marx and Engels (1968b), pp.38-41. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site; bold emphases added. Paragraphs merged.]

 

"In the social production of their existence, men inevitably enter into definite relations, which are independent of their will, namely relations of production appropriate to a given stage in the development of their material forces of production. The totality of these relations of production constitutes the economic structure of society, the real foundation, on which arises a legal and political superstructure and to which correspond definite forms of social consciousness. The mode of production of material life conditions the general process of social, political and intellectual life.... In studying such transformations it is always necessary to distinguish between the material transformation of the economic conditions of production, which can be determined with the precision of natural science, and the legal, political, religious, artistic or philosophic -- in short, ideological forms in which men become conscious of this conflict and fight it out. Just as one does not judge an individual by what he thinks about himself, so one cannot judge such a period of transformation by its consciousness, but, on the contrary, this consciousness must be explained from the contradictions of material life, from the conflict existing between the social forces of production and the relations of production." [Marx (1968), pp.181-82. Bold emphases added.]

 

As a result, those in power, alongside their compliant ideologues, recognised the pressing need to 'justify' undemocratic, hierarchical state power while also rationalising the newly emerging class relations that began to crystallise in early modern Europe. This meant that ruling-class theorists now had to find a novel way of conceptualising 'bourgeois reality', showing that it, too, was somehow 'god-ordained' -- possibly even 'natural' and 'necessary' -- even if it was now subject to limited forms of change.

 

In this respect, Empiricism couldn't rise to the challenge. A fresh wave of Rationalist thought was urgently required -- in order to:

 

(i) Counter the politically dangerous fragmentation of knowledge threatened by the rise of Empiricism, Atomism and Republicanism;

 

(ii) Re-construct and launch a new version of Metaphysical Holism, which was required to 'justify' the Absolutist Nation States that were now coalescing across Europe;1bd and,

 

(iii) Rationalise 'God-given' Royal, Aristocratic, and Ecclesiastic power, wealth and legitimacy, alongside the newly acquired riches and social-position of the bourgeoisie themselves.

 

The theories concocted by Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, Wolff, Kant and Hegel proved to be just what the bourgeois doctor ordered, as fresh waves of Metaphysics flowed freely from the pens of this latest upsurge in ruling-class ideology.1c0

 

But, it wasn't just workers who got screwed (in a new way) by the 'market economy'; general ideas were similarly shafted (but in the same old way).1c

 

However, this hasty, if not desperate, turn to Rationalism proved to be philosophically futile. The fragmentation that general ideas had suffered at the hands Ancient Greek theorists can't be reversed, whoever tries to do it. Any such attempt will always flounder while the syntactic false moves committed by Europe's philosophical forebears remain in place.

 

No surprise then that, despite countless claims to the contrary, the novel theories that emerged from the 17th century onward found it impossible to repair what they had actually been invented to fix: generality. That didn't just present problems for Philosophy; left unresolved it threatened to undermine the nature, scope and validity of science itself. If generality was merely an aspect, a consequence or a result of the operation of each individual 'mind' (not a genuine feature or component of 'things-in-themselves' -- as Rationalists at least liked to think), it was difficult to see what could possibly remain intact of the famed 'objectivity of science'.

 

Associated with this was an additional problem: what was it about each particular idea of the general that actually made it general, or even appear to be general (especially now that all such ideas had been moved and were now located in individual bourgeois heads)?2 Given this post-Renaissance approach to knowledge, there would be nothing but individual ideas floating about in epistemologically-isolated heads, loosely tied together in a manner that became increasingly impossible to fathom, let alone explain.

 

[At this point, it is worth reminding ourselves that it was assumed by early-modern bourgeois theorists (drawn from both wings, Empiricist and Rationalist) that we all construct our 'knowledge of the world' as individuals. It isn't being argued here that these thinkers were actually socially-isolated, only that, as far as their theory of knowledge was concerned, they might as well have been. More has been said about that, here.]

 

Given this 'family of theories', even a general idea like that (i.e., one that, in a vain attempt to conjure 'objectivity' out of 'subjectivity', has been re-labelled "Thought", "The Understanding", or even "Speculative Reason", and which attempts to rope in "every individual" and then inform us what must take place in every 'thinking brain' on the planet) is devoid of sense. If philosophers couldn't account for generality -- largely because they had killed it stone dead over two thousand years earlier (as we discovered in Part One) --, they had no way of accounting for its re-appearance anywhere else, either among the general population, or in the privacy of their own heads! How is it even possible to speak about "the general population" or "every head"/"brain", for example, with anything other than empty phrases if generality had been laid to rest long ago --, including the general nature of words like "population", "head" and "brain", themselves?2a

 

Naturally, some attempt might be made to attach another, yet-to-be-explained, term to the word "idea" -- i.e., "general", as in "general idea" --, but, if all meaningful words in circulation have to be backed by genuine 'mental bullion' (i.e., if they all have to be cashed-out in terms of 'ideas' in 'the mind', as this 'family of theories' consistently maintained), then a phrase like "the general idea of..." would itself still be a particular in 'the mind' of whomsoever invented it, and whatever associationist or "clear and distinct" incantations had been uttered over it.

 

Given the results of Part One, it should now be clear that since traditional theories of predication had turned general words into singular terms (i.e., into Proper Names or Definite Descriptions), each of which denoted an Abstract Particular, then the sentence, "This is the general idea of F" must face the same awkward, unanswerable questions. That is because the phrase, "The general idea of F", is yet another singular term designating an Abstract Particular! [The definite article, of course, gives the game away.]

 

So it was that, in the Empiricist Tradition, there followed several more centuries of pretentious, a priori 'science-on-the-cheap', involving an appeal to the mythical 'process of abstraction', the results of which were backed, not even by printed currency, just more fake moves.

 

[Some might object that Empiricist Epistemology is a posteriori, not a priori. Well, so the official brochure would have us believe. Nevertheless, this approach to knowledge had always been predicated on rather fanciful, a priori, Associationist Psychology, supported by what was in effect little more than fanciful science fiction. (I have said more about that in Essay Thirteen Part Three.)]

 

To suppose otherwise -- i.e., that the word "general" (or any other term, for that matter) is capable of creating generality by its own efforts -- would be tantamount to imagining words themselves are capable of determining, and then projecting, their meanings across the whole of 'semantic space' (with this trick perfectly coordinated across every single epistemologically-isolated, bourgeois brain), as if words themselves were autonomous agents, not the individuals who use them that are. But, unaided -- as a simple mark on the page, or even as an "idea" in the head -- the word "general" seems utterly incapable of rising to the challenge, creating generality out of thin air.

 

Lifting yourself by your bootstraps would be a doddle in comparison.

 

[As noted earlier, Wittgenstein made a similar point about images and signs. See also Note 40a.]

 

On the other hand, if general ideas were capable of representing or "reflecting" "things-in-themselves" (that is, if there actually are 'real universals' that exist 'somewhere', to which general words supposedly 'correspond' or 'refer') -- as the Scientific Realist wing of this approach to epistemology and ontology maintained -- it would prove impossibly difficult to explain the mode of signification of the term, "general idea", without admitting it was no longer general (as we are about to find out).

 

If each general idea or noun (pr adjective, etc.) successfully refers to something, somewhere, 'in reality' -- in Platonic Paradise, Aristotelian Arcadia, Hegelian Hell, Bourgeois Bliss, or, indeed, anywhere else, for that matter -- they could only do so if they functioned as Singular Terms. But, as we saw in Part One, if that were so, neither general ideas nor general words would actually be general, just singular.2b

 

As Donald Davidson remarked (with respect to Aristotle's theory -- but his words apply to any general terms so transformed, quoted earlier):

 

"Aristotle again and again reverts to the claim that if the forms are to serve as universals, then they cannot be separate from the entities of which they are properties. Aristotle agrees with Plato that universals, like the forms, are the objects of scientific study.... Where Aristotle differs from Plato was in holding that universals are not identical with the things of which they are properties, they exist only by virtue of the existence of the things of which they are properties. If universals existed independently, they would take their place alongside the things that instantiate them. Separate existence is just what would make universals like other particulars and thus no longer universal. But doesn't this argument show Aristotle to be confused? If universals can be talked about, they can be referred to. Yet whatever can be referred to is a particular. Confusion seems to have set in: universals are both particulars and at the same time necessarily distinct from particulars." [Davidson (2005), pp.89-90. Bold emphasis added; paragraphs merged.]2c

 

Even if each individual 'bourgeois mind' had its own idea of a given 'general name' (or what it supposedly 'reflected'), which was particular to that 'mind' (as it couldn't fail to be!), the universality that post-Renaissance theorists sought would forever remain elusive, fragmented as it now was in the socially-isolated skulls of all who played this futile game.

 

[I have explained what I mean by "socially-isolated", here.]

 

But, don't just take Davidson's word for it; this is something Hegel himself acknowledged:

 

"The spectacle of so many and so various systems of philosophy suggests the necessity of defining more exactly the relation of Universal to Particular. When the universal is made a mere form and co-ordinated with the particular, as if it were on the same level, it sinks into a particular itself. Even common sense in everyday matters is above the absurdity of setting a universal beside the particulars. Would any one, who wished for fruit, reject cherries, pears, and grapes, on the ground that they were cherries, pears, or grapes, and not fruit? But when philosophy is in question, the excuse of many is that philosophies are so different, and none of them is the philosophy -- that each is only a philosophy. Such a plea is assumed to justify any amount of contempt for philosophy. And yet cherries too are fruit. Often, too, a system, of which the principle is the universal, is put on a level with another of which the principle is a particular, and with theories which deny the existence of philosophy altogether. Such systems are said to be only different views of philosophy. With equal justice, light and darkness might be styled different kinds of light." [Hegel (1975), p.19 §13. Except for the word "besides", bold emphasis alone added.]

 

And, in a roundabout way, so did the young Marx and Engels:

 

"The mystery of critical presentation…is the mystery of speculative, of Hegelian construction.… If from real apples, pears, strawberries and almonds I form the general idea 'Fruit', if I go further and imagine that my abstract idea 'Fruit', derived from real fruit, is an entity existing outside me, is indeed the true essence of the pear, the apple, etc., then -- in the language of speculative philosophy -- I am declaring that 'Fruit' is the 'Substance' of the pear, the apple, the almond, etc. I am saying, therefore, that to be an apple is not essential to the apple; that what is essential to these things is not their real existence, perceptible to the senses, but the essence that I have abstracted from them and then foisted on them, the essence of my idea -- 'Fruit'…. Particular real fruits are no more than semblances whose true essence is 'the substance' -- 'Fruit'…. Having reduced the different real fruits to the one 'fruit' of abstraction -- 'the Fruit', speculation must, in order to attain some semblance of real content, try somehow to find its way back from 'the Fruit', from the Substance to the diverse, ordinary real fruits, the pear, the apple, the almond etc. It is as hard to produce real fruits from the abstract idea 'the Fruit' as it is easy to produce this abstract idea from real fruits. Indeed, it is impossible to arrive at the opposite of an abstraction without relinquishing the abstraction….

 

"The main interest for the speculative philosopher is therefore to produce the existence of the real ordinary fruits and to say in some mysterious way that there are apples, pears, almonds and raisins. But the apples, pears, almonds and raisins that we rediscover in the speculative world are nothing but semblances of apples, semblances of pears, semblances of almonds and semblances of raisins, for they are moments in the life of 'the Fruit', this abstract creation of the mind, and therefore themselves abstract creations of the mind…. When you return from the abstraction, the supernatural creation of the mind, 'the Fruit', to real natural fruits, you give on the contrary the natural fruits a supernatural significance and transform them into sheer abstractions. Your main interest is then to point out the unity of 'the Fruit' in all the manifestations of its life…that is, to show the mystical interconnection between these fruits, how in each of them 'the Fruit' realizes itself by degrees and necessarily progresses, for instance, from its existence as a raisin to its existence as an almond. Hence the value of the ordinary fruits no longer consists in their natural qualities, but in their speculative quality, which gives each of them a definite place in the life-process of 'the Absolute Fruit'.

 

"The ordinary man does not think he is saying anything extraordinary when he states that there are apples and pears. But when the philosopher expresses their existence in the speculative way he says something extraordinary. He performs a miracle by producing the real natural objects, the apple, the pear, etc., out of the unreal creation of the mind 'the Fruit'…. It goes without saying that the speculative philosopher accomplishes this continuous creation only by presenting universally known qualities of the apple, the pear, etc., which exist in reality, as determining features invented by him, by giving the names of the real things to what abstract reason alone can create, to abstract formulas of reason, finally, by declaring his own activity, by which he passes from the idea of an apple to the idea of a pear, to be the self-activity of the Absolute Subject, 'the Fruit.' In the speculative way of speaking, this operation is called comprehending Substance as Subject, as an inner process, as an Absolute Person, and this comprehension constitutes the essential character of Hegel's method." [Marx and Engels (1975a), pp.72-75. Bold emphases alone added. Several paragraphs merged.]

 

As Davidson noted (with which Hegel appeared to concur, as did Marx and Engels), if anything that is supposed to be general is capable of being given a Proper Name, or referred to by means of a singular term (e.g., a definite description, such as "the Fruit"), it can't be general, but must be particular.

 

And generality, like virginity, once lost can't be restored -- or, not without radical surgery.3

 

As Marx and Engels also noted:

 

"Having reduced the different real fruits to the one 'fruit' of abstraction -- 'the Fruit', speculation must, in order to attain some semblance of real content, try somehow to find its way back from 'the Fruit', from the Substance to the diverse, ordinary real fruits, the pear, the apple, the almond etc. It is as hard to produce real fruits from the abstract idea 'the Fruit' as it is easy to produce this abstract idea from real fruits. Indeed, it is impossible to arrive at the opposite of an abstraction without relinquishing the abstraction…." [Ibid; bold emphasis alone added.]

 

How Not  To Solve Philosophical 'Problems' 2.0

 

As night be expected, Empiricists didn't just sit on their thumbs for a couple of centuries, they made numerous attempts to solve these 'problems', doing so by the simple expedient of diverting attention from them and onto unrelated side-issues (to be examined presently). None of them even so much as questioned the complex word-juggling that had given life to this ancient pseudoproblem (again, analysed in detail in Part One), which, of course, meant all their efforts were in vain. One aspect of their attempt to deflect from their (obvious) predicament involved the invention of an irrelevant 'mental' capacity, an almost magical ability the 'mind' allegedly possessed, which 'enabled' it to 'discern' resemblances between the various 'impressions', 'images', 'ideas' the senses sent its way, or which were supposedly cobbled-together from them.

 

But, once again, Aristotle's objection reared its ugly head, only now in a more pernicious form: if there is a problem over the 'resemblances' that exist between objects (of a certain sort) in 'external reality', it is surely a bad idea to retreat from the Real into the Ideal (i.e., into 'the mental') in an attempt to resolve it. Indeed, if this 'process' is hidden away in the recesses of 'the mind', the philosophical 'problem' that this new approach sought to address will now re-appear in a completely intractable form. That is because 'internal processes' like these are even more problematic -- clearly, because they lie beyond any hope of objective or subjective investigation.4

 

Generality, driven inwards in this way, is even more difficult to coax out of solitary confinement.5

 

Platonic Realism, Aristotelian Conceptualism and fashionable Bourgeois Empiricism -- along with a host of other metaphysical doctrines that have since attempted to solve this pseudoproblem -- all ran aground on these unyielding rocks.

 

[To see this, just replace "G1" from earlier with any of the 'abstractions'/'ideas'/'concepts'/'representations'/'Universals' (etc.) concocted by the above traditionalists and contemporary theorists; the rest will follow as before.]

 

By way of contrast, ordinary language not only enables, it allows for, the expression of generality when it is left to those who employ common nouns, verbs and adjectives every day of their lives, but with none of the above fuss. But, these terms soon lose their generality when they are elbowed aside, replaced by the abstract singular terms concocted by Traditional Philosophers.6

 

However, placing such emphasis on an individual's apprehension of generality (howsoever that itself was supposedly achieved by 'the mind') meant that theorists found they could only hope to account for generality by surreptitiously re-employing it elsewhere. This untoward turn-of-events arose largely because traditional thinkers tended to conceive this conundrum epistemologically, perhaps even psychologistically. Unfortunately, the logical and grammatical 'fall from grace' that gave birth to the original 'problem' in Ancient Greece was consistently ignored, buried as it now was under centuries of irrelevant psycho-babble, metaphysical gobbledygook and pseudo-scientific jargon.

 

Which is where it largely remains to this day.6a0

 

As far as Empiricists conceived of this 'problem', if sensory experience presents the 'mind' with particular 'impressions', generality had to be cobbled-together from whatever 'resemblances' the 'mind' (or the brain) happened to 'notice' in each exemplar ('the mind'/brain now having replaced the individual concerned; more about that surreptitious move later, but in much more detail in Essay Thirteen Part Three -- for example, here). This made the entire 'problem' look as if it depended on an individual mind's, or an individual brain's, internal 'recognitional capacities' (with clear echoes of Plato's theory at work here, but now located this side of the 'heavenly divide'), as if the fragmented contents of the latter -- all those 'ideas', 'impressions', 'abstractions' and 'concepts' -- could be inspected like the faces of long lost friends and relatives, who had now perhaps wandered fortuitously into the same room and in some sort of 'pre-arranged order'.

 

[As we have seen, there are countless 'resemblances'/'similarities' between objects and processes, so how 'the mind' manages to focus only a narrow range of them is, to say the least, somewhat mysterious. On that, see Goodman (1970). Henceforth, in order to eliminate needless repetition, I will only refer to 'the mind', but readers should assume I also include 'the brain'/CNS in this, unless otherwise stated. On why the phrase "the mind" has often been put in 'scare quotes', see Essay Thirteen Part Three.]

 

Friends we can almost always recognise, but how on earth is it possible to 'recognise' an idea/concept (let alone any of its 'resemblances') the individual concerned has never encountered before?

 

No good constructing a photo-fit.6a

 

Worse still, none of these 'impressions' or 'ideas' would 'resemble' the next in line without the use of the general terms this 'theory' was itself meant to explain. [That was established earlier.]

 

[Anyway, this takes care the reply that all 'the mind' has to do is spot similarities between 'ideas'/'impressions' in such circumstances, so, a given individual can recognise similarities between 'impressions' they have never met before. Maybe so, but only if they already have access to the right general term so they are able to conclude, "This is the same F as that" (where "F" stands for the general term involved). Without that there would be nothing to compare or contrast anything with, no means by which it could be achieved. "This is the same...", where that empty space (marked by those dots) is empty, itself remains empty of content, and hence is no use at all in this regard. Of course, it could now be countered that individuals who have no language (either they are too young or are impaired in some way) can certainly recognise similarities between 'impressions' they have never met before, as can animals. I have dealt with replies like that immediately below, as well as here.]

 

In which case, "Ah, here is yet another (impression of a) cat!" could never legitimately be uttered by an Empiricist at the beginning of their associationist career, since, at best, what they would really mean is this: "Ah, here is yet another impression/image/sensation of something I haven't right now got a word for...". Or even: "Ah, here is yet another something of something (sic) I haven't right now got any words for...". Furthermore, as that individual's 'epistemological career' progressed, the very best they would be able to do is access an 'idea of cat' -- but, where the word "cat" had come from is, unsurprisingly, left entirely mysterious -- the Proper Name, "CAT", would thereby neutralise its generality.

 

[This sorry tale merges with recent discussions of Wittgenstein's comments about whether or not it is possible for anyone to invent their own private language from scratch. That topic is far too big to enter into here, so readers are directed to Candlish (2019) for an overview. But, Marx himself argued against any such possibility; in which case it is difficult to see how anyone who agrees with him can also give credence to any theory that relies on the 'process of abstraction', which, as Bertell Ollman has pointed out, appears to be based on that very possibility, on the formation of a private language.]

 

The usual response to the above is that each individual learns to associate words like "cat" with their 'ideas'/'impressions'/'representations' of that animal. I will return to discuss the defunct 'associationist psychology' that underpins theories like that later on in this Essay. It is sufficient to note here that any such 'associations' will also be triggered by the word "mammal" and "animal" (or even "object") as much as they would by "cat".

 

[There are similar 'triggering problems' with other co-extensive (and even partially co-extensive) terms. For example, "red" is co-extensive with "colour" (whatever is red is also coloured, but that isn't so the other way round), which associations can't discriminate between. On this, see Cowie (2002) and Mandelbaum (2020). Also see Laurence and Margolis (2012), pp.1-10).]

 

Anyway, given this 'family of theories', general terms have to be distilled painstakingly from a finite range of exemplars, those that fortuitously confront each lone abstractor -- or as each 'mind' supposedly processes them in an unshared and unshareable manner.

 

However, if each socially-isolated 'mind' is supposed to extrapolate successfully from what the few particulars it experiences ('internally' or 'externally'), then, in order to construct the relevant 'abstract general idea' from such meagre resources, each 'sensation', 'impression', 'idea', or 'quale' (singular of qualia) would have to be given a general make-over of some sort (for want of a better term). And, in order to do that, the 'mind' would have to re-connect each of these 'epistemological atoms' -- all the 'sensations', 'impressions', 'ideas' and 'qualia' it encounters  -- with others of the 'same sort', using whatever similar features it happened to notice. But, as we saw earlier, not only does that make it impossible to explain how any two lone abstractors could ever form the 'same idea' (of anything), it makes the whole process dependent on a suspiciously loose notion of "similarity", a term whose meaning itself presupposes generality! In that case, if two 'impressions', a and b, are said to share a "similar" property, designated by the use of a common noun or adjective, "F", -- so that it might be judged that a is F and b is F, and hence that that was enough to be able to decide that a is 'similar' to b in so far as they both share F -- that would only be possible if F were already a general term, otherwise it couldn't be shared, nor could it collect a and b together as 'members' of its "extension".

 

Clearly, this new twist only succeeds in introducing a general idea through the back door while failing to explain either the general or the particular that had earlier slipped out the front. If the two 'impressions' mentioned above are indeed similar, then that would only be so with respect to some 'feature', F, that they both held in common, which feature (of necessity) can't itself be another particular (otherwise it couldn't be held in common -- or at least couldn't apply generally).

 

So, in order to rescue generality from such radical particularisation, a new general term will have to be smuggled in while no one is looking -- or their attention had been distracted.7

 

More about that tactic, presently.

 

[But, what about those with no language, mentioned earlier? They can surely recognise similarities they have never experienced before. Putting to one side worries about the applicability loose term "similarity" (again, on that see Goodman (1970))in such circumstances, maybe they can, but specifying what they register requires the use of general terms, once more. Doesn't this concession reveal that the use of language isn't necessary, after all? Doesn't it show that without language it is possible to recognise similarities that haven't been encountered before, contrary to what was argued earlier? A language-user might require access to general terms, but not a subject without a language, such as an animal, an infant or an impaired individual. However, the original challenge was this: "How is it possible to 'recognise' an idea no one has never encountered before?" That wasn't aimed at the ability to recognise similarities between impressions, but the recognition of novel impressions never met before. In order to recognise one such it would have to have already been 'cognised' -- otherwise it couldn't be re-cognised, obviously. What languageless beings may or may not be able to do is hardly relevant here, since this 'problem' revolves around the use of general terms, which a languageless being doesn't have, by definition. In which case, such languageless subjects can hardly be said to 'abstract' anything if that involves the use of general nouns, adjectives or verbs (etc.), since they have no words. Hence what they are supposed to be able to recognise -- about which we know even less than we know about the 'mysterious process of abstraction' itself(!) --, is surely irrelevant. If anyone still disagrees, please feel free to email me with your best counter-argument.]

 

Independently of the above, just as theologians discovered centuries ago -- in relation to the Doctrine of the Trinity (expressed, for example, in the Athanasian Creed: "Neither confounding the Persons, nor dividing the substance") --, Empiricists found that with regard to their fragmented ideas of generality, it was impossible for them not to confound the particular without dividing the Universal.6b

 

[Note 6b above should in fact be Note 7b, but it would create far too many problems for other links if it were changed! What follows is the DM-equivalent of the problem Plato's theory faced in connection with "participation", mentioned earlier. On this, see Staniland (1973), pp.15-27.]

 

Hence, if each individual shares exactly the same universal of resemblance (call it, "R"), then it will be particular and unique to that individual abstractor; indeed, as we found was the case with "CAT", earlier. That is because the 'general', now faced with vain attempts to distribute it across the entire set of novice abstractors (in order to secure some level of agreement between them) can't escape from its now fragmented nature. So, if "CAT" is understood differently by each lone abstractor (as it must be, given this 'family of theories'), it can no longer be general, but must be particular to each 'mind'. That means R must be fragmented. Each lone abstractor now has their own unique, 'mental idea', 'CAT', which would resemble no one else's idea, 'CAT', unless someone (call her, "NM") had access to the contents of every 'mind' involved and could attest to their identity, using yet another non-fragmented general term!. But, NM, by some miracle, must thereby be able to by-pass the entire 'abstractive process' and declare every individual exemplar, 'CAT', is the same as, and 'reflects' the same, as all the rest, with that judgement itself not having been based on NM's own 'ideas', but on 'reality itself' (whatever that might now mean!). Failing that, no one would be able to declare that all these lone abstractors had the same idea/concept, 'CAT', never mind any other such.

 

[NM would have to by-pass this 'process' and base her judgement on 'reality itself' -- thereby abandoning empiricism -- otherwise her ideas would be trapped in the same epistemological quagmire, thus rendering it useless in this regard.]

 

But, what is true of 'CAT' will be true of all other 'abstractions', and that includes R. All such will be fragmented across an entire population.

 

This divides the Universal.

 

Alas, the universal, now divided, will always be defeated.

 

Conversely, if the above distribution of general ideas hadn't been carried out in a perfectly egalitarian manner, the relevant particulars wouldn't be collected together under the same general term, shared equally by one and all. But, if that were the case, if R had been shared equally across an entire population, so that every abstractor had exactly the same idea of 'CAT', its individuality would be lost -- it would have been confounded, just as predicted.

 

Alas, the individual confounded has now been defeated.

 

So, the general, the Universal, was either divided (and was thereby unique to each lone abstractor) or the particular was confounded (since any ideas held about it/them would all be identical).

 

If the individual is confounded, there will be no individuals of a given type, there will only be one substance, one Universal, one Abstract Idea, spread out, as it were across every one of its apparent instances/'moments'. Each 'seeming particular' would just be a 'local appearance' or 'manifestation' of One Universal -- rather like an emanation or instantiation of 'God' (a doctrine actually propounded by certain forms of Mystical Christianity, and other religions/philosophies), 'who' is supposed to be everywhere all at once. So, to bring this down to earth, each 'seemingly individual' CAT would simply be a 'manifestation' of 'CAT-in-General'. 'Appearances' would then be misleading. While you might foolishly think you are seeing a concrete particular (an individual cat!), in reality all you would be seeing is a 'moment' in the life of a 'Concept' -- 'CAT'. The cat you now think you see is but a mere 'appearance', a brief 'manifestation' of 'CATHOOD'. Its 'reality' would be defined by the Universal, which 'shines' in your direction. We will meet this quandary again later, as DM-theorists vainly try to explain why 'essence contradicts appearances', and why they think 'matter' is just an 'abstraction'. Those who know enough Hegel will no doubt recognise where this train-of-thought is headed. (These points also depend on an earlier argument and might not be fully appreciated by anyone who hasn't read it or hasn't called it to mind.) The critical points raised in this paragraph are, in effect, the same as those advanced by Marx and Engels in a passage quoted several times below.

 

In that case, the stark choice between confounding the individual or dividing the substance (i.e., dividing the general) challenged Empiricists and Rationalists alike, just as it had the Trinitarians -- and for the same basic reason. That is because this entire family of doctrines had descended with modification from the same ancient syntactic screw up we met in Part One.

 

All of which helps explain the continual oscillation in Traditional Ontology between Monism, Dualism and Pluralism -- and why Metaphysicians can't decide between Rationalism, Conceptualism and Nominalism.

 

To paraphrase Wittgenstein: this was in effect an entire Metaphysic distilled out of a drop of grammar! [Wittgenstein (2009), p.233, §315.]

 

Again, Wittgenstein's point was the main theme of Part One.

 

Intelligent Ideas Versus A 'Little Man' In The Head

 

Added On Edit, October 2024 -- Further Background

 

The material below, and the next few sub-sections, contains perhaps the most 'flowery' language in the entire Essay (and possibly even the entire site!), where metaphors and other rhetorical images seem to take over. Mercifully, I have progressively edited much it out, but not all!

 

To continue what was posted in the Preface: the reason for all this 'purple prose' is that I am trying tell a very familiar story in an entirely new way -- and with a political twist thrown in for good measure. The point is to underline the challenge posed to Christian Theology (and hence to much of 'Western Philosophy' and Traditional Thought) by the gradual realisation that contingency exists in nature and the 'threat' this posed the 'social order' in general. An unruly, disorderly world, where there was no overall rationality, no overall plan or purpose, meant there was either no 'God' (an idea that completely undermined Royal 'legitimacy' and hence ruling-class power and privilege), or 'God Himself' was disorderly (an idea that also threatened 'established hierarchy'). The transition to capitalism across Europe led to the replacement of Feudalism with entirely novel capitalist relations, and that brought in its train a renewed threat. [How that was (ideologically) the case will be explained in what follows and in other Essays published at this site, but most Marxists are already aware of the factors involved in this, even if they might not be cognisant of the specific issues raised at this site, in this regard.]

 

If order and legitimacy were to be restored, a philosophical and necessitarian basis for knowledge had to be re-established, and that itself had to be based on three related factors:

 

(a) The 'rational nature' of the universe itself;

 

(b) The rational nature of human cognition; and,

 

(c) Justification had to begin in the individual case. That is part of what made Descartes's philosophy so revolutionary and so paradigmatic. It hit the right notes at just the right time. [Ben-Yami (2015).]

 

So, some way had to be found whereby what seemed to be the disorderly or contingent way human beings experienced the world and then formed ideas about it didn't undermine rational and orderly nature of the universe, but in the end actually 'reflected' it.

 

Hence, this section and those that follow will add to what has already been established above (and in Part One in this respect). As such they are aimed at highlighting the different ways in which the 'restoration of order' (both in thought and 'reality') was attempted by post-Renaissance Philosophers. They will also show how the DM-Classicists were seduced by these new ideas, and, as a result, how "ruling ideas" came to dominate Dialectical Marxism.

 

[Why the above revolutionaries were so easily misled is explained in Essay Nine Parts One and Two.]

 

With respect to the aforementioned DM-Classicists, contingency also threatened their ideas. An irrational world completely undermined Hegelian 'logic' and its associated Teleology. That in turn undermined the legitimacy of any challenge made to class society. If the world was fundamentally irrational, governed by chance, what sort of rational justification could there be for communism? What sort of guarantee could there be that a revolution would even be successful? So, the DM-classicists had to find a way of legitimating their own opposition to the status quo and the society they claimed would emerge as a result. Given the doctrinal and intellectual tradition in which they had all been socialised (with well-established, deeply-embedded "ruling ideas" forming a core factor -- e.g., they were all brought up as Christians, or, in Mao's case, as a Confucian7b), the only way that these lofty aims could be secured was to look for 'logical principles' that were somehow stitched into the fabric of 'reality' and which also mirrored by, or were 'reflected in', human cognition -- 'concepts' that also told them change was not just a core component in, it was a rational component of, the 'cosmic order'. Hence, the 'principles'/'laws' they borrowed from Hegel (upside down or the 'right way up') were dutifully stitched into 'dialectical reality' and imposed on the way human beings cognised that 'reality' -- 'like reflecting like', again. Both were achieved in a way that seemed (to them) to guarantee success. After all, if the Universe -- the 'Totality' -- runs along lines that harmonise with our own (genuine) thought processes (but only if the latter remain faithful to 'the dialectic'), and if all things are 'inter-connected' -- how could Dialectical Marxism possibly fail? Teleology was thereby smuggled into the workers' movement  through the back door -- by non-workers! Concepts were re-connected so that the link between them and 'objects'/'processes' was 'rational'/'logical', once more. Contingency was thereby cast into outer darkness. And that is why the DM-classicists latched onto Hegel's system so readily and so enthusiastically. It gave them exactly what they were looking for (if flipped 'right-side up'). In this way a set of ancient, anthropomorphic, quasi-religious metaphors (that pictured human knowledge 'reflecting' or 'mirroring' nature -- both of which were key components in the Hermetic World-View, and which underpinned Hegel's entire system) came to dominate their (now corrupted) version of Marxism. That is why they all see 'contradictions' and 'negations' everywhere -- as indeed anyone would so think whose theory had just anthropomorphised the entire Universe, and who also imagined it was a 'reflection' of the way human beings reason and talk!

 

And here is Lenin summarising these very ideas (notice how it all follows from the sort of language analysed in Part One!):

 

"Such must also be the method of exposition (i.e., study) of dialectics in general.... To begin with what is the simplest, most ordinary, common, etc., with any proposition: the leaves of a tree are green; John is a man: Fido is a dog, etc. Here already we have dialectics (as Hegel's genius recognised): the individual is the universal.... Consequently, the opposites (the individual is opposed to the universal) are identical: the individual exists only in the connection that leads to the universal. The universal exists only in the individual and through the individual. Every individual is (in one way or another) a universal. Every universal is (a fragment, or an aspect, or the essence of) an individual. Every universal only approximately embraces all the individual objects. Every individual enters incompletely into the universal, etc., etc. Every individual is connected by thousands of transitions with other kinds of individuals (things, phenomena, processes) etcHere already we have the elements, the germs, the concepts of necessity, of objective connection in nature, etc. Here already we have the contingent and the necessary, the phenomenon and the essence; for when we say: John is a man, Fido is a dog, this is a leaf of a tree, etc., we disregard a number of attributes as contingent; we separate the essence from the appearance, and counterpose the one to the other. Thus in any proposition we can (and must) disclose as in a 'nucleus' ('cell') the germs of all the elements of dialectics, and thereby show that dialectics is a property of all human knowledge in general. And natural science shows us (and here again it must be demonstrated in any simple instance) objective nature with the same qualities, the transformation of the individual into the universal, of the contingent into the necessary, transitions, modulations, and the reciprocal connection of opposites. Dialectics is the theory of knowledge of (Hegel and) Marxism. This is the 'aspect' of the matter (it is not 'an aspect' but the essence of the matter) to which Plekhanov, not to speak of other Marxists, paid no attention." [Lenin (1961), pp.359-60. Bold emphases alone added; paragraphs merged. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

In such terms Lenin succeeded in dividing the Universal while confounding the individual, echoing the predicament Trinitarian Christians found themselves in (noted earlier). Notice, too, how Lenin thought he (or his interpretation of Hegel) had reintroduced necessity into nature and society, thereby banishing contingency; viz: "the transformation of the individual into the universal, of the contingent into the necessary...".

 

'Dialectical legitimacy' was back on the table again -- alongside and in competition with bourgeois legitimacy --, all a product of language.

 

In this way, an ancient batch of "ruling ideas" were given a pseudo-materialist coat of paint, which is how and why ruling-class ideology found its way in to Dialectical Marxism, where it remains to this day. [These ideas have been set out in extensive detail in Essay Nine Parts One and Two. This Part of Essay Three is also aimed at exposing the intellectual forces that pushed the founders of our movement in this direction.]

 

However, in what follows there is a parallel image I am also trying to explore, which focuses on the connection between:

 

(i) The 'unruly' impressions and ideas the senses (supposedly) deliver 'the mind' allied with a need to impose some sort of 'order' on these 'inputs' (for the above reasons);

 

(ii) The (hypothesised) 'order' underlying or 'governing' the universe (which is required, as we have just seen, in order to legitimate these moves); and,

 

(iii) The 'unruly' working class upon whom the ruling-class and their ideologues have to impose some sort of order. So, if the world, or our impression of it, had to have order imposed on it (to counteract contingency and atheism), that was also the case with the working class -- in order to regulate and maximise the flow of profit, counteract 'lawlessness', water-down the effect of democracy/republicanism, and, 'god'-forbid(!), prevent revolution.

 

Ruling-class theorists certainly made the following connection: if there was no underlying order to the universe (if everything were fundamentally adventitious and contingent), how would it be possible to rationalise or justify the status quo, class division, oppression and inequality? How would it be possible to legitimate the top-down control of the 'disorderly', 'ignorant masses'? That message wasn't lost on Dialectical Marxists, either, who also echoed this reactionary attitude aimed at the working class. As other Essays at this site have shown, as far as Dialectical Marxists were concerned, the working class is not only unruly --, which means the party must discipline it, or even substitute itself for it -- it is also (even worse!) 'ignorant of dialectics', and, as such, is ideologically backward and in need of teachers who have 'seen the light'. That in turn is because workers have been intellectually befuddled by 'formal thinking', a debased condition compounded by the 'banalities of commonsense'. In addition, their thought has been crippled by an unwise reliance on strictly limited (even 'defective') ordinary language, which means they are all trapped in an 'epistemological fog' generated by an unwise reliance on 'appearances'.

 

In that case, self-appointed, dialectical prophets are going to have to bring the good news to the benighted masses -- "from the outside" --, becoming 'Great Teachers', or even 'Great Helmsmen', of and for the 'ignorant masses'. Plainly, these self-declared prophets need a philosophy all of their own, which only they 'understand', that not only helps 'justify' substitutionism, it rationalises their 'superiority' over the class. [On that, see here, here and here.]

 

Enter DM, courtesy of the non-working-class founders of Dialectical Marxism.

 

That helps explain why these 'dialectical prophets' cling to DM like terminally insecure limpets and why they become extremely abusive when it is challenged. Again, all of this is set out in detail in Parts One and Two of Essay Nine. This Essay merely presents some of the ideological background to the above moves, and which helps explain why Dialectical Marxism has been such an abject, long-term failure.

 

After all, if a revolutionary party adopts and is guided by a philosophy that is a pale reflection of ruling-class ideology and Christian Mysticism, how could anyone realistically expect any other outcome?

 

Yet More Problems

 

Unfortunately, the 'problems' aired in previous sections don't end there. Nor do they become any the less intractable.

 

As should now seem reasonably clear, definitive answers were required for a range of 'awkward questions', not the least of which was this: Exactly how is 'the mind' able to sift through the 'ideas' and 'impressions' the senses supposedly send its way? [Henceforth, these 'ideas' and 'impressions' will simply be called 'inputs'.] An effective response to such a question would have to include convincing answers to further queries about how 'it' manages to sort these 'inputs' into the 'correct mental boxes', with the 'right' general noun or adjective that was either attached, associated with, or attributed to, each. But, as we have just seen, that itself would depend on the individuals concerned, or their 'mind', already having a grasp of the relevant general terms in order to produce the 'correct results', never mind any that are consistent. So, the individual in question would already have to have effective command of the relevant terms (i.e., they would have to be able to use them 'correctly'), which, of course, means that whatever the 'mind' is supposed to be able to do is parasitic on publicly-acquired and communally-performed skills, not the other way round. That is just a long-winded way of saying we are all taught what out words mean, we don't attach out own meaning to them. [I have covered this topic in much greater detail in Essay Thirteen Part Three -- Sections 4 to 8.]

 

[Always assuming, of course, that 'the mind' is able to do anything at all -- on that, see the rest of this sub-section. The reason for all the 'scare' quotes around several of the above words -- like "correct" and "right" -- should become clear reasonably soon. If not, readers might like to skip forward to this section. Why the word "mind" is similarly encased is also explained in Essay Thirteen Part Three, link above.]

 

That is something that began to dawn on Kant (in his own confused way -- confused, since he, too, located this 'sorting' faculty in 'the mind', unwisely ignoring socialisation and the public use of language):

 

"Our cognition arises from two fundamental sources in the mind, the first of which is the reception of representations (the receptivity of impressions), the second of the faculty for cognizing an object by means of these representations (spontaneity of concepts); through the former an object is given to us, through the latter it is thought in relation to that representation (as a mere determination of the mind). Intuition and concepts therefore constitute the elements of all our cognition, so that neither concepts without intuition corresponding to them in some way nor intuition without concepts can yield a cognition.... Thoughts without content are empty, intuitions without concepts are blind." [Kant (1998), pp.193-94, A51/B75. Bold emphases in the original; italic emphasis added. Paragraphs merged. (By "intuition" Kant meant something like "immediate experience" -- Caygill (1995), pp.262-66.)]

 

"Our knowledge springs from two main sources in the mind, first of which is the faculty or power of receiving representations (receptivity for impressions); the second is the power of cognizing by means of these representations (spontaneity in the production of conceptions). Through the first an object is given to us; through the second, it is, in relation to the representation (which is a mere determination of the mind), thought. Intuition and conceptions constitute, therefore, the elements of all our knowledge, so that neither conceptions without an intuition in some way corresponding to them, nor intuition without conceptions, can afford us a cognition." [Online version of the above. As we saw in Part One, Hegel also made a similar point, except he claimed that what Kant called an "intuition" was already conceptualised. How that was even possible was left rather vague.]

 

But, without this necessary pre-condition (i.e., socialisation and the public use of language), 'inter-subjective objectivity' will always remain a vacuous concept.

 

Indeed, this is just another way of saying that these 'inputs' can't be expected to sort themselves neatly into the 'right' groups -- as if they were autonomous, self-directed agents --, since they have neither the wit nor the intelligence to do so. Even for Kant, they required some form of regimentation, externally imposed on them. [That is, this 'sorting' would require regimentation external to the 'inputs' themselves, which would supposedly be provided by 'the mind', its 'cognitive apparatus' or its 'concepts'. How any of that actually worked Kant, alas, kept to himself.]

 

However, in the age-old battle between the One and the Many, the Many have always shown themselves far too 'unruly' and 'ill-disciplined' (so to speak) to be able to regiment themselves in the required manner, while the One was far too 'aloof', and hence 'feeble' and 'weak' (so to speak, once more) to do any regimenting. Nevertheless, if it were even possible to impose some sort of order, 'principles' external to these disorderly 'inputs' (the Many) had to be found, to lend 'the mind' (the One) a helping hand. Never was care in the Community of Ideas more needed than here. And yet, if such 'inputs' were to become more than a 'heap of conceptual dust' (so to speak, again) -- haphazardly deposited inside each cognising skull (i.e., if they weren't to be left unsorted, uncategorised, unconnected) --, some sort of 'care' was essential, which had to be sought from somewhere, and quickly.

 

[Recall, these 'inputs' are the 'impressions' and 'ideas' that the senses supposedly send the 'mind'. The reason for the above stress on urgency was explained earlier.]

 

As seems plain, 'sortal principles' -- necessary to whip all these disorderly 'inputs' into shape -- can't be self-explanatory, nor can they be self-regulating or even self-directing. On the other hand, if they were, there would seem to be no reason why that couldn't also be the case with the 'inputs' themselves. Or, indeed, why the latter couldn't be expected to troop unaided into the 'right metaphysical pigeon holes', certifying their own inter-subjective 'resemblance' with others of their 'kin'. That is, there was no good reason why any such 'inputs' couldn't just assemble themselves under the 'correct' general term without a 'guiding hand' to do it for them, or impose it on them.

 

Indeed, if these 'inputs' were capable of self-regulation, or could sort themselves, that would remove the need for a 'mind' and its 'attendant goons' (all those 'concepts' and 'categories') to whip them into shape.

 

Clearly, the first of the above two options would see 'the mind', or its 'principles', as some sort of 'drill-sergeant', thus anthropomorphising both. The second would throw this 'sergeant' on the scrap heap, implying these 'inputs' were in fact autonomous agents -- anthropomorphising them, instead.

 

[They would all ne anthropomorphised since they would all thereby be granted human capacities and skills, the very thing such theories were introduced to avoid! As we are about to see, that is still the case with theories developed in contemporary Cognitive Theory.] 

 

But several awkward questions remained: Is 'the mind' actually in control here? Or are these 'inputs' autonomous agents, after all? Could such questions even be addressed without crediting both with human characteristics?

 

[There are faint echoes of both halves of the above dilemma in contemporary Cognitive Psychology and Behaviourism. The former anthropomorphises the brain (picturing it as some sort of diminutive human being, lodged inside each skull, an homunculus); the latter scraps 'the mind' altogether, leaving all such 'inputs' to fend for themselves. (There is much more on this in Essay Thirteen Part Three -- where an explanation is given how and why contemporary Cognitive Theory has ended up anthropomorphising the brain and/or its contents.) On this, see Kenny (1984b).]

 

Of course, many Empiricists claimed that 'the mind' was somehow capable of extrapolating way beyond the limited set of 'inputs' the senses sent its way, allowing it to form general ideas themselves, which is what all those 'resemblances' supposedly implied anyway. Unfortunately, this 'solution' left unexplained exactly how any such 'extrapolations' might be carried out without 'the mind' having a (pre-installed) notion of the general to guide it. But that was the very thing that required explanation, to begin with!

 

As we saw earlier, in order to conjure into existence even one such 'abstract general idea', 'the mind' must already have grasped that concept itself, vitiating the whole exercise.

 

As Kant himself might well have asked: Where on earth might that have come from?

 

[The phrase "circular argument" now comes to mind, for some reason. Here is another less abstract way of making the same point: sheepdogs don't spontaneously know how to herd sheep, and drill-sergeants don't grow on trees. It took countless centuries of human social and technological progress to bring humanity to the stage where both were able to do what they now do. If there is such a 'mind' that is capable of regimenting the inputs it receives, it would only be able to do so as a result of analogous forms of social conditioning, not a mythical 'process of abstraction'. Even if there were such a 'process', it would require mastery of the very concept it was originally introduced to explain, generality. And, that would be the result of a socially-acquired skill, not a privately performed trick, which is how abstractionism pictures it.]

 

Nevertheless, if particulars (these 'inputs') are to be marshalled, or 'cognised', into the 'correct' sortal categories by 'the mind' (or by the use of 'rational principles'), there seemed to be only two ways that that might be achieved (both of which have already been hinted at):

 

(A) The first involved reference to specific 'mental faculties' (these days re-branded as "modules") that each novice abstractor supposedly possessed, or to which they had automatic, even privileged, access to do all this regimenting for them -- "mental bodies of armed men", as it were. Bourgeois Ideas, supposedly born free, would now be clapped in chains. [This is the 'mental' equivalent, perhaps, of the Absolutist State.]

 

(B) The second appealed to the 'natural propensities' supposedly possessed by any such 'inputs', which meant that they were capable of regimenting themselves, marching 'voluntarily' into the 'right' 'mental boxes' with no outside assistance. [This is the 'mental equivalent', perhaps, of an 'Anarchist Utopia'.]

 

Taking each in turn:

 

(A) One version of this alternative postulated the existence of "innate ideas"/"principles" that were somehow 'programmed into the mind', either activated or guided by the "laws of thought", the "natural light of reason", or some other component of a given individual's 'mental architectonic'. [Caygill (1995), pp.84-85.]

 

[More recent analogues of this 'mental assembly-line' have these 'cognitive factors' hard-wired into the brain as a "transformational grammar" -- now re-christened, "Unbounded Merge" --, or even as a "Language of Thought", about which we know even less than we do about Dark Matter or the deepest recesses of our planet's oceans.]

 

[On this in general, see Cowie (2002).]

 

A much older version held that 'innate ideas' (also misleadingly labelled "clear and distinct") were, at some level, capable of unerringly guiding aspiring thinkers, allowing them to classify each particular given in experience (or even universally, prior to experience) under the 'correct' general term. How that individual knew what was 'correct' and what was 'incorrect' -- and even how they might arrive at some agreement with others across an entire population over this -- we must pass over in silence, mainly because those who (still) promote this theory, or its modern day reincarnations, also pass over it in silence.

 

Of course, this means Option (A) sits neatly in the Rationalist Camp, and perhaps because of this the temptation became irresistible to bury the source of these 'innate principles' in the mists of time -- boosted of late with a veritable barrage of Neo-Darwinian 'just-so-stories' projected back into the Pleistocene -- original syntax now based on Genetics, not 'Genesis'.8

 

Other versions of Option (A) weren't even remotely Empiricist, staging their appearance in the Cartesian-Leibnizian-Kantian-Hegelian tradition of a priori myth-making.

 

Nevertheless, each variant shared the same fundamental premiss: 'abstractions' were alive and well, and were either living in a skull near you or were perhaps camped out somewhere in 'objective reality' waiting to be enlisted to the cause -- presumably, merely by being 'thought about' by a suitably clued-in 'abstractor' or fast-talking Smart Alec.

 

Even more convenient was the additional fact that while 'abstract ideas' were (somehow) thought to be real, they were also (somehow) capable of transcending actual or possible experience. Indeed, in this respect alone they bore an uncanny resemblance to the 'gods' of yore, and, as was also the case with those defunct 'divinities', these mysterious 'abstractions' underpinned, made possible, gave substance to, or even created, the material world we see around us.

 

This happened, for instance, when a lively subset unceremoniously 'self-developed' while they lived, rent free, in Hegel's head.

 

Unfortunately, given this approach to generality and knowledge, abstract ideas turned out to be more real than the material world we see around us. The latter was, after all, full of lowly, debased, contingent objects and processes -- fit only for destruction, according to Hegel, hence, hardly worth mentioning in Ideal company.

 

Moreover, since these abstractions had been granted rather grandiose titles, that alone (surely!) implied they must exist...somewhere. After all, how could they possibly fail to do so if generation after generation of 'leading minds' and 'influential thinkers' had not only gone to the trouble of identifying them, they had also thoughtfully named them for us? Such generous acts of reification called for, nay demanded, philosophical genuflection -- their inventors thereby labelled 'geniuses' --, which acts of theoretical deference transformed them, making all of them not just real, but Super-Real.

 

"To begin with what is the simplest, most ordinary, common, etc., [sic] with any proposition...: [like] John is a man…. Here we already have dialectics (as Hegel's genius recognized): the individual is the universal…. Consequently, the opposites (the individual is opposed to the universal) are identical: the individual exists only in the connection that leads to the universal. The universal exists only in the individual and through the individual. Every individual is (in one way or another) a universal. Every universal is (a fragment, or an aspect, or the essence of) an individual. Every universal only approximately embraces all the individual objects. Every individual enters incompletely into the universal, etc., etc. Every individual is connected by thousands of transitions with other kinds of individuals (things, phenomena, processes), etc. Here already we have the elements, the germs of the concept of necessity, of objective connection in nature, etc. Here already we have the contingent and the necessary, the phenomenon and the essence; for when we say John is a man…we disregard a number of attributes as contingent; we separate the essence from the appearance, and counterpose the one to the other…. Thus in any proposition we can (and must) disclose as a 'nucleus' ('cell') the germs of all the elements of dialectics, and thereby show that dialectics is a property of all human knowledge in general." [Lenin (1961), pp.357-58, 359-60. Bold emphasis alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site; paragraphs merged.]

 

These 'abstractions' were in effect 'Super-Real' plainly because their 'ontological status', reflecting 'essence', was deemed far superior to the lowly rank 'unreliable appearances' now occupied. This meant, of course, that 'abstractions' alone were capable of generating the Super-Scientific Truths of Traditional Metaphysics, and now DM. As James White pointed out (quoted earlier):

 

"Already with Fichte the idea of the unity of the sciences, of system, was connected with that of finding a reliable starting-point in certainty on which knowledge could be based. Thinkers from Kant onwards were quite convinced that the kind of knowledge which came from experience was not reliable. Empirical knowledge could be subject to error, incomplete, or superseded by further observation or experiment. It would be foolish, therefore, to base the whole of knowledge on something which had been established only empirically. The kind of knowledge which Kant and his followers believed to be the most secure was a priori knowledge, the kind embodied in the laws of Nature. These had been formulated without every occurrence of the Natural phenomenon in question being observed, so they did not summarise empirical information, and yet they held good by necessity for every case; these laws were truly universal in their application." [White (1996a), p.29. In fact, Rationalists since Plato was in diapers had already concluded this.]

 

Even better, our ancestors had helpfully, if not mischievously, buried these 'abstractions' behind what appear to be a perfectly ordinary and familiar grammatical feature of discourse: the subject-copula-predicate form -- even if this supposedly important linguistic artifice only succeeded in advertising its presence in the Indo-European family of languages, rarely anywhere else. Even then (as we saw in Part One) this turned out to be the case only when that form had been twisted way beyond the knotted pretzel stage.

 

As we also saw in Part One, such phony 'never-never-knowledge', such 'science-on-the-cheap', has dominated practically all forms of Traditional Thought since Thales and Anaximander were in diapers. It is, indeed, one of the perennial "ruling ideas":

 

"The ideas of the ruling class are in every epoch the ruling ideas, i.e. the class which is the ruling material force of society, is at the same time its ruling intellectual force. The class which has the means of material production at its disposal, has control at the same time over the means of mental production, so that thereby, generally speaking, the ideas of those who lack the means of mental production are subject to it. The ruling ideas are nothing more than the ideal expression of the dominant material relationships, the dominant material relationships grasped as ideas; hence of the relationships which make the one class the ruling one, therefore, the ideas of its dominance. The individuals composing the ruling class possess among other things consciousness, and therefore think. Insofar, therefore, as they rule as a class and determine the extent and compass of an epoch, it is self-evident that they do this in its whole range, hence among other things rule also as thinkers, as producers of ideas, and regulate the production and distribution of the ideas of their age: thus their ideas are the ruling ideas of the epoch." [Marx and Engels (1970), pp.64-65, quoted from here. Bold emphases added.]

 

Or, to refer back to an earlier image, this version of the theory pictures 'inputs' as if they are analogous to sheep that require herding into the 'correct sheep pens'. If so, do 'concepts', 'categories' and 'rational principles' act like sheepdogs? Or is that just true of 'the intellect'/'one of its modules'?

 

 

Video One: Is This How 'Cognition' Collects Together

Particulars Under General Terms?

 

But, sheep can and do spontaneously form herds, even though they need a sheep dog (or its equivalent) to 'encourage' them into the right 'boxes'/sheep pens. Is that how 'the mind' coerces 'inputs'? Like sheep, do they naturally congregate into herds? Sheep have evolved this propensity as a survival strategy. But, who or what is hunting all these 'inputs' so that they, too, need an analogous survival instinct to drive them into herds? Good luck trying to train a sheepdog to do this with animals that don't naturally form herds -- like cats! In that case, are these 'inputs' cat-like or sheep-like? More to the point: Is the 'mind' sheepdog-like?

 

Such questions naturally lead us into a consideration of the next main Option:

 

(B) The second of the above two Options implied that these 'inputs' somehow congregated 'naturally' of their own efforts, willingly trooping into the 'right mental categories' (labelled or 'determined' by the 'correct' general noun or adjective). But, if they were capable of spontaneously assembling, thereby congregating in the relevant classes, that would suggest they possessed a 'herd instinct' of some sort.

 

Clearly, in order for them to do that 'correctly', they must either:

 

(B1) Possess their own form of 'intellect'; or,

 

(B2) Be capable of 'obeying', or being 'guided by', specific natural or logical 'laws' of some sort or description.

 

As far as (B1) is concerned, these 'inputs' were not only capable of automatically 'recognising' those of 'their kind', they were sufficiently compliant and intelligent enough to be able to flock together with no further ado. That in turn implied they were able to:

 

(B1a) 'Detect' the 'resemblances' they shared with others of their ilk -- suggesting they were surrogate 'minds' themselves, skilled at 'correctly' and unerringly identifying their own close 'mental relatives'. [Echoes here of Plato again.]

 

Alternatively, these spontaneously gregarious 'inputs' were:

 

(B1b) 'Programmed' to behave as if they could act that way.

 

In short, these two sub-options (B1a and B1b) traded on the further belief that:

 

B1a(i): These 'inputs' were minds writ small; or,

 

B1a(ii): 'Minds' were, in effect, incarnate 'Ideas'.

 

Be this as it may, Option B1a(i) found safe haven in Leibniz's mind -- whether this theory was his own idea or he was programmed to think it was is somewhat unclear -- where everything in the universe is 'really' composed of countless pre-programmed, inter-connected 'tiny minds' (i.e., all those "windowless Monads").

 

["Inter-connected" here means each Monad was programmed (by 'God') to behave as if it were reacting to all the rest, when it wasn't. So, the 'connection' was formal not physical -- rather like all those 'internal relations' Hegel concocted.]

 

In a much grander, if not megalomaniacal and narcissistic form, Option B1a(ii) parasitized Hegel's brain. There, 'Mind' became self-developing 'Idea', the Supreme Controller of a Vast Cosmic Mystery Tour. Hegel certainly thought he was the engineer of his own ideas, but if he were correct, he was just the oily rag.

 

However, in relation to B2, the implication seemed to be that natural 'laws' operating on the contents of 'the mind' could account for the regimentation of any 'inputs' it received (or even created) -- a rather odd idea that has resurfaced more recently in several 'naturalistic' theories of mind. Once again, this Option simply reduplicates the very problem it was meant to address, since it implies that an external 'Will' (of some sort) ran both the 'inner' and the 'outer' world, as everything in this 'Mental Cosmos' obeyed orders as if they were law-abiding citizens. Recall what Descartes had to say about this:

 

"The mathematical truths which you call eternal have been laid down by God and depend on him entirely no less than the rest of his creatures. Indeed to say that these truths are independent of God is to talk of him as if he were Jupiter or Saturn and to subject him to the Styx and the Fates. Please do not hesitate to assert and proclaim everywhere that it is God who has laid down these laws in nature just as a king lays down laws in his kingdom." [Descartes (1991), p.23. Letter to Mersenne, 15/04/1630. Bold emphasis added.]

 

[I have covered this specific option in more detail in Essay Thirteen Part Three -- especially in relation to recently re-branded neo-Hegelian theories that have coalesced around what has ironically been called (by its adherents), Critical Realism. A misnomer if ever there was one! See also my comments about Christian Theology, below.]

 

Clearly, in order for something to be capable of "obeying orders" it must be, in some way or to some extent, intelligent (otherwise, the word "obey" must have assumed a completely different meaning -- I will cover the reasons for saying this in more detail in Essay Three Part Five, but some of that material has already appeared in Essay Thirteen Part Three, here and here). Hence, B2-type 'inputs' must be, in some way or to some extent, intelligent. Except, now they are 'controlled' by, and obey, the 'laws of thought', which is just an updated version of the 'mental architectonic' mentioned earlier. However, none of these 'inputs' turn out to be the passive occupants of any of the brains they happen to colonise. Quite the reverse. They are meant to be active agents, contributing in their own unique way to the 'internal cognitive community' in which they find themselves (aka 'consciousness'). As a result, this Inner Microcosm was thought capable of 'reflecting' the Outer Macrocosm -- and, vice versa, as mystics never tire of telling anyone who will listen. They reflect the world since the world reflects them, in a 'like-recognises-like' sort of way. This clearly amounted to a re-vamped, this-worldly version of Plato's metaphysic. In that case, it turns out that a 'properly functioning mind' will be 'well-ordered' because the Cosmos is 'well-ordered' -- and vice versa. Indeed, this is where the word "rational" originally came from. [On that, see Dodds (1951)]. The Inner and the Outer ('Thought' and 'Being') were thus capable of knowing -- i.e., reflecting -- each other, because both were fundamentally the same, both were 'Mind', or the product of 'Mind'.

 

There is a faint echo of this reified metaphor in Kant; a deafening roar in Hegel.

 

[This elaborates on similar points made earlier; see also the additional note, above.]8ao

 

Small wonder then that Traditional Theories of causation (especially those that invoke 'physical law' -- more on that in Essay Three Part Five, too) are shot-through with mysterious forces, anthropomorphic concepts and animistic language -- and which can only be made 'to work' if inappropriate modal terms (like "necessary" and "must") are pressed into service.8a

 

["Inappropriate" for reasons set out in Essays Twelve Part One and Thirteen Part Three.]

 

That in turn suggests these 'laws' -- and, indeed, the objects and processes that 'obey' them -- were both a reification of, and a projection onto, 'reality' of subjective psychological/'mental' capacities and dispositions. Philosophers who thought along such lines in effect found themselves peering down a deep well of metaphysical fantasy and, unsurprisingly, seeing their own reflection looking back up at them.9

 

That might help explain the connection Marx himself made with some of Feuerbach's main conclusions:

 

"Feuerbach's great achievement is.... The proof that philosophy is nothing else but religion rendered into thought and expounded by thought, i.e., another form and manner of existence of the estrangement of the essence of man; hence equally to be condemned...." [Marx (1975e), p.381. I have used the on-line version, here. Bold emphasis and link added.]

 

"The characteristic human mode of being, as distinct from that of the animal, is not only the basis, but also the object of religion. But religion is the consciousness of the infinite; hence it is, and cannot be anything other than, man’s consciousness of his own essential nature, understood not as a finite or limited, but as an infinite nature. A really finite being has not even the slightest inkling, let alone consciousness, of what an infinite being is, for the mode of consciousness is limited by the mode of being. The consciousness of the caterpillar, whose life is confined to a particular species of plant, does not extend beyond this limited sphere; it is, of course, able to distinguish this plant from other plants, but that is the entire extent of its knowledge. In a case where consciousness is so limited but where, precisely because of this limitation, it is also infallible and unerring, we speak of instinct rather than consciousness. Consciousness in the strict sense, or consciousness properly speaking, and consciousness of the infinite cannot be separated from each other; a limited consciousness is no consciousness; consciousness is essentially infinite and all-encompassing. The consciousness of the infinite is nothing else than the consciousness of the infinity of consciousness. To put it in other words, in its consciousness of infinity, the conscious being is conscious of the infinity of its own being." [Feuerbach (1957), pp.2-3. The online version I have quoted here is different from the 1957 edition here referenced. Bold emphases alone added.]

 

In other words, where humans think they see 'god' they actually see themselves, writ large. In like manner, Philosophers fool themselves, too; where, for instance, they think they see 'Being' in fact they see themselves, writ large. No surprise then that Hegel found he had to re-enchant the universe in order to make his ideas 'work'. No surprise then that Empiricists had to credit 'ideas' with surrogate human capacities, or that Rationalists transformed 'the human mind' into an homunculus, where 'consciousness' was in effect 'a little man' in the head. It is also why DM-fans claim to see human conversations taking place everywhere, right across the universe, in the shape of all those 'contradictions' and 'negations'.

 

So, it turns out that Feuerbach was more perceptive than he, or Marx, ever suspected.

 

From a different direction, this 'family of  theories' also implied the human mind was intelligent/rational simply because the universe was. That peculiar (reversed) theory can be seen in the equally odd idea that the universe became 'self-conscious' with the emergence of humanity -- a doctrine implicit in Hegel, but openly promoted by the likes of Teilhard de Chardin, Bergson, and, perhaps even more surprisingly, several Marxist dialecticians (Ted Grant, for one). That animistic inference was itself a consequence of the tortured 'logic' that supposedly mirrored the 'self-developing concepts' of the Superhuman (Hegelian) Alter-Ego that allegedly ran the entire show: 'The Absolute' (that we met in Part One), or "the Totality" (that we will meet in Essay Eleven Part One).

 

Given this overall approach, not only was the Real Rational and the Rational Real, there was only the Rational, only 'the Mind'.

 

Here is Hegel, laying the 'blame' where it ultimately belonged:

 

"Plato, who must be numbered among the Socratics, was the most renowned of the friends and disciples of Socrates, and he it was who grasped in all its truth Socrates' great principle that ultimate reality lies in consciousness, since, according to him, the absolute is in thought, and all reality is Thought. He does not understand by this a one-sided thought, nor what is understood by the false idealism which makes thought once more step aside and contemplate itself as conscious thought, and as in opposition to reality; it is the thought which embraces in an absolute unity reality as well as thinking, the Notion and its reality in the movement of science, as the Idea of a scientific whole. While Socrates had comprehended the thought which is existent in and for itself, only as an object for self-conscious will, Plato forsook this narrow point of view, and brought the merely abstract right of self-conscious thought, which Socrates had raised to a principle, into the sphere of science. By so doing he rendered it possible to interpret and apply the principle.... Plato is one of those world-famed individuals, his philosophy one of those world-renowned creations, whose influence, as regards the culture and development of the mind, has from its commencement down to the present time been all-important. For what is peculiar in the philosophy of Plato is its application to the intellectual and supersensuous world, and its elevation of consciousness into the realm of spirit. Thus the spiritual element which belongs to thought obtains in this form an importance for consciousness, and is brought into consciousness; just as, on the other hand, consciousness obtains a foothold on the soil of the other. The Christian religion has certainly adopted the lofty principle that man's inner and spiritual nature is his true nature, and takes it as its universal principle, though interpreting it in its own way as man's inclination for holiness; but Plato and his philosophy had the greatest share in obtaining for Christianity its rational organization, and in bringing it into the kingdom of the supernatural, for it was Plato who made the first advance in this direction." [Hegel (1995), pp.1-2. Bold emphases added; paragraphs merged.]

 

No, excuses comrades; this is where your core ideas originated -- in the fevered imagination of that card-carrying, ruling-class mystic, Plato.

 

Here is Hegel again, with one of the few other conclusions he managed to get right:

 

"Every philosophy is essentially an idealism or at least has idealism for its principle, and the question then is only how far this principle is carried out." [Hegel (1999), pp.154-55; §316. Bold emphasis added.]

 

But, as Hegel knew full well, these readily collapse into one or other of the Idealisms he speaks about -- Subjective or Objective -- indeed, as we have just seen.10

 

Even More Headaches For Dialecticians

 

As we are about to see, 'problems' like these turn DM into a persistent cause of Dialectical Migraine.

 

Traditional 'solutions' to such spurious 'philosophical problems' -- spurious, because, in the 'West', they were originally based on a class-motivated misconstrual of a small and unrepresentative structural quirk of Indo-European grammar (as we saw in Part One and Essay Two). Unfortunately, the 'solutions' offered by post-Renaissance Philosophers only succeeded in creating two further difficulties for Traditional Thought to grapple with.11

 

Oddly enough, both of these 'problems' re-surfaced in a modified form in 'the DM-theory of abstraction', as we are about to discover.

 

Induction And The Social Nature Of Knowledge

 

The first of the aforementioned 'difficulties' subsequently came to be known as the "Problem of Induction", which was itself based on the (presumed) theoretical possibility that future objects, processes and events might fail to behave the way they have always done (or seemed to have done) in the past.12

 

[In what follows I have deliberately ignored the difference between Inductive Logic and 'everyday inductive reasoning', just as I have passed over in silence whether or not human beings in general actually rely on inductive reasoning of any sort. I have also ignored several specialised or highly technical areas (outwith the sciences) where this form of reasoning is relied on as a matter of course -- for example, in opinion poll surveys, market research, census taking, betting, non-specialised weather forecasting, popular questionnaires, entertainment, etc., etc. Nor am I concerned here with Mathematical Induction. My aim is simply to look at how and why some philosophers have questioned 'inductive-style reasoning' (howsoever that is conceived), and in what way it impacts on issues that are the main focus of Essay Three (in all its Parts).]

 

As noted above, the 'Problem of Induction' was based on the supposed fact that generalisations about the course of nature can't provide a deductively sound basis for any belief that objects, processes and events will always behave 'the same way' in the future as they have in the past. Or, more generally, that the course of nature will remain constant, or even predictable, from day-to-day (howsoever that itself might be understood). So, for example, just because water has always frozen at a certain temperature that doesn't mean it will freeze at that temperature in future (always assuming the water concerned has the same level of purity and is cooled at 'normal' atmospheric pressure, etc., etc.). Or, to use David Hume's example, just because bread has always nourished us in the past that doesn't mean it always will. In that case, he claimed there is no contradiction in supposing it won't:

 

"All the objects of human reason or enquiry may naturally be divided into two kinds, to wit, relations of ideas, and matters of fact. Of the first kind are the sciences of geometry, algebra, and arithmetic, and in short, every affirmation which is either intuitively or demonstratively certain. That the square of the hypotenuse is equal to the square of the two sides, is a proposition which expresses a relation between these figures. That three times five is equal to the half of thirty, expresses a relation between these numbers. Propositions of this kind are discoverable by the mere operation of thought, without dependence on what is anywhere existent in the universe. Though there never were a circle or triangle in nature, the truths demonstrated by Euclid would for ever retain their certainty and evidence. Matters of fact, which are the second objects of human reason, are not ascertained in the same manner; nor is our evidence of their truth, however great, of a like nature with the foregoing. The contrary of every matter of fact is still possible, because it can never imply a contradiction, and is conceived by the mind with the same facility and distinctness, as if ever so conformable to reality. That the sun will not rise tomorrow is no less intelligible a proposition, and implies no more contradiction, than the affirmation, that it will rise." [Hume, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, Part I. Link and bold emphases added; paragraphs merged.]

 

The overall idea here was brought out rather well by the following remarks -- which neatly link this topic with generality and the (traditional) reference to 'universals':

 

"But there is a price to be paid for this new methodology. About a hundred years after Bacon, Hume (1711-1776) pointed out the problem.

'The bread, which I formerly eat, nourished me; that is, a body of such sensible qualities was, at that time, endued with such secret powers: But does it follow, that other bread must also nourish me at another time, and that like sensible qualities must always be attended with like secret powers? The consequence seems nowise necessary.' [This passage is taken from Part II of Hume's An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, which can be accessed here -- RL.]

"If we want to be very careful and not lump things into the same category, if types are not real, if the only real things are particular individuals, then there are no general truths about bread. We can describe the colour, shape, texture, taste and so on of this piece of bread, but if the general kind 'bread' isn't real, then whatever I learn about this piece of bread won't help me learn anything about the next piece of bread. That is the crucial usefulness of real types: if 'cat' is a real type, and not simply a nominal type, then whatever I learn about this particular cat will help me understand all cats. I can learn and know something about how to cure a problem with your cat if I have studied other cats, as long as they are identical in nature. If there is no reality to their unity as cats, then every new particular is just a new thing, and we can learn about it only by studying it; nothing else we study can possibly help us. So the existence of universals turns out to have a very profound impact on scientific methodology and epistemology." [Quoted from here. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site; spelling modified to agree with UK English. Links and bold emphases added.]

 

[I hasten to add that neither the above opinions nor what follows in the next sub-section represent my view. Once again, my aim here is simply to underline the serious (and ultimately insoluble) problems faced by traditional attempts to address the 'problem of induction', and, by implication, the 'solution' offered by any form of Essentialism.]

 

Of course, where Hume went wrong was to overlook the fact that if something that is taken to be bread failed to nourish those who ate it (all things being equal!), we would have good reason to question whether it was bread to begin with.

 

Hume's overall argument (in this instance) also borders on science fiction, the philosophical mis-use of which I have criticised in Essay Thirteen Part Three.

 

However, as we have already seen several times, traditional 'answers' to the 'problem of Universals' only succeeded in transforming it into another conundrum involving Abstract Particulars, which, if they exist, may or may not themselves behave the same way tomorrow as they do today! In that case, while these Abstract Particulars might be thoroughly Ideal -- i.e., they appear to be 'Mental' or 'Heavenly' entities of some sort -- there is no guarantee that even if they faithfully tow the line on Wednesday, they will continue doing so one minute past midnight, Thursday morning.

 

The significance of that remark should become clear as this Essay unfolds.

 

Particular Problems With Abstractions

 

It could be objected that we are actually dealing here with changeless abstractions (although it isn't too clear that a DM-fan can consistently endorse that response). Even if that were so, the words used to express any such ideas aren't abstract (i.e., words are typically (and obviously!) physical objects, or form part of very real material processes, such as speech), and, given this theory, there is no guarantee that any such words will mean the same next week what they mean today. Or even that any memories we have of such words and their meanings -- or even the meaning of the 'abstractions' themselves -- will remain fixed, either.

 

[If everything does change, including these 'abstractions', do they do so dialectically or non-dialectically? If the former, does Abstractor A's 'abstractions' change at exactly the same rate as Abstractor B's? If they do, then we have here something that is identical, namely the rate at which these 'abstractions' are changing, contrary to the DM-claim that nothing is identical. On the other hand, if they change at different rates, then these two characters must fail to communicate since they will mean something different by their 'abstractions'. Furthermore, if this change is dialectical, what are the 'internal contradictions' operating here? According to the DM-classics, such change occurs when 'dialectical opposites' struggle among themselves and then change into each other. What then are these 'opposites'? And if abstraction, G1 (from earlier), has any such 'opposite', it must be not-G1 (but where that has come from might be difficult to explain). So, according the aforementioned classics, G1 and not-G1 must 'struggle' with each other (but, how an 'abstraction' can struggle with anything, let alone another 'abstraction', might be even harder to explain -- I have said much more about questions like this in Essay Eight Part Two, here), and then change into their opposites. In that case, G1 must change into not-G1 and not-G1 must change into G1! if so, what exactly is the resulting difference here? One moment we have G1 and not-G1, the next we still have G1 and not-G1! It looks like we have here change with no change, a fitting 'dialectical conundrum' for those who like this way of confusing themselves, and others, to solve. Alternatively, if this change isn't 'dialectical', then DM isn't a comprehensive theory and Engels was wrong when he said this about it: "Dialectics, however, is nothing more than the science of the general laws of motion and development of nature, human society and thought." (Engels (1976), p.180. Bold added.) 'Abstractions' are part of 'thought', one presumes. Of course, if 'abstractions' don't change, then the DM-criticism of the LOI is itself misconceived. Either way, DM takes yet another body blow. (On this, see also my comments on the Heraclitean Flux, below.]

 

[LOI = Law Of Identity.]

 

It is worth reminding ourselves that the whole point of inventing 'Universals' (and 'abstractions') in the first place was to secure reliable knowledge by imposing some sort of control and order -- i.e., identity, regimentation, definition and unification -- on particulars (as the above passage and those quoted below remind us). Empirical, piece-meal and changeable 'knowledge' was regarded as inferior and unreliable, which is why appeal was made to 'rational principles' to save the day. But, the result was a creation of yet more particulars -- an novel 'abstract' variety -- that had been stripped of their generality. But, if the general is now particular itself (i.e., if each of these 'Universals'/'abstractions' has had generality surgically removed -- developments that were analysed in detail in Part One), what could now do all this identifying, controlling, regimenting, collecting and defining? The general was supposed to be the exclusive purview of the 'rational intellect', along with its 'abstractions'; sense experience only interfaced with the particular (so we have been told). Who has ever seen a 'general cat'? What would 'one' even look like? Who has ever eaten 'general fruit'? What would 'one' of those look like? How would 'one' even taste? Who has ever smelt a general rose or felt a general pain? That is why the formation of 'the general idea of a cat', or 'of fruit', required the exercise of the 'mental skill of abstraction', or so we have been told. No one has ever even claimed to have 'abstracted' anything using just their eyes, their ears, their nose, their finger tips or their taste buds. In this area of 'knowledge' the senses in the end drop out as irrelevant -- or, at best, they are merely conveyers of data, lowly 'messengers' -- since the body was held in Platonic and Neoplatonic contempt in the Rationalist/Christian tradition. Hence, as history has shown, this branch of Philosophy seemed only too happy to kill the messenger.

 

[But, what could possibly count as the general smell of a rose? Or even the smell of a general rose? What could conceivably count as the general experience of pain? Or even the experience of general pain? What actually is a 'general pain', a 'general experience' or even a 'general rose'? Has anyone ever felt a general itch? Faced with such questions, abstractionism appears to be falling apart before our eyes (no pun intended) -- or, rather, before our general eyes... Nevertheless, such awkward questions will have to be passed over in silence for now. I will return to them again later on in this Essay.]

 

As we have seen, DM-theorists define the (allegedly) 'abstract' nature of facts, or even 'matter itself', along just such lines:

 

"[A]ll science generalizes and abstracts from 'empirically verifiable facts.' Indeed, the very concept of 'fact' is itself an abstraction, because no one has ever eaten, tasted, smelt, seen or heard a 'fact,' which is a mental generalization that distinguishes actually existing phenomena from imaginary conceptions. Similarly, all science 'deductively anticipates' developments -- what else is an hypothesis tested by experimentation? The dialectic is, among other things, a way of investigating and understanding the relationship between abstractions and reality. And the 'danger of arbitrary construction' is far greater using an empirical method which thinks that it is dealing with facts when it is actually dealing with abstractions than it is with a method that properly distinguishes between the two and then seeks to explain the relationship between them." [Rees (1998), p.131. Bold emphasis added.]

 

In that case, whatever the material body experiences (i.e., 'sensation' and 'appearances') was suspect from the beginning and required ratification by an appeal to 'abstractions'. If that weren't the case, why appeal to abstraction to begin with? Here is Lenin again:

 

"Logical concepts are subjective so long as they remain 'abstract,' in their abstract form, but at the same time they express the Thing-in-themselves. Nature is both concrete and abstract, both phenomenon and essence, both moment and relation." [Lenin (1961), p.208. Bold emphases alone added.]

 

"Thought proceeding from the concrete to the abstract -- provided it is correct (NB)… -- does not get away from the truth but comes closer to it. The abstraction of matter, the law of nature, the abstraction of value, etc., in short all scientific (correct, serious, not absurd) abstractions reflect nature more deeply, truly and completely." [Ibid., p.171. Bold emphases alone added.]

 

Why say this if the what the body experiences is fully trustworthy? This is just Platonic/Christian contempt for the body given a 'Marxist' veneer.

 

Analogous criticisms were central to the objections Marx and Engels's levelled against Hegel's method early on in their intellectual development (whatever else they later came to believe). There is no such contempt expressed in the following; quite the reverse in fact:

 

"The mystery of critical presentation…is the mystery of speculative, of Hegelian construction.If from real apples, pears, strawberries and almonds I form the general idea 'Fruit', if I go further and imagine that my abstract idea 'Fruit', derived from real fruit, is an entity existing outside me, is indeed the true essence of the pear, the apple, etc., then -- in the language of speculative philosophy -- I am declaring that 'Fruit' is the 'Substance' of the pear, the apple, the almond, etc. I am saying, therefore, that to be an apple is not essential to the apple; that what is essential to these things is not their real existence, perceptible to the senses, but the essence that I have abstracted from them and then foisted on them, the essence of my idea -- 'Fruit'…. Particular real fruits are no more than semblances whose true essence is 'the substance' -- 'Fruit'…. Having reduced the different real fruits to the one 'fruit' of abstraction -- 'the Fruit', speculation must, in order to attain some semblance of real content, try somehow to find its way back from 'the Fruit', from the Substance to the diverse, ordinary real fruits, the pear, the apple, the almond etc. It is as hard to produce real fruits from the abstract idea 'the Fruit' as it is easy to produce this abstract idea from real fruits. Indeed, it is impossible to arrive at the opposite of an abstraction without relinquishing the abstraction….

 

"The main interest for the speculative philosopher is therefore to produce the existence of the real ordinary fruits and to say in some mysterious way that there are apples, pears, almonds and raisins. But the apples, pears, almonds and raisins that we rediscover in the speculative world are nothing but semblances of apples, semblances of pears, semblances of almonds and semblances of raisins, for they are moments in the life of 'the Fruit', this abstract creation of the mind, and therefore themselves abstract creations of the mind…. When you return from the abstraction, the supernatural creation of the mind, 'the Fruit', to real natural fruits, you give on the contrary the natural fruits a supernatural significance and transform them into sheer abstractions. Your main interest is then to point out the unity of 'the Fruit' in all the manifestations of its life…that is, to show the mystical interconnection between these fruits, how in each of them 'the Fruit' realizes itself by degrees and necessarily progresses, for instance, from its existence as a raisin to its existence as an almond. Hence the value of the ordinary fruits no longer consists in their natural qualities, but in their speculative quality, which gives each of them a definite place in the life-process of 'the Absolute Fruit'.

 

"The ordinary man does not think he is saying anything extraordinary when he states that there are apples and pears. But when the philosopher expresses their existence in the speculative way he says something extraordinary. He performs a miracle by producing the real natural objects, the apple, the pear, etc., out of the unreal creation of the mind 'the Fruit'…. It goes without saying that the speculative philosopher accomplishes this continuous creation only by presenting universally known qualities of the apple, the pear, etc., which exist in reality, as determining features invented by him, by giving the names of the real things to what abstract reason alone can create, to abstract formulas of reason, finally, by declaring his own activity, by which he passes from the idea of an apple to the idea of a pear, to be the self-activity of the Absolute Subject, 'the Fruit.' In the speculative way of speaking, this operation is called comprehending Substance as Subject, as an inner process, as an Absolute Person, and this comprehension constitutes the essential character of Hegel's method." [Marx and Engels (1975a), pp.72-75. Bold emphases alone added. Several paragraphs merged.]

 

So, abstractionism creates 'semblances' of fruit, not fruit, and since no one has ever eaten the 'semblance of an apple' (to state the obvious, they just eat apples!), this theory makes a mockery of our everyday (materialist) experience of the world. Hence, by-passing the body and everyday experience, abstraction ends up destroying the particular since it generates, or turns them into, mere 'semblances'. The material world, which seems to be composed only of particulars, has thereby been demoted -- after all, has anyone ever sat on a general chair, bought a general can of beer, walked a general dog or even read a general book written by Marx or Lenin? Given this (Idealist) approach to 'knowledge', the physical universe isn't 'fully real', it is a shadow world populated by what look like ghosts. What is really real, really substantial, is the hidden/'mental' world of 'abstractions', which, like the 'gods', no one has ever experienced, nor could they. Is it any wonder then that DM-theorists distrust 'appearances' and, like Hegel, regard 'the abstract' as the only source, or the only guarantor, of (genuine) knowledge --, even if they then (inconsistently!) go on to declare that "truth is always concrete":

 

"Dialectical logic demands that we should go further. Firstly, if we are to have a true knowledge of an object we must look at and examine all its facets, its connections and 'mediacies'. That is something we cannot ever hope to achieve completely, but the rule of comprehensiveness is a safeguard against mistakes and rigidity. Secondly, dialectical logic requires that an object should be taken in development, in change, in 'self-movement' (as Hegel sometimes puts it). This is not immediately obvious in respect of such an object as a tumbler, but it, too, is in flux, and this holds especially true for its purpose, use and connection with the surrounding world. Thirdly, a full 'definition' of an object must include the whole of human experience, both as a criterion of truth and a practical indicator of its connection with human wants. Fourthly, dialectical logic holds that 'truth is always concrete, never abstract', as the late Plekhanov liked to say after Hegel...." [Lenin (1921), pp.90-93. Bold emphases alone added; quotation marks altered to conform with conventions adopted at this site.]

 

Here is where Lenin got that idea -- not from scientists, or his own experience of the world, but from a Christian Mystic:

 

"The same evolution of thought which is exhibited in the history of philosophy is presented in the System of Philosophy itself. Here, instead of surveying the process, as we do in history, from the outside, we see the movement of thought clearly defined in its native medium. The thought, which is genuine and self-supporting, must be intrinsically concrete; it must be an Idea; and when it is viewed in the whole of its universality, it is the Idea, or the Absolute. The science of this Idea must form a system. For the truth is concrete; that is, while it gives a bond and principle of unity, it also possesses an internal source of development. Truth, then, is only possible as a universe or totality of thought; and the freedom of the whole, as well as the necessity of the several sub-divisions, which it implies, are only possible when these are discriminated and defined." [Hegel (1975), p.19, §14. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"In such a sentence as 'God is eternal', we begin with the conception of God, not knowing as yet what he is: to tell us that, is the business of the predicate. In the principles of logic, accordingly, where the terms formulating the subject-matter are those of thought only, it is not merely superfluous to make these categories predicates to propositions in which God, or, still vaguer, the Absolute, is the subject, but it would also have the disadvantage of suggesting another canon than the nature of thought. Besides, the propositional form (and for proposition, it would be more correct to substitute judgment) is not suited to express the concrete -- and the true is always concrete -- or the speculative. Every judgment is by its form one-sided and, to that extent, false." [Ibid., §31, p.51. Bold emphasis added.]

 

Which conclusions Hegel, of course, connected with his rather odd concept of 'God':

 

"The division of Logic now given, as well as the whole of the previous discussion on the nature of thought, is anticipatory; and the justification, or proof of it, can only result from the detailed treatment of thought itself. For in philosophy, to prove means to show how the subject by and from itself makes itself what it is. The relation in which these three leading grades of thought, or of the logical Idea, stand to each other must be conceived as follows. Truth comes only with the notion; or, more precisely, the notion is the truth of being and essence, both of which, when separately maintained in their isolation, cannot but be untrue, the former because it is exclusively immediate, the latter because it is exclusively mediate. Why then, it may be asked, begin with false and not at once with the true. To which we answer that truth, to deserve the name, must authenticate its own truth: which authentication, here within the sphere of logic, is given, when the notion demonstrates itself to be what is mediated by and with itself, and thus at the same time to be truly immediate. This relation between the three stages of the logical Idea appears in a real and concrete shape thus: God, who is the truth, is known by us in His truth, that is, as absolute spirit, only in so far as we at the same time recognize that the world which He created, nature and the finite spirit, are, in their difference from God, untrue." [Ibid., §83, p.122. Bold emphases added.]

 

How the apparent inconsistency between the claims that "truth is concrete" and knowledge depends on abstraction might be resolved was dealt with in Part One (briefly summarised, below). How the other problem that has emerged (i.e., the fact that the 'process of abstraction' turns particulars into 'semblances') is also to be resolved will have to be passed over in silence since DM-theorists have yet to address it. [Once more, I will return to this topic later in this Essay, when I examine the (connected) distinction that has traditionally been drawn between 'appearance' and 'reality'/'essence', which DM-fans have also unwisely bought into.]

 

In the meantime, here is Hegel making the same point (about fruit), but drawing all the wrong conclusions from it (which errors were exposed by Marx and Engels, earlier):

 

"The spectacle of so many and so various systems of philosophy suggests the necessity of defining more exactly the relation of Universal to Particular. When the universal is made a mere form and co-ordinated with the particular, as if it were on the same level, it sinks into a particular itself. Even common sense in everyday matters is above the absurdity of setting a universal beside the particulars. Would any one, who wished for fruit, reject cherries, pears, and grapes, on the ground that they were cherries, pears, or grapes, and not fruit? But when philosophy is in question, the excuse of many is that philosophies are so different, and none of them is the philosophy -- that each is only a philosophy. Such a plea is assumed to justify any amount of contempt for philosophy. And yet cherries too are fruit. Often, too, a system, of which the principle is the universal, is put on a level with another of which the principle is a particular, and with theories which deny the existence of philosophy altogether. Such systems are said to be only different views of philosophy. With equal justice, light and darkness might be styled different kinds of light." [Hegel (1975), p.19 §13. Except for the word "besides", bold emphasis alone added.]

 

"Essence becomes matter in that its reflection is determined as relating itself to essence as to the formless indeterminate. Matter is therefore the differenceless identity which is essence, with the determination of being the other of form. It is consequently the real basis or substrate of form, because it constitutes the reflection-into-self of the form-determinations, or the self-subsistent element to which the latter are related as to their positive subsistence. If abstraction is made from every determination, from all form of anything, what is left over is indeterminate matter. Matter is a sheer abstraction. (Matter cannot be seen, felt, and so on -- what is seen, felt, is a determinate matter, that is, a unity of matter and form). This abstraction from which matter proceeds is, however, not merely an external removal and sublating of form, rather does form, as we have seen, spontaneously reduce itself to this simple identity." [Hegel (1999), pp.450-51, §§ 978-979. Bold emphasis alone added. Typos in the on-line version corrected. Paragraphs merged.]

 

And yet, the above is exactly what Engels himself subsequently concluded (and, rather fittingly, he did so by contradicting his earlier thoughts):

 

"It is the old story. First of all one makes sensuous things into abstractions and then one wants to know them through the senses, to see time and smell space. The empiricist becomes so steeped in the habit of empirical experience, that he believes that he is still in the field of sensuous experience when he is operating with abstractions.... The two forms of existence of matter are naturally nothing without matter, empty concepts, abstractions which exist only in our minds. But, of course, we are supposed not to know what matter and motion are! Of course not, for matter as such and motion as such have not yet been seen or otherwise experienced by anyone, only the various existing material things and forms of motions. Matter is nothing but the totality of material things from which this concept is abstracted and motion as such nothing but the totality of all sensuously perceptible forms of motion; words like matter and motion are nothing but abbreviations in which we comprehend many different sensuous perceptible things according to their common properties. Hence matter and motion can be known in no other way than by investigation of the separate material things and forms of motion, and by knowing these, we also pro tanto know matter and motion as such.... This is just like the difficulty mentioned by Hegel; we can eat cherries and plums, but not fruit, because no one has so far eaten fruit as such." [Engels (1954), pp.235-36. Bold emphases alone added.]

 

Here, too, is Lenin, emulating both Hegel and Engels:

 

"If abstraction is made from every determination and Form of a Something, indeterminate Matter remains. Matter is a pure abstract. (-- Matter cannot be seen or felt, etc. -- what is seen or felt is a determinate Matter, that is, a unity of Matter and Form)." [Lenin (1961), pp.144-45. Bold emphasis alone added. The original passage from Hegel has been reposted in Note 10a.]10a

 

Subsequent DM-theorists (including John Rees, quoted above) argued along similar lines. Here are two more examples, but this time drawn from diametrically opposite wings of Dialectical Marxism (both of them using the same example -- fruit/cherries!):

 

"Engels…attacks those who fail to see [that scientific] concepts are abstractions from real experience, and [who] ask about what is 'matter as such' or 'motion as such'. 'Matter as such and motion as such have not yet been seen or experienced by anyone, but only the various, actually existing material things and forms of motion. Matter is nothing but the totality of material things from which this concept is abstracted, and motion as such nothing but the totality of sensuously perceptible forms of motion; words like matter and motion are nothing but abbreviations in which we comprehend many differently sensuously perceptible things according to their common properties. Hence matter and motion can be known in no other way than by investigation of the separate material things and forms of motion'. Engels gives us an analogy, 'We can eat cherries and plums, but not fruit, because no one has so far eaten fruit as such.'" [McGarr (1994), pp.152-53; quoting Engels (1954), pp.235-36 (reproduced above). Paragraphs merged; bold emphases added.]

 

"One quite often hears people say 'all things consist of matter'. They do not consist of matter. They are the specific, concrete forms of its manifestation. Matter as such is an abstraction. Looking for a uniform matter as the principle of everything is like wanting to eat not cherries but fruit in general. But fruit is also an abstraction. Matter cannot be contrasted to separate things as something immutable to something mutable. Matter in general cannot be seen, touched or tasted. What people see, touch or taste is only a certain form of matter. Matter is not something that exists side by side with other things, inside them or at their basis. All existing formations are matter in its various forms, kinds, properties and relations. There is no such thing as 'unspecific' matter. Matter is not simply the real possibility of all material forms, it is their actual existence. The only property that is relatively separate from matter is consciousness as an ideal and not material phenomenon." [Spirkin (1983), p.67. Bold emphases added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

Which is why Lenin also said the following (partly quoted above):

 

"Thought proceeding from the concrete to the abstract -- provided it is correct (NB)… -- does not get away from the truth but comes closer to it. The abstraction of matter, the law of nature, the abstraction of value, etc., in short all scientific (correct, serious, not absurd) abstractions reflect nature more deeply, truly and completely." [Lenin (1961), p.171. Bold emphasis alone added.]

 

"Knowledge is the reflection of nature by man. But this is not simple, not an immediate, not a complete reflection, but the process of a series of abstractions, the formation and development of concepts, laws, etc., and these concepts, laws, etc., (thought, science = 'the logical Idea') embrace conditionally, approximately, the universal, law-governed character of eternally moving and developing nature." [Ibid., p.182. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Bold emphasis alone added.]

 

This helps resolve an (apparent) inconsistency, noted earlier. While, for Lenin, it is still true that "all truth is concrete", it is the abstract that (supposedly) enables a theorist to grasp the particular and hence the concrete, even if that will only ever fully be realised at the end of an 'infinite process'. [We will return to that aspect of the theory later, too. As noted above, how this implies particulars cease being mere 'semblances' and become 'concrete' is still unclear; more about that below, too.]

 

So, just like Plato and every other Rationalist, Lenin thought that genuine knowledge arose out of, or was enabled by means of, the general, not the particular. In which case, particulars not only have to be collected-together, or even amalgamated, under a general concept/term, each one in the end is only a particular because of this. Hence, each individual given in experience is an individual of a certain type (i.e., it instantiates a specific 'Universal', 'concept' or 'abstraction'), and that is what (supposedly) guarantees its future (law-like) behaviour. So, particulars aren't free 'to do whatever they like'; they are born in chains and there they remain until the day they "perish".

 

[We will also return to that image, later.]

 

Hegel scholar, Katharina Dulckeit, neatly summarised Hegel's views (also quoted earlier) in the following terms:

 

"[It] must be remembered that [Hegel's] analysis of the forms of judgment in the Logic is motivated by his interest in essential judgement. There are two conditions for such judgements. To begin with, a judgement is an essential judgement only if P tells us precisely and exclusively what s is; no less and no more. But merely predicating universals of particulars is insufficient for this, unless the term in the predicate position at once expresses the essential nature of the subject. This, in turn, argues Hegel, is possible only if the 'is' expresses some identity between s and P. For if essential determination were possible exclusively via predication, the subject and the predicate would remain separate and the relation between them expressed by the copula would remain external. As a consequence, s would refer to one thing, namely an individual, while P would designate something distinct from s, namely a universal. But the truth of sense-certainty in the Phenomenology has already been shown that qua individual, an individual is grasped only through the mediation of universals. It follows that divorced from these, it would then have to be an individual without a universal nature, i.e., a bare individual.... Thus, if s and P are utterly distinct they must be mutually exclusive, which means that s will necessarily be bare, and P necessarily abstract.... Clearly then, where judgements of essence are concerned, the 'is' of predication will not do because it entails the distinction between s and P which would commit us to a metaphysical thesis already overcome in the Phenomenology." [Dulckeit (1989), pp.115-16. Bold emphases alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site; links added. I have subjected passages like this to sustained criticism in Appendix D of Part One.]

 

Which is a point Lenin was trying to make in this passage:

 

"To begin with what is the simplest, most ordinary, common, etc., [sic] with any proposition...: [like] John is a man…. Here we already have dialectics (as Hegel's genius recognized): the individual is the universal…. Consequently, the opposites (the individual is opposed to the universal) are identical: the individual exists only in the connection that leads to the universal. The universal exists only in the individual and through the individual. Every individual is (in one way or another) a universal. Every universal is (a fragment, or an aspect, or the essence of) an individual. Every universal only approximately embraces all the individual objects. Every individual enters incompletely into the universal, etc., etc. Every individual is connected by thousands of transitions with other kinds of individuals (things, phenomena, processes), etc. Here already we have the elements, the germs of the concept of necessity, of objective connection in nature, etc. Here already we have the contingent and the necessary, the phenomenon and the essence; for when we say John is a man…we disregard a number of attributes as contingent; we separate the essence from the appearance, and counterpose the one to the other…. Thus in any proposition we can (and must) disclose as a 'nucleus' ('cell') the germs of all the elements of dialectics, and thereby show that dialectics is a property of all human knowledge in general." [Lenin (1961), pp.359-60. Bold emphases alone added; paragraphs merged.]

 

It is also why Engels added the following remark:

 

"'Fundamentally, we can know only the infinite.' In fact all real exhaustive knowledge consists solely in raising the individual thing in thought from individuality into particularity and from this into universality, in seeking and establishing the infinite in the finite, the eternal in the transitory…. All true knowledge of nature is knowledge of the eternal, the infinite, and essentially absolute…. The cognition of the infinite…can only take place in an infinite asymptotic progress." [Engels (1954), pp.234-35. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Bold emphasis alone added; paragraphs merged.]

 

And here is a passage from a dusty old Stalinist text from the 1930s that expands on these (rather odd) ideas:

 

"The central fallacy involved in all metaphysical reasoning is -- expressed in terms of logic -- the complete confusion of the relations between the categories of Particular and General: of Unique and 'Universal.' Thus, for instance, if I affirm: 'John is a Man' I affirm that 'John' is a particular specimen of the general (or 'universal') category 'Man'. I understand what 'John' is by subsuming him under (or 'identifying him with') the wider category 'Man'. Metaphysical reasoning proceeds on the tacit or explicit assumption that the general category 'Man' and the particular category 'John' exist independently of each other: that over and above all the Particular 'Johns' in creation (and 'Toms,' and 'Dicks' and 'Harrys' and so on) over and above all particular men, there exists somewhere -- and would exist if all particular men ceased to be, or had never been -- the general category 'Man.'...

 

"The dialectical method traverses this rigid metaphysic completely. The category 'Man' includes, certainly, all possible 'men.' But 'Man' and 'men', though distinct, separate, and separable logical categories, are only so as logical discriminations, as ways of looking at one and the same set of facts. 'Man' -- is -- all men, conceived from the standpoint of their generality -- that in which all men are alike. 'Men' is a conception of the same fact -- 'all men' -- but in respect of their multiplicity, the fact that no two of them are exactly alike. For dialectics, the particular and the general, the unique and the universal -- for all their logical opposition -- exist, in fact, in and by means of each other. The 'Johniness' of John does not exist, cannot possibly be conceived as existing, apart from his 'manniness'. We know 'Man' only as the common characteristic of all particular men; and each particular man is identifiable, as a particular, by means of his variation from all other men -- from that generality 'Man' by means of which we classify 'all men' in one group.

 

"It is the recognition of this 'identity of all (logical pairs of) opposites,' and in the further recognition that all categories form, logically, a series from the Absolutely Universal to the Absolutely Unique -- (in each of which opposites its other is implicit) -- that the virtue of Hegel's logic consists…. Let us now translate this into concrete terms. John is -- a man. Man is a category in which all men (John, and all the not-Johns) are conjoined. I begin to distinguish John from the not-Johns by observing those things in which he is not -- what the other men are. At the same time the fact that I have to begin upon the process of distinguishing implies…that, apart from his special distinguishing characteristics, John is identical with all the not-Johns who comprise the rest of the human race. Thus logically expressed, John is understood when he is most fully conceived as the 'identity' of John-in-special and not-John (i.e. all man (sic)) in general.

 

"…When I affirm that 'John is a man' I postulate the oppositional contrast between John and not-John and their coexistence (the negation of their mutual negation) all at once. Certainly as the logical process is worked in my mind I distinguish first one pole, then the other of the separation and then their conjunction. But all three relations -- or better still, the whole three-fold relation -- exists from the beginning and its existence is presupposed in the logical act…." [Jackson (1936), pp.103-06. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Bold emphases alone added. Several paragraphs merged. Again, I have subjected this passage to sustained criticism in Part One. Comrade Jackson failed to notice that in speaking this way he had only succeeded in shooting generality in the head -- indeed, as we have seen.]

 

Here, too, is Bertell Ollman (also emulating Plato), arguing that sense experience (on its own) is far too random, the data it has to deal with far too varied, complex and reliant on the particular to be comprehensible (as such), which is why he claims we all have to engage in 'abstraction'; we all have to 'mentally process' whatever the senses supposedly send the 'mind'. That is, we all allegedly focus on certain aspects of reality and 'mentally collect together' the particulars we experience there (or, rather, we do so with their 'reflections'/'images'), but they have already somehow been grouped together under specific concepts (since we never experience what is called 'a bare particular'. Because we don't encounter generality in experience, we have to apply/supply generality, or general concepts, in order to be able to experience the world and begin to comprehend it (even if only partially/'relatively'), which, as we have seen, is a thoroughly Kantian idea:

 

"In one sense, the role Marx gives to abstraction is simple recognition of the fact that all thinking about reality begins by breaking it down into manageable parts. Reality may be in one piece when lived, but to be thought about and communicated it must be parceled (sic) out. Our minds can no more swallow the world whole at one sitting than can our stomachs. Everyone then, and not just Marx and Marxists, begins the task of trying to make sense of his or her surroundings by distinguishing certain features and focusing on and organizing them in ways deemed appropriate. 'Abstract' comes from the Latin, 'abstrahere', which means 'to pull from.' In effect, a piece has been pulled from or taken out of the whole and is temporarily perceived as standing apart. We 'see' only some of what lies in front of us, 'hear' only part of the noises in our vicinity, 'feel' only a small part of what our body is in contact with, and so on through the rest of our senses. In each case, a focus is established and a kind of boundary set within our perceptions distinguishing what is relevant from what is not. It should be clear that 'What did you see?' (What caught your eye?) is a different question from 'What did you actually see?' (What came into your line of vision?). Likewise, in thinking about any subject, we focus on only some of its qualities and relations. Much that could be included -- that may in fact be included in another person's view or thought, and may on another occasion be included in our own -- is left out. The mental activity involved in establishing such boundaries, whether conscious or unconscious -- though it is usually an amalgam of both -- is the process of abstraction." [Ollman (2003), p.60. Bold emphases alone added; paragraphs merged.]

 

[The only problem here is that for Hegel (as Dulckeit pointed out), whatever is given in experience is already a 'particular of a certain type'. (That was integral to Hegel's criticism of Kant.) Particulars can't be experienced in any other way. How any of this is actually supposed to work is, alas, still a mystery (i.e., it is if we insist on approaching this topic in the way Traditional Philosophers have always done -- ignoring the public use of ordinary language). Nevertheless, I will also have to draw a veil over this intractable 'problem' for the present.]

 

We have met the following passage several times already, but it neatly sums up an attitude promoted by the theorists who influenced the above DM-classicists:

 

"Already with Fichte the idea of the unity of the sciences, of system, was connected with that of finding a reliable starting-point in certainty on which knowledge could be based. Thinkers from Kant onwards were quite convinced that the kind of knowledge which came from experience was not reliable. Empirical knowledge could be subject to error, incomplete, or superseded by further observation or experiment. It would be foolish, therefore, to base the whole of knowledge on something which had been established only empirically. The kind of knowledge which Kant and his followers believed to be the most secure was a priori knowledge, the kind embodied in the laws of Nature. These had been formulated without every occurrence of the Natural phenomenon in question being observed, so they did not summarise empirical information, and yet they held good by necessity for every case; these laws were truly universal in their application." [White (1996a), p.29. Bold emphasis added.]

 

It is also worth noting at this point that the passages quoted above -- and this is especially true of the ideas Plato, Hegel and Engels concocted -- directly link DM-ideas on this topic to ancient, mystical theories of knowledge, which directly connects the latter with a given Knower's access to 'the mind of god' (which is the 'ultimate reality' for Plato and Hegel -- and, as it turns out, the only 'reality'). We see this attitude further underlined in the following:

 

"The view that the objects of immediate consciousness, which constitute the body of experience, are mere appearances (phenomena) was another important result of the Kantian philosophy. Common Sense, that mixture of sense and understanding, believes the objects of which it has knowledge to be severally independent and self-supporting; and when it becomes evident that they tend towards and limit one another, the interdependence of one upon another is reckoned something foreign to them and to their true nature. The very opposite is the truth. The things immediately known are mere appearances -- in other words, the ground of their being is not in themselves but in something else. But then comes the important step of defining what this something else is. According to Kant, the things that we know about are to us appearances only, and we can never know their essential nature, which belongs to another world we cannot approach. Plain minds have not unreasonably taken exception to this subjective idealism, with its reduction of the facts of consciousness to a purely personal world, created by ourselves alone. For the true statement of the case is rather as follows. The things of which we have direct consciousness are mere phenomena, not for us only, but in their own nature; and the true and proper case of these things, finite as they are, is to have their existence founded not in themselves but in the universal divine Idea. This view of things, it is true, is as idealist as Kant's; but in contradistinction to the subjective idealism of the Critical philosophy should be termed absolute idealism. Absolute idealism, however, though it is far in advance of vulgar realism, is by no means merely restricted to philosophy. It lies at the root of all religion; for religion too believes the actual world we see, the sum total of existence, to be created and governed by God." [Hegel (1975, §45, p.73. Links in the original. Bold emphases alone added.]

 

"The Essence must appear or shine forth. Its shining or reflection in it is the suspension and translation of it to immediacy, which, while as reflection-into-self it is matter or subsistence, is also form, reflection-on-something-else, a subsistence which sets itself aside. To show or shine is the characteristic by which essence is distinguished from Being -- by which it is essence; and it is this show which, when it is developed, shows itself, and is Appearance. Essence accordingly is not something beyond or behind appearance, but -- just because it is the essence which exists -- the existence is Appearance (Forth-shining).

 

"Existence stated explicitly in its contradiction is Appearance. But appearance (forth-showing) is not to be confused with a mere show (shining). Show is the proximate truth of Being or immediacy. The immediate, instead of being, as we suppose, something independent, resting on its own self, is a mere show, and as such it is packed or summed up under the simplicity of the immanent essence. The essence is, in the first place, the sum total of the showing itself, shining in itself (inwardly); but, far from abiding in this inwardness, it comes as a ground forward into existence; and this existence being grounded not in itself, but on something else, is just appearance. In our imagination we ordinarily combine with the term appearance or phenomenon the conception of an indefinite congeries of things existing, the being of which is purely relative, and which consequently do not rest on a foundation of their own, but are esteemed only as passing stages. But in this conception it is no less implied that essence does not linger behind or beyond appearance. Rather it is, we may say, the infinite kindness which lets its own show freely issue into immediacy, and graciously allows it the joy of existence. The appearance which is thus created does not stand on its own feet, and has its being not in itself but in something else. God who is the essence, when he lends existence to the passing stages of his own show in himself, may be described as the goodness that creates the world: but he is also the power above it, and the righteousness, which manifests the merely phenomenal character of the content of this existing world, whenever it tries to exist in independence." [Ibid., §131, pp.186-87. Links in the original; bold emphases added.]

 

"[W]e must presuppose intelligence enough to know, not only that God is actual, that He is the supreme actuality, that He alone is truly actual; but also, as regards the logical bearings of the question, that existence is in part mere appearance, and only in part actuality." Ibid., p.9, §6; bold emphasis added.]

 

"This objective thinking then, is the content of pure science. Consequently, far from it being formal, far from it standing in need of a matter to constitute an actual and true cognition, it is its content alone which has absolute truth, or, if one still wanted to employ the word matter, it is the veritable matter -- but a matter which is not external to the form, since this matter is rather pure thought and hence the absolute form itself. Accordingly, logic is to be understood as the system of pure reason, as the realm of pure thought. This realm is truth as it is without veil and in its own absolute nature. It can therefore be said that this content is the exposition of God as he is in his eternal essence before the creation of nature and a finite mind. Anaxagoras is praised as the man who first declared that Nous, thought, is the principle of the world, that the essence of the world is to be defined as thought. In so doing he laid the foundation for an intellectual view of the universe, the pure form of which must be logic. What we are dealing with in logic is not a thinking about something which exists independently as a base for our thinking and apart from it, nor forms which are supposed to provide mere signs or distinguishing marks of truth; on the contrary, the necessary forms and self-consciousness of thought are the content and the ultimate truth itself." [Hegel (1999), pp.50-51, §53-54. Bold emphases alone added. Links also added; paragraphs merged.]

 

"If mind and true opinion are two distinct classes, then I say that there certainly are these self-existent ideas unperceived by sense, and apprehended only by the mind; if, however, as some say, true opinion differs in no respect from mind, then everything that we perceive through the body is to be regarded as most real and certain. But we must affirm that to be distinct, for they have a distinct origin and are of a different nature; the one is implanted in us by instruction, the other by persuasion; the one is always accompanied by true reason, the other is without reason; the one cannot be overcome by persuasion, but the other can: and lastly, every man may be said to share in true opinion, but mind is the attribute of the gods and of very few men. Wherefore also we must acknowledge that there is one kind of being which is always the same, uncreated and indestructible, never receiving anything into itself from without, nor itself going out to any other, but invisible and imperceptible by any sense, and of which the contemplation is granted to intelligence only." [Plato (1997c), 51e-52a, pp.1254-55. I have used the on-line version here. Bold emphases added. The published edition translates the third set of highlighted words as follows: "It is indivisible -- it cannot be perceived by the senses at all -- and it is the role of the understanding to study it." Cornford renders it thus: "[It is] invisible and otherwise imperceptible; that, in fact, which thinking has for its object." (Cornford (1997), p.192.)]

 

This shows that Hegel and Plato (from whom DM-theorists ultimately derived their core ideas, especially concerning 'abstraction' and its intimate connection with the formation of knowledge) held these peculiar beliefs for theological reasons. This is the original inspiration for remarks like the following from Engels and Lenin (even though they both repudiated the theism involved):

 

"'Fundamentally, we can know only the infinite.' In fact all real exhaustive knowledge consists solely in raising the individual thing in thought from individuality into particularity and from this into universality, in seeking and establishing the infinite in the finite, the eternal in the transitory…. All true knowledge of nature is knowledge of the eternal, the infinite, and essentially absolute…. The cognition of the infinite…can only take place in an infinite asymptotic progress." [Engels (1954), pp.234-35. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Bold emphasis alone added; paragraphs merged.]

 

"To begin with what is the simplest, most ordinary, common, etc., [sic] with any proposition...: [like] John is a man…. Here we already have dialectics (as Hegel's genius recognized): the individual is the universal…. Consequently, the opposites (the individual is opposed to the universal) are identical: the individual exists only in the connection that leads to the universal. The universal exists only in the individual and through the individual. Every individual is (in one way or another) a universal. Every universal is (a fragment, or an aspect, or the essence of) an individual. Every universal only approximately embraces all the individual objects. Every individual enters incompletely into the universal, etc., etc. Every individual is connected by thousands of transitions with other kinds of individuals (things, phenomena, processes), etc. Here already we have the elements, the germs of the concept of necessity, of objective connection in nature, etc. Here already we have the contingent and the necessary, the phenomenon and the essence; for when we say John is a man…we disregard a number of attributes as contingent; we separate the essence from the appearance, and counterpose the one to the other…. Thus in any proposition we can (and must) disclose as a 'nucleus' ('cell') the germs of all the elements of dialectics, and thereby show that dialectics is a property of all human knowledge in general." [Lenin (1961), pp.359-60. Bold emphases alone added; paragraphs merged.]

 

The above remarks simply represent a non-theological way of making basically the same point as Plato and Hegel: everything around us -- every concrete object and process -- only exists and is concrete because of an invisible world of 'Universals'/'Concepts'/'abstractions' that underpin, constitute or define them. But, these 'Universals' (etc.) can only be ascertained via, or at the end of, an 'infinite epistemological journey', mediated by practice (which is eerily analogous to the infinite voyage every soul supposedly has to embark upon in their return to its source in 'god' -- the ultimate form of Subject-Object Identity). As such, for DM-theorists, these particulars can't ever actually be 'concrete' (why that is so will be explained below), but must forever remain mere 'semblances', at some level or to some extent.

 

For DM-supporters, this dalliance with Hegelian Mysticism (upside down or 'the right way up') means there are no real particulars -- all are mere 'semblances' (at least those given in experience). Even matter itself doesn't exist (having been declared an 'abstraction'); there are simply particular instances of 'it' -- but what this 'it' is we are never told! [Or, rather according to Lenin, matter is simply what we experience in sensation, and we have just seen that Dialectical Marxists don't trust experience -- unless there is an 'abstraction' on hand to legitimate it, or lend it substantiality.]

 

Despite this, the use of words like "mystery", "mysterious", "mysticism" and  "mystical" might cause some offence (especially among DM-fans); but these are terms that Marx and Engels themselves used to describe the results of the 'process of abstraction' and the transformation of particulars into 'semblances':

 

"The mystery of critical presentation…is the mystery of speculative, of Hegelian construction.… If from real apples, pears, strawberries and almonds I form the general idea 'Fruit', if I go further and imagine that my abstract idea 'Fruit', derived from real fruit, is an entity existing outside me, is indeed the true essence of the pear, the apple, etc., then -- in the language of speculative philosophy -- I am declaring that 'Fruit' is the 'Substance' of the pear, the apple, the almond, etc. I am saying, therefore, that to be an apple is not essential to the apple; that what is essential to these things is not their real existence, perceptible to the senses, but the essence that I have abstracted from them and then foisted on them, the essence of my idea -- 'Fruit'…. Particular real fruits are no more than semblances whose true essence is 'the substance' -- 'Fruit'…. Having reduced the different real fruits to the one 'fruit' of abstraction -- 'the Fruit', speculation must, in order to attain some semblance of real content, try somehow to find its way back from 'the Fruit', from the Substance to the diverse, ordinary real fruits, the pear, the apple, the almond etc. It is as hard to produce real fruits from the abstract idea 'the Fruit' as it is easy to produce this abstract idea from real fruits. Indeed, it is impossible to arrive at the opposite of an abstraction without relinquishing the abstraction….

 

"The main interest for the speculative philosopher is therefore to produce the existence of the real ordinary fruits and to say in some mysterious way that there are apples, pears, almonds and raisins. But the apples, pears, almonds and raisins that we rediscover in the speculative world are nothing but semblances of apples, semblances of pears, semblances of almonds and semblances of raisins, for they are moments in the life of 'the Fruit', this abstract creation of the mind, and therefore themselves abstract creations of the mind…. When you return from the abstraction, the supernatural creation of the mind, 'the Fruit', to real natural fruits, you give on the contrary the natural fruits a supernatural significance and transform them into sheer abstractions. Your main interest is then to point out the unity of 'the Fruit' in all the manifestations of its life…that is, to show the mystical interconnection between these fruits, how in each of them 'the Fruit' realizes itself by degrees and necessarily progresses, for instance, from its existence as a raisin to its existence as an almond. Hence the value of the ordinary fruits no longer consists in their natural qualities, but in their speculative quality, which gives each of them a definite place in the life-process of 'the Absolute Fruit'.

 

"The ordinary man does not think he is saying anything extraordinary when he states that there are apples and pears. But when the philosopher expresses their existence in the speculative way he says something extraordinary. He performs a miracle by producing the real natural objects, the apple, the pear, etc., out of the unreal creation of the mind 'the Fruit'…. It goes without saying that the speculative philosopher accomplishes this continuous creation only by presenting universally known qualities of the apple, the pear, etc., which exist in reality, as determining features invented by him, by giving the names of the real things to what abstract reason alone can create, to abstract formulas of reason, finally, by declaring his own activity, by which he passes from the idea of an apple to the idea of a pear, to be the self-activity of the Absolute Subject, 'the Fruit.' In the speculative way of speaking, this operation is called comprehending Substance as Subject, as an inner process, as an Absolute Person, and this comprehension constitutes the essential character of Hegel's method." [Marx and Engels (1975a), pp.72-75. Bold emphases alone added. Several paragraphs merged.]

 

So, readers might now see why words like "mystical" and "mysticism" are both appropriate and justified. Not only is 'the process of abstraction' a complete mystery (we have seen that no one who imagines there is such a process has ever been able to describe it in anything other than the vaguest of terms), but the results themselves are no less mysterious. For example, not one single DM-fan has ever been able to explain what any of the 'abstractions' that emerge at the end of this 'process' actually are. Nor can they tell us where they supposedly exist, or even how they relate to the particulars that allegedly instantiate them. The entire theory has been shrouded in mystery for over two thousand years -- where it remains to this day.

 

DM-fans don't even ask these questions!

 

[Having said that, I recently discovered an attempt made to describe the 'process of abstraction' in some detail: Laurence and Margolis (2012). I will say more about this failed attempt in Interlude One.]

 

That should hardly surprise any of my readers, given the origin of this approach to 'knowledge' in Ancient Greek Mysticism, later fortified by the infusion of a heady dose of Christian Hermeticism, courtesy of Hegel. But, we have here an entire metaphysic based on a 'process' that to this day remains a total mystery.

 

So, the above 'laws' (or 'principles of cognition'), that the aforementioned Rationalists were seeking, involved an appeal to the general, and hence to 'Universals', in order to comprehend, or at least articulate, the particular. Paradoxically, that was also true of the Empiricists, who also had to acknowledge that 'genuine knowledge' only emerged as 'the mind' somehow cobbled-together the general from the particular. [But, often in their case, these inputs were dreaded 'bare particulars' -- involving the 'myth of the given'. On that, see Sellars (1997). (This links to a PDF.)]

 

But, as we have also seen, both traditions led 'post-Renaissance 'bourgeois thought' down yet another blind alley -- and there it, too, remains to this day.

 

In that case, an appeal to 'Universals' (in order to resolve the 'Problem if Induction') turns out to be no help at all -- since they are all particulars, too. Because of that they can no more guarantee their own future 'law-like' behaviour, than ordinary particulars can -- or, at least, not without another hierarchy of 'Universals' to do that for them, and so on ad infinitem...

 

Of course, any theory  based on the Heraclitean Flux [HF] -- such as DM -- only succeeds in torpedoing itself. That is because, if there is a universal HF, in what way could what happens in the future be identical with the past? Perhaps worse, under such circumstances not even the words "identical" and "resemble" will remain the same from moment-to-moment! If everything is always changing, that must surely apply to words and their meanings, which must also be the case with each and every 'abstraction', too. How could any of this be otherwise if the HF is in charge?

 

[The 'relative stability of language' response, which is often wheeled out at this point, has been neutralised here.]

 

This 'problem' also partly arose out of the mistaken belief that scientific theories themselves express a special sort of truth. When that idea is questioned, a solution to the 'problem of induction' soon suggests itself.

 

[Notice the use of the word "theory" here. I am not impugning scientific facts -- or even scientific theory! To state the obvious: facts aren't the same as theories. These rather controversial claims will be expanded upon and defended in Essay Thirteen Part Two.]

 

Nevertheless, when the above train-of-thought (in relation to the HF) is pressed more emphatically than is usually the case, several rather surprising conclusions soon follow: Since both the flow of ideas 'in the mind' (or even those 'in the brain' of an Über-Rationalist, like Hegel), alongside any sensations that accompany (or cause) them), are also events, 'subjective' experience itself can't avoid being thrown into doubt, which in turn raises questions about the future behaviour even of 'mental events'.

 

[The reader should keep in mind the fact that the following comments only apply if we were to adopt the above way of conceptualising knowledge. Again, they don't represent my views, even though they do represent my way of undermining this long-standing tradition.]

 

In that case, our experience of anything that has yet to occur (which must also include our own future thoughts and actions) might fail to 'resemble' what they had been, or seemed to have been, in the past. Even the nature and behaviour of our sensations and ideas could also alter from moment-to-moment, given this approach to knowledge (and especially if we factor in the HF). If we experience an idea now as an idea of a certain sort, it could be experienced, thought of, or interpreted as something totally different tomorrow, even though it might prove impossible to say right now what that might be. That itself would either be because we don't yet possess the relevant language or because that language might itself have changed before we succeed in uttering, or even thinking, anything at all.

 

[The moral of these rather sobering thoughts is that the HF is no respecter of ideas or of those who are foolish enough to give it any credence. If true, it holds sway over everything they experience, conclude, think, say or believe -- not one atom of which will be the same now as it was a fraction of a second earlier. If HF-ers (i.e., those who give credence to the theory there is an HF) imagine otherwise, they aren't bona fide HF-ers. They are just inconsistent philosophical windbags.]  

 

Recall, 'abstractions' were originally invented to provide some sort of philosophical -- or even scientific -- stability to the deliverances of the senses. They were supposed to help provide a secure foundation for knowledge, a basis that transcended the particular by 'ascending' to the general -- i.e., to 'Universals', 'Concepts' and 'Categories'. They were supposed to be far superior to, and more reliable than, ephemeral, contingent, transient facts based on experience/'appearances'. That is why Plato and his ilk invented them. It was the whole point of his Allegory of the Cave. [On that, see Appendix B of Essay Eight Part Two.] It was also the attitude motivating the German Idealists (this was quoted earlier):

 

"Already with Fichte the idea of the unity of the sciences, of system, was connected with that of finding a reliable starting-point in certainty on which knowledge could be based. Thinkers from Kant onwards were quite convinced that the kind of knowledge which came from experience was not reliable. Empirical knowledge could be subject to error, incomplete, or superseded by further observation or experiment. It would be foolish, therefore, to base the whole of knowledge on something which had been established only empirically. The kind of knowledge which Kant and his followers believed to be the most secure was a priori knowledge, the kind embodied in the laws of Nature. These had been formulated without every occurrence of the Natural phenomenon in question being observed, so they did not summarise empirical information, and yet they held good by necessity for every case; these laws were truly universal in their application." [White (1996a), p.29. Bold emphasis added.]

 

Here again is Hegel echoing and amplifying these very ideas:

 

"The view that the objects of immediate consciousness, which constitute the body of experience, are mere appearances (phenomena) was another important result of the Kantian philosophy. Common Sense, that mixture of sense and understanding, believes the objects of which it has knowledge to be severally independent and self-supporting; and when it becomes evident that they tend towards and limit one another, the interdependence of one upon another is reckoned something foreign to them and to their true nature. The very opposite is the truth. The things immediately known are mere appearances -- in other words, the ground of their being is not in themselves but in something else. But then comes the important step of defining what this something else is. According to Kant, the things that we know about are to us appearances only, and we can never know their essential nature, which belongs to another world we cannot approach. Plain minds have not unreasonably taken exception to this subjective idealism, with its reduction of the facts of consciousness to a purely personal world, created by ourselves alone. For the true statement of the case is rather as follows. The things of which we have direct consciousness are mere phenomena, not for us only, but in their own nature; and the true and proper case of these things, finite as they are, is to have their existence founded not in themselves but in the universal divine Idea. This view of things, it is true, is as idealist as Kant's; but in contradistinction to the subjective idealism of the Critical philosophy should be termed absolute idealism. Absolute idealism, however, though it is far in advance of vulgar realism, is by no means merely restricted to philosophy. It lies at the root of all religion; for religion too believes the actual world we see, the sum total of existence, to be created and governed by God." [Hegel (1975, §45, p.73. Links in the original. Bold emphases added; paragraphs merged.]

 

However, the above approach will always prove to be futile, if not counter-productive. That is because anyone who accepts it will now have to appeal to 'abstractions' -- i.e., 'Universals', 'Concepts', 'Categories', 'Principles' and 'Ideas', every one of which has been privately processed and created -- in order to guarantee the stability and permanence of 'rational knowledge', setting it above 'empirical instability', or 'variability' -- ensuring the latter don't undermine the status of philosophical/scientific knowledge. But, as we have seen, each of these 'abstractions' is a particular (or the Proper Names thereof), so they are absolutely no use in this respect. As such they are subject to the very same suspicions about their own future constancy that (allegedly) confront ordinary material particulars (e.g., the regular occurrence of sunrise and the nourishing property of bread, mentioned earlier). In which case, any theory that countenances the validity of the HF implies that no particular -- abstract or concrete -- is capable of providing a secure basis for a single general conclusion about the future constancy of nature and 'rational' thought.

 

There are no self-certifying ideas to be had here -- given this self-torpedoing way of conceiving this 'problem'.

 

Worse still: any 'solution' to this 'problem' (should one ever be found!) will be subject to the same suspicions, and hence could itself be experienced as a non-solution the very next day -- especially if we were foolish enough buy into the HF.

 

Naturally, expressed the way this entire topic has been for countless generations, any attempt to 'solve the problem of induction' -- i.e., demonstrate how the present 'binds' the future so that it 'resembles' the past -- has already lost its way. In fact, as should now seem clear, phrases like "The present" and "The future" are also particulars (or they are singular terms that 'refer' to certain Abstract Particulars, alongside that other Abstract Particular, 'Time'), and are, as such, totally incapable of preventing the theories adopted by anyone who accepts this approach to knowledge from sliding off into oblivion.

 

And, therein lies a clue to the dissolution to this family of 'problems': as Marx himself suggested, the solution here is to reject this entire way of doing philosophy.

 

Not even the anti-materialist, Aristocratic Philosophers who invented it could make head or tail of it!

 

Nor has anyone since...

 

A New Approach Called For

 

As we now know -- mainly because it was revealed in Part One -- the original source of these 'difficulties' lay in a series ideologically-driven, linguistic tricks engineered by Ancient Greek metaphysicians, logicians and grammarians. In which case, the dissolution of over two millennia of such class-compromised confusion recommends itself.

 

Or it does so to genuine materialists.

 

The bottom line here is the realisation that if 'the mind' is capable of experiencing only a finite number of exemplars from which it has to piece-together (or apply) general ideas, subsequent experience could always refuse to play ball, as it were. In that case, given this way of picturing 'reality', the future might fail to 'resemble' the past in any meaningful sense. Not only might the Sun fail to rise (tomorrow), and water fail to boil at a given temperature, but cats might refuse to walk about on mats and Hegel might even begin to make sense.

 

Of course, as already noted, it might prove possible side-step such 'difficulties' if 'the mind' was thought capable of gaining direct access to a 'Third Realm' where these 'abstract ideas' (i.e., Universals, General Concepts and Categories, etc., etc.) supposedly hang out, and which, when 'reflected' in, or used by, 'the mind' were somehow capable of regimenting whatever 'inputs' the senses sent its way. Alternatively, if we are prepared to go all the way, and on a good day, they might even be able to 'construct reality itself' (which seems to be the mad dog approach Hegel adopted, as have more than a handful of Empiricists). In that case, that would mean any such theorist could legitimately claim the future course of events is guaranteed to resemble the past (in the manner indicated above).

 

However, in relation to the above Empiricists, if 'the mind' were to prove capable of controlling the 'unruly inputs' delivered by the senses, something a little more robust than Locke's Social Contract or Hume's 'habits of mind' would be required. Unfortunately, Ancient Greek theories that spoke about, or which relied on, there being a rational and ordered Cosmos (upon which basis a rational and orderly society might be built) didn't sit too well with the socially-, and politically-fragmented bourgeois world that began to emerge in the 17th and 18th centuries. This Humpty-Dumpty couldn't be put back together again:

 

 

 

Figure Five: A Smashing Metaphor For Empiricist Epistemology? 

 

 

A completely novel approach, specifically designed fit the new social landscape, was called for.

 

As already noted, Hume attempted to address this 'problem' by appealing to rather vague 'habits', which amounted to an Associationist theory of human cognition. This was (somehow!) thought capable of forming a secure basis for expectations about the future course of events, predicated on past experience, shaped by these 'habits'. Clearly, this nebulous theory was susceptible to the challenges set out in earlier paragraphs of this sub-section -- because of which, any series of events -- past, present or future -- will become the target of the same sceptical questions. In that case, it is difficult to see how 'habits of mind' would emerge unscathed. Or must we now appeal to a habit of the habits of the mind to guarantee the constancy of any given habit? Or are 'habits of the mind' the only processes in the entire universe that always behave tomorrow like they have today? Assume that on day one, Habit1 underpins the expectation that B should follow A (where "A" and "B" are event tokens). But, what if on day two Habit1 now registers the expectation that C should instead follow A? Would there not now have to be a second order habit, Habit2, that underpinned the expectation that Habit1 will behave itself and guarantee the expectation that B follows A, once more? What is to stop Habit2 from now 'misbehaving'? What is to stop it from manifesting the expectation that Habit1 underpins the expectation that D follows A? Maybe then there is a third order habit, Habit3, that will rescue the day? But, what if it, too, 'misbehaves'...?

 

One suspects another infinite regress is gathering in the wings.

 

The abandonment of the 'logical', or necessary connection between a Universal and the particulars that fall under it -- i.e., the 'rational' or 'metaphysical' relationship between an object and its properties (which we also met earlier) --, that took place in the High Middle Ages (with the rise of Nominalism (but the cracks were already forming in the work of several post-Aristotelian theorists; the Nominalists merely forced them wide enough for all to see), introduced radical contingency, not just into Traditional Theories of Causation, but 'Reality Itself'. This development wasn't, of course, unconnected with a decline in the power of the Papacy as Feudalism itself began to unravel, giving way to early forms of the 'free' market economy.

 

[Those tantalising threads will be pulled on much further in another Essay.]

 

Rationalist Philosophers (like Spinoza and Leibniz) made valiant attempts to repair the damage such untoward developments had inflicted on the 'Rational Order of Reality', the 'God' of Christianity and 'His' relation to 'creation'. To that end, they constructed entirely new 'necessitarian' theories that sought to re-establish a logical connection between a given substance and its 'accidents', linking a given object with its properties. Unfortunately, these theories were themselves based on the same old "ruling ideas" -- i.e., principally on:

 

(i) The quasi-religious dogma that 'Reality' is 'Rational', which meant that fundamental 'truths' about 'it' may be derived from thought/language alone; and,

 

(ii) The same defective analysis of subject-predicate propositions that gave rise to these 'problems' in the first place.

 

[On the general background to this, see, for example, Copleston (2003a, 2003b, 2003c), and the references given below.]

 

Here is how I have made similar points in Essay Eleven Part Two -- which formed part of a brief consideration of certain aspects of Christian Fundamentalism and 'Intelligent Design' that also happen to be relevant to the above issues:

 

There is an excellent summary of the two main avenues theists have taken in their attempt to conceive of the relationship between 'God' and 'His' creation in Osler (2004), pp.15-35. [Not unexpectedly, these neatly mirror the tensions that plague the DM-account of nature, too.]

 

Here follows a summary of the relevant parts of Osler's thesis (with a few additional comments of my own thrown in for good measure):

 

Traditionally, there were two ways of conceiving 'God's' relation to material reality:

 

(a) 'He' is related to it by necessity, as an expression of 'His' nature; or,

 

(b) 'He' is related to it contingently -- as an expression of 'His' 'free will'.

 

If (a) were the case, there would be a logical connection between the properties of created beings and their 'essence' -- i.e., the logical core of each being, which is either an expression of its unique nature, or of the 'kind' to which it belongs. In turn, this would be a consequence of the logical or conceptual links that exist between 'creation' and 'God's Nature'. If that weren't the case, it would introduce radical contingency into creation, undermining 'God's Nature' and 'His' control of 'Creation'. As a result language and logic must constitute reality (why that is so is outlined here).

 

[Also worth pointing out is the fact that Super-Truths like this -- about fundamental aspects of 'reality' -- may only be accessed via speculative thought.]

 

This means that all that exists is either:

 

(i) An expression of the logical properties inherent in 'God'; or,

 

(ii) An emanation from 'God'.

 

That is, material reality must be logically 'emergent' from, and hence connected with, the 'Deity'. So, the universe 'issues' forth from 'His' nature 'eternally' and a-temporally, outside of time, since that is where 'He exists'. Everything must therefore be inter-linked by 'internal', or 'necessary', relations, all of which are derived from, and constituted by, 'concepts' implicit in 'God', which are consequently mirrored in fundamental aspects of creation. This idea is prominent in Plotinus and subsequent Neo-Platonists, like Hegel.

 

Given this approach, it is clear that the vast majority of 'ordinary' human beings are incapable of accessing, nor can they even comprehend, this 'rational' view of 'reality'. Their lack of knowledge, education and 'divine illumination' means that, at best, they misperceive these 'logical properties' as contingent qualities. Hence, for them, appearances fail to match underlying "essence". Naturally, this implies that "commonsense" and ordinary language are fundamentally unreliable.

 

Now, where have we heard all that before? Email me if you know.

 

Option (b), on the other hand, implied that 'God' acted freely when 'He' created the world. So, if 'He' wasn't acting under any form of 'compulsion', logical or conceptual -- i.e., 'He' wasn't acting on the basis of the logical properties inherent in 'His' nature -- then there will be no logical or necessary connection between 'The Creator' and 'His Creation'. Nor, indeed, would there be such between each created being. Every object and process in reality would therefore be genuinely contingent, and appearances will no longer be 'deceptive', since they can't mask the hidden, esoteric 'essences' mentioned above -- for there are none. That being the case, there are no synthetic a priori truths (as these later came to be known) ascertainable by thought alone. The only path to knowledge was through observation, experiment, and a careful study of the 'Book of Nature'. It is no coincidence then that the foundations of modern science were laid in the Middle Ages largely by theorists who adopted this view of 'God' -- for example, Jean Buridan.

 

[On this, see also: Copleston (2003c), pp.153-67, Crombie (1970, 1979), Grant (1996), Hannam (2009), Lindberg (2007).]

 

In post-Renaissance thought, the 'necessitarian' tradition re-surfaced in the work of Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, Wolff, and Hegel; the 'voluntarist' tradition saw the light of day in an attenuated form in the work of Newton, the Empiricists, and the so-called "mechanists". They all tended to stress the connection between 'God's' free will and contingency in nature, alongside the primacy of empirical over a priori knowledge and the superiority of observation and experiment over speculation and abstract theory.

 

[Admittedly, the above categories are rather crude; for example, Descartes was a mechanist, but his theory put him on the same side of the fence as Spinoza and Leibniz, whereas Gassendi was also a mechanist, but his ideas aligned him with the voluntarists. On this, see Copleston (2003d).]

 

So, when Fundamentalist Christians, for example, look at nature and see design everywhere, they also claim to see 'irreducible complexity' -- the handiwork of 'God' -- and they either put this down to 'His' free creation, or they see it as an expression of logical properties imposed on nature by the Logos (depending, of course, on how they view the nature of 'The Creator' and 'His' relation to the world).

 

Christian mechanists saw design in nature, too, but their theories became increasingly deistic, and later openly atheistic. The admission of a contingent link between 'God' and nature severed the logical connection that earlier theorists had postulated, making "the God hypothesis" seem increasingly redundant. [Laplace -- "I have no need of that hypothesis".]

 

[On this, see Lovejoy (1964). [This links to a PDF.] There is an excellent account of this in Redwood (1976); see also Dillenberger (1988). A classic expression of these developments can be found in the debate between Leibniz and Clarke. Cf., Alexander (1956), and Vailati (1997).]

 

Much of this controversy had been motivated much earlier by the work of the Medieval Nominalists, whose theories also sundered the logical link between a substance and its properties as part of a reaction to the tradition begun by Avicenna (Ibn Sīnā, with his separation of 'essence' and 'existence' in created beings), Averroës (Ibn Rushd), and the so-called "Latin Averroists" (e.g., Siger of Brabant). The latter argued strongly in favour of Aristotle's doctrine of natural necessity, thus undermining 'God's' free will -- at least, so far as the Roman Catholic Church saw things. This reaction was also prompted by philosophical worries about the nature of transubstantiation and the relation between the 'essence' of the emblems (the bread and the wine in the Eucharist) and their 'accidents' (their apparent properties). Here 'appearances' most definitely couldn't reflect 'essence' otherwise the bread would look like human flesh and the wine would smell of blood!

 

The aforementioned reaction was occasioned by the 'Condemnations of 1277', whereby the Bishop of Paris, Étienne Tempier, condemned 219 propositions, among which was the Averroist interpretation of Aristotle -- particularly the idea that the created order was governed by logical necessity. The most important response to these condemnations appeared in the work of the Nominalist, William of Ockham, who, as a result, stressed the 'free will of God' and thus the contingent nature of the world. For Ockham, this meant that there were no 'essences' in nature, nor were the apparent properties of bodies (their 'accidents', again) logically connected with their 'nominal essence' (as this later came to be called by Locke).

 

[On this, see: Osler (2004), Copleston (2003b), pp.136-55, 190-95, 437-41, Copleston (2003c), pp.43-167, and Copleston (2003e), pp.79-107.]

 

In the 18th century, a resurgence of the 'necessitarian' tradition motivated, among other things, the "re-enchantment" of nature in the theories concocted by the Natürphilosophers and Hegel -- and later still in those invented by Marxist Dialecticians.

 

[On this, see Harrington (1996), Lenoir (1982), Richards (2002), and Essay Fourteen Parts One and Two, when they are published. More details can be found in Foster (1934), Hooykaas (1973), Lindberg (2007), and Osler (2004). For the Hermetic background to all this, see Magee (2008). Cf., also Essay Twelve (summary here). At a later date I will publish an essay on Leibniz I wrote as an undergraduate, which anticipated some of the ideas in Osler's book, for example.]

 

So, where Christians see design, DM-fans see "internal relations". Same problematic, same tainted source, same bogus 'solution' to this set of pseudo-problems.12a

 

In such inhospitable surroundings not only must the 'Concepts' and 'Abstractions' (i.e., those judged capable of 'guiding' 'ideas' into the 'right mental pigeonholes') be robust enough to do all the 'sorting' ('behind the backs of the producers', as it were, since no one is normally aware this is taking place -- which is, of course, why it took several fast-talking philosophers to 'discover' it and then persuade a few in their gullible audience to give it some credence), they must also exist prior to, and be independent of, experience. If that weren't the case, they would risk suffering the very same slings and arrows of outrageous fortune themselves. So, if experience were incapable of delivering 'genuine knowledge' (or so we have been told by generations of Rationalists), 'Universals', 'Principles', 'Concepts', Representations' and 'Abstractions' have to be held aloof, elevated way beyond the contingent world of 'appearances', or suffer the same sceptical mauling.

 

After all, 'bad associations' spoil useful 'abstractions'.

 

'Epistemological Thermidor'

 

Initially, at least as far as 'crude materialists' were concerned, it wasn't easy to account either for the source or the 'effectiveness of these 'muscular concepts' -- i.e., all those 'mental constructs' ('frameworks', 'principles', 'categories', and 'abstractions', etc., etc.), which did all the regimenting and permitted of no exceptions. However, it turned out that this 'entirely new approach' -- the aforementioned 'philosophical rescue' (for want of a better term) -- came from an entirely unexpected source: German Idealism. More specifically, and even more revealingly, it strode onto the intellectual stage in the form of an impossibly convoluted re-vamp of Ancient Greek Neoplatonism with just enough Hermeticism thrown in to attract the attention of those who dote on totally incomprehensible gobbledygook, who also imagine there's a 'hidden meaning' buried in all that impenetrable verbiage...somewhere.

 

The baroque systems of thought concocted by these Teutonic Idealists saw the invention of Self-Developing, Super-'Concepts', fortified by Industrial Strength 'Categories' that packed enough metaphysical clout to control the 'untamed' deliverances of the senses. These days such 'heavy-duty principles' have been boosted even further by the addition of a handful of impressive-sounding phrases -- such as, "natural-", "ontological-", "metaphysical-necessity", and "apodictic certainty". Such rugged, hairy-chested jargon was mandatory otherwise the feral 'inputs' the senses sent the mind's way might refuse to behave, which might in turn imply the unexpected, the adventitious, the seemingly impossible, happens on a regular basis. This might even mean fires begin freezing water, fish spontaneously break out in song, Conservatives stop lying, and Dialectical Marxism -- no, stop laughing at the back(!) -- becoming a ringing success.13

 

Furthermore, such testosterone-infused 'Concepts', 'Categories' and 'Principles' also had to be logical -- indeed, 'dialectical' --, if they were to prove capable of exercising rigid control over the future course of events -- or even the future deliverances of the senses and the overall direction of 'thought' --, ensuring that every single 'input' was efficiently processed and slotted into the 'right' metaphysical pigeon holes, each labelled with the 'correct' general term.

 

This is, of course, where the traditional confusion of talk about talk with talk about the world came into its own. If you run-together the relationship between 'concepts' and the 'particulars' they supposedly regiment, it a little too easy to imagine that objects and their properties must be related in the same way in 'extra-mental reality' as the former are in 'the mind'. A few short steps further soon motivates the hyper-bold idea that the entire universe is controlled the same way -- leading to the conclusion that how a given thinker just so happens to knit concepts and objects together in 'consciousness' is how 'reality itself' actually operates. But, only those who want to be counted as Conceptual Megalomaniacs will allow that train of thought to run to its illogical conclusion.

 

Here once again is Hegel scholar, Katharina Dulckeit, who reveals how Hegel proposed to 'repair the damage' inflicted on necessitarianism as a result of the dissolution of Feudalism and the rise of Capitalism (a fall from 'philosophical grace' epitomised by the 'English' turn to Empiricism in the 17th and 18th centuries):

 

"[It] must be remembered that [Hegel's] analysis of the forms of judgment in the Logic is motivated by his interest in essential judgement. There are two conditions for such judgements. To begin with, a judgement is an essential judgement only if P tells us precisely and exclusively what s is; no less and no more. But merely predicating universals of particulars is insufficient for this, unless the term in the predicate position at once expresses the essential nature of the subject. This, in turn, argues Hegel, is possible only if the 'is' expresses some identity between s and P. For if essential determination were possible exclusively via predication, the subject and the predicate would remain separate and the relation between them expressed by the copula would remain external. As a consequence, s would refer to one thing, namely an individual, while P would designate something distinct from s, namely a universal. But the truth of sense-certainty in the Phenomenology has already been shown that qua individual, an individual is grasped only through the mediation of universals. It follows that divorced from these, it would then have to be an individual without a universal nature, i.e., a bare individual.... Thus, if s and P are utterly distinct they must be mutually exclusive, which means that s will necessarily be bare, and P necessarily abstract.... Clearly then, where judgements of essence are concerned, the 'is' of predication will not do because it entails the distinction between s and P which would commit us to a metaphysical thesis already overcome in the Phenomenology." [Dulckeit (1989), pp.115-16. Bold emphases alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site; links added. I have subjected passages like this to sustained criticism in Appendix D of Part One.]

 

As we will see in Essay Seven Part Three, Lenin latched onto Hegel's 'Rationalist' response to Empiricist Theories of Causation, which subsequently formed the central core of 'the dialectical theory of change'. [Readers are referred to that Essay for more details.]

 

So, bourgeois ideas, supposedly 'born free' ('free' at least of archaic notions of necessity) were now clapped in chains. The 'free market of ideas' that the 17th and 18th century 'revolution in the head' ushered in was now over. This Rationalist/Idealist 'rescue mission', with its industrial strength 'concepts', looked far more like a 'mental Thermidor' than it did any sort of liberation.14

 

[CNS = Central Nervous System.]

 

But, one nagging question remained: How could something even as 'powerful' as these heavy duty 'Logical Principles' (involving the supposed 'identity between a subject and a predicate') guarantee that future events, or our impressions of them, will always behave as expected? Unfortunately for Hegel (and those who paid him any heed), the 'rational principles' living rent-free in his head turned out to be particulars, too, and as such were no less in need of regimentation themselves. Otherwise, there would be no good reason to see why ordinary particulars needed regimenting, in the first place. After all, how could an abstraction (physically-, and causally-divorced from the material world) actually control anything? Why would something that is physical -- in 'external reality', or even in the CNS, such as an 'input' -- 'obey' an abstraction? How could anything that lacks intelligence, or even sentience (i.e., all those 'inputs', once more) do any obeying to begin with? How could something non-material control anything material?

 

After all, not even concepts-on-steroids can actually make anything happen.

 

[That knotty problem -- which is similar to the one that confronted Descartes as he tried to explain how a non-material 'soul' could affect a material body, or the one Platonists/neo-Platonists face when they attempt to explain how mathematical objects and structures are capable of interacting with the world (i.e., whether or not they are causally efficacious) --, has yet to be solved by scientists and philosophers alike. In fact, after well over two thousand years, they're not even close! (This extra pseudoproblem will be addressed in Essay Three Part Five. Some of that material has already been published in Essay Thirteen Part Three, here and here.)]

 

The point at issue here is in fact reasonably straightforward: logical principles per se can't create generality out of thin air; generality emerges from the application of a rule, which neither words nor 'Concepts' -- nor even 'Principles' and 'Categories' -- can quite manage on their own. It requires human beings (and then only when acting as social agents, part of a collective) to determine what constitutes the correct application of a rule, As has been pointed out several times, that is because 'Concepts', 'Abstractions', 'Categories' and 'Principles' have neither the wit, intelligence nor social structure sufficient to the task.

 

[It is worth reminding the reader, again, that what follows isn't simply my opinion of bourgeois theory, it is implied by their own words.]

 

That was, indeed, the point of emphasising the social and theoretical atomisation that gave birth to the bourgeois, 'logical' principles mentioned earlier in this Essay. The fragmentation introduced into epistemology (in both its Rationalist and Empiricist wings) meant that, in the heads of these socially-isolated thinkers, 'Concepts' (etc.) could only operate as the Proper Names of Abstract Particulars -- or, indeed, as those Particulars themselves --, destroying generality and undermining the unity of the proposition.14a0

 

[So, for example, 'The concept of time' (in Kant) and 'The concept of Being' (in Hegel) are both Abstract Particulars (or they are singular terms designating such).]

 

Clearly, 'Logical Principles' like these could only succeed in regimenting 'inputs' delivered to them by the senses if they managed to control the latter's future behaviour, which implied they were intelligent -- or even social -- agents themselves. Indeed, the way they were characterised suggested they might actually exist in 'external reality', and were even 'Ideas in self-development'. [That inference, courtesy of Hegel, represents a classic example of the conflation of talk about talk with talk about the world.] Either that, or they were 'internal regulative principles' that whipped the 'raw deliverances of the senses' into shape. [That anthropomorphic inference we can pin on Kant.]

 

In Hegel, this doctrine completely eroded the distinction between Mind and Matter -- which is clearly why Engels thought he could get away with arguing that matter is just an abstraction, employing virtually same argument (and even using the same example!) as Hegel:

 

"When the universal is made a mere form and co-ordinated with the particular, as if it were on the same level, it sinks into the particular itself. Even common sense in everyday matters is above the absurdity of setting a universal beside the particulars. Would anyone, who wished for fruit, reject cherries, pears, and grapes, on the ground that they were cherries, pears or grapes, and not fruit?" [Hegel (1975), p.19, §13, quoted from here. Bold emphasis alone added.]

 

"It is the old story. First of all one makes sensuous things into abstractions and then one wants to know them through the senses, to see time and smell space. The empiricist becomes so steeped in the habit of empirical experience, that he believes that he is still in the field of sensuous experience when he is operating with abstractions.... The two forms of existence of matter are naturally nothing without matter, empty concepts, abstractions which exist only in our minds. But, of course, we are supposed not to know what matter and motion are! Of course not, for matter as such and motion as such have not yet been seen or otherwise experienced by anyone, only the various existing material things and forms of motions. Matter is nothing but the totality of material things from which this concept is abstracted and motion as such nothing but the totality of all sensuously perceptible forms of motion; words like matter and motion are nothing but abbreviations in which we comprehend many different sensuous perceptible things according to their common properties. Hence matter and motion can be known in no other way than by investigation of the separate material things and forms of motion, and by knowing these, we also pro tanto know matter and motion as such.... This is just like the difficulty mentioned by Hegel; we can eat cherries and plums, but not fruit, because no one has so far eaten fruit as such." [Engels (1954), pp.235-36. Bold emphasis alone added.]

 

"N.B. Matter as such is a pure creation of thought and an abstraction. We leave out of account the qualitative differences of things in lumping them together as corporeally existing things under the concept matter. Hence matter as such, as distinct from definite existing pieces of matter, is not anything sensuously existing." [Ibid., p.255. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"When the universal is made a mere form and co-ordinated with the particular, as if it were on the same level, it sinks into the particular itself. Even common sense in everyday matters is above the absurdity of setting a universal beside the particulars. Would anyone, who wished for fruit, reject cherries, pears, and grapes, on the ground that they were cherries, pears or grapes, and not fruit?" [Hegel (1975), p.19, §13, quoted from here. Bold emphasis alone added.]

 

"Essence becomes matter in that its reflection is determined as relating itself to essence as to the formless indeterminate. Matter is therefore the differenceless identity which is essence, with the determination of being the other of form. It is consequently the real basis or substrate of form, because it constitutes the reflection-into-self of the form-determinations, or the self-subsistent element to which the latter are related as to their positive subsistence. If abstraction is made from every determination, from all form of anything, what is left over is indeterminate matter. Matter is a sheer abstraction. (Matter cannot be seen, felt, and so on -- what is seen, felt, is a determinate matter, that is, a unity of matter and form). This abstraction from which matter proceeds is, however, not merely an external removal and sublating of form, rather does form, as we have seen, spontaneously reduce itself to this simple identity." [Hegel (1999), pp.450-51, §§ 978-979. Bold emphasis alone added. Typos in the on-line version corrected. Paragraphs merged.]

 

In which case, controlling the future behaviour of anything that might seem to be accidental or adventitious (in the mind or in the world) now became a question concerning the self-discipline of, and oversight by, a series of self-developing 'Concepts'. In fact, these 'Concepts' controlled the future because they possessed, or even embodied, a 'revolutionary new logic', a 'dialectical logic', which a was, fortuitously, capable of powering the entire Cosmos. In which case, it now seemed plain that this all-conquering logic could easily take care of all these apparent 'contingencies' (since they were now magicked into necessities), thus guaranteeing the (underlying) rational course of nature.

 

[This 'logic' was itself based on a mis-applied metaphor about how arguments themselves 'edge toward' a conclusion. That at least explains the presence of the word "contradiction". There is no other reason for using it.]

 

This new 'logic' laid down the law, which meant that everything in nature -- Mind and Matter -- bent the knee to its Contradictory Will. We saw this earlier in Lenin's appropriation of these Hegelian fantasies:

 

"To begin with what is the simplest, most ordinary, common, etc., [sic] with any proposition...: [like] John is a man…. Here we already have dialectics (as Hegel's genius recognized): the individual is the universal…. Consequently, the opposites (the individual is opposed to the universal) are identical: the individual exists only in the connection that leads to the universal. The universal exists only in the individual and through the individual. Every individual is (in one way or another) a universal. Every universal is (a fragment, or an aspect, or the essence of) an individual. Every universal only approximately embraces all the individual objects. Every individual enters incompletely into the universal, etc., etc. Every individual is connected by thousands of transitions with other kinds of individuals (things, phenomena, processes), etc. Here already we have the elements, the germs of the concept of necessity, of objective connection in nature, etc. Here already we have the contingent and the necessary, the phenomenon and the essence; for when we say John is a man…we disregard a number of attributes as contingent; we separate the essence from the appearance, and counterpose the one to the other…. Thus in any proposition we can (and must) disclose as a 'nucleus' ('cell') the germs of all the elements of dialectics, and thereby show that dialectics is a property of all human knowledge in general." [Lenin (1961), pp.359-60. Bold emphases alone added; paragraphs merged.]

 

Compare that with what we read earlier:

 

"[It] must be remembered that [Hegel's] analysis of the forms of judgment in the Logic is motivated by his interest in essential judgement. There are two conditions for such judgements. To begin with, a judgement is an essential judgement only if P tells us precisely and exclusively what s is; no less and no more. But merely predicating universals of particulars is insufficient for this, unless the term in the predicate position at once expresses the essential nature of the subject. This, in turn, argues Hegel, is possible only if the 'is' expresses some identity between s and P. For if essential determination were possible exclusively via predication, the subject and the predicate would remain separate and the relation between them expressed by the copula would remain external. As a consequence, s would refer to one thing, namely an individual, while P would designate something distinct from s, namely a universal. But the truth of sense-certainty in the Phenomenology has already been shown that qua individual, an individual is grasped only through the mediation of universals. It follows that divorced from these, it would then have to be an individual without a universal nature, i.e., a bare individual.... Thus, if s and P are utterly distinct they must be mutually exclusive, which means that s will necessarily be bare, and P necessarily abstract.... Clearly then, where judgements of essence are concerned, the 'is' of predication will not do because it entails the distinction between s and P which would commit us to a metaphysical thesis already overcome in the Phenomenology." [Dulckeit (1989), pp.115-16. Bold emphases alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site; links added. I have subjected passages like this to sustained criticism in Appendix D of Part One.]

 

Plato's World Soul was thereby given a new lease of life (and not just to run amok in Dialectical Marxism). It now ran the entire show, which meant the future course of events was under the iron control of this bright and shiny new 'logic' -- which was, disappointingly, just a revamped version of that Soul's 'animating spirit'. Words, whose meaning had originally been based on the social application of linguistic rules, were now re-configured as a universal expression of 'Self-Developing Consciousness'. The individual 'Bourgeois Mind' was thus magnified and projected across the universe so that it now ran the entire show (at least in the imagination).

 

[And if you agree, don't forget to pick up your complementary, 'I am a Conceptual Megalomaniac' t-shirt, designed for all who think like you, waiting in the Idealist Gift Shop on the way out!]

 

As we have also seen, Ancient and Medieval Logicians -- by their mis-characterisation of predication, in tandem with the invention of all these 'abstractions' -- destroyed any possibility of expressing generality. In its place, an ersatz 'generality' was substituted for it (as an expression of 'God's Mind' -- conveniently working away inside Hegel's skull). Unfortunately for Dialectical Marxists, even when this fantasy is flipped and then "put back on its feet", the logical blunders on which it was based remain in place. Blunders don't cease being blunders by the simple expedient of rotating them through 180º! Indeed, in Hegel's hands, logic was fetishised all the more, transmogrified into a 'spirit' that animated 'inert matter'. This now breathed life into the (moribund) concepts of matter invented by 'crude materialists'. Indeed, without this 'animating spirit' -- without all those 'contradictions', 'negations and 'mediations' -- matter would remain forever inert. 'Reality' itself would be like "a clock without a spring":

 

"Contradiction is the root of all movement and life, and it is only in so far as it contains a contradiction that anything moves and has impulse and activity." [Hegel (1999), p.439, §956. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"It was absolutely necessary to explain why the American 'radical' intellectuals accept Marxism without the dialectic (a clock without a spring)." [Trotsky (1971), p.56. Bold emphasis added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

Hegel's 'Self-Developing Mind' -- now "back on its feet" --, 're-animated matter', which, in effect, amounted to the re-enchantment of Nature. [Harrington (1996).]14a1

 

Paradoxically, but no less implausibly, the 'Iron Laws of the Cosmos' were supposed to be wholly compatible with human freedom! These 'Self-Developing Concepts' were, of course, 'free' because they were a law unto themselves. Indeed, they even seemed to control 'God', who, it turned out, was actually being led like a dog on a leash, dragged along by 'His' very own 'self-developing Ideas', almost as if 'He' couldn't help 'Himself'. 'He' was both 'object' and 'subject' of the all-powerful 'dialectic'. The 'Master' turned into 'Slave' -- the 'Slave' into 'Master'.

 

But, as far as humanity was concerned, the 'good news' turned out to be the exact opposite; according to this theory, the more an individual subjects herself to these 'Laws', the 'freer' she became!

 

So, ironically, the more human beings are in chains, the less they are in chains!

 

Such are the Consolations of The Dialectic...

 

Christianity is supposed to be the religion of slaves, so it is hardly surprising that DM (i.e., 'right side up Christian Mysticism') turns out to be the philosophy of 'radical' slaves.

 

Here is a classic statement of this counterintuitive idea (by Engels himself):

 

"Another opposition in which metaphysics is entangled is that of chance and necessity. What can be more sharply contradictory than these two thought determinations? How is it possible that both are identical, that the accidental is necessary, and the necessary is also accidental? Common sense, and with it the majority of natural scientists, treats necessity and chance as determinations that exclude each other once for all. A thing, a circumstance, a process is either accidental or necessary, but not both. Hence both exist side by side in nature; nature contains all sorts of objects and processes, of which some are accidental, the others necessary, and it is only a matter of not confusing the two sorts with each other.... And then it is declared that the necessary is the sole thing of scientific interest and that the accidental is a matter of indifference to science. That is to say: what can be brought under laws, hence what one knows, is interesting; what cannot be brought under laws, and therefore what one does not know, is a matter of indifference and can be ignored.... That is to say: what can be brought under general laws is regarded as necessary, and what cannot be so brought as accidental. Anyone can see that this is the same sort of science as that which proclaims natural what it can explain, and ascribes what it cannot explain to supernatural causes; whether I term the cause of the inexplicable chance, or whether I term it God, is a matter of complete indifference as far as the thing itself is concerned. Both are only equivalents for: I do not know, and therefore do not belong to science. The latter ceases where the requisite connection is wanting.

 

"In opposition to this view there is determinism, which passed from French materialism into natural science, and which tries to dispose of chance by denying it altogether. According to this conception only simple, direct necessity prevails in nature.... [T]hese are all facts which have been produced by an irrevocable concatenation of cause and effect, by an unshatterable necessity.... With this kind of necessity we likewise do not get away from the theological conception of nature. Whether with Augustine and Calvin we call it the eternal decree of God, or Kismet [Destiny -- RL] as the Turks do, or whether we call it necessity, is all pretty much the same for science. There is no question of tracing the chain of causation in any of these cases; so we are just as wise in one as in another, the so-called necessity remains an empty phrase, and with it -- chance also remains -- what it was before.... Hence chance is not here explained by necessity, but rather necessity is degraded to the production of what is merely accidental. If the fact that a particular pea-pod contains six peas, and not five or seven, is of the same order as the law of motion of the solar system, or the law of the transformation of energy, then as a matter of fact chance is not elevated into necessity, but rather necessity degraded into chance....

 

"In contrast to both conceptions, Hegel came forward with the hitherto quite unheard-of propositions that the accidental has a cause because it is accidental, and just as much also has no cause because it is accidental; that the accidental is necessary, that necessity determines itself as chance, and, on the other hand, this chance is rather absolute necessity. (Logik, II, Book III, 2: Reality.) Natural science has simply ignored these propositions as paradoxical trifling, as self-contradictory nonsense, and, as regards theory, has persisted on the one hand in the barrenness of thought of Wolffian metaphysics, according to which a thing is either accidental or necessary, but not both at once; or, on the other hand, in the hardly less thoughtless mechanical determinism which in words denies chance in general only to recognise it in practice in each particular case.... The previous idea of necessity breaks down. To retain it means dictatorially to impose on nature as a law a human arbitrary determination that is in contradiction to itself and to reality, it means to deny thereby all inner necessity in living nature, it means generally to proclaim the chaotic kingdom of chance to be the sole law of living nature.... The evolution of a concept, or of a conceptual relation (positive and negative, cause and effect, substance and accidency) in the history of thought, is related to its development in the mind of the individual dialectician, just as the evolution of an organism in palaeontology is related to its development in embryology (or rather in history and in the single embryo). That this is so was first discovered for concepts by Hegel. In historical development, chance plays its part, which in dialectical thinking, as in the development of the embryo, is summed up in necessity." [Engels (1954), pp.217-22. Bold emphases and links alone added. Several paragraphs merged. Four minor typos corrected. (I have informed the editors over at the Marxist Internet Archive). On this, see also here.]

 

Exactly how that settles this knotty problem Engels unfortunately neglected to say. Merely reminding his readers that Hegel asserted this, or claimed that, is no explanation if what the latter dogmatically opined is even more obscure than the 'problem' it was meant to solve!

 

No doubt we will be told that the answer to such questions is: 'The dialectic works in mysterious ways...'.

 

But, not only is a rose by any other still a rose, so is slavery.

 

Rousseau thought he could justify social control somewhat similarly (but less mysteriously):

 

"In order then that the social compact may not be an empty formula, it tacitly includes the undertaking, which alone can give force to the rest, that whoever refuses to obey the general will shall be compelled to do so by the whole body. This means nothing less than that he will be forced to be free; for this is the condition which, by giving each citizen to his country, secures him against all personal dependence. In this lies the key to the working of the political machine; this alone legitimises civil undertakings, which, without it, would be absurd, tyrannical, and liable to the most frightful abuses." [Rousseau (1913), p.15; Book One, Chapter Seven. Bold emphasis added.]

 

But what he had in mind wasn't the sort of 'Ideal Thermidor' required to control all these (potentially) unruly 'inputs' (or even what they supposedly 'reflected'). In sharp contrast, while Hegel's 'logic' seemed to offer real hope in this direction, he soon discovered that his Ideas controlled him, not he them. By fetishising the thoughts he imagined were ('logically') fighting it out inside his head, he turned them into what were in effect self-directed agents, and himself into a compliant stooge. By these means he magicked the animated contents of his head into 'laws' that ran the entire universe. Hence, for him, what had once been the product of the social relations between human beings (language, inference, negation, contradiction) not only ended up manipulating his thoughts, they now powered 'Reality'!

 

As noted earlier, critics might be forgiven for labelling this, 'Ontology for Megalomaniacs'. It is indeed the philosophical equivalent of a seriously deranged individual claiming to be Napoleon -- or, perhaps even worse, 'God Himself'.

 

According to Hegel, his crazy Ideas appear to have taken over the Asylum! Instead of the 'psychologically-challenged' contradicting themselves, Hegel's universe did that for them!

 

 

Video Two: The Marat-Sade -- A Fitting Dramatisation

Of The Contents Of Hegel's Head

 

[The full title of the above infamous play by Peter Weir is: The Persecution and Assassination of Jean-Paul Marat Performed by the Inmates of the Asylum of Charenton Under the Direction of the Marquis de Sade.]

 

In relation to this, Feuerbach plainly got things (slightly) wrong: Hegel's 'God' in fact results from the projection of linguistic rules and human characteristics both inwards and outwards -- into himself, and then onto the universe.

 

This should therefore be renamed, Feuerbach 2.0, involving:

 

Speculation on Steroids, Metaphysics on Mescaline, Anthropomorphism on Amphetamines, Epistemology on Ecstasy, Ontology on OxyContin and Logic on LSD!

 

[These are the 'substitute opiates' Marx might very well have spoken about if he were alive today -- and this is why he would have been right.]

 

But, it is precisely here, over such issues, that the fetishisation of language -- detailed in Part One -- elbowed its way into Dialectical Philosophy, and hence into Dialectical Marxism.

 

Subsequently for DM-fans, their ideas supposedly 'reflected' the world, but that turns out to be the case only if Hegel's 'logic' is allowed to control their thoughts and lead them by the nose, too.14a2

 

No wonder then that Max Eastman expressed himself as follows:

 

"Hegelism is like a mental disease; you can't know what it is until you get it, and then you can't know because you have got it." [Eastman (1926), p.22. Bold emphasis added.]

 

[Anyone who objects to my quoting Max Eastman should check this out and then perhaps think again.]

 

Which, of course, helps explain the quasi-religious fervour with which 'The Sacred Dialectic' is protected and defended by all those whose brains it has colonised.

 

[On that, see here and here.]

 

The Anti-Democratic Decay Of Dialectical Marxism

 

As we will see in Essay Nine Part Two, Hegel's 'logic' turned out to be far too feeble to be able to control anything (other than, perhaps, cloud the thought-processes of the unfortunates who look to him for guidance), which has meant that the leaders of Marxist parties find they have to control the ideas in their party members' heads, externally. That is, they have to do so by force, imposing DM-ideology undemocratically -- by means of ostracisation ('organisational quarantine'), silencing, demotion, expulsion, (sectarian) party fragmentation, exiling, incarceration, assassination, or even execution ('where necessary').

 

[How many of the above DM-inspired tactics actually work has been detailed in Essay Nine Part Two (for instance, here and here). In addition, the truly disastrous effect that Hegel's ideas have had on Dialectical Marxism has been set out at length in Sections Two to Eight of the same Essay. Readers are directed there for more information and supporting proof.]

 

So much, then, for 'dialectical freedom' and inner-party democracy...

 

However, Hegel's Idealist 'solution' only succeeded in creating another, related problem: If autonomous 'concepts'/'principles' such as these were necessary if order were to be re-imposed on recalcitrant reality -- or, at least, on any ideas held about it --, and if knowledge is still dependent on the vicissitudes of human cognition, then DM-'principles' only succeed in undermining themselves. If the 'Cosmic Order' can only be comprehended by being put into some sort of 'order' inside each compliant skull (by anthropomorphising 'reality' via the ideas held about it), then that approach can't avoid self-destruction. That is because, if ordinary human beings can't be relied on (i.e., if the vernacular and 'commonsense' are untrustworthy -- which is the ideologically-motivated accusation that originally helped give birth to this family of theories in Ancient Greece), then these 'inner human beings' (these anthropomorphised, 'Self-Developing Hegelian Ideas'), and their mysterious 'internal relations', must be equally suspect.

 

If the ideas of everyday, material human beings can't be trusted because of their reliance on 'appearances', what confidence can be placed on the reliability of these inner, ghostly spectres, these 'shadow human beings'?

 

[We will see that issue return to haunt DM-apologists later on in this Essay.]

 

Worries like these are all the more problematic not just because it is challenging enough to account for the social nature of knowledge in the individual case, but because it becomes impossibly difficult when generalised to take into account an entire community of individuals supposedly able to perform the same trick and arrive at the same conclusions from their limited experience and finite stock of ideas. [As we saw earlier.]

 

Given this Bourgeois Individualist approach, conceptual coordination across the whole of humanity would surely be miraculous. Indeed, that would still be the case if this were restricted to the inhabitants of a small village, let alone a large city or a nation state.

 

In fact, it is far more likely that every member of this self-appointed panel of 'professional abstractors' (i.e., DM-theorists) -- or, indeed, every single Hegel scholar -- is actually dancing to a different 'dialectical tune' playing in each socially-atomised, epistemologically-isolated head.

 

[Apologies again for all those mixed metaphors!]

 

The problems we met earlier (concerning the social, psychological and epistemological fragmentation introduced into 'western thought' by the rise of capitalism) re-surfaces precisely here. Hence, in the realm of ideas alone, it now proves impossible to undo the effect that bourgeois social relations introduced into epistemology -- but only if these pseudo-problems are addressed along lines criticised at this site. The bottom line is that if every single human being (never mind every single dialectician) has to perform these yet-to-be-described-with-any-clarity 'feats of abstraction' in their socially-isolated heads, there can be no such thing as socialised knowledge.

 

[I have explained what is meant by the term, "socially-isolated", below.]

 

This helps account for the countless failed 'theories of knowledge' post-Renaissance Philosophers have concocted over the last four hundred years, to add to those that had been dreamt up over the previous two thousand.

 

Nevertheless, in connection with Dialectical Marxism the individual was encouraged to strike back, initially disguised as the Dialectical Guru Himself -- Hegel. Only he (and perhaps his DM-progeny) were 'licensed' to comprehend these 'self-developing concepts', and thereby understand the course of history, generously passing the 'good news' on to the rest of humanity (who, mysteriously, failed to pay much attention or even express the slightest hint of gratitude). Dialectical Philosophers now became Dialectical Prophets -- the 'Marxist wing' promoting what was in effect a Substitutionist Ideology as its founding creed.14a

 

Once more, given this approach to knowledge, no matter how robust the physical or psychological coercion involved, coordination across an entire population (or even a significant proportion of it -- let alone a single party!) would be nigh on miraculous. Or, it would be unless, of course, it had been un-democratically imposed on party members by the party Itself -- or by the Glorious Leader, 'The Great Helmsman'. Hence it is that in much of Dialectical Marxism, 'logic' and reasonableness were replaced by the Mailed Fist of the Stalinised State (or its less oppressive western correlates -- various Central Committees). Failing that, in non-Stalinist parties, the ever watchful Guardians of Orthodoxy took over -- one prize example of which has been described in detail, here. Given DM-Epistemology, we can now see why this must be so: the only viable way to turn 'knowledge' based on 'abstraction' into party doctrine is via enforced conformity and coercion. That certainly helps explain the ideological centralisation and the lack of internal discussion on issues connected with 'dialectics' in all such parties (except within certain very limited respects) -- as well as the level and intensity of the vitriol aimed at (internal) DM-critics by the faithful.

 

If DM were a valid, well-supported theory, none of this would be necessary.

 

That is why the much more effective Mailed Fist of The Dialectical Magus -- which sometimes assumes the portly shape of a Gerry Healy, elsewhere that of a Mao Zedong, a Castro, a Bob Avakian, a Marlene Dixon, an Abimael Guzmán, or even the Great Teacher Himself, Stalin -- helps guarantee 'good epistemological order' inside each dialectical party and each 'compliant' dialectical skull.

 

[As noted above, exactly how 'Epistemological Stalinism' like this has worked its way into practically every area of Dialectical Marxism, and hence into virtually every party and tendency on the far left, is explored at length in Essay Nine Part Two.]

 

Problems Continue To Multiply Like Japanese Knotweed

 

Despite this, the fact that, in every day life, inter-subjective agreement actually takes place (and countless times, 24/7) suggests the above fanciful, bourgeois individualist approach to knowledge is thoroughly misguided. Indeed, when the day-to-day requirements imposed on each active agent by the natural and social world are factored in, this Post-Renaissance approach to knowledge falls apart even faster than a Kier Starmer 'pledge'.

 

The reasons for asserting this aren't hard to find, either, and they are even more problematic than any that have already been suggested (but, once again, only if we assume 'abstractionism' is a valid theory). Not only is it is highly unlikely that each abstractor would form the same general idea of the same objects and processes based on their limited stock of data -- which is itself challenging enough in view of the fact that no two people share exactly the same experiences or draw the same conclusions from them, but, the word "same" attracts the same difficulties (irony intended!) -- as we are about to see. If no two minds can check the supposed 'similarities' in or between the ideas held by any other mind, there is no way that a social process based on abstraction could even begin to work. Questions would naturally arise whether the 'same' ideas of anything (abstract, particular, concrete, general, or even dialectical) had actually taken root in such 'epistemologically-isolated', 'dialectical brains'. And those worries would persist until it had been established whether or not each abstractor had the 'same' idea about the word "same", never mind anything else.14b

 

And, how on earth might that be established, for goodness sake?

 

Worse still: given the 'dialectical view of identity', the 'problem' itself can't even be stated, let alone resolved. The peremptory DM-rejection of the LOI (or the DM-criticism levelled against it) now returns to haunt Dialectical Marxism, but in a novel way. By confusing a logical issue with an epistemological red-herring, the search for what had been touted as a superior form of 'dialectical knowledge', or 'logic', finds itself trapped in the solipsistic dungeon mentioned in Note 15 (link below).

 

[LOI = Law of Identity.]

 

Once more, that is because it has yet to be explained how any two 'dialectical abstractors' could form the same general, or even the same particular, idea of anything whatsoever -- even before the 'dialectical juggernaut' begins to roll --, let alone how a check might be made whether or not either of them had managed to perform this miraculous trick correctly. And, that isn't so much because no aspiring abstractor has access to the 'content' of the minds belonging to other abstractors, it is because it has yet to be established whether they even have the same idea of the word "correct"!15

 

Once more: how on earth might that be established, for goodness sake?

 

Again, it is no use looking to practice to rescue this ramshackle theory from itself, for it has yet to be established whether or not any two abstractors have the same abstract (or even 'concrete') idea of practice!

 

Once more, how on earth might that...?

 

[The reader is encouraged to finish that sentence for herself.]

 

[By "socially-isolated" I don't mean to suggest that each intrepid abstractor is literally isolated from all the rest -- as if they all lived on separate desert islands -- only that DM-epistemology holds that knowledge (etc.) begins with whatever they manage to process in their head as an individual, which must be the case from birth onwards. Clearly, this means that as far as language and knowledge are concerned, they might as well be literally isolated. Given this view of abstraction it is impossible to build a workable, or even a believable, theory of the social nature of language and knowledge. As Bertell Ollman pointed out, each abstractor will have constructed what is, in all but name, a private language, which, in tandem with Lenin's theory of knowledge, ends up isolating every single one of them from all the rest. The final result is that, with respect to any such shared language, they all live inside what is in effect a solipsistic universe. (I have developed this line-of-thought more extensively in Essay Thirteen Part One; readers are directed there for more details. See also Appendix Three of this Essay.)]

 

It is equally unclear how even this seemingly minor worry (about the generality of what were supposed to be general ideas) may be communicated between members of this 'community' of lone abstractors, at least not without employing the very concept that originally required explanation -- generality --, along with the application of the LOI as a rule of language.16

 

Perhaps more problematic still (i.e., for those who at least say they accept even a minimally social view of language and knowledge -- i.e., Dialectical Marxists in their saner moments) is the following: How might it be ascertained whether or not the same ideas of anything (abstract, concrete, general or particular) have been inherited correctly from previous generations of intrepid abstractors? Without access to a time machine, mind probes -- and, once more, a pre-installed grasp of the very things that had supposedly been bequeathed to later generations (i.e., general ideas, again!) -- no one would be in any position to determine the accuracy of a single 'concept' allegedly belonging to, or passed along by, this 'shared inheritance'.

 

Of course, given the validity of DM-epistemology, no start could even be made constructing knowledge of any sort or description. Not only would such an 'intentional edifice' have no secure foundation -- since its basis (i.e., supposedly inherited knowledge) has already been shown to be no firmer than quicksand -- no two prospective 'labourers' would have the same plot of land on which to work, nor would they have the same plan to guide them, the same materials to work with, or the remotest idea about what could even count as the 'same brick'!

 

This means that, based on the strictures dialecticians have placed on any concrete application of the LOI, no two people could have the same general -- or even the same particular -- idea of anything whatsoever. Nor could they even have the same idea about approximate identity (so that they could conclude their ideas only roughly coincided with those held by anyone else). If the word "same" can't be the same in any two heads (which it can't if the LOI is rejected), the phrase "approximately the same" stands no chance.

 

Worse still, if the DM-criticisms of the LOI are valid, no dialectician would have the same (or even approximately the same) general (or particular) idea that they possessed about anything a few seconds earlier, so that they could say, concerning their own opinions, that they were even approximately stable from moment-to-moment.

 

In that case, of course, the 'process of abstraction' can't even get off the ground!

 

At this stage it should hardly need pointing out that 'the process of abstraction' can make no start, nor register any progress, where there is nothing common to abstract, or no shared ideas, impressions or concepts to work with from moment-to-moment -- never mind those that can't be shared across an entire population of socially-isolated dialectical abstractors.

 

[Once more, the 'relative stability of language' defence was neutralised in Essay Six -- as was the reply that DM-theorists don't reject the LOI, they just question its applicability, especially in relation to change.]16a

 

An appeal to memory at this point would be to no avail, either. That is because, not only are memories themselves subject to the HF, it has yet to be established whether or not anyone involved in this intellectual merry-go-round has the same memory even of the meaning of the word "memory", from moment-to-moment, let alone the words "language" or "word"!

 

Once again: how on earth might any of that be established, for goodness sake?

 

[I hasten to add, once again, that the above sceptical remarks do not represent my views! They are only being aired here to expose the yawning chasm of scepticism and radical doubt implied both by Traditional-, and DM-Epistemology.] 

 

In this way, abstractionism has not only undermined the legitimate status of every single dialectical proposition (a result also established in Part One of this Essay), the entire project has only succeeded in strangling itself before birth, since its adherents unwisely bought into the bourgeois doctrine that we all form abstractions in the privacy of our own heads.

 

[Readers who question that assertion are encouraged to check this and this out, where it has been fully substantiated.]

 

Of course, that is why a claim was made at the end of Part One that the (hypothetical) activities of our heroic 'ancestral abstractors' couldn't have taken place, since no sense can be made of the supposition that they could.

 

Driven To Abstraction

 

The above points could be brushed aside as a grossly unfair misrepresentation, perhaps even a distortion, of DM, typical of these Essays and this site.

 

After all, as TAR notes:

 

"…[A]ll science 'deductively anticipates' developments -- what else is an hypothesis tested by experimentation?" [Rees (1998), p.131.]

 

That appears to contradict the claim made earlier that DM-epistemology can't cope with future contingencies. If scientists actually use abstractions -- and legitimately so in order to predict the future course of events, and with great accuracy -- how could it be problematic for DM-theorists to do likewise? What stops dialecticians from projecting their ideas into the future, especially when their theories are subject to constant check? Alas for Ms Lichtenstein, successful practice refutes the countless negative conclusions drawn at this site.

 

Or, so it might be argued...

 

Quite apart from the fact that practice has actually delivered the opposite verdict (on that, see Essay Ten Part One), it is worth pointing out that, based on DM's own principles (not mine!), the above neat and tidy, pro-DM picture would only work if 'reality itself' were Ideal. That is because, even if the author of TAR were correct that science "'deductively anticipates…' developments", that would only be possible if reality already had an 'underlying logical structure', was 'externalised thought' and, as such, were no different in form from Objective Idealism.

 

[The reasons for making such bold counter-claims were given at the beginning of Part One of Essay Three. Readers are directed there for more details. This topic will be re-examined at greater length in Essay Twelve (summary here).]

 

Among other things, Part One showed that:

 

(i) Traditional Theorists, at best, extrapolate from a limited body of (presumed) facts -- resulting in what they acknowledge is merely 'partial knowledge' -- to conclusions about all of reality, for all of time; and,

 

(ii) This approach was motivated by an ideologically-driven, but syntactically inept re-interpretation of general words as the Proper Names of Abstract Particulars, thus destroying generality -- which, ironically, it had originally sought to account for and explain. The serious errors generated by this grammatical 'wrong turn' were magnified when the 'abstractions' that had just been invented were projected onto what was in effect a 'shadow-reality' that exists anterior to 'appearances', which supposedly underpins the material world. This ersatz-reality was then regarded as 'more real' than the physical universe we see around us. Based on this, even a 'right-way-up' version of Hegelianism (i.e., DM) will always turn out to be just as Ideal as the original ('upside down') version.

 

As a result of the influence that Hegel's system/method has had on the founders of our movement, Dialectical Marxists in general have bought into this unworkable theory of knowledge (for reasons explored in Essay Nine Part Two), even though it undermines their entire worldview. That is because it is based on a series of linguistic tricks and distortions, not on scientific evidence -- or even on evidence drawn from everyday experience, still less from revolutionary practice.17

 

[What scientists supposedly do or do not do will be covered later on in this Essay.]

 

Of course, dialecticians certainly don't see things this way. They view DM as philosophically sound and quintessentially scientific, but the evidence and argument presented so far (and set out in the rest of this Essay, and at this site) throws considerable doubt on that rather peremptory conclusion.

 

'Reality': Abstract, Concrete -- Or Both?

 

The second difficulty (mentioned earlier) isn't unconnected with the first, but has somewhat different implications.

 

As we have seen, traditional solutions to the 'problem of Universals' only appeared to succeed because they either:

 

(i) Anthropomorphised the brain (along with its ideas); or they,

 

(ii) Fetishised language, so that the product of social interaction (language) was reified and transformed into the relation between objects and processes, or it became those objects and processes themselves. We saw this happen throughout Part One in connection with Traditional Theorists and dialecticians' confusion of talk about talk with talk about the world -- for example, here and here

 

As we have also discovered, in order to explain the operation of 'the mind', Empiricists found that they had to postulate the existence of what were in effect 'intelligent ideas', which were either spontaneously gregarious or were somehow capable of 'intelligently obeying' externally imposed rules/laws.

 

On the other hand, Rationalists held that contingent objects and processes themselves (or the 'unreflective' ideas we have of them) couldn't form a secure or reliable basis either for scientific or for philosophical knowledge. In fact, as they reasoned, the reverse was the case: it was the nature and development of their own ideas, or the operation of principles hard-wired in their 'consciousness'/'mind' (by 'God' or by 'nature'), that explained the 'outer' world. So, 'rational thought' was the key to understanding 'reality'. Naturally, this inverted the 'direction' of epistemology, which ended up dictating to nature what it must be like or what it must contain, as opposed to finding out what it actually contained or what it was actually like. That in turn implied 'reality' was fundamentally Ideal, fundamentally 'mind-like'.

 

All this is so far reasonably clear.

 

The next part isn't.

 

On the basis of the 'entire family of rationalist world-views', Traditional Theorists thought they had constructed (or had even 'discovered') what they took to be nature's fundamental "principles"/"laws", but what they didn't do was conclude that their theories were true merely because nature and society were law-governed. On the contrary, many held that the connection was much tighter than this. They imagined they were able to read these 'laws' into nature and society because the mind was structured in a specific way. Furthermore, the very 'possibility of experience' meant that the world (both natural and social) had to be structured in the same way, otherwise we couldn't experience it or know anything about it.18 This placed human rationality -- or, to be honest, the 'rationality' of the select few who thought along these lines (and who either had sufficient leisure time to be able to do all this 'thinking', or who enjoyed the financial backing of a rich patron; now often replaced the long-suffering tax-payer) -- right at the centre of 'the meaning'/'cognitive universe'. So, what was supposed to have been a 'Copernican Revolution' in Philosophy and Science turned out to be the exact opposite: its Ptolemaic reorientation. 'The human mind' now constructed the world and as such lay at its 'cognitive centre', not the other way round. Human thought became the arbiter of what did, or even could, exist -- or what couldn't -- based on a distorted view of language. Indeed, for a few hard core Rationalists, 'the mind' and its machinations actually constituted the world.

 

And it was to these 'Mad Dog Rationalists' that early Dialectical Marxists unwisely paid heed.

 

[On the pernicious nature of Idealism and why many still opt for it (several of which motivating factors unfortunately apply with equal measure to Marxist dialecticians), see: 'Idealism: A Victorian Horror-Story, Parts I and II', in Stove (1991), pp.83-177. (However, in relation to Stove's work, readers should take note of the caveats and warnings posted here.)]

 

This also helps explain why so many DM-fans end up as open-and-honest Mystics, or even Buddhists! Here is what I have written about that elsewhere at this site:

 

Indeed, the esoteric language Hegel himself used suggests, to those who dote on jargon like this, that there are 'ineffable truths' that lie beyond language, toward which Hegel and those who follow him can only hope to grope, and which can be grasped (in howsoever an attenuated form) by those who 'understand' dialectics -- i.e., exclusively those capable of contemplating these 'ineffables' directly via the 'concepts' to which Hegel alluded, as opposed to the actual words he used, but by no one else. Of course, that is only to be expected of genuine mystics, or, indeed, expected of the aspiring DM-Mystics who litter Dialectical Marxism.

 

This helps explain why so many dialecticians express a liking for Daoism and/or Buddhism, and why some even revert to open and honest mysticism (Michael Kosok, Roy Bhaskar, Andrew Collier, Graham Priest, and Terry Eagleton perhaps being the latest examples). Indeed, the tendency for radicals to become mystics is what motivated Lenin to write MEC. This also explains why Counterfire, home of leading Dialectical Marxists and ex-members of the UK-SWP, can publish an article extolling the virtues of Buddhism, even roping Marx himself in this! On that, see Ledwith (2023). It also explains why dialectician extraordinaire, Graham Priest, accepts some form of Buddhism. On that, see here and Priest (2014). Then there is this unfortunate video about Buddhism and Science, by Priest. In addition, he has written about the use of "contradictions" in Buddhism; cf., this on-line article by Yasuo Deguchi, Jay Garfield and Graham Priest (this links to a PDF). No wonder he also has a penchant for Hegel and the latter's dalliance with "contradictions".

 

[I have said more about the connection between Daoism and 'dialectics', especially the Maoist strain, in Note 07b. A detailed survey of the close link that exists between Daoism and Maoist 'Dialectics' can now be accessed here.]

 

If, as tradition would have it, both the world and the human 'mind' are 'reflections' of 'God's Mind', then the 'inter-reflection' between 'mind' and world, world and 'mind', would appear to guarantee that philosophical thought, left to its own devices, was capable of penetrating beneath 'surface appearances', right to the heart of 'Being Itself', uncovering its 'hidden essence'. General laws thus seemed to be either the result of these 'self-directed' concepts, which accurately captured or mirrored nature's deepest secrets, or they were in effect their constitutive cause (i.e., what Aristotle might have called their material and formal cause).

 

Hermetic Philosophers imagined that the Microcosm of the human 'mind' reflected the Macrocosm of 'God's' creation because both were the same 'substance', 'Mind'. As we have seen, that idea dates back at least to Plato:

 

"If mind and true opinion are two distinct classes, then I say that there certainly are these self-existent ideas unperceived by sense, and apprehended only by the mind; if, however, as some say, true opinion differs in no respect from mind, then everything that we perceive through the body is to be regarded as most real and certain. But we must affirm that to be distinct, for they have a distinct origin and are of a different nature; the one is implanted in us by instruction, the other by persuasion; the one is always accompanied by true reason, the other is without reason; the one cannot be overcome by persuasion, but the other can: and lastly, every man may be said to share in true opinion, but mind is the attribute of the gods and of very few men. Wherefore also we must acknowledge that there is one kind of being which is always the same, uncreated and indestructible, never receiving anything into itself from without, nor itself going out to any other, but invisible and imperceptible by any sense, and of which the contemplation is granted to intelligence only." [Plato (1997c), 51e-52a, pp.1254-55. I have used the on-line version here. Bold emphases added. The published edition translates the third set of highlighted words as follows: "It is indivisible -- it cannot be perceived by the senses at all -- and it is the role of the understanding to study it." Cornford renders it thus: "[It is] invisible and otherwise imperceptible; that, in fact, which thinking has for its object." (Cornford (1997), p.192.) See also Note 1b.]

 

And we have already seen Descartes rehearse similar thoughts and ideas:

 

"The mathematical truths which you call eternal have been laid down by God and depend on him entirely no less than the rest of his creatures. Indeed to say that these truths are independent of God is to talk of him as if he were Jupiter or Saturn and to subject him to the Styx and the Fates. Please do not hesitate to assert and proclaim everywhere that it is God who has laid down these laws in nature just as a king lays down laws in his kingdom." [Descartes (1991), p.23. Letter to Mersenne, 15/04/1630. Bold emphasis added.]

 

Mystical versions of this doctrine (which found their way into NeoPlatonism and Christian Hermeticism) held that union with 'God' was of a piece with union with Nature (or, rather, with its 'Essence'), which helps explain the origin of what turned out to be the main problematic of German Idealism: 'Subject-Object Identity'. Here is Engels on this topic (and by "thinking" he clearly meant "thinking subject"):

 

"The great basic question of all philosophy, especially of more recent philosophy, is that concerning the relation of thinking and being. From the very early times when men, still completely ignorant of the structure of their own bodies, under the stimulus of dream apparitions came to believe that their thinking and sensation were not activities of their bodies, but of a distinct soul which inhabits the body and leaves it at death -- from this time men have been driven to reflect about the relation between this soul and the outside world.... But the question of the relation of thinking and being had yet another side: in what relation do our thoughts about the world surrounding us stand to this world itself? Is our thinking capable of the cognition of the real world? Are we able in our ideas and notions of the real world to produce a correct reflection of reality? In philosophical language this question is called the question of identity of thinking and being, and the overwhelming majority of philosophers give an affirmative answer to this question.... The most telling refutation of this as of all other philosophical crotchets is practice -- namely, experiment and industry. If we are able to prove the correctness of our conception of a natural process by making it ourselves, bringing it into being out of its conditions and making it serve our own purposes into the bargain, then there is an end to the Kantian ungraspable 'thing-in-itself'. The chemical substances produced in the bodies of plants and animals remained just such 'things-in-themselves' until organic chemistry began to produce them one after another, whereupon the 'thing-in-itself' became a thing for us...." [Engels (1888), pp.593-95. Bold emphases added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Spelling modified to agree with UK English. Paragraphs merged.]

 

In Hegel's system, the union between the 'Knower and the Known' was itself guaranteed by the correct application of Divine -- aka 'Dialectical' -- 'Logic'. The Mystical 'Rosicrucian Wedding' had finally been consummated.18a

 

As one on-line commentator pointed out in relation to Engels's version of this idea (and in response to John Rees):

 

"Thus our dialectical thought process is a reflection of a material dialectic; we are able to grasp and understand nature because we are able to understand its essential processes. This is horribly close to Hegel's claim that the root of all being is the Concept, and that we are able to understand the world because it is, at its base, rational. Now, if [Engels is] saying that the mind mirrors the world that's one thing, as the distinction between mind and matter is preserved. But...it seems that he's in fact saying that we can grasp the world because we think dialectically, and because the world is itself dialectical. There is therefore an identity between the two, rather than an opposition. This would seem to convict him of idealism, of replicating the same errors previously identified in Hegel: namely, the transposition of human agency onto some kind of cosmic force." [Quoted from here, accessed 06/06/2024. Bold emphases added; paragraphs merged. Minor typo corrected.]     

 

Empiricist theories arrived at vaguely analogous conclusions, but from a completely different direction, expressed in markedly different language.19

 

Either way -- as Hegel himself pointed out -- every current, branch and form of Traditional Philosophy sooner or later found its way back to the Ideal home from whence it had evolved:

 

"Every philosophy is essentially an idealism or at least has idealism for its principle, and the question then is only how far this principle is carried out." [Hegel (1999), pp.154-55; §316. Bold added.]20

 

Nevertheless, the serious problems this approach to knowledge brought in its train re-surfaced in DM, only now in a much more acute form. Dialecticians claim that their system somehow reverses the above process of cognition (in order to neutralise its obvious Idealist implications, albeit after its "mystical shell" has been removed, leaving behind its "rational kernel" -- I am quoting Marx here, not to censure him but to criticise the use to which his words have been put; I have taken a completely different view of them, drawn from the Afterword to the Second Edition of Das Kapital, in Essay Nine Part One). Hence, dialecticians claim their theory has rotated Hegel's system through 180º, which means it now stands proudly on its own materialist legs -- hardly noticing that the Ideal backside is now located where the materialist head used to be.

 

Well, that at least helps account for all the 'hot air'...

 

However, 'logical chicanery' like this wasn't designed to operate in reverse, which is why Idealist Forward Gear always remains engaged.

 

As Essay Two has shown, dialecticians proceed as if it were quite natural, if not completely uncontroversial, to derive universal and necessary truths about nature and society from thought, from language or from 'concepts' alone. Not only do they act as if they think their laws and a priori theories are applicable to all of reality, for all of time, they have to talk this way. It comes with the territory.

 

[Those who think that the above allegations are wildly inaccurate are invited to check Essay Two for themselves (link above), along with the scores of quotations from the DM-classics (and even more from secondary DM-theorists), which confirm their accuracy. Why they think this way is revealed in Essay Nine Part Two.]

 

Here is part of the reason: The Dialectical Macrocosm and the Dialectical Microcosm are two sides of the same coin. That is because this entire world-view was inherited (in a modified form) from Aristocratic Greek thinkers who designed it and fully intended it should work this way. These ancient "ruling-ideas" now rule 'radical' brains because, to DM-fans, they seem so natural, so quintessentially 'philosophical', who could possibly doubt them (other than political enemies)? If DM-theorists didn't think and talk like this, they wouldn't have a 'genuine philosophy' to call their own, certainly not one that Lenin claimed was the final and legitimate heir of the 'very best elements' of 'western thought':

 

"The history of philosophy and the history of social science show with perfect clarity that there is nothing resembling 'sectarianism' in Marxism, in the sense of its being a hidebound, petrified doctrine, a doctrine which arose away from the high road of the development of world civilisation. On the contrary, the genius of Marx consists precisely in his having furnished answers to questions already raised by the foremost minds of mankind. His doctrine emerged as the direct and immediate continuation of the teachings of the greatest representatives of philosophy, political economy and socialism. The Marxist doctrine is omnipotent because it is true. It is comprehensive and harmonious, and provides men with an integral world outlook irreconcilable with any form of superstition, reaction, or defence of bourgeois oppression. It is the legitimate successor to the best that man produced in the nineteenth century, as represented by German philosophy, English political economy and French socialism." [Lenin, Three Sources and Component Parts of Marxism. Bold emphases alone added. Paragraphs merged.]20a

 

Hence, DM-theorists are lapel-clutchingly desperate to be seen as the rightful heirs of the 'western' philosophical tradition -- which is, of course, the intellectual equivalent of wanting to 'hang with the cool kids'.

 

It is also one of the main reasons HCDs both dislike and disregard my Essays; my work repudiates this entire tradition and (as they see things) it compounds that 'error' by failing to use post-Kantian philosophical gobbledygook. In the meantime, they have well and truly 'sold their radical souls' to these ruling-class forms-of-thought, which means they resent anyone who has the temerity to point this out, or whose refusal to join in a sell-out of this magnitude exposes their inexcusable compromise and ideological complicity with the class enemy.

 

Harsh words indeed, but they are as merited as they have been well earned.

 

Nevertheless, if DM-abstractions provide the 'metaphysical glue' that supposedly binds together what would otherwise be rather fragmentary, even unreliable, knowledge -- or which even enables the formation of knowledge, as Lenin argued --, what else could these remnants of Ancient Greek Word-Magic imply about Nature except that it is just One Big Idea? Our knowledge is guaranteed by abstraction because, deep down, the world is just One Big Abstraction.

 

"Logical concepts are subjective so long as they remain 'abstract,' in their abstract form, but at the same time they express the Thing-in-themselves. Nature is both concrete and abstract, both phenomenon and essence, both moment and relation." [Lenin (1961), p.208. Italic emphases in the original.]

 

"Thought proceeding from the concrete to the abstract -- provided it is correct (NB)… -- does not get away from the truth but comes closer to it. The abstraction of matter, the law of nature, the abstraction of value, etc., in short all scientific (correct, serious, not absurd) abstractions reflect nature more deeply, truly and completely." [Ibid., p.171. Italic emphases in the original.]

 

Perhaps we can also now understand why Lenin argued this way: DM is the Ideal Offspring of an equally Ideal Family. And this family tree stretches right back into the mists of ruling-class time.

 

That also explains why DM-theorists think matter is abstract.

 

Of course, dialecticians never tire of telling us that their 'abstractions' have been derived from nature and society (via some sort of 'law of cognition'), and have been "tested in practice":

 

"Testing by facts or by practice respectively, is to be found here in each step of the analysis." [Lenin (1961), p.318.]

 

Unfortunately, the above considerations cast serious doubt on the validity of that claim.

 

Nevertheless, as the Essays published at this site unfold, these 'infant doubts' will mature quite alarmingly.

 

Collective Error Over General Terms

 

Nominalism aside, traditional theories concerning the origin and nature of Abstract General Ideas all shared the belief that 'the mind' was somehow capable of ascending from particulars (given in experience) to the general (not so given) -- or, perhaps the other way round (depending on which Idealist was telling the tale): 'the mind' was supposedly capable of 'ascertaining' general 'concepts' by unifying particulars under an 'objective law', or by means of something called an "apprehension". The first alternative envisioned this taking place as 'the mind' progressively disregarded the unique ("accidental" or "inessential") properties and predicates (these two terms/concepts now irreversibly conflated) belonging to particulars given in experience. The second had 'the mind' searching for wider connections in order to 'uncover', or expose, the hidden 'essences' that lay behind 'appearances'.21

 

That alone should have prompted anyone who at least claimed to be materialists to pause for more than just a moment. What on earth could be so materialist about a theory that has to withdraw from the material into the Ideal, or which had to disregard multiple features of the material world in such an irresponsible and peremptory manner, in order to 'advance knowledge'?

 

The pay-off, so we have been led to believe, was the greater 'explanatory power and understanding' both approaches supposedly enabled. But, if the latter is gained at the expense of populating the world with nearly as many 'abstractions' as there are material bodies, and which, paradoxically, turn out to be 'more real' than those material bodies themselves(!) -- since these 'abstractions' are required in order to explain the nature and behaviour of objects and process in 'reality', not the other way round -- one wonders what sort of victory has been won over Idealism. One would have thought the word "capitulation" was more appropriate. At best, it would represent a 'victory' of the same order, perhaps, as that of the Church over 'sin', 'crime' and war -- or, that of Social Democracy over Capitalism. This question becomes all the more ironic when it is recalled that dialectics is incapable of explaining anything (which the reader will, I am sure, increasingly appreciate as the Essays published at this site unfold), a disconcerting outcome further compounded by the additional fact that Dialectical Marxism has been such an abject, long-term failure. [Those two features aren't, of course, unrelated.]

 

In fact, the opposite outcome looks far more likely (which is yet another rather fitting 'dialectical inversion'' for readers to ponder). That is because this entire approach is based on the ancient, Idealist dogma that the material world is somehow insufficient to itself, that it isn't fully real, and that it 'essentially' depends on something that is 'real', which has therefore to be immaterial for the material world to be 'real', an idea that itself depends on the mystical dogma that the universe requires an underlying superstructure of Ideal Principles to make it work, if not allow it to exist or even keep it in existence.

 

The result is that DM-theorists (would you credit it!) also believe that matter is far too crude and lifeless to do anything on its own (recall: Engels, taking his lead from Hegel, actually called matter an "abstraction"!) -- even though this appears to be all that nature has to offer. According to these Idealists (and their enablers in Dialectical Marxism), nature also requires a 'Logic' of some sort to make it tick, give it life and even lend it 'substance'.

 

"Contradiction is the root of all movement and life, and it is only in so far as it contains a contradiction that anything moves and has impulse and activity." [Hegel (1999), p.439, §956. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"So long as we consider things at rest and lifeless, each one by itself…we do not run up against any contradictions in them…. But the position is quite different as soon as we consider things in their motion, their change, their life, their reciprocal influence. Then we immediately become involved in contradictions. Motion itself is a contradiction…. [T]here is a contradiction objectively present in things and processes themselves, a contradiction is moreover an actual force...." [Engels (1976), pp.152-53. Bold emphases added.]

 

"Dialectics…prevails throughout nature…. [T]he motion through opposites which asserts itself everywhere in nature, and which by the continual conflict of the opposites…determines the life of nature." [Engels (1954), p.211. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"The identity of opposites…is the recognition…of the contradictory, mutually exclusive, opposite tendencies in all phenomena and processes of nature…. The condition for the knowledge of all processes of the world in their 'self-movement,' in their spontaneous development, in their real life, is the knowledge of them as a unity of opposites. Development is the 'struggle' of opposites. The two basic (or two possible? or two historically observable?) conceptions of development (evolution) are: development as decrease and increase, as repetition, and development as a unity of opposites (the division of a unity into mutually exclusive opposites and their reciprocal relation). In the first conception of motion, self-movement, its driving force, its source, its motive, remains in the shade (or this source is made external -- God, subject, etc.). In the second conception the chief attention is directed precisely to knowledge of the source of 'self'-movement. The first conception is lifeless, pale and dry. The second is living. The second alone furnishes the key to the 'self-movement' of everything existing; it alone furnishes the key to the 'leaps,' to the 'break in continuity,' to the 'transformation into the opposite,' to the destruction of the old and the emergence of the new. The unity (coincidence, identity, equal action) of opposites is conditional, temporary, transitory, relative. The struggle of mutually exclusive opposites is absolute, just as development and motion are absolute." [Lenin (1961), pp.357-58. Bold emphases alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Paragraphs merged.]

 

"The law of contradiction in things, that is, the law of the unity of opposites, is the basic law of materialist dialectics.... As opposed to the metaphysical world outlook, the world outlook of materialist dialectics holds that in order to understand the development of a thing we should study it internally and in its relations with other things; in other words, the development of things should be seen as their internal and necessary self-movement, while each thing in its movement is interrelated with and interacts on the things around it. The fundamental cause of the development of a thing is not external but internal; it lies in the contradictoriness within the thing. There is internal contradiction in every single thing, hence its motion and development.... The universality or absoluteness of contradiction has a twofold meaning. One is that contradiction exists in the process of development of all things, and the other is that in the process of development of each thing a movement of opposites exists from beginning to end....There is nothing that does not contain contradictions; without contradiction nothing would exist.... Thus it is already clear that contradiction exists universally and is in all processes, whether in the simple or in the complex forms of motion, whether in objective phenomena or ideological phenomena.... Contradiction is universal and absolute, it is present in the process of the development of all things and permeates every process from beginning to end...." [Mao (1937), pp.311-18. Bold emphases added; paragraphs merged.]

 

Well, we all know which religion is based on anthropomorphisms like these -- and, on a belief in The Logos.

 

Spoiler: apparently, in one form or another, the vast majority! We have already seen this from the Gospel of John:

 

"In the beginning was the Word [λόγος -- logos], and the Word was with God, and the Word was God. He was with God in the beginning. Through him all things were made; without him nothing was made that has been made. In him was life, and that life was the light of all mankind." [John 1:1-4. Bold emphasis added.]

 

And this also helps explain why Lenin could declare that he preferred intelligent Idealism to "crude materialism". Plainly, he hadn't fully shaken off the regressive influence of the sort of Christian Mysticism that had been forced down his throat as a child (his family was Russian Orthodox, into which faith Lenin had been baptised and inducted):

 

"Intelligent idealism is closer to intelligent materialism than stupid materialism. Dialectical idealism instead of intelligent; (sic) metaphysical, undeveloped, dead, crude, rigid instead of stupid." [Lenin (1961), p.274. Bold emphasis added. (I explain why he said this, here.)]

 

From this, it is quite clear that Lenin meant "Dialectical idealism is closer to intelligent materialism than crude materialism...".22

 

Many other dialecticians quote this passage, always approvingly -- for example, here, here, here, here and here (the last of these links to a PDF).

 

By nailing their colours to this (class-compromised) mast, DM-fans have unfortunately placed themselves on the side of the 'Gods'.

 

Diodorus Siculus was, I think, the originator of that particular trope:

 

"When the Gigantes about Pallene chose to begin war against the immortals, Herakles fought on the side of the gods, and slaying many of the Sons of Ge [or Gaia, the 'Earth Goddess' -- RL] he received the highest approbation. For Zeus gave the name of Olympian only to those gods who had fought by his side, in order that the courageous, by being adorned by so honourable a title, might be distinguished by this designation from the coward; and of those who were born of mortal women he considered only Dionysos and Herakles worthy of this name." [Diodorus Siculus, Library of History 4.15.1.]

 

That metaphor alludes to an image painted in Hesiod's Theogony (links at the end), later put to use by Plato in his dialogue, Sophist (i.e., Plato 1997b), which is one of his more profound surviving works. Indeed, the Sophist and two of his other dialogues -- Theaetetus (Plato (1997e)) and Parmenides (Plato (1997d)) -- are the principle source of much of subsequent Idealism.

 

The following excerpt from the Sophist reports on a conversation between an Eleatic "Stranger" (who appears to be a follower of Parmenides) and a character called "Theaetetus":

 

"Stranger. We are far from having exhausted the more exact thinkers who treat of being and not-being. But let us be content to leave them, and proceed to view those who speak less precisely; and we shall find as the result of all, that the nature of being is quite as difficult to comprehend as that of not-being....

 

"...There appears to be a sort of war of Giants and Gods going on amongst them; they are fighting with one another about the nature of essence.

 

"Theaetetus. How is that?

 

"Stranger. Some of them are dragging down all things from heaven and from the unseen to earth, and they literally grasp in their hands rocks and trees; of these they lay hold, and obstinately maintain, that the things only which can be touched or handled have being or essence, because they define being and body as one, and if any one else says that what is not a body exists they altogether despise him, and will hear of nothing but body.

 

"Theaetetus. I have often met with such men, and terrible fellows they are.

 

"Stranger. And that is the reason why their opponents cautiously defend themselves from above, out of an unseen world, mightily contending that true essence consists of certain intelligible and incorporeal ideas; the bodies of the materialists, which by them are maintained to be the very truth, they break up into little bits by their arguments, and affirm them to be, not essence, but generation and motion. Between the two armies, Theaetetus, there is always an endless conflict raging concerning these matters.

 

"Theaetetus. True.

 

"Stranger. Let us ask each party in turn, to give an account of that which they call essence.

 

"Theaetetus. How shall we get it out of them?

 

"Stranger. With those who make being to consist in ideas, there will be less difficulty, for they are civil people enough; but there will be very great difficulty, or rather an absolute impossibility, in getting an opinion out of those who drag everything down to matter. Shall I tell you what we must do?

 

"Theaetetus. What?

 

"Stranger. Let us, if we can, really improve them; but if this is not possible, let us imagine them to be better than they are, and more willing to answer in accordance with the rules of argument, and then their opinion will be more worth having; for that which better men acknowledge has more weight than that which is acknowledged by inferior men. Moreover we are no respecters of persons, but seekers after truth." [Plato (1997b), pp.267-68, 246a-246d. I have used the on-line version here. Bold emphases added.]

 

[As noted earlier, this battle is described in Hesiod's Theogony (lines 675-715), a copy of which is available here.]

 

Again: from this it is quite clear that Marxist Dialecticians are far closer to the 'Idealist Gods' than they are to the 'Materialist Giants'!23

 

Clearly, that further explains why DM-theorists insist matter is just an 'abstraction'.

 

They are, if nothing else, consistent team-players -- alas, for the wrong team!

 

Abstractionism: Have We Come To Bury It -- Or Praise It?

 

You Have Nothing To Lose But Your Confusion

 

Unfortunately, unlike Capitalism, Abstractionism has attracted few effective gravediggers, and those it has managed to accrue have proved to be even less successful at overthrowing the latter than workers have been at toppling the former. That is largely because these would-be-undertakers were (and still are) far more content simply to underline the psychological impossibility of the 'abstractionist project' than they are to expose its logical flaws --, or, indeed, reveal its ideologically-compromised origin and motivating factors.

 

So, this "ruling idea" lumbers on to "rule" another day and another compliant DM-fan.

 

More recently, however, Abstractionism has been subjected to a series of destructive critiques, but still it limps along. That in turn is partly because many of those who avowedly came to bury it -- unlike Shakespeare's Mark Antony -- ended up praising it by emulating it. In so doing they only succeeded in breathing new life into its moribund corpse, and that they did by inventing brand new 'essentialist' theories of their own.24

 

Public Criteria Vs Private Gain

 

As we have seen, an ability to talk about cats and dogs, for instance, depends on an already established grasp (in use) of the relevant general terms (otherwise, plainly, nothing could be said about these animals). This fact needs no explanation, nor could one be offered that didn't also have to employ the very language which required explaining in the first place --, i.e., general terms.25

 

If the above observations have anything going for them, it perhaps lies in the fact they re-direct our attention away from any attempt to investigate (obscure) 'internal processes' and 'privately executed' capacities -- supposedly possessed by each 'lone abstractor' --, and re-directs it toward socially acquired, publicly performed, checkable skills and abilities, in order to understand the linguistic expression of generality, and how it is connected with socially-acquired, socially-legitimated and socially-disseminated knowledge.

 

Of course, only an anti-materialist would register a complaint at this point.

 

Which is why emphasis has been placed at this site -- in accord with Marx's advice -- on our use of ordinary language in a public domain. It is also why serious questions have been raised about the ability we are all supposed to possess of being able to 'squeeze abstract epistemological juice' out of 'desiccated discourse', in the 'privacy of our own heads'.

 

In contrast once more, the approach adopted here means that human cognition is open to view, subject to public scrutiny and inter-subjective verification, unlike the mysterious, 'internal rituals' that supposedly constitute the 'process of abstraction' --, which, it is worth recalling, no one seems able to describe with any clarity, and which even fails to deliver what had all along been advertised for it.26

 

Particular Problems With 'Dialectical Generality'

 

It has been argued at length (both above and in Part One) that instead of beginning with the general as a way of advancing toward knowledge of the particular, the DM-'process of abstraction' in fact turns general words into the Proper Names of Abstract Particulars -- and it then goes precisely nowhere with them. That not only distorts the way language actually works (destroying the capacity it has for saying anything at all along the way), it stalls the 'dialectical juggernaut' in its tracks even before it can be tested in practice.

 

Much of the rest of Essay Three is aimed at elaborating upon, and then substantiating, these sweeping accusations.

 

Anti-Abstractionism

 

'Mental Strip-Tease'?

 

[This used to form part of Note 24.]

 

While we are at it, what exactly are the common features that can be abstracted from (or even attributed to) all shades of, say, the colour blue? Or, the notes played on the trombone or even a set of bagpipes? What is common to the taste of different wines or different herbs? Or, the feel of silk, wool and nylon? Or, the smell of roses, honeysuckle and wet dogs?

 

Admittedly, in relation to several of the above the use of other general terms might come into play -- but they, too, will attract similar questions. For instance, an appeal might be made to certain tastes or aromas that can be detected in different wines -- such as: "a fruity bouquet". But, once more, what are the common features of "fruity bouquets"? One answer to that question might involve a reference to the taste or smell of Lychees, for example. But, what are the common features of the taste/smell of Lychees? And so on, ad infinitem.

 

[I owe this general point to Geach (1957); on this see also Cowie (2002) and Laurence and Margolis (2012), pp.1-10. Of course, considerations like these raise issues concerning the relation between science and 'common sense', a topic entered into in more detail below. This topic also involves the ancient and erroneous idea that the properties of bodies can be treated as objects in their own right, an idea that is not unconnected with the equally odd idea that there can be 'bare particulars;' -- that is objects that have lost all their properties (mentioned earlier), either actually or in thought alone. I will have more to say about this presently.]

 

As argued earlier:

 

Who has ever seen a 'general cat'? What would 'one' even look like? Who has ever eaten 'general fruit'? What would 'one' of those look like? How would 'one' even taste? Who has ever smelt a general rose or felt a general pain? That is why the formation of 'the general idea of a cat', or 'of fruit', required the exercise of the 'mental skill of abstraction', or so we have been told. No one has ever even claimed to have 'abstracted' anything using just their eyes, their ears, their nose, their finger tips or their taste buds. In this area of 'knowledge' the senses in the end drop out as irrelevant -- or, at best, they are merely conveyers of data, lowly 'messengers' -- since the body was held in Platonic and Neoplatonic contempt in the Rationalist/Christian tradition. Hence, as history has shown, this branch of Philosophy seemed only too happy to kill the messenger.

 

[But, what could possibly count as the general smell of a rose? Or even the smell of a general rose? What could conceivably count as the general experience of pain? Or even the experience of general pain? What actually is a 'general pain', a 'general experience' or even a 'general rose'? Has anyone ever felt a general itch? Faced with such questions, abstractionism appears to be falling apart before our eyes (no pun intended) -- or, rather, before our general eyes....]

 

That is of course why Abstractionists and Dialectical Marxists prefer to talk instead about "essence" -- as in, the "essence of an individual" (such as an apple, a cat, or a man). Here for example are Marx and Engels again, critiquing Hegel:

 

"The mystery of critical presentation…is the mystery of speculative, of Hegelian construction.… If from real apples, pears, strawberries and almonds I form the general idea 'Fruit', if I go further and imagine that my abstract idea 'Fruit', derived from real fruit, is an entity existing outside me, is indeed the true essence of the pear, the apple, etc., then -- in the language of speculative philosophy -- I am declaring that 'Fruit' is the 'Substance' of the pear, the apple, the almond, etc. I am saying, therefore, that to be an apple is not essential to the apple; that what is essential to these things is not their real existence, perceptible to the senses, but the essence that I have abstracted from them and then foisted on them, the essence of my idea -- 'Fruit'…. Particular real fruits are no more than semblances whose true essence is 'the substance' -- 'Fruit'…. Having reduced the different real fruits to the one 'fruit' of abstraction -- 'the Fruit', speculation must, in order to attain some semblance of real content, try somehow to find its way back from 'the Fruit', from the Substance to the diverse, ordinary real fruits, the pear, the apple, the almond etc. It is as hard to produce real fruits from the abstract idea 'the Fruit' as it is easy to produce this abstract idea from real fruits. Indeed, it is impossible to arrive at the opposite of an abstraction without relinquishing the abstraction….

 

"The main interest for the speculative philosopher is therefore to produce the existence of the real ordinary fruits and to say in some mysterious way that there are apples, pears, almonds and raisins. But the apples, pears, almonds and raisins that we rediscover in the speculative world are nothing but semblances of apples, semblances of pears, semblances of almonds and semblances of raisins, for they are moments in the life of 'the Fruit', this abstract creation of the mind, and therefore themselves abstract creations of the mind…. When you return from the abstraction, the supernatural creation of the mind, 'the Fruit', to real natural fruits, you give on the contrary the natural fruits a supernatural significance and transform them into sheer abstractions. Your main interest is then to point out the unity of 'the Fruit' in all the manifestations of its life…that is, to show the mystical interconnection between these fruits, how in each of them 'the Fruit' realizes itself by degrees and necessarily progresses, for instance, from its existence as a raisin to its existence as an almond. Hence the value of the ordinary fruits no longer consists in their natural qualities, but in their speculative quality, which gives each of them a definite place in the life-process of 'the Absolute Fruit'.

 

"The ordinary man does not think he is saying anything extraordinary when he states that there are apples and pears. But when the philosopher expresses their existence in the speculative way he says something extraordinary. He performs a miracle by producing the real natural objects, the apple, the pear, etc., out of the unreal creation of the mind 'the Fruit'…. It goes without saying that the speculative philosopher accomplishes this continuous creation only by presenting universally known qualities of the apple, the pear, etc., which exist in reality, as determining features invented by him, by giving the names of the real things to what abstract reason alone can create, to abstract formulas of reason, finally, by declaring his own activity, by which he passes from the idea of an apple to the idea of a pear, to be the self-activity of the Absolute Subject, 'the Fruit.' In the speculative way of speaking, this operation is called comprehending Substance as Subject, as an inner process, as an Absolute Person, and this comprehension constitutes the essential character of Hegel's method." [Marx and Engels (1975a), pp.72-75. Bold emphases alone added. Several paragraphs merged.]

 

Here is Lenin:

 

"Logical concepts are subjective so long as they remain 'abstract,' in their abstract form, but at the same time they express the Thing-in-themselves. Nature is both concrete and abstract, both phenomenon and essence, both moment and relation." [Lenin (1961), p.208. Bold emphasis alone added.]

 

"Such must also be the method of exposition (i.e., study) of dialectics in general.... To begin with what is the simplest, most ordinary, common, etc., with any proposition: the leaves of a tree are green; John is a man: Fido is a dog, etc. Here already we have dialectics (as Hegel's genius recognised): the individual is the universal.... Consequently, the opposites (the individual is opposed to the universal) are identical: the individual exists only in the connection that leads to the universal. The universal exists only in the individual and through the individual. Every individual is (in one way or another) a universal. Every universal is (a fragment, or an aspect, or the essence of) an individual. Every universal only approximately embraces all the individual objects. Every individual enters incompletely into the universal, etc., etc. Every individual is connected by thousands of transitions with other kinds of individuals (things, phenomena, processes) etc. Here already we have the elements, the germs, the concepts of necessity, of objective connection in nature, etc. Here already we have the contingent and the necessary, the phenomenon and the essence; for when we say: John is a man, Fido is a dog, this is a leaf of a tree, etc., we disregard a number of attributes as contingent; we separate the essence from the appearance, and counterpose the one to the other. Thus in any proposition we can (and must) disclose as in a 'nucleus' ('cell') the germs of all the elements of dialectics, and thereby show that dialectics is a property of all human knowledge in general. And natural science shows us (and here again it must be demonstrated in any simple instance) objective nature with the same qualities, the transformation of the individual into the universal, of the contingent into the necessary, transitions, modulations, and the reciprocal connection of opposites. Dialectics is the theory of knowledge of (Hegel and) Marxism. This is the 'aspect' of the matter (it is not 'an aspect' but the essence of the matter) to which Plekhanov, not to speak of other Marxists, paid no attention." [Lenin (1961), pp.359-60. Bold emphases alone added; paragraphs merged. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

Here is Marcuse:

 

"The doctrine of Essence seeks to liberate knowledge from the worship of 'observable facts' and from the scientific common sense that imposes this worship.... The real field of knowledge is not the given fact about things as they are, but the critical evaluation of them as a prelude to passing beyond their given form. Knowledge deals with appearances in order to get beyond them. 'Everything, it is said, has an essence, that is, things really are not what they immediately show themselves. There is therefore something more to be done than merely rove from one quality to another and merely to advance from one qualitative to quantitative, and vice versa: there is a permanence in things, and that permanent is in the first instance their Essence.' The knowledge that appearance and essence do not jibe is the beginning of truth. The mark of dialectical thinking is the ability to distinguish the essential from the apparent process of reality and to grasp their relation." [Marcuse (1973), pp.145-46. Marcuse is here quoting Hegel (1975), p.163, §112. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions employed at this site. Minor typo corrected.]

 

And Spirkin:

 

"The concept of essence and phenomenon. All thinking people want to get at the essence. They seek it like hidden treasure, which lies at the heart of things and controls them. Essence may be considered in global terms, as the ultimate foundation of the universe, in terms of various categories, such as the essence of the human being, for example, and in the sense of the main thing in an individual object.... The essence of any specific individual is that which he is by virtue of his nature. It is the essential principle in a person, the core of his 'ego'. One could say that it is the special thing in any given person that he cannot lose without ceasing to be himself. Essence is the organising principle of connection between the basic elements or aspects of an object. It is a kind of thread upon which everything hangs; cut it and the whole assembly falls to pieces. Nothing is left but elusive particles and the general order is destroyed. Essence is closely related to content. In fact, it is content, but not the whole content, only the main, basic part of it. Essence is related to all categories, to quality, for example. But quality does not exhaust essence. It expresses only one of its aspects. To reveal essence one must discover measure or proportion, the unity of quality and quantity. The path to essence lies through the categories of cause and law. Essence is an integral category, which embraces structure, part and whole, individual, particular and general, content and quality, proportion, contradiction, causality and law; it may also be regarded as an interweaving of the laws of the existence and functioning of an object. As the fundamental basis of the existence of an object essence manifests itself fully or partially, in the form of mere appearance -- as a phenomenon.

 

"What is a phenomenon? It is a manifestation of essence, which possesses true actuality only as a consequence of certain forms of its self-manifestation. Just as leaves, flowers, branches and fruit express in an external form the essence of a plant, so ethical, aesthetic, political, philosophical and scientific ideas express the essence of a certain social system. The concept of phenomenon may be understood as a manifestation of something underlying, profound. This is similar to the way we use the term 'symptom' as the external manifestation of the essence of some disease, a headache, for example. Essence, on the other hand, is the principle and foundation of a certain mode of the external expression of things. Phenomenon as the external aspect is based on the internal essence. It is that in which the principle has expressed itself. What matters for a phenomenon is the result of the functioning of the principle as essence. The categories of essence and phenomenon characterise the interdependence of processes that take place in reality and the level to which thought has penetrated its object, whether we are still only on the surface or have broken through to the essence. A phenomenon usually expresses only some facet of essence, one of its aspects. For example, many manifestations of the essence of a certain type of malignant tumour may have been well researched, but its essence still remains an ominous secret. The essence is hidden from view while the phenomenon stands out on the surface. If essence is something general, phenomenon is individual, expressing only one element of essence; if essence is something profound, phenomenon is external, richer and more colourful; if essence is something stable and necessary, phenomenon is transient, changing and accidental....

 

"The common properties and relations of things are identified on the basis of generalisation in the form of concepts and are denoted by substantive nouns, for example, man, law, cause, etc. In each individual there may be something general, which is its essence. Why is the general intrinsically connected with the individual? Because it is the law of the birth and life of the individual. The general plays a constructive role in the emergence of the individual. The general contains a law which insistently demands that certain processes should follow a certain course in any individual phenomenon of the given class. For example, the information recorded in the molecular structures of the cellular nucleus is a general programme, in accordance with which the organism's processes of individual development occur and its hereditary features are passed on from generation to generation. The human being's generic essence in the general groundwork of heredity is transmitted from generation to generation and in unity with all the natural and social conditions creates individuality. But upon this groundwork that is common to the whole line of descent each descendant draws its own individual, unique pattern. The individual is dominated by the general, which ruthlessly 'forces' it as something transient to perish again and again for the sake of preserving the general as something stable: the individual dies but the race lives on." [Spirkin (1963), pp.106-10. Bold emphases alone added; quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Several paragraphs merged.]

 

Finally, here is Konstantinov:

 

"Essence and appearance are correlated categories. They are characterised thorough one another. Whereas essence is something general, appearance is individual, expressing only an element of essence; whereas essence is something profound and intrinsic, appearance is external, yet richer and more colourful; whereas essence is something stable and necessary, appearance is more transient, changeable and accidental. The difference between the essential and the unessential is not absolute but relative. For instance, at one time it was considered that the essential property of the chemical element was its atomic weigh. Later this essential property turned out to be the charge of the atomic nucleus. The property of atomic weight did not cease to be essential, however. It is still essential in the first approximation, essential on a less profound level (sic!), and is further explained on the basis of the charge of the atomic nucleus. Essence is expressed in its many outward manifestations. At the same time essence may not only express itself in these manifestations. When we are in the process of gaining sensory knowledge of a thing, phenomena sometimes seem to us to be not what they are in reality. This seemingness is not generated by our consciousness. It arises through our being influenced by real relationships in the objective conditions of observation. Those who thought the Sun rotated around the Earth took the seeming appearance of things for the real thing. Under capitalism the wages of the worker seem to be payment for all his work, but in reality only part of his work is paid, while the rest is appropriated by the capitalists free of charge in the form of surplus value, which constitutes the source of their profit. Thus to obtain a correct understanding of an event, to get to the bottom of it, we must critically test the evidence of immediate observation, and make a clear distinction between the seeming and the real, the superficial and the essential. Knowledge of the essence of things is the fundamental task of science. Marx wrote that if essence and appearance directly coincided, all science would be superfluous. The history of science shows that knowledge of essence is impossible without considering and analysing the various forms in which it is manifest. At the same time these various forms cannot be correctly understood without penetrating to their 'foundation', their essence." [Konstantinov (1974), pp.191-92. Bold emphases alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site; paragraphs merged

 

[Later on in this Essay I will return to consider many of the above passages (along with several others) again, in order to criticise the distinction traditionally drawn between "appearance" and "reality"/"essence" -- for example,  here and here.]

 

The ancient idea that there actually are 'essences' will be subjected to critical scrutiny in Essay Thirteen Part Two. [Some of that material has already been published in Essay Eight Part Two, in reply to an article by Scott Meikle.] While plausible sounding answers might be given to questions concerning the "essence" of various assorted animals, plants, compounds and elements (although the material published in Essay Eight Part Two casts considerable doubt even on that), none at all seem possible for many of the items mentioned above (and others that were omitted). In that case, it is worth asking what is the 'essence' of pain, of doubt, of hope, of love, of puzzlement, of error or even of a pile of dust or an irritating itch? But, the vast majority of us know how to use words associated with these phenomena, which alone shows that their correct use doesn't require there be an "essence" underpinning any of them (or it doesn't require any knowledge of that "essence", even if there were one) -- which is probably why it seems impossible to think of any such in each case. To that list we might well add the following: what is the 'essence' of a word, a comma, a question mark or a pan of spaghetti? Or, even: what is the 'essence' of essence? But these general words certainly possess meanings, which can't be related to their "essence" since they appear not to have one (or, once more, at least none that a user needs to know before she is able to use the relevant words correctly). Even if there were an 'essence' of an apple, or a cat (or even of cats in general), of water or gold, human beings were using words like "apple", "cat", "water" and "gold" for countless centuries before scientists came up with (possible) answers to such questions. That too shows the meaning even of these terms (which are among the favourite examples used by essentialists) has nothing to do with any supposed 'essence'.

 

[I will be dealing with recent objections to the sort of responses offered in the previous paragraph -- such as those posed by Hilary Putnam -- in Essay Thirteen Part Two. Until then, readers are directed to the above Essay -- as well as Hacker (2007), pp.29-56, Dupré (1993, 2002), van Brakel (2000), and VandeWall (2006).]

 

As we have so far seen, traditional theorists almost universally tend to depict properties, qualities and relations as objects in their own right that can in turn enter into their own relation with one another, This is just another example of the age-old confusion of talk about talk with talk about the world we have seen several times already. This amounts to the systematic conflation of objects in the world (and the properties and relations they can be said to exhibit or into which they may enter) with the formal devices we have in language that allow us to talk about them. No wonder this approach led to centuries of confusion, paradox, 'contradiction' and insoluble conundrum. But, instead of locating the source of these artificially-generated problems in the confusion of talk about talk with talk about the world, Traditional Theorists blamed language, 'commonsense', ordinary 'folk theory' and 'formal logic' (in the case of Hegel and his groupies). This overall approach lies behind another confused idea that there can be such things a 'bare particulars', for if an object can be (or can be thought to be) distinguished from all its properties, or it can even be separated from them (again in reality or in thought), then there must be particulars that have no properties.

 

[Those who want to descend into this theoretical fog should check out the references listed earlier. My response is based on ideas aired in Essay Four, here and in Note 13 and Note 14 of that Essay.] 

 

Based on this, one of the more bizarre aspects of the mysterious 'process of abstraction' (which is in fact little different from the method adopted, or even advocated, by many DM-theorists, something else that is rarely noticed -- an important example of which is criticised extensively in Appendix One) is the analogy often drawn between the properties an object possesses, or the relations into which it can enter, and items of clothing. As noted above, this involves a tendency to treat properties and relations as objects in their own right. [In fact, Chappell (1964) and Simons (1994) explicitly draw this analogy, and the analogy itself lies behind the use of the word "bare", anyway!] Hence, according to one version of the 'abstractive process' (dominant in the Empiricist tradition), as each outwardly unique distinguishing feature of a given particular is treated as a removable 'object', and then 'peeled off' (or "disregarded") by 'the intellect', the 'true general form' of the original object, or bearer of that property in question, is gradually supposed to 'become apparent'. In the limit, these properties and relations all belong to a 'bare particular' -- or, alternatively, the 'object itself' is just a 'bundle' of such properties and relations, there being no underlying particular that carries them all.

 

But, this peculiar disrobing ceremony takes place in the 'mind's eye', far from public scrutiny and any sort of check, uniquely accessible to those who seem capable of 'metaphysically undressing' things like tables, chairs, cats, dogs, planets and galaxies. Indeed, 'conceptual strippers' like this must be capable of deciding what has to be true, not only of all the many examples of 'the same sort' (for instance, all cats) that haven't yet been 'skinned' this way (by anyone at all, not just themselves), but also of the many more (cats, again) that no human will ever experience. All this 'fantasy surgery' is supposedly based on a brief 'internal inspection' of a seriously limited sample of such ghostly spectres, and nothing else.

 

[Incidentally, when it is pointed out that no one can check the 'internal processes' supposedly going on in anyone else's head, that isn't meant to impugn the individuals concerned or question their honesty and integrity. They could be 100% truthful and the same constraints would still apply. The issue here revolves around the lack of public scrutiny, not the honesty or the integrity of the individual involved. Even they can't check and hence validate their own 'internal processes' -- as has already been established. The words "correct" and "right" are no more applicable here than they would be in relation to someone who tried to determine their own height by simply laying the flat of their hand on the top of their head, or who tried to measure their weight by standing on one of their hands, and nothing more.]

 

However, and this should hardly need pointing out, properties don't resemble apparel in any meaningful sense. If this had ever been an apt analogy, these 'metaphysical garments' (i.e., an object's properties) should be just as shareable as items of clothing are. On that basis, dogs might legitimately be expected to be capable of singing like canaries, kettles able to recite the Gettysburg Address and dialecticians accept criticism without deflecting or becoming abusive.

 

Nevertheless, the analogy with clothing is as inapt as any could be. For one thing, it is surely a mistake to conclude that clothing is causally related to -- or organically connected with -- the body of its wearer. But, the properties of an object are linked (in many different ways) to its constitution. Colour, for example, is intimately connected with the atomic and molecular structure of the item in question -- and, of course, the light source -- to name just two of the relevant factors. For another, while clothing may perhaps serve to hide, or even hinder, the appreciation of underlying form, an object's properties advertise it, they don't mask it. They are, so to speak, 'metaphysically transparent'.

 

That is a point Hegel himself tried to make in his own obscure way. [On that, see below.] The opposite idea, of course, undermines the 'necessary connection' that is supposed to exist between an 'essence' and its 'accidents'/'properties' and threatens the 'rationality of reality' (discussed earlier -- here, here and here). It would also completely undermine Lenin's attempt to incorporate Hegel's response to Hume's criticisms of Rationalist theories of causation, which was an integral component of his version of DM.

 

Moreover, and perhaps more absurdly, properties can't be peeled away from objects as part of an invisible, 'internal disrobing ceremony'. Or, if they can, one would expect the nature of each underlying 'object' should become clearer in all its naked glory as the proceedings unfold. In fact, we find the opposite is the case as each 'metaphysical burlesque show' progresses.

 

If, for instance, a cat were to lose too many of its properties as it was 'mentally skinned', it would surely cease to be a cat. Clearly, this philosophically-flayed 'ex-cat' (or, now in fact, 'non-cat') would serve rather badly in any subsequent generalisations based on it. Indeed, strip the average moggie of enough of its properties and it would be impossible to decide whether or not the rest of the abstractive process had even been carried out on the same mammal, the same animal, or, for that matter, on the same physical object -- let alone the 'same idea' of one or more of these.

 

Furthermore, in the absence of any rules governing the 'process of abstraction' (such as where to begin, which feature to abstract first, which second -- which never) one person's abstractions would surely differ from those of the rest of the 'abstractive community'. For instance, while Abstractor A might begin by ignoring (or attributing) Tiddles's engaging purr, Abstractor B might start with her four legs, Abstractor C might commence with her shape, while Abstractor D might begin with her number (i.e., one). But, do we (should they?) ignore (or attribute) first, second or third this cat's colour, fur, fleas, whiskers, tail, intestines, shape, age...? Moreover, as part of the 'abstractive process', which number relevant to each cat is to be abstracted from it (or even attributed to it): the one cat, its two ears, its four legs, its dozen or so whiskers or the several trillion atoms of which it is composed...? [Incidentally how is it possible to ignore or abstract number? Wouldn't that leave 'an object' with no number, and then even rule out zero? But what do zero cats even look like?] And where do we stop? Are we to whittle-away from, or attribute to, this unfortunate mammal its position on the mat, the last dozen or so things it did, its current relation to the Crab Nebula..., or what?

 

Perhaps even worse: the 'disrobing analogy' pictures properties as objects that bodies or processes possess. For example, it is surely only possible to 'abstract colour' if it were treated as an individual in its own right, rather like an organ or a limb -- or even a hat or a coat -- that can be removed from a given body. This is just another untoward consequence of the 'process of abstraction' itself, whereby the general nouns and adjectives we use to speak about such properties (colour, texture, taste -- or even items of clothing) are transformed into the Proper Names of yet more Abstract Particulars (as we saw in Part One). On one version of this 'process', we end up removing a series of Abstract Particulars -- not properties, as originally intended -- from an increasing ghostly spectre. On another, we end up with the reverse of this: attributing Abstract Particulars to what in fact now amounts to an Idealist Apparition.

 

It could be objected that none of the above really matter; the results will be the same. But, how do we know? Is there a Philosophers' Rule Book to guide us? Is there an Abstractionist's Algorithm we all unconsciously (or even consciously) 'follow', somehow programmed into each of us at birth (or is it at conception)? Do we have access to a set of tried-and-tested instructions we all implicitly appear, not just to know about, but how to use/implement? Are we all instinctive abstractors, or do we need training? Are there any YouTube videos or websites that explain this process, step-by-step? [A comprehensive Google search will return a negative answer on both counts. If anyone disagrees and has found one (or even several!), please email me with the details (and links), and I'll delete much of Parts One and Two of Essay Three! Update October 2024: Since writing this, I have discovered one attempt to describe the 'process of abstraction' -- Laurence and Margolis (2012). I will say more about this failed attempt in Interlude One.] And, if it turns out that there are metaphysical disrobing protocols that determine the order in which Tiddles's qualities are to be removed from, or attributed to, her -- so that this process might be executed correctly by the entire Community of Intrepid Abstractors -- when and where did they learn them? On the other hand, if there are none, how might each aspiring abstractor know whether or not they had abstracted Tiddles the same way each time?

 

Do we all keep a (secret) Abstractor's Diary? An internal log of what we did the last time we thought about that cat -- or any cat?

 

Even if there were clear -- let alone plausible -- answers to such questions, another annoying 'difficulty' would soon block our path: it would still be impossible for anyone to check a single one of these 'abstractions' to see if they tallied with those 'produced' by anyone else -- or, for that matter, whether or not they had 'abstracted' them correctly. In fact, the word "correct" can gain no grip in such circumstances -- since, as Wittgenstein pointed out, whatever seems correct will be correct. [That would be like buying two copies of the same edition of a newspaper (on the same day) to check if the first copy had got a certain story 'right'.] But, for something to be correct it needs to be checked against a standard that isn't dependent on the subjective impression of the one doing the checking, or that relies on the very same source. And yet in relation to this 'process' and its supposed results, there is no such standard. Given this theory, everyone's notion of a cat will be private to that individual. They have no way of checking their 'abstractions' with those 'arrived at' by anyone else, which means, of course, there can be no standard, 'abstract cat' to serve as an exemplar, and hence nothing by means of which anyone's 'abstractions' might be deemed 'correct'.

 

And those strictures apply to the 'abstractions produced' by each individual abstracter. So, Abstracter E will have no way of knowing whether or not her own 'abstractions' were correct, or if they were the same as, or were different from, those 'arrived at' yesterday or even a few seconds earlier, by her! Again, it is no use appealing to memory here, since the meaning of the word "memory" is subject to the very same strictures.

 

[Of course, for anyone who accepts the HF, no memory could be trusted, anyway. Once again, it must be stressed that the sceptical conclusions reached above do not represent my views. They are only being aired to undermine abstractionism. There are far better ways of making sense of our capacity to gain knowledge, but only if the defective and radially confused traditional approach is completely abandoned.]

 

It could be objected (indeed, it has been objected by the likes of A. J. Ayer -- e.g., Ayer (1971), replied to by Rhees (1971)), that such doubts (about memory, for example) would also apply to any external or social check on the meaning or veracity of the words we use. If memory in general is thrown into question, how would anyone be able to remember the meaning of any of their words? That would appear to undermine all social theories of language and knowledge.

 

That objection misses the point. No one (other than those who accept the HF) is questioning memory, only the theory that there is a 'process of abstraction' which tells us what our words (especially general words like "memory") mean. Reject that idea, along with the traditional philosophical approach to such questions (for the reasons set out in both Parts of Essay Three, as well as Essay Twelve Part One), take Marx's advice to return to the ordinary language of the working class, and watch such pseudoproblems simply disappear.

 

Later on in this Essay I will be pointing out the following in relation to Andrew Sayer and Bertell Ollman's 'theory of abstraction':

 

Just like Ollman, Andrew Sayer's attempt to characterise this 'process' reveals that he, too, thinks it is an individualised, private skill in relation to which we all seem to be 'natural' experts:

 

"The sense in which the term ['abstract' -- RL] is used here is different [from its ordinary use -- RL]; an abstract concept, or an abstraction, isolates in thought a one-sided or partial aspect of an object." [Sayer (1992), p.87. In a footnote, Sayer adds "My use of 'abstract' and 'concrete' is, I think, equivalent to Marx's" (p.277, note 3). Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Bold emphasis alone added. The page numbers are completely different in the Second Corrected Edition, i.e., Sayer (2010), p.59 and p.187, respectively.]

 

As was the case with Ollman -- and, indeed, everyone else who has written about this obscure 'process' (many of whom have been quoted in both Parts of Essay Three) --, we aren't told by Sayer how anyone manages to do this, still less why it doesn't result in the construction of a 'private language'.

 

Indeed, this is something Ollman himself has pointed out:

 

"What, then, is distinctive about Marx's abstractions? To begin with, it should be clear that Marx's abstractions do not and cannot diverge completely from the abstractions of other thinkers both then and now. There has to be a lot of overlap. Otherwise, he would have constructed what philosophers call a 'private language,' and any communication between him and the rest of us would be impossible. How close Marx came to fall into this abyss and what can be done to repair some of the damage already done are questions I hope to deal with in a later work...." [Ollman (2003), p.63. Bold emphasis added.]

 

Well, it remains to be seen if Professor Ollman can solve a problem that has baffled everyone else for centuries -- that is, of those who have even so much as acknowledged it exists!

 

It is to Ollman's considerable credit, therefore, that he is at least aware of it.

 

In fact, Ollman is the very first dialectician I have encountered (in nigh on thirty years) who even acknowledges this 'difficulty'!

 

[Be this as it may, I have devoted Essay Thirteen Part Three to an analysis of this topic; the reader is referred there for more details. Update August  2024: After over 21 years, there is still no sign of Ollman's 'solution' to this 'problem'. Nor is there any indication that others have taken up the challenge on his behalf, or that a single DM-fan (since Ollman raised this issue) even regards this as a 'difficulty' that needs addressing!]

 

Of course, none of this fancy footwork would be necessary if Ollman recognised that even though Marx gestured in its direction, HM doesn't need this obscure 'process' (that is, where any sense can be made of it) -- or, indeed, if he acknowledged that Marx's emphasis on the social nature of knowledge and language completely undercuts abstractionism.

 

[Nor does Ollman appear to take into consideration Marx's own refutation of this 'process' in The Holy Family.]

 

Naturally, this means that there is no way this obscure process can form the basis of 'objective' science (and that remains the case even if we were to substitute "idealisation" for "abstraction"). Plainly, that is because:

 

(i) No one has access to the results of anyone else's 'mental machinations' (or 'idealisations');

 

(ii) There appear to be no rules governing the production of these 'abstractions' --, or, indeed, governing the entire 'process' itself; and, as we have just seen,

 

(iii) There is no standard of right, here.

 

By way of contrast, in the real world, agreement is invariably achieved in and by the use of publicly accessible, general terms that are already in common use, words that were present in the vernacular long before a single one of us was a twinkle in our (hypothetical) ancestral abstractors' eye.

 

[Note: I am not questioning scientific idealisation, only the claim that it is a private, internal, 'mental process'.]

 

One obvious reply to the above might be that we abstract by concentrating only on those factors that are "relevant" to the enquiry at hand. But, what are these "relevant factors"? And who decides? How might they be specified before any such enquiry even begins? Surely, in order to know what is "relevant" to the successful process of, say, 'abstracting a cat', one would already have to know how to use the general term "cat", otherwise:

 

(a) The 'abstractor' involved would have no idea what the target of her intended abstractive endeavours actually was supposed to be; and,

 

(b) The accuracy of any 'abstractions' that might emerge as a result would rightly be called into question, alongside several more such concerning the competency of the abstractor herself.

 

If the abstractor in question doesn't already know how to use the word "cat", what faith can be put in anything she subsequently 'abstracts', or even reports about these 'abstractions'? On the other hand, if each intrepid abstractor already knows how to use the word "cat" (in order to 'abstract' the 'right' object), one might well wonder what the point is of trying to 'abstract' that furry mammal in the first place? It would seem to be about as pointless as checking to see if you know your own name by looking it up in a telephone directory or on the Internet.

 

[Anyway, we have already seen that the 'process of abstraction' requires knowledge of the very concepts being 'abstracted' before they were 'abstracted', vitiating the entire exercise.]

 

Again, in response it could be argued that past experience guides us. But, how does it do that? Can any of us recall being asked about, or made to study, the heroic deeds of intrepid abstractors from the days of yore? Does past experience transform itself into a sort of personal Microsoft Office Assistant -- or these days, maybe, Cortana -- if we hit the right internal 'Help' key? But, what kind of explanation would that be of the supposedly intelligent 'process of abstraction' if it requires such a guiding hand? And where on earth did this 'inner PA' receive its training?

 

Once more, it could be objected that in the investigation of, say, the biology of cats, it is important for scientists to find out what these animals have in common with other members of the same species, family, order, class and phylum, so that relevant generalisations might be made about them. In order to do that, zoologists disregard (or attribute) certain features common to cats and concentrate on those they share with other mammals, vertebrates, living organisms, and so on --, be they morphological, ecological, behavioural, genetic or biochemical (etc.). Clearly, in each case, and at each stage, greater abstraction is required.

 

Or, so a response might try to maintain...

 

Nevertheless, if this is what "abstraction" means, it is surely synonymous with a publicly accessible and checkable set of behavioural/linguistic skills and performances, similar in all but name to description, analysis and classification (etc.). It has nothing to do with a 'private, internal skill' we are all supposed not only to possess, but also to be able to utilise effortlessly and correctly -- namely, an ability to polish rough and ready particulars into smooth general concepts. If abstraction were an occult (i.e., a hidden), inner process, then, as noted above, no two people would agree over the general idea of, say, a mammal, let alone a cat. All would have their own idiosyncratic inner, but intrinsically un-shareable and un-checkable, exemplars.

 

Again, one response to this could be that while we might use language to facilitate the transition from a private to the public arena, that doesn't impugn our abstractive skills. Unfortunately, that objection introduces topics discussed at length in Essay Thirteen Part Three, so readers are directed there for more details.

 

Nevertheless, a few preliminary remarks are worth making in response.

 

Human beings have generally managed to agree on what animals they consider belong to, say, the Class Mammalia -- i.e., especially individuals who possess the necessary education and qualifications, who also show they have the required linguistic and organisational skills/competency. We might even join with Hilary Putnam and call this a legitimate division of linguistic labour (although, without implying any acceptance of his other ideas concerning 'essentialism'). However, this doesn't include individuals who possess unspecified and mysterious 'abstractive powers'. So, for example, trainee zoologists don't gain their qualifications by demonstrating to their teachers and examiners an expertise in the 'inner dissection' or 'internal processing' of 'mental images', 'ideas' and 'concepts'. The same is true of qualified and practising zoologists. In fact, and on the contrary, they all have to demonstrate their mastery of highly specialised techniques, relevant terminology and current theory, which skills they are required to exhibit publicly, showing they are capable of applying them in appropriate circumstances and in a manner specified by, and consistent with, the standards and expectations laid down by their teachers, their adjudicators, their colleges and their professions. [On the ordinary and scientific use of such terms, see Dupré (1993), pp.15-84.]

 

The widespread illusion that we are all experts in the 'internal dismemberment' of images, ideas or concepts is now, and has always been, motivated by a further set of confusions, which also arose out of Traditional Philosophy: the belief that the intelligent use of general words depends on some sort of internal, naming, representing, 'reflecting' or processing ritual/ceremony. [On this, see the references cited in Essay Thirteen Part Three.] In effect, this once more amounts to the belief that, despite appearances to the contrary, all words are names, and that meaning something involves an 'inner act of meaning', 'naming' or 'representing', which matches words to specific images, sensations, processes or ideas 'in the mind/brain'. This paradigm certainly dominated Lenin's theory in MEC, as well as the rather fragmentary ideas Marx and Engels expressed on this topic, and, as usual, this idea originated in Ancient Greece (this was partially quoted earlier):

 

"The essence of the theory of Ideas lay in the conscious recognition of the fact that there is a class of entities, for which the best name is probably 'universals', that are entirely different from sensible things. Any use of language involves the recognition, either conscious or unconscious, of the fact that there are such entities; for every word used, except proper names -- every abstract noun, every general noun, every adjective, every verb, even every pronoun and every preposition -- is a name for something of which there are or may be instances." [Ross (1961), p.225. Bold emphasis added.]

 

[MEC = Materialism and Empirio-Criticism (i.e., Lenin (1972).]

 

At work here are several other inappropriate metaphors, which in turn trade on the further idea that 'consciousness' functions rather like an internal theatre, TV or computer display. The latter are now refined perhaps with analogies drawn against Microsoft Windows or some other programme of the same sort, where 'the mind' is often pictured as "modular" -- operated, no doubt, by an internal analogue of a computer geek, skilled at 'clicking' on the right internal 'icons', or 'apps', at the right moment, filing items in the right folders, setting-up useful and efficient 'networks', etc., etc. Given this family of metaphors, understanding is modelled on the way we ordinarily look at pictures and computer monitors, but now applied to 'internal representations', with each of us employing the equivalent of an 'inner eye' to appraise whatever is projected onto some sort of 'internal flat screen'.

 

[Again, this set of wildly inappropriate metaphors underpins Pixar's recent film, Inside Out (and again in 2024, Inside Out 2), which is itself based on an 'Homunculus', a 'little-man-in-the-head' Theory of Mind, briefly considered earlier, but in more detail in Essay Thirteen Part Three.]

 

These tropes are a faint echo of Plato's theory of 'knowledge by acquaintance', expressed in and by his Allegory of the Cave. [On that, see Appendix B of Essay Eight Part Two.]

 

[Of course, Plato's tropes were intended to make a different set of points, but for present purposes his focus on vision is the relevant factor here.]

 

As we have seen, contemporary, bourgeois versions of this (hackneyed) family of ideas regard knowledge as the passive processing of 'representations' in the 'mind' of each socially-isolated, lone abstractor -- although among Dialectical Marxists, this approach to knowledge is further augmented by a series of gestures made toward practice coupled with the active engagement of the individual 'mind' involved -- examined in Appendix Three. Nevertheless, both views of knowledge acquisition still picture it as a form of acquaintance, in relation to which the reasoning appears to be little more complex than this: just as we all know our friends by personal acquaintance, or by sight, so we all know the contents of our minds (all those 'concepts', 'images' and 'abstractions') by 'internal acquaintance' and 'inner sight'.

 

This once again reminds us why Traditional Theorists argue that knowledge is some sort of relation between the Knower and the Known. In this case, we are the Knowers and our own (internal) ideas are the Known. This has the unfortunate consequence of trapping dialecticians in their own solipsistic dungeon!

 

[There is more on this in Essays Three Part Four, Thirteen Part Three (here and here), and Six. It was also briefly discussed earlier.]

 

Don't Scientists Employ Abstraction?

 

As seems reasonably clear, if this privatised 'abstractive skill' had ever been of any importance in the history of science, we would find evidence of it in the work of the vast majority, if not every single, scientist.

 

Alas there is none.

 

Even an attempt to investigate the truth of that particular claim (i.e., that there is no evidence that scientists indulged in the private dismemberment of 'images', 'reflections', ideas or even 'abstractions' in their heads/'minds') would automatically throw into doubt the role that 'the process of abstraction' is supposed to occupy in science itself. That is because such an inquiry would have to examine physical evidence -- i.e., the notes, documents and writings left behind by these scientists, not their brains. Indeed, any recognition that what counts here as relevant evidence (i.e., the publicly available, written records they left behind -- alongside the equipment and techniques they used (etc.), coupled with their social surroundings, circumstances and ideological commitments, as opposed to the 'contents of their heads') would confirm that in their actual practice, no historian of any intelligence genuinely believes that abstract ideas (understood in the traditional sense, as the product of 'inner acts of intellection') underpin scientific knowledge, whatever theoretical or philosophical views they might otherwise entertain or even rehearse in public.

 

Here, as elsewhere, actions speak louder than abstractions.

 

[Again, several examples (drawn from the work of a handful of 'great' scientists), which disprove the contention that they were all 'abstractors extraordinaire', will be given in Essay Thirteen Part Two. (See also below.)]

 

Admittedly, there might be (several) scientists who actually disagree with this way of characterising the methods they employ (even if the latter are 'mental'), nevertheless their practical activity belies whatever post hoc rationalisations or re-descriptions they care to advance concerning the nature of their work or the procedures they follow.

 

Except in certain areas of obsolete psychology, whenever scientists endeavour to advance scientific knowledge, they neither report on the results of their own 'internal processing of mental entities', nor on the contents of their heads. And, they certainly don't require the same with respect to the 'cranial contents' of others in their field. On the contrary, as far as their work is concerned they develop novel hypotheses (at the very least) by extending the use and application of publicly accessible words, scientific techniques and, in many cases currently established theory. And, this they do, among other things, by employing analogy and metaphor in tandem with the innovative use of general terms that are already to be found the scientific lexicon or the public domain. All of this is (often) allied with the construction of tailor-made (mathematical, computer or even physical) models and targeted "thought experiments" (which also employ publicly accessible words), augmented by the utilisation of a range of other rhetorical devices.

 

[On this in general, see the references listed here. Naturally, that doesn't mean these factors aren't related to, or even constrained by, the development of the forces and relations of production. But, as noted earlier, such issues will be discussed in more detail in Essay Thirteen Part Two.]

 

Despite this, it could be objected that the above remarks thoroughly misrepresent the way that knowledge advances. In fact (but edited down), an objector might argue as follows: Ms Lichtenstein is wrong; scientists aim to discover the underlying nature of objects and processes in order to reveal the laws and regularities (etc.) that govern the natural and social world. Further: if the objector is a DM-advocate, they might even quote this famous passage from Volume Three of Das Kapital:

 

"But all science would be superfluous if the outward appearance and the essence of things directly coincided." [Marx (1981), p.956; Marx (1998), p.804.]

 

[I have commented on this quotation more fully in Essay Twelve Part One; readers are directed there for more details. Also see my demolition of the (connected) 'appearance'/'reality' distinction, below.]

 

Just to take just one example: let us suppose that an animal's 'essential' nature -- allegedly arrived at by the use of increasingly refined 'abstractions' -- turned out to be its DNA (or, if not that, it turns out to be something else, call it "EN"). Another, but more general example might be the way that Physicists extend knowledge by developing increasingly 'abstract' theories expressed in, or by, complex mathematical formulae, structures, models and laws.

 

But, that can't be correct. Scientists manifestly didn't discover DNA, and then understand its role in genetics, by the use of greater or more refined abstractions. They used the theoretical and practical advances achieved by both previous and contemporaneous researchers -- and those results weren't arrived at by 'abstraction', either --, which they then augmented with their own ideas, expressed, not in 'mental imagery', but in a public language, once more. [Even mathematics and logic are public languages, albeit of a complex and highly technical nature.] Such advances might also have been accomplished by, or have received an input from, teams of scientists working in related research traditions or areas of investigation. Added to this might be the results of other innovative experiments in the same or connected fields. All of these were, and still are, based on cooperative work, thought, communication and observation -- frequently assisted by the use of simple of complex models and yet more 'thought experiments'. Once again, all of which are expressed in a public language, subsequently published, appraised and checked in the open by other qualified researchers.

 

Even if we factor in the competition and secrecy enjoined or enforced by proprietary ownership and 'intellectual property rights' under capitalism, that doesn't significantly alter this picture, it just greatly reduces the size and scope of the social pool of those involved in this now greatly diminished public arena. That is, such factors mean smaller teams might end up working in specific areas of research, often connected with defence and commercial projects/interests, less frequently elsewhere. But, even in more restrictive and secretive environments, such as scientific and technological research carried out in the military-industrial complex, this is still the case: work is done in the open, in a public language, but this now takes place in highly restricted and heavily surveilled areas.   

 

None of these (save, perhaps, 'thought experiments') even remotely looks like a 'mental process', still less an example of 'abstraction' carried out in a hidden, 'inner' sanctum. And, as far as 'thought experiments' are concerned, these, too, are typically rehearsed in the public domain and in a public language. Any alleged 'mental processes' that accompany them are likewise advanced by an innovative use of language -- but, with the volume turned down.

 

['Thought experiments' will be discussed in more detail in Essay Thirteen Part Two; some of the relevant literature devoted to them has been referenced in Essay Four. See also the remarks made about 'mental arithmetic' below, which are highly relevant to understanding the above points about 'thought experiments' and 'idealisation'.]

 

Are Abstractions 'Mentally' Processed?

 

Of course, it could be objected that no one really thinks abstraction is "done in the head", or that scientists don't use a publicly accessible language in connection with their work. Hence, it might be argued that scientists nevertheless endeavour to form abstract ideas, idealisations and theories based on their use of these and other resources. In which case, many of the above remarks, and those in Part One, are irrelevant, if not completely misguided.

 

Or so it might be claimed...

 

First, that isn't what DM-theorists themselves have to say about the 'process of abstraction'. As we have already seen, DM itself grew directly out of the Rationalist Tradition in Philosophy, whose theorists largely agreed with Plato about the source and nature of 'reliable knowledge':

 

"If mind and true opinion are two distinct classes, then I say that there certainly are these self-existent ideas unperceived by sense, and apprehended only by the mind; if, however, as some say, true opinion differs in no respect from mind, then everything that we perceive through the body is to be regarded as most real and certain. But we must affirm that to be distinct, for they have a distinct origin and are of a different nature; the one is implanted in us by instruction, the other by persuasion; the one is always accompanied by true reason, the other is without reason; the one cannot be overcome by persuasion, but the other can: and lastly, every man may be said to share in true opinion, but mind is the attribute of the gods and of very few men. Wherefore also we must acknowledge that there is one kind of being which is always the same, uncreated and indestructible, never receiving anything into itself from without, nor itself going out to any other, but invisible and imperceptible by any sense, and of which the contemplation is granted to intelligence only." [Plato (1997c), 51e-52a, pp.1254-55. I have used the on-line version here. Bold emphases added. The published edition translates the third set of highlighted words as follows: "It is indivisible -- it cannot be perceived by the senses at all -- and it is the role of the understanding to study it." Cornford renders it thus: "[It is] invisible and otherwise imperceptible; that, in fact, which thinking has for its object." (Cornford (1997), p.192.)]

 

Again, here is what we read about the Rationalists who directly influenced dialecticians (also quoted earlier):

 

"Already with Fichte the idea of the unity of the sciences, of system, was connected with that of finding a reliable starting-point in certainty on which knowledge could be based. Thinkers from Kant onwards were quite convinced that the kind of knowledge which came from experience was not reliable. Empirical knowledge could be subject to error, incomplete, or superseded by further observation or experiment. It would be foolish, therefore, to base the whole of knowledge on something which had been established only empirically. The kind of knowledge which Kant and his followers believed to be the most secure was a priori knowledge, the kind embodied in the laws of Nature. These had been formulated without every occurrence of the Natural phenomenon in question being observed, so they did not summarise empirical information, and yet they held good by necessity for every case; these laws were truly universal in their application." [White (1996a), p.29. Bold emphasis added.]

 

And this is what Kant had to say about such 'knowledge':

 

"Our cognition arises from two fundamental sources in the mind, the first of which is the reception of representations (the receptivity of impressions), the second of the faculty for cognizing an object by means of these representations (spontaneity of concepts); through the former an object is given to us, through the latter it is thought in relation to that representation (as a mere determination of the mind). Intuition and concepts therefore constitute the elements of all our cognition, so that neither concepts without intuition corresponding to them in some way nor intuition without concepts can yield a cognition.... Thoughts without content are empty, intuitions without concepts are blind." [Kant (1998), pp.193-94, A51/B75. Bold emphases added; paragraphs merged. (By "intuition" Kant meant something like "immediate experience" -- Caygill (1995), pp.262-66.)]

 

"Our knowledge springs from two main sources in the mind, first of which is the faculty or power of receiving representations (receptivity for impressions); the second is the power of cognizing by means of these representations (spontaneity in the production of conceptions). Through the first an object is given to us; through the second, it is, in relation to the representation (which is a mere determination of the mind), thought. Intuition and conceptions constitute, therefore, the elements of all our knowledge, so that neither conceptions without an intuition in some way corresponding to them, nor intuition without conceptions, can afford us a cognition." [Online version of the above. As we saw in Part One (and again, below), Hegel also made similar points, except he claimed what Kant called an "intuition" was already conceptualised. How that was possible he left rather vague. Bold emphases added.]

 

Here, too, is Hegel echoing the above sentiments:

 

"To reach rational knowledge by our intelligence is the just demand of the mind which comes to science. For intelligence, understanding, is thinking, pure activity of the self in general; and what is intelligible is something from the first familiar and common to the scientific and unscientific mind alike, enabling the unscientific mind to enter the domain of science. (p.7, §13)

 

"It is this process by which science in general comes about, this gradual development of knowing, that is set forth here in the Phenomenology of Mind. Knowing, as it is found at the start, mind in its immediate and primitive stage, is without the essential nature of mind, is sense-consciousness. To reach the stage of genuine knowledge, or produce the element where science is found – the pure conception of science itself – a long and laborious journey must be undertaken. This process towards science, as regards the content it will bring to light and the forms it will assume in the course of its progress, will not be what is primarily imagined by leading the unscientific consciousness up to the level of science: it will be something different, too, from establishing and laying the foundations of science; and anyway something else than the sort of ecstatic enthusiasm which starts straight off with absolute knowledge, as if shot out of a pistol, and makes short work of other points of view simply by explaining that it is to take no notice of them. (pp.15-16, §27)

 

"...Thoughts become fluent and interfuse [fused together -- RL], when thinking pure and simple, this inner immediacy, knows itself as a moment, when pure certainty of self abstracts from itself. It does not 'abstract' in the sense of getting away from itself and setting itself on one side, but of surrendering the fixed quality of its self-affirmation, and giving up both the fixity of the purely concrete -- which is the ego as contrasted with the variety of its content -- and the fixity of all those distinctions [the various thought-functions, principles, etc.] which are present in the element of pure thought and share that absoluteness of the ego. In virtue of this process pure thoughts become notions, concepts, and are then what they are in truth, self-moving functions, circles, are what their substance consists in, are spiritual entities. (p.20, §33)

 

"Looked at as the concatenation of their content, this movement is the necessitated development and expansion of that content into an organic systematic whole. By this movement, too, the road, which leads to the notion of knowledge, becomes itself likewise a necessary and complete evolving process. This preparatory stage thus ceases to consist of casual philosophical reflections, referring to objects here and there, to processes and thoughts of the undeveloped mind as chance may direct; and it does not try to establish the truth by miscellaneous ratiocinations, inferences, and consequences drawn from circumscribed thoughts. The road to science, by the very movement of the notion itself, will compass the entire objective world of conscious life in its rational necessity. (p.20, §34)

 

"...What mind prepares for itself in the course of its phenomenology is the element of true knowledge. In this element the moments of mind are now set out in the form of thought pure and simple, which knows its object to be itself. They no longer involve the opposition between being and knowing; they remain within the undivided simplicity of the knowing function; they are the truth in the form of truth, and their diversity is merely diversity of the content of truth. The process by which they are developed into an organically connected whole is Logic or Speculative Philosophy. (pp.21-22, §37)

 

"Here we find contained the principle that Being is Thought: here is exercised that insight which usually tends to deviate from the ordinary non-conceptual way of speaking of the identity of thought and being. In virtue, further, of the fact that subsistence on the part of what exists is self-identity or pure abstraction, it is the abstraction of itself from itself, in other words, is itself its own want of identity with itself and dissolution – its own proper inwardness and retraction into self -- its process of becoming. (p.33, §54)

 

[The above were taken from the Preface to Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit (also called Phenomenology of Mind) i.e., Hegel (1977), pp.7-33). Bold emphases added; quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Had similar passages been quoted from the rest of the book (never mind other works of Hegel's), this Essay would have been tens of thousands of words longer!]

 

As we have seen, this is how Marx and Engels summed up Hegel's method of 'abstraction':

 

"The mystery of critical presentation…is the mystery of speculative, of Hegelian construction.If from real apples, pears, strawberries and almonds I form the general idea 'Fruit', if I go further and imagine that my abstract idea 'Fruit', derived from real fruit, is an entity existing outside me, is indeed the true essence of the pear, the apple, etc., then -- in the language of speculative philosophy –- I am declaring that 'Fruit' is the 'Substance' of the pear, the apple, the almond, etc. I am saying, therefore, that to be an apple is not essential to the apple; that what is essential to these things is not their real existence, perceptible to the senses, but the essence that I have abstracted from them and then foisted on them, the essence of my idea -- 'Fruit'…. Particular real fruits are no more than semblances whose true essence is 'the substance' -- 'Fruit'…. Having reduced the different real fruits to the one 'fruit' of abstraction -- 'the Fruit', speculation must, in order to attain some semblance of real content, try somehow to find its way back from 'the Fruit', from the Substance to the diverse, ordinary real fruits, the pear, the apple, the almond etc. It is as hard to produce real fruits from the abstract idea 'the Fruit' as it is easy to produce this abstract idea from real fruits. Indeed, it is impossible to arrive at the opposite of an abstraction without relinquishing the abstraction….

 

"The main interest for the speculative philosopher is therefore to produce the existence of the real ordinary fruits and to say in some mysterious way that there are apples, pears, almonds and raisins. But the apples, pears, almonds and raisins that we rediscover in the speculative world are nothing but semblances of apples, semblances of pears, semblances of almonds and semblances of raisins, for they are moments in the life of 'the Fruit', this abstract creation of the mind, and therefore themselves abstract creations of the mind…. When you return from the abstraction, the supernatural creation of the mind, 'the Fruit', to real natural fruits, you give on the contrary the natural fruits a supernatural significance and transform them into sheer abstractions. Your main interest is then to point out the unity of 'the Fruit' in all the manifestations of its life…that is, to show the mystical interconnection between these fruits, how in each of them 'the Fruit' realizes itself by degrees and necessarily progresses, for instance, from its existence as a raisin to its existence as an almond. Hence the value of the ordinary fruits no longer consists in their natural qualities, but in their speculative quality, which gives each of them a definite place in the life-process of 'the Absolute Fruit'.

 

"The ordinary man does not think he is saying anything extraordinary when he states that there are apples and pears. But when the philosopher expresses their existence in the speculative way he says something extraordinary. He performs a miracle by producing the real natural objects, the apple, the pear, etc., out of the unreal creation of the mind 'the Fruit'…. It goes without saying that the speculative philosopher accomplishes this continuous creation only by presenting universally known qualities of the apple, the pear, etc., which exist in reality, as determining features invented by him, by giving the names of the real things to what abstract reason alone can create, to abstract formulas of reason, finally, by declaring his own activity, by which he passes from the idea of an apple to the idea of a pear, to be the self-activity of the Absolute Subject, 'the Fruit.' In the speculative way of speaking, this operation is called comprehending Substance as Subject, as an inner process, as an Absolute Person, and this comprehension constitutes the essential character of Hegel's method." [Marx and Engels (1975a), pp.72-75. Bold emphases alone added. Several paragraphs merged.]

 

As their younger selves, Marx and Engels clearly regarded 'abstraction' as a private, individualised process, the products of which they describe as "abstract creations of the mind" and an "unreal creation of the mind" -- just as the Essays posted at this site have maintained.

 

So, it should hardly surprise us when DM-theorists (who have in general ignored -- and, in effect, rejected -- the above conclusions drawn by Marx and Engels, along with their demolition of Hegel's method and 'abstractionism' in general) emulate Hegel and the rest of the ruling-class Rationalist Tradition stretching back at least to Plato. This has left them promoting and privileging the 'mental processes' that supposedly give rise to all these 'abstractions', which they then claim are necessary in order to form a secure foundation for the advancement of knowledge.

 

Here are just a few examples where DM-theorists have (perhaps inadvertently) confirmed the above accusations -- beginning with Lenin (followed by John Rees, Alexander Spirkin and then several others):

 

"The approach of the (human) mind to a particular thing, the taking of a copy (= a concept) of it is not a simple, immediate act, a dead mirroring, but one which is complex, split into two, zig-zag-like, which includes in it the possibility of the flight of fantasy from life; more than that: the possibility of the transformation (moreover, an unnoticeable transformation, of which man is unaware) of the abstract concept, idea, into a fantasy.... For even in the simplest generalisation, in the most elementary general idea ('table' in general), there is a certain bit of fantasy. (Vice versa: it would be stupid to deny the role of fantasy, even in the strictest science...." [Lenin (1961), pp.370-71. All but one instance of bold emphasis added. Italics in the original. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

"Thought proceeding from the concrete to the abstract -- provided it is correct (NB)… -- does not get away from the truth but comes closer to it. The abstraction of matter, the law of nature, the abstraction of value, etc., in short all scientific (correct, serious, not absurd) abstractions reflect nature more deeply, truly and completely. From living perception to abstract thought, and from this to practice, -- such is the dialectical path of cognition of truth, of the cognition of objective reality." [Ibid., p.171. Bold emphases alone added.]

 

"Knowledge is the reflection of nature by man. But this is not simple, not an immediate, not a complete reflection, but the process of a series of abstractions, the formation and development of concepts, laws, etc., and these concepts, laws, etc., (thought, science = 'the logical Idea') embrace conditionally, approximately, the universal, law-governed character of eternally moving and developing nature." [Ibid., p.182. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Bold emphases alone added.]

 

"[A]ll science generalizes and abstracts from 'empirically verifiable facts.' Indeed, the very concept of 'fact' is itself an abstraction, because no one has ever eaten, tasted, smelt, seen or heard a 'fact,' which is a mental generalization that distinguishes actually existing phenomena from imaginary conceptions. Similarly, all science 'deductively anticipates' developments -- what else is an hypothesis tested by experimentation? The dialectic is, among other things, a way of investigating and understanding the relationship between abstractions and reality. And the 'danger of arbitrary construction' is far greater using an empirical method which thinks that it is dealing with facts when it is actually dealing with abstractions than it is with a method that properly distinguishes between the two and then seeks to explain the relationship between them." [Rees (1998), p.131. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Bold emphases alone added.]

 

"Abstraction is the mental identification, singling out of some object from its connections with other objects, the separation of some attribute of an object from its other attributes, of some relation between certain objects from the objects themselves. Abstraction is a method of mental simplification, by which we consider some one aspect of the process we are studying. The scientist looks at the colourful picture which any object presents in real life through a single-colour filter and this enables him to see that object in only one, fundamentally important aspect. The picture loses many of its shades but gains in clarity. Abstraction has its limit. One cannot abstract the flame from what is burning. The sharp edge of abstraction, like the edge of a razor can be used to whittle things down until nothing is left. Abstraction can never be absolute. The existence of content shows intrinsically in every abstraction. The question of what to abstract and what to abstract from is ultimately decided by the nature of the objects under examination and the tasks confronting the investigator. Kepler, for example, was not interested in the colour of Mars or the temperature of the Sun when he sought to establish the laws of the revolution of the planets. What we get as a result of the process of abstracting is various concepts about certain objects, such as 'plant', 'animal', 'human being', ideas about the separate properties of objects and the relations between them ('whiteness', 'volume', 'length', 'heat capacity', etc.).

 

"Idealisation as a specific form of abstraction is an important technique in scientific cognition. Abstract objects do not exist and cannot be made to exist in reality, but they have their prototypes in the real world. Pure mathematics operates with numbers, vectors and other mathematical objects that are the result of abstraction and idealisation. Geometry, for example, is concerned with exact circles, but physical object is never exactly circular; perfect roundness is an abstraction. It cannot be found in nature. But it is an image of the real: it was brought into existence by generalisation from experience. Idealisation is a process of forming concepts, whose real prototypes can be indicated only to a certain degree of approximation. As a result of idealisation there comes into being a theoretical model in which the characteristics and aspects of the objects under investigation are not only abstracted from their actual empirical multiformity but also, by means of mental construction, are made to stand out in a sharper and more fully expressed form than in reality itself. As examples of concepts resulting from idealisation we may take such things as the 'point' (an object which has neither length, nor height, nor breadth); or 'the straight line', the 'circle', and so on.... The mental transition from the more general to the less general is a process of limitation. Without generalisation there can be no theory. Theory, on the other hand, is created so that it can be applied in practice to solve certain specific problems. For example, when measuring objects or building certain technical structures, we must always proceed from the more general to the less general and the individual, there must always be a process of limitation. The grotesque fantastic images of mythology with its gods and monsters are closer to ordinary reality than the reality of the microworld conceived in the form of mathematical symbols. One can see that the turn towards the abstract is a very obvious trend of our time. Recourse to the abstract may also be observed in art, in abstract pictures and sculptures.

 

"The abstract and the concrete. The concept of 'the concrete' is used in two senses. First, in the sense of something directly given, a sensuously perceived and represented whole. In this sense the concrete is the starting point of cognition. But as soon as we treat it theoretically the concrete becomes a concept, a system of scientific definitions revealing the essential connections and relations of things and events, their unity in diversity. So the concrete appears to us first in the form of a sensuously observable image of the whole object not yet broken down and not understood in its law-governed connections and mediations, but at the level of theoretical thought it is still a whole, but internally differentiated, understood in its various intrinsic contradictions. The sensuously concrete is a poor reflection of phenomena, but the concrete in thought is a richer, more essential cognition. In contrast to the abstract the concrete is only one moment in the process of cognition, we understand it by comparing it with the abstract. Abstraction usually suggests to us some thing 'mental', 'conceptual', in contrast to the sensuously observable. The abstract is also thought of as something one-sided, poor, incomplete, separated, or as a property, a relation, a form, etc. withdrawn from its connection with the whole. And in this sense not only a concept but even an observable image, for example, a diagram, a drawing, an abstract painting, stylisation, a symbol may be abstract. The category of abstraction is contradictory. It is dead, one-sided, separated from the living phenomenon, but it is also an essential step towards the knowledge of a concrete fact brimming with life. We call knowledge abstract also in the sense that it reflects a fragment of reality, as it were, stripped down, refined and thereby impoverished. Abstractions are 'bits' of whole objects, and our thinking works with such 'bits'. From separate abstractions thought constantly returns to the restoration of concreteness, but each time on a new, higher basis. This is the concreteness of concepts, categories, and theories reflecting unity in diversity.

 

"What do we mean by cognition as a process of ascent from the abstract to the concrete? '...[C]ognition rolls onwards from content to content. First of all, this advance is determined as beginning from simple determinatenesses the succeeding ones becoming ever richer and more concrete. For the result contains its beginning and its course has enriched it by a fresh determinateness. The universal constitutes the foundation; the advance is therefore not to be taken as a flowing from one other to the next other. In the absolute method the Notion maintains itself in its otherness. the universal in its particularisation, in judgment and reality; at each stage of its further determination it raises the entire mass of its preceding content, and by its dialectical advance it not only does not lose anything or leave anything behind, but carries along with it all it has gained, and inwardly enriches and consolidates itself." [Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel's Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe. Fünfter Band. Wissenschaft der Logic. Berlin, 1834, Verlag von Duncker und Humblot, S.348-49. (This is in fact Hegel (1999), p.840. §1809.)] Seen in this light, the process of abstraction is a realisation of the principle: one must step back in order to get a better view. The dialectics of the cognition of reality lies in the fact that by 'flying away' from this sensuously given reality on the 'wings' of abstraction, one may from the heights of concrete theoretical thought better 'survey' the essence of the object under investigation. Such is the history and logic of scientific cognition. Here we have the essence of the Marxist method of ascent from the abstract to the concrete. According to Marx, this method is the means by which thought assimilates the concrete, reproduces it by linking up concepts into an integrated scientific theory, which reproduces the objective separateness of the objects and the unity of its essential properties and relations. The concrete is concrete because it is a synthesis of many definitions, and, consequently, a unity of the diversity. The principle of concreteness means that we must approach facts of natural and social life not with general formulas and diagrams but by taking into exact account all the real conditions in which the target of our research is located and distinguish the most important, essential properties, connections, and tendencies that determine its other aspects." [Spirkin (1983), pp.232-35. Bold emphases alone added; quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. I have used the translation found in Hegel (1999), not Spirkin's version. Several paragraphs merged.]

 

"Abstraction -- a form of cognition based on the mental identification of an object's essential properties and connections...a synonym of 'mental' or 'conceptual'...". [Krapivin (1985), p.278. Bold emphases added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

"Human thought is not only mediate; it is also an abstract and generalised reflection of reality. The process whereby a number of properties of an object and the relations between them are discarded, and the property or relation we are concerned with is singled out, or identified, is called an abstraction. Man's thought is abstract precisely because it operates with concepts developed as a result of abstraction. Any abstraction also contains at the same time a certain generalisation . The abstraction of identification, for example, helped from such concepts, among others, as 'man', 'animal', 'commodity', 'revolution', 'socialism' and 'capitalism'. The abstraction of isolation underlies such concepts as 'hardness', 'whiteness', 'kindness', 'cruelty', 'democracy', and others. So-called idealisation is often used in scientific knowledge when an object is taken in its 'pure form': 'a point' (i.e., an object without extension), 'line', 'ideal gas', 'ideally elastic body', etc. There are also other kinds of abstraction. The process of abstracting and generalising is based on the mental operations of analysis and synthesis. The former is a disjunction of an integral object into its components-- its properties and aspects -- and the mental singling out of its separate features. The latter is a method of mentally combining the elements and properties of the object under scrutiny." [Kharin (1981), pp.219-20. Bold emphases added.]

 

"To abstract a phenomenon or object we must split it up mentally into its properties, relationships, parts, stages of development, and so on." [Konstantinov, et al (1974), p.220. Bold emphasis added.]

 

Here, too, is Bertell Ollman:

 

"The philosophy of internal relations bans finite parts from Marx's ontology. The world, it would have us believe, is not like that. Then, through the mental process of abstraction, Marx draws a set of provisional boundaries in this relational world to arrive at parts that are better suited-chiefly through the inclusion of significant elements of change and interaction-to the particular investigation he has in mind. [Ollman (2003), p.5. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"Dialectics restructures our thinking about reality by replacing the commonsense notion of 'thing' (as something that has a history and has external connections with other things) with notions of 'process' (which contains its history and possible futures) and 'relation' (which contains as part of what it is its ties with other relations). Nothing that didn't already exist has been added here. Rather, it is a matter of where and how one draws boundaries and establishes units (the dialectical term is 'abstracts') in which to think about the world. The assumption is that while the qualities we perceive with our five senses actually exist as parts of nature, the conceptual distinctions that tell us where one thing ends and the next one begins both in space and across time are social and mental constructs." [Ibid., p.13. Bold emphases added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

"In his most explicit statement on the subject, Marx claims that his method starts from the 'real concrete' (the world as it presents itself to us) and proceeds through 'abstraction' (the intellectual activity of breaking this whole down into the mental units with which we think about it) to the 'thought concrete' (the reconstituted and now understood whole present in the mind) (Marx (1904), pp.293-94; this is a reference to A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy -- RL). The real concrete is simply the world in which we live, in all its complexity. The thought concrete is Marx's reconstruction of that world in the theories of what has come to be called 'Marxism.' The royal road to understanding is said to pass from the one to the other through the process of abstraction.

 

"In one sense, the role Marx gives to abstraction is simple recognition of the fact that all thinking about reality begins by breaking it down into manageable parts. Reality may be in one piece when lived, but to be thought about and communicated it must be parceled (sic) out. Our minds can no more swallow the world whole at one sitting than can our stomachs. Everyone then, and not just Marx and Marxists, begins the task of trying to make sense of his or her surroundings by distinguishing certain features and focusing on and organizing them in ways deemed appropriate. 'Abstract' comes from the Latin, 'abstrahere', which means 'to pull from.' In effect, a piece has been pulled from or taken out of the whole and is temporarily perceived as standing apart. We 'see' only some of what lies in front of us, 'hear' only part of the noises in our vicinity, 'feel' only a small part of what our body is in contact with, and so on through the rest of our senses. In each case, a focus is established and a kind of boundary set within our perceptions distinguishing what is relevant from what is not. It should be clear that 'What did you see?' (What caught your eye?) is a different question from 'What did you actually see?' (What came into your line of vision?). Likewise, in thinking about any subject, we focus on only some of its qualities and relations. Much that could be included -- that may in fact be included in another person's view or thought, and may on another occasion be included in our own -- is left out. The mental activity involved in establishing such boundaries, whether conscious or unconscious -- though it is usually an amalgam of both -- is the process of abstraction.

 

"Responding to a mixture of influences that include the material world and our experiences in it as well as to personal wishes, group interests, and other social constraints, it is the process of abstraction that establishes the specificity of the objects with which we interact. In setting boundaries, in ruling this far and no further, it is what makes something one (or two, or more) of a kind, and lets us know where that kind begins and ends. With this decision as to units, we also become committed to a particular set of relations between them -- relations made possible and even necessary by the qualities that we have included in each -- a register for classifying them, and a mode for explaining them. In listening to a concert, for example, we often concentrate on a single instrument or recurring theme and then redirect our attention elsewhere. Each time this occurs, the whole music alters, new patterns emerge, each sound takes on a different value, etc. How we understand the music is largely determined by how we abstract it. The same applies to what we focus on when watching a play, whether on a person, or a combination of persons, or a section of the stage. The meaning of the play and what more is required to explore or test that meaning alters, often dramatically, with each new abstraction. In this way, too, how we abstract literature, where we draw the boundaries, determines what works and what parts of each work will be studied, with what methods, in relation to what other subjects, in what order, and even by whom. Abstracting literature to include its audience, for example, leads to a sociology of literature, while an abstraction of literature that excludes everything but its forms calls forth various structural approaches, and so on.

 

"From what has been said so far, it is clear that 'abstraction' is itself an abstraction. I have abstracted it from Marx's dialectical method, which in turn was abstracted from his broad theories, which in turn were abstracted from his life and work. The mental activities that we have collected and brought into focus as 'abstraction' are more often associated with the processes of perception, conception, defining, remembering, dreaming, reasoning, and even thinking. It is not surprising, therefore, if the process of abstraction strikes many people as both foreign and familiar at the same time. Each of these more familiar processes operates in part by separating out, focusing, and putting emphasis on only some aspects of that reality with which they come into contact. In 'abstraction' we have simply separated out, focused, and put emphasis on certain common features of these other processes. Abstracting 'abstraction' in this way is neither easy nor obvious, and therefore relatively few people have done it. Consequently, though everyone abstracts, of necessity, only a few are aware of it as such. This philosophical impoverishment is reinforced by the fact that most people are lazy abstractors, simply and uncritically accepting the mental units with which they think as part of their cultural inheritance. A further complication in grasping 'abstraction' arises from the fact that Marx uses the term in four different, though closely related, senses. First and most important, it refers to the mental activity of subdividing the world into the mental constructs with which we think about it, which is the process that we have been describing. Second, it refers to the results of this process, the actual parts into which reality has been apportioned. That is to say, for Marx, as for Hegel before him, 'abstraction' functions as a noun as well as a verb, the noun referring to what the verb has brought into being. In these senses, everyone can be said to abstract (verb) and to think with abstractions (noun). But Marx also uses 'abstraction' in a third sense, where it refers to a suborder of particularly ill-fitting mental constructs. Whether because they are too narrow, take in too little, focus too exclusively on appearances, or are otherwise badly composed, these constructs do not allow an adequate grasp of their subject matter." [Ibid., pp.60-62.Bold emphases alone added. Several paragraphs merged. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Referencing conventions modified for the same reason.]

 

"The process of abstraction, which we have been treating as an undifferentiated mental act, has three main aspects or modes, which are also its functions vis-à-vis the part abstracted on one hand and the system to which the part belongs and which it in turn helps to shape on the other. That is, the boundary setting and bringing into focus that lies at the core of this process occurs simultaneously in three different, though closely related, senses. These senses have to do with extension, level of generality, and vantage point. First, each abstraction can be said to achieve a certain extension in the part abstracted, and this applies both spatially and temporally. In abstracting boundaries in space, limits are set in the mutual interaction that occurs at a given point of time. While in abstracting boundaries in time, limits are set in the distinctive history and potential development of any part, in what it once was and is yet to become. Most of our examples of abstraction so far have been drawn from what we shall now call 'abstraction of extension.'" [Ibid., p.74. Bold emphasis added. All these links lead to a PDF of Ollman's book.]

 

Not forgetting our old 'friends', Woods and Grant:

 

"Without abstraction it is impossible to penetrate the object in 'depth,' to understand its essential nature and laws of motion. Through the mental work of abstraction, we are able to get beyond the immediate information provided by our senses (sense-perception), and probe deeper. We can break the object down into its constituent parts, isolate them, and study them in detail. We can arrive at an idealised, general conception of the object as a 'pure' form, stripped of all secondary features. This is the work of abstraction, an absolutely necessary stage of the process of cognition." [Woods and Grant (1995), pp.85-87. Bold emphases added.]

 

Here, too, is Academic Marxist, Andrew Sayer:

 

"The sense in which the term ['abstract' -- RL] is used here is different [from its ordinary use -- RL]; an abstract concept, or an abstraction, isolates in thought a one-sided or partial aspect of an object. [In a footnote, Sayer adds 'My use of "abstract" and "concrete" is, I think, equivalent to Marx's' (p.277, note 3).]" [Sayer (1992), p.87. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Bold emphasis alone added. The page numbers are completely different in the Second Corrected Edition, i.e., Sayer (2010), p.187 and p.59, respectively.]

 

Finally, here is another Academic Marxist, but one with whom I engaged in discussion recently:

 

"Critical thought demands abstraction. We must organize the manifold objects of reality in the thought realm of our minds, which means we have to provisionally distance ourselves from the complex, concrete appearances and start with the most simple and abstract category that captures the phenomena we are attempting to understand. Hence, Marx starts with the commodity in the abstract." [Quoted from here. Bold emphasis added; spelling modified to agree with UK English.]

 

As we found out was the case with Ollman -- and this applies to everyone else who has written on this topic --, beyond a few vague gestures, accompanied by no little hand-waving, we are never told exactly how the above 'process' actually works, or even why it doesn't result in the creation of a 'private language'. As we also saw, Ollman himself pointed this out:

 

"What, then, is distinctive about Marx's abstractions? To begin with, it should be clear that Marx's abstractions do not and cannot diverge completely from the abstractions of other thinkers both then and now. There has to be a lot of overlap. Otherwise, he would have constructed what philosophers call a 'private language,' and any communication between him and the rest of us would be impossible. How close Marx came to fall into this abyss and what can be done to repair some of the damage already done are questions I hope to deal with in a later work...." [Ollman (2003), p.63. Bold emphasis added.]

 

'Mentally-Processed', According To Marx Himself

 

Finally, here is Marx himself (in an oft-quoted passage, which unfortunately contradicts what he had to say earlier about 'abstraction'):

 

"There are characteristics which all stages of production have in common, and which are established as general ones by the mind; but the so-called general preconditions of all production are nothing more than these abstract moments with which no real historical stage of production can be grasped....

 

"It seems to be correct to begin with the real and the concrete, with the real precondition, thus to begin, in economics, with e.g. the population, which is the foundation and the subject of the entire social act of production. However, on closer examination this proves false. The population is an abstraction if I leave out, for example, the classes of which it is composed. These classes in turn are an empty phrase if I am not familiar with the elements on which they rest. E.g. wage labour, capital, etc. These latter in turn presuppose exchange, division of labour, prices, etc. For example, capital is nothing without wage labour, without value, money, price etc. Thus, if I were to begin with the population, this would be a chaotic conception of the whole, and I would then, by means of further determination, move analytically towards ever more simple concepts, from the imagined concrete towards ever thinner abstractions until I had arrived at the simplest determinations. From there the journey would have to be retraced until I had finally arrived at the population again, but this time not as the chaotic conception of a whole, but as a rich totality of many determinations and relations. The former is the path historically followed by economics at the time of its origins. The economists of the seventeenth century, e.g., always begin with the living whole, with population, nation, state, several states, etc.; but they always conclude by discovering through analysis a small number of determinant, abstract, general relations such as division of labour, money, value, etc. As soon as these individual moments had been more or less firmly established and abstracted, there began the economic systems, which ascended from the simple relations, such as labour, division of labour, need, exchange value, to the level of the state, exchange between nations and the world market. The latter is obviously the scientifically correct method. The concrete is concrete because it is the concentration of many determinations, hence unity of the diverse. It appears in the process of thinking, therefore, as a process of concentration, as a result, not as a point of departure, even though it is the point of departure in reality and hence also the point of departure for observation and conception. Along the first path the full conception was evaporated to yield an abstract determination; along the second, the abstract determinations lead towards a reproduction of the concrete by way of thought. In this way Hegel fell into the illusion of conceiving the real as the product of thought concentrating itself, probing its own depths, and unfolding itself out of itself, by itself, whereas the method of rising from the abstract to the concrete is only the way in which thought appropriates the concrete, reproduces it as the concrete in the mind. But this is by no means the process by which the concrete itself comes into being. For example, the simplest economic category, say e.g. exchange value, presupposes population, moreover a population producing in specific relations; as well as a certain kind of family, or commune, or state, etc. It can never exist other than as an abstract, one-sided relation within an already given, concrete, living whole. As a category, by contrast, exchange value leads an antediluvian existence. Therefore, to the kind of consciousness -- and this is characteristic of the philosophical consciousness -- for which conceptual thinking is the real human being, and for which the conceptual world as such is thus the only reality, the movement of the categories appears as the real act of production -- which only, unfortunately, receives a jolt from the outside -- whose product is the world; and -- but this is again a tautology -- this is correct in so far as the concrete totality is a totality of thoughts, concrete in thought, in fact a product of thinking and comprehending; but not in any way a product of the concept which thinks and generates itself outside or above observation and conception; a product, rather, of the working-up of observation and conception into concepts. The totality as it appears in the head, as a totality of thoughts, is a product of a thinking head, which appropriates the world in the only way it can, a way different from the artistic, religious, practical and mental appropriation of this world. The real subject retains its autonomous existence outside the head just as before; namely as long as the head's conduct is merely speculative, merely theoretical. Hence, in the theoretical method, too, the subject, society, must always be kept in mind as the presupposition.

 

"But do not these simpler categories also have an independent historical or natural existence pre-dating the more concrete ones? That depends. Hegel, for example, correctly begins the Philosophy of Right with possession, this being the subject's simplest juridical relation. But there is no possession preceding the family or master-servant relations, which are far more concrete relations. However, it would be correct to say that there are families or clan groups which still merely possess, but have no property. The simple category therefore appears in relation to property as a relation of simple families or clan groups. In the higher society it appears as the simpler relation of a developed organization. But the concrete substratum of which possession is a relation is always presupposed. One can imagine an individual savage as possessing something. But in that case possession is not a juridical relation. It is incorrect that possession develops historically into the family. Possession, rather, always presupposes this 'more concrete juridical category.' There would still always remain this much, however, namely that the simple categories are the expressions of relations within which the less developed concrete may have already realized itself before having posited the more many-sided connection or relation which is mentally expressed in the more concrete category; while the more developed concrete preserves the same category as a subordinate relation. Money may exist, and did exist historically, before capital existed, before banks existed, before wage labour existed, etc. Thus in this respect it may be said that the simpler category can express the dominant relations of a less developed whole, or else those subordinate relations of a more developed whole which already had a historic existence before this whole developed in the direction expressed by a more concrete category. To that extent the path of abstract thought, rising from the simple to the combined, would correspond to the real historical process." [Marx (1986), pp.37-39. Bold emphases alone added. The on-line translation has been quoted here -- i.e., Marx (1973) -- while the page numbers are those found in the MECW edition -- i.e., Marx (1986) -- which translates the above words slightly differently but in a way that still makes the same points. I have linked to both versions so readers can check this for themselves.]

 

"As a rule, the most general abstractions arise only in the midst of the richest possible concrete development, where one thing appears as common to many, to all. Then it ceases to be thinkable in a particular form alone. On the other side, this abstraction of labour as such is not merely the mental product of a concrete totality of labours. Indifference towards specific labours corresponds to a form of society in which individuals can with ease transfer from one labour to another, and where the specific kind is a matter of chance for them, hence of indifference. Not only the category, labour, but labour in reality has here become the means of creating wealth in general, and has ceased to be organically linked with particular individuals in any specific form....

 

"In the succession of the economic categories, as in any other historical, social science, it must not be forgotten that their subject -- here, modern bourgeois society -- is always what is given, in the head as well as in reality, and that these categories therefore express the forms of being, the characteristics of existence, and often only individual sides of this specific society, this subject, and that therefore this society by no means begins only at the point where one can speak of it as such; this holds for science as well. This is to be kept in mind because it will shortly be decisive for the order and sequence of the categories....

 

"Every moment, in calculating, accounting etc., that we transform commodities into value symbols, we fix them as mere exchange values, making abstraction from the matter they are composed of and all their natural qualities. On paper, in the head, this metamorphosis proceeds by means of mere abstraction; but in the real exchange process a real mediation is required, a means to accomplish this abstraction." [bid., pp.41-80. Bold emphases alone added. Again, the on-line translation has been quoted here -- i.e., Marx (1973) -- while the page numbers are those found in the MECW edition -- i.e., Marx (1986) -- which translates the above words slightly differently but in a way that still makes the same points. I have linked to both versions so readers can check this for themselves.]

 

Marx reasoned along similar lines in his early work, too:

 

"The premises from which we begin are not arbitrary ones, not dogmas, but real premises from which abstraction can only be made in the imagination. They are the real individuals, their activity and the material conditions under which they live, both those which they find already existing and those produced by their activity. These premises can thus be verified in a purely empirical way." [Marx and Engels (1976), p.31. Bold emphasis added.]

 

So, Marx clearly connects abstraction with what goes on "in the head", processed "mentally", "by the mind" and "in the imagination".

 

[Admittedly, in Marx (1986), he also says it takes place "on paper" (and "in the head"), but he nowhere explained how the former is actually carried out -- nor has anyone since. I suspect Marx was referring to the writing down of results that had been achieved 'mentally'.]

 

This is what Alex Callinicos had to say about the above passage (by Marx):

 

"First, the process of knowledge is one that takes place within thought. Neither its commencement nor its conclusion involves any direct encounter with the real. To start with the 'real precondition' involves its evaporation into 'an abstract determination'. And where the 'scientifically correct method' is employed its result is, not the concrete reality itself but the 'reproduction of the concrete by way of thought'. Marx emphasis this point...:

 

'The concrete totality is a totality of thoughts, concrete in thought, in fact a product of thinking and comprehending;...a product...of the working-up of observation and conception into concepts. The totality as it appears in the head, as a totality of thoughts, is a product of a thinking head, which appropriates the world in the only way it can, a way different from the artistic, religious, practical and mental appropriation of this world. The real subject retains its autonomous existence outside the head just as before; namely as long as the head's conduct is merely speculative, merely theoretical.' [Marx (1986), loc cit. Bold added.]

 

"In this way the central thesis of empiricism, that scientific knowledge rests upon the direct access of the subject to reality, was overturned. Instead attention was focussed upon the process of theoretical knowledge itself, 'the working-up of observation and conception into concepts'....

 

"Second, Marx advances a new theory of scientific abstraction, which tells us something about the internal structure of the process of knowledge. When Marx writes that:

 

'the method of rising from the abstract to the concrete is only the way in which thought appropriates the concrete, reproduces it as the concrete in the mind',  [Marx (1986), loc cit. Bold added.].

 

"he is setting behind him classical epistemology's theory of abstraction. The theory he rejects is one in which abstraction is essentially the process whereby thought abstracts from the real the essential relationships which it makes the first principles of the science. Abstraction is identified analysis -- thought penetrates the real, paring away the inessential phenomena in order to grasp the underlying essence.... The notion of science as a process taking place within thought implies a breach with this theory of abstraction, since any direct relation between thought and reality is denied." [Callinicos (1978), pp.136-38. Emphases in the original, except in place of italics Callinicos uses underlining; bold added. Several paragraphs merged; minor typos corrected. Referencing and formatting conventions altered to conform with those adopted at this site.]

 

As we have seen, Callinicos has seriously misunderstood Empiricism -- or to be more accurate, he ignores the many ways it is fundamentally like the Rationalist Tradition in its approach to knowledge (as earlier sections of this Part of Essay Three have shown). As we will also see, even Hegel rejects this way of interpreting our 'encounter with the real'. Nevertheless, Callinicos at least underlines the connection between abstraction and 'what goes on in the head'.

 

[Having said that, it isn't too clear that Callinicos would express himself this way today, almost forty-five years later!]

 

Be this as it may, I have subjected much of the above (and not just what Callinicos has to say) to detailed criticism across Parts One and Two of this Essay.

 

In which case, it is now undeniable that DM-theorists (across all wings of Dialectical Marxism) believe the 'process of abstraction' is carried out 'in the head'/'in the mind' -- precisely as argued at this site.

 

But, as we have seen, that isn't what scientists themselves actually do. Nor is it what anyone does. The opposite idea is a myth invented and promulgated by Traditional Philosophers, amateur metaphysicians and DM-fans alike.

 

These somewhat controversial claims (i.e., those relating to what scientists do, as opposed to what they or others say they do, or what they or others imagine they do --, or, indeed, what certain philosophers think they do) will be substantiated (and illustrated) more fully in Essay Thirteen Part Two (much of that material has been summarised and included in the last few sub-sections of this Essay, anyway). The claim that the rest of us engage in abstraction has also been subjected to sustained and destructive criticism throughout Parts One and Two of Essay Three.

 

However, I will say more about science, scientists and what they do (or do not do) in a later sub-section: "Appearance and Reality".

 

Anti-Abstractionists

 

Berkeley And Frege

 

[This also used to be part of Note 24.]

 

Nevertheless, Anti-abstractionism is a relatively recent development. [And that is because abstractionism is one of the "ruling ideas".] Why it is a recent development will be revealed in Essay Twelve Part Seven (summarised here). The first major thinker to subject the possibility there were any 'abstract general ides' to searching criticism (that is, outside the Medieval Nominalist tradition) was George Berkeley.

 

[Berkeley's arguments against abstract ideas are summarised in Dancy (1987), pp.24-40; a different approach, connected with Berkeley's Philosophy of Mathematics, can be found in Jesseph (1993), pp.9-43. On Berkeley in general, see here; his case against abstraction is expertly summarised here.]

 

Berkeley's arguments in this regard are psychologically orientated, based on the observation that it is impossible for him to form an abstract idea of anything whatsoever since that would require whatever it was that was (supposedly) abstracted both possessed and did not possess incompatible properties at one and the same time. So, he asks whether anyone:

 

"[H]as, or can attain to have, an idea that shall correspond with the description that is here given of the general idea of a triangle, which is, neither oblique, nor rectangle, equilateral, equicrural (Isosceles -- RL), nor scalenon (Scalene -- RL), but all and none of these at once." [Berkeley (1975b), p.81.]

 

Based on his own inability to form any such 'abstract ideas', Berkeley casts serious doubt on the capacity of others to conceive of them, either:

 

"I can imagine a man with two heads or the upper parts of a man joined to the body of a horse. I can consider the hand, the eye, the nose, each by itself abstracted or separated from the rest of the body. But then whatever hand or eye I imagine, it must have some particular shape and colour. Likewise the idea of a man that I frame to myself, must be either of a white, or a black, or a tawny, a straight, or a crooked, a tall or low, or a middle-sized man. I cannot by any effort of thought conceive the abstract idea above described [of a general man]. And it is equally impossible for me to form the abstract idea of motion distinct from the body moving, and which is neither swift nor slow, curvilinear nor rectilinear; and the like may be said of all other abstract general ideas whatsoever." [Ibid., p.78.]

 

That isn't to deny the above points might be translated into some sort of logical form, based on what we mean by such terms. Given Berkeley's other comments about the importance of ordinary language, it is a little surprising he didn't go down that route.

 

A somewhat similar argument can be found in Frege (in his review of Husserl's Philosophy of Arithmetic):

 

"Abstraction

 

"The author himself finds a difficulty about the abstraction that provides the general concept of the collective. He says (p.84):

 

'The peculiarities of the individual contents that are collected...must be completely abstracted from, but at the same time their connection must be maintained. This seems to involve a difficulty, if not a psychological impossibility. If we take the abstraction seriously, then the individual contents vanish, and so, naturally, does their collective unity, instead of remaining behind as a conceptual extract. The solution is obvious. To abstract from something simply means: not to attend to it specially.' 

 

"The kernel of this explanation is obviously to be found in the word 'specially'. Inattention is a very strong lye; it must be applied at not too great a concentration, so that everything does not dissolve, and likewise not too dilute, so that it effects a sufficient change in the things. Thus it is a question of getting the right degree of dilution; this is difficult to manage, and I at any rate have never succeeded.... [Detaching our attention] is particularly effective. We attend less to a property, and it disappears. By making one characteristic after another disappear, we get more and more abstract concepts…. Inattention is a most efficacious logical faculty; presumably this accounts for the absentmindedness of professors. Suppose there are a black and a white cat sitting side by side before us. We stop attending to their colour, and they become colourless, but are still sitting side by side. We stop attending to their posture, and they are no longer sitting (though they have not assumed another posture), but each one is still in its place. We stop attending to position; they cease to have place, but still remain different. In this way, perhaps, we obtain from each one of them a general concept of Cat. By continual application of this procedure, we obtain from each object a more and more bloodless phantom. Finally we thus obtain from each object a something wholly deprived of content; but the something obtained from one object is different from the something obtained from another object -- though it is not easy to say how." [Frege (1980), pp.84-85. Bold emphases alone added; several paragraphs merged.]

 

Frege's sharpest criticisms were reserved for contemporaneous theorists who imagined that mathematical concepts could be created, or perhaps apprehended, by a 'process of abstraction'; in particular, the views of the 19th century mathematician and Mystical Platonist, Georg Cantor (and this also included the latter's 'followers'):

 

"We may begin here by making a general observation. When negroes from the heart of Africa see a telescope or pocket watch for the first time, they are inclined to credit these things with the most astounding magical properties. Many mathematicians react to philosophical expressions in a similar manner. I am thinking in particular here of the following: 'define' (Brahma), 'reflect' (Vishnu), 'abstract' (Shiva). The names of the Indian gods in brackets are meant to indicate the kind of magical effects the expressions are supposed to have. If, for instance, you find that some property of a thing bothers you, you abstract from it. But if you want to call a halt to this process of destruction so that the properties you want to see retained should not be obliterated in the process, you reflect on these properties. If, finally, you feel sorely the lack of certain properties in the thing, you bestow them on it by definition. In your possession of these miraculous powers you are not far removed from the Almighty. The significance this would have is practically beyond measure. Think of how these powers could be put to use in the classroom: the teacher has a good-natured but lazy and stupid pupil. He will then abstract from the laziness and the stupidity, reflecting all the while on the good-naturedness. Then by means of a definition he will confer on him the properties of keenness and intelligence. Of course so far people have confined themselves to mathematics. The following dialogue may serve an illustration:

 

'Mathematician: The sign √(−1) has the property of yielding -1 when squared.

 

'Layman: This pattern of printer's ink on paper? I can't see any trace of this property. Perhaps it has been discovered with the aid of a microscope or by some chemical means?

 

'Mathematician: It can't be arrived at by any process of sense perception. And of course it isn't produced by the mere printer's ink either; a magic incantation, called a definition, has first to be pronounced over it.

 

'Layman: Ah, now I understand. You expressed yourself badly. You mean that a definition is used to stipulate that this pattern is a sign for something with those properties.

 

'Mathematician: Not at all! It is a sign, but it doesn't designate or mean anything. It itself has these properties, precisely in virtue of the definition.

 

'Layman: What extraordinary people you mathematicians are, and no mistake! You don't bother at all about the properties a thing actually has, but imagine that in their stead you can bestow a property on it by a definition -- a property that the thing in its innocence doesn't dream of -- and now you investigate the property and believe in that way you can accomplish the most extraordinary things!'

 

"This illustrates the might of the mathematical Brahma. In Cantor it is Shiva and Vishnu who receive the greater honour. Faced with a cage of mice, mathematicians react differently when the number of them is in question. Some…include in the number the mice just as they are, down to the last hair; others -- and I may surely count Cantor amongst them -- find it out of place that hairs should form part of the number and so abstract from them. They find in mice a whole host of things besides which are out of place in number and are unworthy to be included in it. Nothing simpler: one abstracts from the whole lot. Indeed when you get down to it everything in the mice is out of place: the beadiness of their eyes no less than the length of their tails and the sharpness of their teeth. So one abstracts from the nature of the mice. But from their nature as what is not said; so one abstracts presumably from all their properties, even from those in virtue of which we call them mice, even from those in virtue of which we call them animals, three-dimensional beings -- properties which distinguish them, for instance, from the number 2.

 

"Cantor demands more: to arrive at cardinal numbers, we are required to abstract from the order in which they are given. What is to be understood by this? Well, if at a certain moment we compare the positions of the mice, we see that of any two one is further to the north than the other, or that both are to the same distance to the north. The same applies to east and west and above and below. But this is not all: if we compare the mice in respect of their ages, we find likewise that of any two one is older than the other or that both have the same age. We can go on and compare them in respect of their length, both with and without their tails, in respect of the pitch of their squeaks, their weight, their muscular strength, and in many other respects besides. All these relations generate an order. We shall surely not go astray if we take it that this is what Cantor calls the order in which things are given. So we are meant to abstract from this order too. Now surely many people will say 'But we have already abstracted from their being in space; so ipso facto we have already abstracted from north and south, from difference in their lengths. We have already abstracted from the ages of the animals, and so ipso facto from one's being older than another. So why does special mention also have to be made of order?'

 

"Well, Cantor also defines what he calls an ordinal type; and in order to arrive at this, we have, so he tells us, to stop short of abstracting from the order in which the things are given. So presumably this will be possible too, though only with Vishnu's help. We can hardly dispense with this in other cases too. For the moment let us stay with the cardinal numbers.

 

"So let us get a number of men together and ask them to exert themselves to the utmost in abstracting from the nature of the pencil and the order in which its elements are given. After we have allowed them sufficient time for this difficult task, we ask the first 'What general concept…have you arrived at?' Non-mathematician that he is, he answers 'Pure Being.' The second thinks rather 'Pure nothingness', the third -- I suspect a pupil of Cantor's -- 'The cardinal number one.' A fourth is perhaps left with the woeful feeling that everything has evaporated, a fifth -- surely a pupil of Cantor's -- hears an inner voice whispering that graphite and wood, the constituents of the pencil, are 'constitutive elements', and so arrives at the general concept called the cardinal number two. Now why shouldn't one man come out with the answer and the other with another? Whether in fact Cantor's definitions have the sharpness and precision their author boasts of is accordingly doubtful to me. But perhaps we got such varying replies because it was a pencil we carried out our experiment with. It may be said 'But a pencil isn't a set.' Why not? Well then, let us look at the moon. 'The moon is not a set either!' What a pity! The cardinal number one would be only too happy to come into existence at any place and at any time, and the moon seemed the very thing to assist at the birth. Well then, let us take a heap of sand. Oh dear, there's someone already trying to separate the grains. 'You are surely not going to try and count then all! That is strictly forbidden! You have to arrive at the number by a single act of abstraction....' 'But in order to be able to abstract from the nature of a grain of sand, I must surely first have looked at it, grasped it, come to know it!' 'That's quite unnecessary. What would happen to the infinite cardinals in that case? By the time you had looked at the last grain, you would be bound to have forgotten the first ones. I must emphasise once more that you are meant to arrive at the number by a single act of abstraction. Of course for that you need the help of supernatural powers. Surely you don't imagine you can bring it off by ordinary abstraction. When you look at books, some in quarto, some in octavo, some thick, some thin, some in Gothic type and some in Roman and you abstract from these properties which distinguish them, and thus arrive at, say, the concept 'book', this, when you come down to it, is no great feat. Allow me to clarify for you the difference between ordinary abstraction and the higher, supernatural, kind.

 

"With ordinary abstraction we start out by comparing objects a, b, c, and find that they agree in many properties but differ in others. We abstract from the latter and arrive at a concept Φ under which a and b and c all fall. Now this concept has neither the properties abstracted from nor those common to a, b and c. The concept 'book', for instance, no more consists of printed sheets -- although the individual books we started by comparing do consist of such -- than the concept 'female mammal' bears young or suckles them with milk secreted from its glands; for it has no glands. Things are quite different with supernatural abstraction. Here we have, for instance, a heap of sand...." [Frege (1979), pp.69-71. Unfortunately, the manuscript breaks off at this point. Italic emphases in the original. Links added; quotation marks altered, and the passage reformatted, to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

Frege's parody of Cantor here illustrates just how ridiculous it is to suppose that abstraction can create mathematical concepts out of mere signs, or, indeed, out of anything.

 

[Frege's comments find an echo in the thoughts of the late Fraser Cowley, quoted elsewhere in this Essay. Frege's criticisms of Cantor are summarised in Dauben (1979), pp.220-25. A more detailed discussion of these issues can be found in Dummett (1991). On the mystical provenance of much of Cantor's decidedly odd ideas, see Aczel (2000).]

 

The Young Marx And Engels

 

[This material also used to appear in Note 24.]

 

There are several remarkably similar passages to the above in Marx's earlier work:

 

"Is it surprising that everything, in the final abstraction -- for we have here an abstraction, and not an analysis -- presents itself as a logical category? Is it surprising that, if you let drop little by little all that constitutes the individuality of a house, leaving out first of all the materials of which it is composed, then the form that distinguishes it, you end up with nothing but a body; that if you leave out of account the limits of this body, you soon have nothing but a space -- that if, finally, you leave out of account the dimensions of this space, there is absolutely nothing left but pure quantity, the logical category? If we abstract thus from every subject all the alleged accidents, animate or inanimate, men or things, we are right in saying that in the final abstraction the only substance left is the logical categories. Thus the metaphysicians, who in making these abstractions, think they are making analyses, and who, the more they detach themselves from things, imagine themselves to be getting all the nearer to the point of penetrating to their core…. Just as by means of abstraction we have transformed everything into a logical category, so one has only to make an abstraction of every characteristic distinctive of different movements to attain movement in its abstract condition -- purely formal movement, the purely logical formula of movement. If one finds in logical categories the substance of all things, one imagines one has found in the logical formula of movement the absolute method, which not only explains all things, but also implies the movement of things...." [Marx (1978), pp.99-100. Bold emphases alone added; paragraphs merged.]

 

However, in a passage that has already been quoted several times -- taken from The Holy Family, and which reveals Marx and Engels at the height of their philosophical powers when young -- we find the following acute observations (notice a similar reference to Vishnu that we met in Frege's remarks, above):

 

"Now that Critical Criticism as the tranquillity of knowledge has 'made' all the mass-type 'antitheses its concern', has mastered all reality in the form of categories and dissolved all human activity into speculative dialectics, we shall see it produce the world again out of speculative dialectics. It goes without saying that if the miracles of the Critically speculative creation of the world are not to be 'desecrated', they can be presented to the profane mass only in the form of mysteries. Critical Criticism therefore appears in the incarnation of Vishnu-Szeliga as a mystery-monger.... ["Szeliga" was the pseudonym of a young Hegelian, Franz Zychlinski -- RL] The mystery of the Critical presentation of the Mystéres de Paris is the mystery of speculative, of Hegelian construction. Once Herr Szeliga has proclaimed that 'degeneracy within civilisation' and rightlessness in the state are 'mysteries', i.e., has dissolved them in the category 'mystery', he lets 'mystery' begin its speculative career. A few words will suffice to characterise speculative construction in general. Herr Szeliga's treatment of the Mystéres de Paris will give the application in detail.

 

"If from real apples, pears, strawberries and almonds I form the general idea 'Fruit', if I go further and imagine that my abstract idea 'Fruit', derived from real fruit, is an entity existing outside me, is indeed the true essence of the pear, the apple, etc., then -- in the language of speculative philosophy -- I am declaring that 'Fruit' is the 'Substance' of the pear, the apple, the almond, etc. I am saying, therefore, that to be an apple is not essential to the apple; that what is essential to these things is not their real existence, perceptible to the senses, but the essence that I have abstracted from them and then foisted on them, the essence of my idea -- 'Fruit'. I therefore declare apples, pears, almonds, etc., to be mere forms of existence, modi, of 'Fruit'. My finite understanding supported by my senses does of course distinguish an apple from a pear and a pear from an almond, but my speculative reason declares these sensuous differences inessential and irrelevant. It sees in the apple the same as in the pear, and in the pear the same as in the almond, namely 'Fruit'. Particular real fruits are no more than semblances whose true essence is 'the substance' -- 'Fruit'. By this method one attains no particular wealth of definition. The mineralogist whose whole science was limited to the statement that all minerals are really 'the Mineral' would be a mineralogist only in his imagination. For every mineral the speculative mineralogist says 'the Mineral', and his science is reduced to repeating this word as many times as there are real minerals. Having reduced the different real fruits to the one 'fruit' of abstraction -- 'the Fruit', speculation must, in order to attain some semblance of real content, try somehow to find its way back from 'the Fruit', from the Substance to the diverse, ordinary real fruits, the pear, the apple, the almond etc. It is as hard to produce real fruits from the abstract idea 'the Fruit' as it is easy to produce this abstract idea from real fruits. Indeed, it is impossible to arrive at the opposite of an abstraction without relinquishing the abstraction.

 

"The speculative philosopher therefore relinquishes the abstraction 'the Fruit', but in a speculative, mystical fashion -- with the appearance of not relinquishing it. Thus it is really only in appearance that he rises above his abstraction. He argues somewhat as follows: If apples, pears, almonds and strawberries are really nothing but 'the Substance', 'the Fruit', the question arises: Why does 'the Fruit' manifest itself to me sometimes as an apple, sometimes as a pear, sometimes as an almond? Why this semblance of diversity which so obviously contradicts my speculative conception of Unity, 'the Substance', 'the Fruit'? This, answers the speculative philosopher, is because 'the Fruit' is not dead, undifferentiated, motionless, but a living, self-differentiating, moving essence. The diversity of the ordinary fruits is significant not only for my sensuous understanding, but also for 'the Fruit' itself and for speculative reason. The different ordinary fruits are different manifestations of the life of the 'one Fruit'; they are crystallisations of 'the Fruit' itself. Thus in the apple 'the Fruit' gives itself an apple-like existence, in the pear a pear-like existence. We must therefore no longer say, as one might from the standpoint of the Substance: a pear is 'the Fruit', an apple is 'the Fruit', an almond is 'the Fruit', but rather 'the Fruit' presents itself as a pear, 'the Fruit' presents itself as an apple, 'the Fruit' presents itself as an almond; and the differences which distinguish apples, pears and almonds from one another are the self-differentiations of 'the Fruit' and make the particular fruits different members of the life-process of 'the Fruit'. Thus 'the Fruit' is no longer an empty undifferentiated unity; it is oneness as allness, as 'totality' of fruits, which constitute an 'organically linked series of members'. In every member of that series 'the Fruit' gives itself a more developed, more explicit existence, until finally, as the 'summary' of all fruits, it is at the same time the living unity which contains all those fruits dissolved in itself just as it produces them from within itself, just as, for instance, all the limbs of the body are constantly dissolved in and constantly produced out of the blood.

 

"We see that if the Christian religion knows only one Incarnation of God, speculative philosophy has as many incarnations as there are things, just as it has here in every fruit an incarnation of the Substance, of the Absolute Fruit. The main interest for the speculative philosopher is therefore to produce the existence of the real ordinary fruits and to say in some mysterious way that there are apples, pears, almonds and raisins. But the apples, pears, almonds and raisins that we rediscover in the speculative world are nothing but semblances of apples, semblances of pears, semblances of almonds and semblances of raisins, for they are moments in the life of 'the Fruit', this abstract creation of the mind, and therefore themselves abstract creations of the mind. Hence what is delightful in this speculation is to rediscover all the real fruits there, but as fruits which have a higher mystical significance, which have grown out of the ether of your brain and not out of the material earth, which are incarnations of 'the Fruit', of the Absolute Subject. When you return from the abstraction, the supernatural creation of the mind, 'the Fruit', to real natural fruits, you give on the contrary the natural fruits a supernatural significance and transform them into sheer abstractions. Your main interest is then to point out the unity of 'the Fruit' in all the manifestations of its life…that is, to show the mystical interconnection between these fruits, how in each of them 'the Fruit' realizes itself by degrees and necessarily progresses, for instance, from its existence as a raisin to its existence as an almond. Hence the value of the ordinary fruits no longer consists in their natural qualities, but in their speculative quality, which gives each of them a definite place in the life-process of 'the Absolute Fruit'.

 

"The ordinary man does not think he is saying anything extraordinary when he states that there are apples and pears. But when the philosopher expresses their existence in the speculative way he says something extraordinary. He performs a miracle by producing the real natural objects, the apple, the pear, etc., out of the unreal creation of the mind 'the Fruit'. And in regard to every object the existence of which he expresses, he accomplishes an act of creation. It goes without saying that the speculative philosopher accomplishes this continuous creation only by presenting universally known qualities of the apple, the pear, etc., which exist in reality, as determining features invented by him, by giving the names of the real things to what abstract reason alone can create, to abstract formulas of reason, finally, by declaring his own activity, by which he passes from the idea of an apple to the idea of a pear, to be the self-activity of the Absolute Subject, 'the Fruit.' In the speculative way of speaking, this operation is called comprehending Substance as Subject, as an inner process, as an Absolute Person, and this comprehension constitutes the essential character of Hegel's method." [Marx and Engels (1975a), pp.54-60. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Bold emphases alone added. Several paragraphs merged.]

 

This quotation almost completely demolishes the DM-theory of abstraction. It is a pity that both Marx and Engels later seem to have lost the philosophical clarity of thought they displayed in this passage. In many respects it anticipates Frege's and Wittgenstein's approach to abstract general ideas, even though it is phrased in a completely different philosophical idiom.

 

It is worth underlining the fact that this passage exposes the sham nature of the 'dialectical circuit', not just Hegel's use of it. As Marx and Engels point out:

 

"Having reduced the different real fruits to the one 'fruit' of abstraction -– 'the Fruit', speculation must, in order to attain some semblance of real content, try somehow to find its way back from 'the Fruit', from the Substance to the diverse, ordinary real fruits, the pear, the apple, the almond etc…. Indeed, it is impossible to arrive at the opposite of an abstraction without relinquishing the abstraction…. When you return from the abstraction, the supernatural creation of the mind, 'the Fruit', to real natural fruits, you give on the contrary the natural fruits a supernatural significance and transform them into sheer abstractions. Your main interest is then to point out the unity of 'the Fruit' in all the manifestations of its life…that is, to show the mystical interconnection between these fruits, how in each of them 'the Fruit' realizes itself by degrees and necessarily progresses, for instance, from its existence as a raisin to its existence as an almond. Hence the value of the ordinary fruits no longer consists in their natural qualities, but in their speculative quality, which gives each of them a definite place in the life-process of 'the Absolute Fruit.'" [Ibid., pp.58-60. Bold emphases alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site; paragraphs merged.]

 

Marx and Engels were perfectly clear: no amount of "careful empirical" checking can turn a creature of abstraction back into its concrete alter ego:

 

"Indeed, it is impossible to arrive at the opposite of an abstraction without relinquishing the abstraction…. When you return from the abstraction, the supernatural creation of the mind, 'the Fruit', to real natural fruits, you give on the contrary the natural fruits a supernatural significance and transform them into sheer abstractions." [Ibid. Bold emphasis alone added.]

 

It is also worth pointing out that Marx and Engels anticipated (several aspects of) the approach adopted in these Essays -- i.e., that abstract general ideas are the result of a syntactically inept re-configuration of ordinary general terms (covered in detail in Part One of this Essay). As they themselves note:

 

"The ordinary man does not think he is saying anything extraordinary when he states that there are apples and pears. But when the philosopher expresses their existence in the speculative way he says something extraordinary. He performs a miracle by producing the real natural objects, the apple, the pear, etc., out of the unreal creation of the mind 'the Fruit'…. It goes without saying that the speculative philosopher accomplishes this continuous creation only by presenting universally known qualities of the apple, the pear, etc., which exist in reality, as determining features invented by him, by giving the names of the real things to what abstract reason alone can create, to abstract formulas of reason, finally, by declaring his own activity, by which he passes from the idea of an apple to the idea of a pear, to be the self-activity of the Absolute Subject, 'the Fruit.'" [Ibid., p.60. Bold emphases alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site; paragraphs merged.]

 

This represents a move away from a purely psychological critique of abstractionism. Marx and Engels quite rightly argue that it is a distortion of language that gives rise to these 'abstractions'. Indeed, they also underlined this approach to ordinary language (and the distortion it suffers in the hands of Philosophers) in The German Ideology (also partially quoted earlier):

 

"For philosophers, one of the most difficult tasks is to descend from the world of thought to the actual world. Language is the immediate actuality of thought. Just as philosophers have given thought an independent existence, so they had to make language into an independent realm. This is the secret of philosophical language, in which thoughts in the form of words have their own content. The problem of descending from the world of thoughts to the actual world is turned into the problem of descending from language to life. We have shown that thoughts and ideas acquire an independent existence in consequence of the personal circumstances and relations of individuals acquiring independent existence. We have shown that exclusive, systematic occupation with these thoughts on the part of ideologists and philosophers, and hence the systematisation of these thoughts, is a consequence of division of labour, and that, in particular, German philosophy is a consequence of German petty-bourgeois conditions. The philosophers would only have to dissolve their language into the ordinary language, from which it is abstracted, to recognise it as the distorted language of the actual world, and to realise that neither thoughts nor language in themselves form a realm of their own, that they are only manifestations of actual life." [Marx and Engels (1970), p.118. Bold emphases alone added; paragraphs merged.]

 

The highlighted words above serve as one of the guiding principles of this site. Indeed, Wittgenstein himself could almost have written them. It directly connects abstractionism with linguistic distortion.

 

In his perceptive analysis of Metaphysics, the late Fraser Cowley had this to say about 'abstract universals':

 

"In the traditional doctrine, according to which one can both refer to universals and predicate them of particulars and other universals, a general term like 'lion' would signify or designate a universal. This universal would be predicated of a particular in such a sentence as 'This is a lion' and referred to in such a sentence as 'The lion is a creature of the cat family.' The lion being carnivorous and subject, I believe, to melancholy in captivity, that universal would be carnivorous and subject to melancholy. And just as one can point to an animal and say 'this kind' or 'this species', so one should be able to point to one and say 'This universal comes from East Africa'…. But clearly 'universal' is not admissible in such contexts, and this shows that the logical syntax is quite different from that of 'kind,' 'sort,' 'type,' 'species,' and so on…. Many people have tried in their metaphysical performances consciously or half consciously to avoid such nonsense by referring, for example, to the universal which is allegedly predicated in 'This beast is a lion,' by the expression 'lionhood.' Many similar malformations occur in philosophical writings -– doghood, thinghood, eventhood, and so on. They are formed by mistaken analogy with manhood, womanhood, girlhood, widowhood, bachelorhood, and of course not with neighborhood, hardihood, falsehood, likelihood, or Little Red Riding Hood." [Cowley (1991), p.92. Italic emphases in the original. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site; paragraphs merged.]

 

Linguistic monstrosities like those above -- and worse -- positively litter the pages of books and articles written by Traditional Philosophers in their Ancient, Medieval and Modern incarnations. For example, in a recent book on 'the nature of Time' we find the following rather bizarre terminology:

 

"Any property partly composed of presentness, apart from the two properties of pastness and futurity is not an A-property." [Smith (1993), p.6.]

 

In relation to which we note with Frege that the powers of certain Hindu Deities have again been channelled in order to conjure (out of thin air) the required temporal 'properties': "pastness", "presentness" and "futurity." There are countless pages of material like this in contemporary Metaphysics, and not just in connection with theories concerning 'the nature of Time'.

 

[Sustained criticism of abstract general concepts and ideas (as well as Essentialism, itself) can be found in the following: Hallett (1984, 1988, 1991) and Kennick (1972). A more general refutation of abstractionism is developed in Geach (1957). A broad attack on the nature of abstract objects can be accessed in Teichmann (1992). See also here.]

 

'Appearance' And 'Reality'

 

As noted several times, 'abstractionism' is intimately connected with another ancient Aristocratic distinction -- i.e., the one drawn between 'appearance' and 'reality'. The 'process of abstraction' is supposed enable philosophers to delve beneath 'appearances' in order to access 'abstract' ideas, concepts and 'essences', which are somehow more real than 'surface appearances'. So, anyone who buys into this approach to the acquisition of knowledge is also buying into the theory that 'Reality' is in the end Ideal. If 'abstractions' enjoy a 'level of reality' set above that of the material objects we meet in the world around us -- especially if the former somehow lend 'substance' to, or even constitute, the latter -- then how can this approach be described as anything other than full-blooded Idealism?

 

One of the more important issues in need of resolution is whether or not 'appearances' are in some way deceptive, or even false. As we will see, DM-theorists equivocate on this topic, mainly because Hegel did, too. However, as we will also see, what they actually say implies they do think 'appearances' are in some sense false or misleading. But, as with most things in this area, crystal clear conclusions are hard to find -- and even harder to justify.

 

It is to such issues and their consequences that I now turn.

 

The Underlying 'Essence' Of 'Being'

 

A cursory glance through the first half of this Essay might prompt the conclusion that it ignores the fact that scientists actually use the process of abstraction in their search for knowledge, and have done so for many centuries. Hence, according to that widely held belief -- certainly widely held among DM-fans -- they (still) do so in order to discover, or, perhaps, 'uncover', the underlying, "objective" or "essential" nature of 'reality'.

 

[The first part of that counter-claim was in fact examined earlier, here and here; both halves will be re-examined in more detail in Essay Thirteen Part Two, to be published in late 2025.]

 

However, the above objection invites scrutiny of three distinctions that DM-theorists have also inherited from Traditional Metaphysics; i.e., those between:

 

(i) "Appearance" and "Reality";

 

(ii) "Essence" and "Accident"; and,

 

(iii) "Necessity" and "Contingency". [This particular topic will be covered in much more detail in Essay Three Part Five.]

 

Once again dialecticians have (unwisely) bought into these ancient, Aristocratic distinctions, naively accepting what was originally a class-motivated dogma that 'appearances' aren't 'fully real', and that 'abstraction' (or 'thought') is required if philosophers and scientists are to penetrate the outer shell of 'appearances' in order to gain (genuine, if only partial and 'relative') knowledge of the underlying 'rational order of reality'. [And, yes, I do know that philosophy and science weren't overtly distinguished until way into the 19th century, but that doesn't mean no (earlier) distinction was drawn between them. That issue will also be explored in Essay Thirteen Part Two.]

 

Earlier we saw Plato set the stage for this:

 

"If mind and true opinion are two distinct classes, then I say that there certainly are these self-existent ideas unperceived by sense, and apprehended only by the mind; if, however, as some say, true opinion differs in no respect from mind, then everything that we perceive through the body is to be regarded as most real and certain. But we must affirm that to be distinct, for they have a distinct origin and are of a different nature; the one is implanted in us by instruction, the other by persuasion; the one is always accompanied by true reason, the other is without reason; the one cannot be overcome by persuasion, but the other can: and lastly, every man may be said to share in true opinion, but mind is the attribute of the gods and of very few men. Wherefore also we must acknowledge that there is one kind of being which is always the same, uncreated and indestructible, never receiving anything into itself from without, nor itself going out to any other, but invisible and imperceptible by any sense, and of which the contemplation is granted to intelligence only." [Plato (1997c), 51e-52a, pp.1254-55. I have used the on-line version here. Bold emphases added. The published edition translates the third set of highlighted words as follows: "It is indivisible -- it cannot be perceived by the senses at all -- and it is the role of the understanding to study it." Cornford renders it thus: "[It is] invisible and otherwise imperceptible; that, in fact, which thinking has for its object." (Cornford (1997), p.192.)]

 

The adoption by DM-theorists of the above (general) approach held out the prospect that they, too, could comprehend scientifically and philosophically, not just 'appearances', but the 'essence(s)' that supposedly underpinned each object and process in nature and society.

 

Ironically, as we are about to discover, that is the exact opposite of what finally emerged at the end of this (futile) exercise.

 

In connection with this, TAR advanced the following remarks:

 

"The important thing about a Marxist understanding of the distinction between the appearance of things and their essence is twofold: 1) by delving beneath the mass of surface phenomena, it is possible to see the essential relations governing historical change -- thus beneath the appearance of a free and fair market transaction it is possible to see the exploitative relations of class society, but, 2) this does not mean that surface appearances can simply be dismissed as ephemeral events of no consequence. In revealing the essential relations in society, it is also possible to explain more fully than before why they appear in a form different to their real nature. To explain, for instance, why it is that the exploitative class relations at the point of production appear as the exchange of 'a fair day's work for a fair day's pay' in the polished surface of the labour market." [Rees (1998), p.187. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Bold emphases alone added.]

 

Other dialecticians have expressed more-or-less the same ideas:

 

"But this tendency in capitalism goes even further. The fetishistic character of economic forms, the reification of all human relations, the constant expansion and extension of the division of labour which subjects the process of production to an abstract, rational analysis, without regard to the human potentialities and abilities of the immediate producers, all these things transform the phenomena of society and with them the way in which they are perceived. In this way arise the 'isolated' facts, 'isolated' complexes of facts, separate, specialist disciplines (economics, law, etc.) whose very appearance seems to have done much to pave the way for such scientific methods. It thus appears extraordinarily 'scientific' to think out the tendencies implicit in the facts themselves and to promote this activity to the status of science. By contrast, in the teeth of all these isolated and isolating facts and partial systems, dialectics insists on the concrete unity of the hole. Yet although it exposes these appearances for the illusions they are -- albeit illusions necessarily engendered by capitalism in this 'scientific' atmosphere it still gives the impression of being an arbitrary construction." [Lukacs (1971), p.6. Bold emphasis added; paragraphs merged. Link in the original.]

 

"It is because of this very sequence of the successive grades of scientific knowledge that science can evolve. Knowledge advances by the road of contradiction. It is accompanied by errors, by deviations from the direct attainment of its object. The external appearance of things for a time hides the true content of objects from the eyes of the seeker. Thus when first we look at merchant-capitalist society the relations between people are hidden by the relations between things. But the practical mastery of the material world tears away the covering of appearance from the objects of investigation, rectifies error by transforming into actuality the true objective content of knowledge, and purges science of the illusory. Scientific experience, which is handed over by one generation to the next, and is each time enriched by some new scientific discovery, is all the time increasing the possibility of an adequate knowledge of the objective world. The experience of industrial practice, the traditions of revolution, scientific discoveries, the store of ideas, are handed over from one epoch to the next and ever more deeply disclose the infinite possibilities of human thought. In the unlimited advance of human history, at every new step of its development there is a fuller, richer, more diverse revelation of the absolute content of the material world, which content, though confined within historically limited ideas, is nevertheless absolute truth. The progressive advance of human thought, the law-governed connection of its different stages, were guessed in an inspired manner by Hegel, who criticized both the metaphysical view of knowledge (which admits only the eternity of truths), and relativism. In his Phenomenology of Spirit he characterizes the succession of philosophic systems in the following words:

 

'The more the ordinary mind takes the opposition between true and false to be fixed, the more is it accustomed to expect either agreement or contradiction with a given philosophical system, and only to see the one or the other in any explanation about such a system. It does not conceive the diversity of philosophical systems as the progressive evolution of truth; rather it sees only contradiction in that variety. The bud disappears when the blossom breaks through, and we might say that the former is refuted by the latter; in the same way when the fruit comes, the blossom may be explained to be a false form of the plant’s existence, for the fruit appears as its true nature in place of the blossom. These stages are not merely differentiated; they supplant one another as being incompatible with one another. But the ceaseless activity of their own inherent nature makes them at the same time moments of an organic unity, where they not merely do not contradict one another, but where one is as necessary as the other; and this equal necessity of all moments constitutes from the outset the life of the whole.' [We might note in passing the batty nature of Hegel's analogy between budding plants and the advance of knowledge -- RL. (Bold emphasis added by RL.)]

 

"But, for Hegel, the inevitable development which gives rise to these different ideas and successive systems arises from a merely logical unfolding, so that they are revealed finally as only moments of the 'absolute idea.' For dialectical materialists the unity of relative and absolute truth is based on the limitless development of social-historic practice, in which the systematic connections of the material world are disclosed." [Shirokov (1937), pp.123-24. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Bold emphases alone added. Shirokov is here quoting Hegel (1977), p.2, although that published edition differs slightly from the version posted at the Marxist Internet Archive (to which I have linked), and the alternative quoted by Shirokov.]

 

"[Appearance is a] philosophical term concerned with the relativity of perception and the difference between immediately given sensual knowledge and conceptual knowledge of the lawfulness of thingsAppearance is the dialectic of Form and Content, the recognition of the difference between them. In Hegel's Logic, Appearance is the second grade of Essence, moving beyond the recognition of the outer form of a thing to its lawful, inner character or content. Appearance is a modification of Being which includes Essence but is transient and unstable, because it is still partial or abstractly one-sided." [Glossary of terms at the Marxist Internet Archive. Bold emphasis alone added; link in the original.]

 

"Now, if you've never thought critically about how a capitalist economy works or never had the benefit of reading Marx, then all of that probably sounds like some pretty crazy sh*t. About as crazy as telling Joshua of the Hebrew Bible that the Sun is the stationary centre of the universe (or our solar system) and the Earth revolves around it. Only a madman would think such a thing. It is obvious that the Sun rises in East and sets in the West. But, in reality, the Sun rising and falling around the Earth is merely the form of appearance that the Sun takes from our immediate experience. If we took the Sun simply as it appears, never thought critically about its movements or lack thereof, then we would never be able to apprehend the nature of our solar system. Critical thought demands abstraction. We must organize the manifold objects of reality in the thought realm of our minds, which means we have to provisionally distance ourselves from the complex, concrete appearances and start with the most simple and abstract category that captures the phenomena we are attempting to understand. Hence, Marx starts with the commodity in the abstract." [Quoted from here. Bold emphases added; spelling modified to conform with UK English. Paragraphs merged.]

 

"But, as Marx said, 'all science would be superfluous if the outward appearance and the essence of things directly coincided' and the sun appears to go round the earth but in reality, as we all now know, it is the other way round." [John Molyneux, quoted from here. Accessed 09/02/2018. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"As we know appearances can be deceptive. Each day the sun appears to circumnavigate the earth, when the reality is that the earth travels around the sun. We therefore need to penetrate the veil of appearance in order to reveal the reality that is disguised within. That is the reason for Marxist economic theory. As the Soviet economist Rubin explained, 'Marx approaches human society by starting with things, and going through labour. He starts with things which are visible and moves to phenomena which have to be revealed by means of scientific research...'. We must see beyond the appearance of things to the real relationships." [Rob Sewell, quoted from here. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Link and bold emphases added.]

 

[Several more remarks like these -- from the likes of Herbert Marcuse, George Novack, Mao and others -- have been quoted in the next main sub-section.]

 

But, according to Rees -- who clearly agrees with Rubin, Shirokov, Lukacs and Hegel (at least in this respect) -- a commitment to scientific knowledge also involves a belief that:

 

"There is a deeper reality, but it must be able to account for the contradiction between it and the way it appears." [Rees (1998), p.188. Bold emphases added.]

 

This is apparently where the process of abstraction enters into the picture (no pun intended!):

 

"[K]nowledge requires an active process of abstraction capable of discriminating between essence and appearance." [Ibid., p.189. Bold added.]

 

"Critical thought demands abstraction. We must organize the manifold objects of reality in the thought realm of our minds, which means we have to provisionally distance ourselves from the complex, concrete appearances and start with the most simple and abstract category that captures the phenomena we are attempting to understand." [Quoted from here. Bold emphases added.]

 

Nevertheless, abstraction can't simply operate in isolation:

 

"[A]bstraction can be a method of seeing reality more clearly…[but] consciousness must issue in practical activity, which will furnish the proof of whether or not our conceptions of the world are accurate…. In conscious activity, human beings overcome the abstractness of thought by integrating it with concrete, immediate reality in all its complexity -- this is the moment when we see whether thought really does assume an objective form, whether it really can create the world, or whether it has mistaken the nature of reality and is therefore unable to enter the historical chain as an objective force which, in the case of the class struggle, seizes the masses…. [F]or Lenin practice overcomes the distinction between subjective and objective and the gap between essence and appearance." [Rees (1998), pp.190-91. Bold emphasis added. Paragraphs merged.]

 

Unfortunately, it is far from clear what much of the above actually means (and that isn't just because of the obscure language it uses). However, for present purposes attention will be confined to the supposed 'contradiction' between "appearance" and "deeper reality" (as both of these terms supposedly apply to the natural world).

 

["Social contradictions" will also be examined below, but in much more detail Essay Eight Parts Two and Three.]

 

As pointed out earlier, by these comments (and those quoted below), DM-theorists have clearly accepted the theory that 'surface appearances' (in nature and society) aren't 'fully real' (or might even be illusory), compared with the hidden, 'abstract world' that lies beneath -- which is 'fully real'.

 

As pointed out earlier, based on a 'process' that no one -- certainly not DM-theorists -- can explain, or even describe, Dialectical Marxists have accepted a theory that tries to tell us that there is a hidden world underlying 'appearances', accessible to thought alone, and which is the 'real world', not the material universe we see around us. And, as if to add insult to injury, they declare -- alongside card-carrying Idealists and Mystics -- that matter itself is an 'abstraction'

 

By such commitments, dialecticians reveal that they too are Idealists, whatever other terms they might prefer to use to describe themselves.

 

But why should that surprise anyone, given the fact that dialecticians have appropriated a theory concocted by a Christian Mystic (upside down or 'the right way up')?

 

Does 'Reality' Contradict 'Appearances'?

 

'Essence' and 'Appearance'

 

Do 'appearances' motivate false beliefs? Dialecticians appear to be rather confused about this (irony intended).

 

On the other hand, maybe hasty remarks like these are themselves seriously misleading?

 

In which case, it might be wise to back-track a little and examine in slightly more detail what Hegel and several DM-theorists have said about the connection between 'appearance' and 'reality'/'essence'/'actuality', as well as any connection it might have with the nature and origin of false beliefs.

 

[Having said that, there would hardly be much point in distinguishing 'appearance' from 'essence'/'reality' if they always agreed or coincided, or both delivered the unvarnished truth. Nor would there have been much point Marx asserting what he did about science, namely: "[A]ll science would be superfluous if the outward appearance and the essence of things directly coincided." (Marx (1981), p.956; Marx (1998), p.804.)]

 

Hegel

 

Unfortunately, trying to find a clear, joined-up or even consistent set of ideas in anything Hegel committed to paper on this topic (and practically everything else!) would be rather like looking for a tiny sliver of straw-coloured cotton buried somewhere in a dozen large haystacks while wearing sunglasses at dusk on an overcast, late Autumn day after knocking back half a bottle of Jim Beam!

 

Nevertheless, here are some of the things he did say (migraine tablets on stand-by):

 

"The view that the objects of immediate consciousness, which constitute the body of experience, are mere appearances (phenomena) was another important result of the Kantian philosophy. Common Sense, that mixture of sense and understanding, believes the objects of which it has knowledge to be severally independent and self-supporting; and when it becomes evident that they tend towards and limit one another, the interdependence of one upon another is reckoned something foreign to them and to their true nature. The very opposite is the truth. The things immediately known are mere appearances -- in other words, the ground of their being is not in themselves but in something else. But then comes the important step of defining what this something else is. According to Kant, the things that we know about are to us appearances only, and we can never know their essential nature, which belongs to another world we cannot approach. Plain minds have not unreasonably taken exception to this subjective idealism, with its reduction of the facts of consciousness to a purely personal world, created by ourselves alone. For the true statement of the case is rather as follows. The things of which we have direct consciousness are mere phenomena, not for us only, but in their own nature; and the true and proper case of these things, finite as they are, is to have their existence founded not in themselves but in the universal divine Idea. This view of things, it is true, is as idealist as Kant's; but in contradistinction to the subjective idealism of the Critical philosophy should be termed absolute idealism. Absolute idealism, however, though it is far in advance of vulgar realism, is by no means merely restricted to philosophy. It lies at the root of all religion; for religion too believes the actual world we see, the sum total of existence, to be created and governed by God." [Hegel (1975, §45, p.73. Links in the original. Bold emphases alone added.]

 

"The Essence must appear or shine forth. Its shining or reflection in it is the suspension and translation of it to immediacy, which, while as reflection-into-self it is matter or subsistence, is also form, reflection-on-something-else, a subsistence which sets itself aside. To show or shine is the characteristic by which essence is distinguished from Being -- by which it is essence; and it is this show which, when it is developed, shows itself, and is Appearance. Essence accordingly is not something beyond or behind appearance, but -- just because it is the essence which exists -- the existence is Appearance (Forth-shining).

 

"Existence stated explicitly in its contradiction is Appearance. But appearance (forth-showing) is not to be confused with a mere show (shining). Show is the proximate truth of Being or immediacy. The immediate, instead of being, as we suppose, something independent, resting on its own self, is a mere show, and as such it is packed or summed up under the simplicity of the immanent essence. The essence is, in the first place, the sum total of the showing itself, shining in itself (inwardly); but, far from abiding in this inwardness, it comes as a ground forward into existence; and this existence being grounded not in itself, but on something else, is just appearance. In our imagination we ordinarily combine with the term appearance or phenomenon the conception of an indefinite congeries of things existing, the being of which is purely relative, and which consequently do not rest on a foundation of their own, but are esteemed only as passing stages. But in this conception it is no less implied that essence does not linger behind or beyond appearance. Rather it is, we may say, the infinite kindness which lets its own show freely issue into immediacy, and graciously allows it the joy of existence. The appearance which is thus created does not stand on its own feet, and has its being not in itself but in something else. God who is the essence, when he lends existence to the passing stages of his own show in himself, may be described as the goodness that creates the world: but he is also the power above it, and the righteousness, which manifests the merely phenomenal character of the content of this existing world, whenever it tries to exist in independence." [Ibid., §131, pp.186-87. Links in the original; bold emphases added.]

 

Once more, this shows Hegel held these peculiar ideas for theological reasons. Even so, what he says here (e.g., "essence does not linger behind or beyond appearance") appears to contradict what we read below (no pun intended). I'll return to consider that possible interpretation presently.  

 

"Essence that issues from being seems to confront it as an opposite; this immediate being is, in the first instance, the unessential. But secondly, it is more than merely unessential being, it is essenceless being, it is illusory being [Illusory Being, Schein = Appearance -- RL.] Thirdly, this illusory being is not something external to or other than essence; on the contrary, it is essence's own illusory being. The showing of this illusory being within essence itself is reflection." [Hegel (1999), §818, p.394. Bold emphases alone added.]

 

This clearly implies that the opposite of 'essence' is 'illusory being' (Schein = appearance or illusion), and that can only mean that that opposite is in 'some sense false' or misleading. It is hard to see how anything that is "illusory" could be true, or fail to motivate a false belief --, or, at the very least, fail to be misleading. Indeed, Hegel even says as much:

 

"The view that the objects of immediate consciousness, which constitute the body of experience, are mere appearances (phenomena) was another important result of the Kantian philosophy. Common Sense, that mixture of sense and understanding, believes the objects of which it has knowledge to be severally independent and self-supporting; and when it becomes evident that they tend towards and limit one another, the interdependence of one upon another is reckoned something foreign to them and to their true nature. The very opposite is the truth. The things immediately known are mere appearances -- in other words, the ground of their being is not in themselves but in something else." [Ibid., §45, p.73. Bold emphasis added.]

 

Whatever is the "very opposite" of "the truth" can hardly be anything other than false or misleading.

 

[But see below, where that remark has been qualified.]

 

Michael Inwood adds the following thoughts concerning Hegel's opinions in this area:

 

"Essence shows or appears (scheint), but itself remains hidden behind a veil of Schein.... This suggests the idea of a world that is the reverse of the world of appearances, in which everything that has, in our world, a certain quality, has, in the world in itself, the opposite quality." [Inwood (1992), pp.39-40. Bold emphases alone added.]

 

Once more, it isn't easy to see how factors like this would fail to motivate false beliefs.

 

However, Hegel's theory is rather more complex than the above brief remarks might suggest (and why that earlier remark about trying to find a thin sliver of cotton thread hidden in several haystacks was apposite). It isn't as if 'essence' is 'true' and 'appearance' is 'false', to put it at its crudest. The relation between these two is much more involved (if that, too, is even the correct word to use here!). The background is again supplied for us by Inwood:

 

"Kant held that objects with which we are acquainted are appearances. So too does Hegel, or at least he regards some of them as appearances. But he does not mean the same by 'appearance' as Kant does. Kant distinguishes carefully between the words 'appearance' (Erscheinung) and 'illusion' (Schein). All phenomenal objects are appearances, in the sense that they are merely the way in which reality as it is in itself appears to us. But we can, nevertheless, distinguish between the illusory and the real within our experience, within the realm of appearances:

 

'When I say that the intuition of outer objects and the self-intuition of the mind alike represent the objects and the mind, in space and time, as they affect our sense, that is, as they appear. I do not mean to say that these objects are a mere illusion. For in an appearance the objects, nay even the properties that we ascribe to them, are always regarded as something actually given. Since, however, in the relation of the given object to the subject, such properties depend on the mode of intuition of the subject, this object as appearance is to be distinguished from itself as object in itself.' [Inwood is here quoting Kant (1998), B69, p.190, although he has employed a different translation. Link added.]

 

"Hegel, too, distinguishes between Schein and Erscheinung, but not in the same way that Kant does. The word Schein, for example, does not mean only 'illusion', but has connotations, over and above those which Kant ascribed to it, in virtue of its association with the verb scheinen, 'to shine'. Moreover, unlike Kant, Hegel calls physical entities Schein at least as often as he characterises them as Erscheinungen, though this is due in part to his liking for the pun on Sein ['to be' -- RL]. The important point, however, is that when Hegel claims that objects are appearances he does not mean what Kant meant:

 

'The objects of which we are immediately aware are mere appearances, i.e.,... they have the ground of their being not in themselves but in something else. But then the further question is how this something else is determined. According to the Kantian philosophy the things of which we are aware are only appearances for us, and their in-itself (Ansich) remains for us an inaccessible beyond.... The true situation is in fact this, that the things of which we are immediately aware are mere appearances not only for us but in themselves (an sich) and that the very essence (Bestimmung) of things which are thereby finite is to have the ground of their being not in themselves but in the universal divine idea. This conception of things is then also to be denoted as idealism, but, in contrast to that subjective idealism of the critical philosophy, as absolute idealism. This absolute idealism, although it goes beyond ordinary, realistic consciousness, is yet in substance so little to be regarded as the property of philosophy that it rather forms the basis of all religious consciousness, in so far as this too regards the sum of everything that exists (da ist), in general the world we see, as created and governed by God.' [Hegel (1975), §45, p.73. (This is a different translation of a passage quoted earlier.)]

 

"We might infer from this passage that everything except the logical idea itself is an appearance." [Inwood (2002), pp.408-09. Bold emphases alone added.]

 

Inwood then points out that even this might be to misinterpret Hegel(!), who sometimes distinguishes objects from appearances, although it isn't easy to see how he can do so consistently (no irony intended). Anyone interested can read for themselves Inwood's valiant attempt (over the next few pages of his book) to make some sort of coherent sense out of what Hegel was trying to say -- Inwood (2002), pp.409-16. In the end he is forced to conclude that for Hegel everything in the phenomenal world is an appearance, but grounded in "the logical idea", and hence in 'God'. [Ibid., p.413.]

 

In that case, comments like this are highly misleading:

 

"Hegel rejects the idea that reality is something which underlies appearance. He says that reality is manifest in appearance. Characteristics that we normally think only apply to our representations of reality actually apply to reality itself." [Sorensen (2003), p.304. Italics in the original.]

 

If 'reality' were indeed structured as Sorensen thinks Hegel imagined they were, why would we need philosophers to bring us the good news and open our eyes? It is precisely because a philosopher like Hegel thought that such 'gems of wisdom' were hidden from those who only rely on appearances -- and who are thereby deceived into thinking that this is all there is -- that he argued the way he did. [Not that it is quite as easy as Sorensen seems to think determining what, if anything, Hegel was actually banging on about!] Hence, even for Sorensen's version of Hegel, 'reality' lies behind 'appearances', although it has to 'shine' through (whatever that means) for thinkers like him, but not the rest of us, to see. No one before Hegel noticed all this 'shining', so for everyone else who thinks like this, appearances act more like shutters than they do windows.

 

 

Figure Six: Notice How The World Just 'Shines'

Through These Shutters?

 

Anyway, as we are about to see, Dialectical Marxists greatly 'simplified' this picture (in fact they hacked it to pieces in order to try to make some sort of sense of the tangled mess Hegel dumped on them!), which means it is more than a moot point whether they have been faithful to the distinction between 'appearance' and 'essence'/'reality' as Hegel seemed to conceived it. [Irony and mild sarcasm intended.]

 

Admittedly, it could be argued that 'Marxist dialectics' must stand or fall on its own merits. Quite so, but since Marxists use Hegel as some sort of philosophical Zimmer Frame, it isn't easy to see how 'Marxist dialectics' can stand on its own two (appearances of) feet.

 

 

Figure Seven: Is This The Reliable Support Hegel Appears

To Lend DM-Theorists?

 

It is to what they have to say that I now turn.

 

Dialectical Marxists

 

Despite the fact that dialecticians assert that 'appearance' and 'reality' (or, 'essence' and 'appearance', etc.) "contradict" each other, they seldom tell us with any clarity what that means, nor do they illustrate this alleged clash with a convincing array examples drawn from the natural world. [Those that supposedly arise in society will be examined presently.] Nevertheless, even if DM-theorists were to provide their readers with a full and complete explanation -- and, indeed, one blessed with uncharacteristic clarity -- it would still be difficult to see what the 'contradiction' here (between 'appearance' and 'reality') might actually be.26a

 

Admittedly, in addition to the passages quoted in an earlier sub-section and below, Marxist dialecticians have made some attempt to explain what they mean, albeit in manner not yet blessed with the sort of clarity intimated in the previous paragraph. Here, for example, is Herbert Marcuse expressing the overall idea (as best he can):

 

"Under the rule of formal logic, the notion of the conflict between essence and appearance is expendable if not meaningless; the material content is neutralised; the principle of identity is separated from the principle of contradiction (contradictions are the fault of incorrect thinking); final causes are removed from the logical order.... Existing as the living contradiction between essence and appearance, the objects of thought are of that 'inner negativity' which is the specific quality of their concept. The dialectical definition defines the movement of things from that which they are not to that which they are. The development of contradictory elements, which determines the structure of its object, also determines the structure of dialectical thought. The object of dialectical logic is neither the abstract, general form of objectivity, nor the abstract, general form of thought -- nor the data of immediate experience. Dialectical logic undoes the abstractions of formal logic and of transcendental philosophy, but it also denies the concreteness of immediate experience. To the extent to which this experience comes to rest with the things as they appear and happen to be, it is a limited and even false experience. It attains its truth if it has freed itself from the deceptive objectivity which conceals the factors behind the facts -- that is, if it understands its world as a historical universe, in which the established facts are the work of the historical practice of man. This practice (intellectual and material) is the reality in the data of experience; it is also the reality which dialectical logic comprehends." [Marcuse (1968), pp.114-17. Bold emphases alone added; paragraphs merged.]

 

"The doctrine of Essence seeks to liberate knowledge from the worship of 'observable facts' and from the scientific common sense that imposes this worship.... The real field of knowledge is not the given fact about things as they are, but the critical evaluation of them as a prelude to passing beyond their given form. Knowledge deals with appearances in order to get beyond them. 'Everything, it is said, has an essence, that is, things really are not what they immediately show themselves. There is therefore something more to be done than merely rove from one quality to another and merely to advance from one qualitative to quantitative, and vice versa: there is a permanence in things, and that permanent is in the first instance their Essence.' The knowledge that appearance and essence do not jibe is the beginning of truth. The mark of dialectical thinking is the ability to distinguish the essential from the apparent process of reality and to grasp their relation." [Marcuse (1973), pp.145-46. Marcuse is here quoting Hegel (1975), p.163, §112. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions employed at this site. Minor typo corrected.]

 

[We will see in Essay Eight Part Three how wide of the mark the opening sentence of the first of the above two passages actually is (i.e., concerning the lack of any connection between 'the principle of identity' and 'the principle of contradiction'). In addition, Marcuse's risible and ill-informed attempt to criticise Wittgenstein, Analytic Philosophy and the ordinary language of working people (in One Dimensional Man) has already been taken apart in Essay Thirteen Part Three.]

 

[FL = Formal Logic; HCD = High Church Dialectician; LCD = Low Church Dialectician (follow the links for an explanation of those terms).]

 

The above passages, of course, say more-or-less the same as John Rees (quoted earlier), but with just enough obscure jargon thrown in to bamboozle the 'uninitiated' -- and impress 'intellectuals'.

 

Even so, the reader will no doubt have noticed that an HCD of Marcuse's undoubted stature quotes not one single FL-text, or one single logician, in support of the following rather bold allegation:

 

"Under the rule of formal logic, the notion of the conflict between essence and appearance is expendable if not meaningless...". [Ibid.]

 

Marcuse must know that there are/were plenty of ancient and modern logicians and philosophers who did in fact adopt this way of talking about the distinction between 'essence' and 'appearance', even though FL itself doesn't seem to enter into any of this directly (or no more than rocket science itself depends on cookery). On the other hand, if it does, we still await proof that "Under the rule of formal logic, the notion of the conflict between essence and appearance is expendable if not meaningless." Marcuse certainly offered his readers none.

 

However, the next comment reveals a depth of confusion one normally associates with the logically-challenged LCD-wing of Dialectical Muddle:

 

"...the principle of identity is separated from the principle of contradiction (contradictions are the fault of incorrect thinking)...". [Ibid.]

 

So, it seems that HCD-honchos like Marcuse are just as clueless about FL as their lowly LCD-brethren appear to be. Indeed, as we have seen (here, for example), Hegel committed several of his own egregious logical blunders, upon which insecure foundation Marcuse unwisely based many of his own ideas.

 

This is quite apart from the (easily confirmed) fact that contradictions aren't the result of "incorrect thinking". As Marcuse should have known, had he bothered to stay awake in any logic classes, or lectures, he attended as a student (if he was actually present in any!), they can be, and often are, the result of one or more of the following:

 

(a) A genuine disagreement between two individuals;

 

(b) An argument aimed at constructing a reductio ad absurdum;

 

(c) A mismatch between theory and observation in the sciences (more on that in Essay Thirteen Part Two);

 

(d) An illustrative example in logic (where no mistakes have been made); or,

 

(e) An indirect proof in mathematics.

 

[(b) and (e) are, of course, variants of one another.]

 

In which case, many contradictions can be, and are, the result of an application of 'correct' thinking. One imagines Marcuse has simply confused falsehood with invalidity -- a 'rooky mistake', if ever there was one.

 

Finally, it is worth pointing out that Marcuse admits the following:

 

"To the extent to which this experience comes to rest with the things as they appear and happen to be, it is a limited and even false experience." [Ibid. Bold emphasis added.]

 

It seems he, too, holds the view that appearances can be, and (often?) are, false.

 

George Novack also weighed in on this topic -- and he did so with a characteristically brazen foray into dogmatic apriorism:

 

"What distinguishes essence or essential reality from mere appearance? A thing is truly real if it is necessary, if its appearance truly corresponds to its essence, and only so long as it proves itself to be necessary. Hegel, being the most consistent idealist, sought the source of this necessity in the movement of the universal mind, in the Absolute Idea. Materialists, on the other hand, locate the roots of necessity in the objective world, in the material conditions and conflicting forces which create, sustain and destroy all things. But, from the purely logical standpoint, both schools of philosophy agree in connecting reality with necessity.

 

"Something acquires reality because the necessary conditions for its production and reproduction are objectively present and operative. It becomes more or less real in accordance with the changes in the external and internal circumstances of its development. It remains truly real only so long and insofar as it is necessary under the given conditions. Then, as conditions change, it loses its necessity and its reality and dissolves into mere appearance. Let us consider a few illustrations of this process, this contradiction between essence and appearance, resulting from the different forms assumed by matter in its motion. In the production of the plant, seed, bud, flower and fruit are all equally necessary phases or forms of its existence. Taken separately, each by itself, they are all equally real, equally necessary, equally rational phases of the plant's development. [Here we see Novack isn't ashamed to cite approvingly Hegel's batty idea about blossoms, which we met earlier -- RL.]

 

"Yet each in turn becomes supplanted by the other and thereby becomes no less unnecessary and non-real. Each phase of the plant's manifestation appears as a reality and then is transformed in the course of development into an unreality or an appearance. This movement, triadic in this particular case, from unreality into reality and then back again to unreality, constitutes the essence, the inner movement behind all appearance. Appearance cannot be understood without an understanding of this process. It is this that determines whether any appearance in nature, society or in the mind is rational or non-rational." [Novack (1971), pp.86-87. Bold emphases added. Several paragraphs merged.]

 

It isn't my immediate concern to criticise this (almost classic) example of Mystical Natürphilosophie (however, it will be in a later Essay), but merely to note:

 

(a) The fanciful way that the term "contradiction" has been employed (without justification) by Novack; and,

 

(b) His idiosyncratic use of the word "appearance".

 

Exactly why a seed turning into a plant makes the seed an "appearance" Novack failed to say (except he seems happy to receive Hegel's word on such matters as Gospel Truth), but why any of this is a 'contradiction' he left no less mysterious. Of course, Novack's 'appearance' idea might be a faint echo of a theory Hegel aired that anything that is transient or which lacks permanence' [Inwood (2002), pp.408-13] -- and hence anything that does not "have the ground of [its] being...in [itself] but in something else" -- is an 'appearance'. In that sense, a plant (such as a tree) makes its first appearance as a seed, then as a seedling, next as a sapling and finally as a mature tree. But how does Novack know that something is "real" only if its "appearance" coincides with its "essence" (always assuming that there are such things as 'essences', to begin with)? That is, how does he know this over and above merely accepting Hegel's diktat to that effect?

 

Hegel's decidedly odd theory is in turn connected with the undeniable fact that some things 'appear' for a short time and then disappear or fade away, like someone who:

 

(i)   Has a part in a play (as in "NN, now appearing in Death of a Salesman on Broadway");

 

(ii)  Occupies an official position for a year;

 

(iii) Testifies in court (as in "NM is appearing for the defence");

 

(iv) Is famous only for fifteen minutes; or, maybe even when we,

 

(v) Describes how another looks -- as in "Her appearance gave her away; she was clearly amused", or "His appearance changes from day-to-day; he is a master of disguise."

 

Except for (v), what any of the above have to do with what appears to be the case when we observe the rise and fall of the Sun, the behaviour of sticks in water, or the change in size of our friends as the walk away from us is far from clear. In which case, Hegel appears to have conflated two different senses of "appear" (irony intended): what something looks like and transience.

 

In the second  of the above senses (i.e., transience) we might, at a stretch, say that a plant or a flower is "an appearance". At a stretch, that is certainly a valid (if trivial) point, but it is still unclear what it has to do with 'essence' and 'appearance'. Originally, the point here was, of course, to contrast the transient existence of certain phenomenal objects and processes with those that are perhaps more permanent. For example, the play mentioned above might only be on Broadway for a season, while Broadway will still be there after the play is well gone. So, it looks like (no pun intended) 'essence' is somehow connected with permanence, 'appearance' (in the sense that Hegel and Novack seem to intend) with transience. And yet, do any of these 'more permanent features of the world' have the 'ground of their being' within themselves (to paraphrase Hegel), or, from Hegels' perspective, do they not also 'rely on God'? If the latter is the case, then even 'essences' are also 'appearances', since even for Hegel, they too depend on 'God' -- and for DM-theorists none are permanent, either, all are subject to the HF. Will Broadway still be there in five billion years time? Will plants and seeds? I think there is room to suppose they might not. So, it seems they too are 'appearances', if we were to accept Hegel's typology, his weird use of language and the HF.

 

Furthermore, what connection is there between 'appearances' in the first of the two above senses? That is in terms of what something might look like and which might end up deceiving us -- again, like the way that sticks appear to bend when partially immersed in water, the way the Sun appears to rise in the East, fall in the West, or how objects seem to change in size as they recede from us or advance toward us. What connection is there with this sense of "appearance" and the sort of 'appearances' associated with a lack of permanence? Presumably sticks will still look bent when partially immersed in water in a hundred million years' time, just as the apparent motion of the Sun will remain the same as long as the Sun, the Earth and human beings still exist. If so, it seems these 'appearances' (connected with what something looks like) must also be 'essences' since they appear to be permanent features of the natural world.

 

In such terms, examples (i)-(iv) don't seem to have anything to do with deception (actual or potential). Or is it to be imagined that when some appears in a play they really aren't appearing in that play and are deceiving us? Or that, if someone appears for the defence they really appearing for the prosecution? In addition, (ii) and (iv) also don't seem to have anything to do with deception, with how things just appear to be but really aren't.

 

This means, of course, that the distinction itself (at least in so far as Hegel conceived it) has now either become absurd or was based on linguistic confusion.

 

[Be this as it may, how any of the above considerations are connected with 'contradiction' is still far from clear. I say much more about this below.]

 

But, what about (v) (here repeated)?

 

(v) [Like someone who] Describes how another looks -- as in "Her appearance gave her away; she was clearly amused", or "His appearance changes from day-to-day; he is a master of disguise." 

 

In such cases, appearances are often not only under volitional/intentional control, they can sometimes deceive (whether or not that is itself intentional). In addition, such appearances can change from day-to-day and in different lighting conditions -- or even as a result of other factors (such as the age, health, mood and physical condition of the individual concerned). So, at first sight (no pun intended!), this set of examples seems to be the closest to those intended by Hegel and DM-theorists (in this respect), since it combines the two alternatives mentioned above -- i.e., the way certain things look and their transience. But, since this particular phenomenon is clearly connected with human behaviour (whether the latter is voluntary, involuntary, intentional or unintentional), they can hardly be connected with what Novack thought he meant when he spoke about plants and seeds.

 

Nevertheless, Option (v) does seem to offer a lifeline (of sorts) to DM-fans. But, as we have seen several times (in other Essays -- for example, Eight Part Two), a lifeline like this soon turns into a noose (or something equally lethal). That is because 'appearances' like these (in relation to what human beings can or can't do and/or what takes place in the natural world) are in no way contradictory (why that is so will be explained in detail presently), nor do they have anything to do with any underlying 'essences'. So, whatever else they are, they can't be 'dialectical'. [I return to consider such phenomena later -- here, here and here.]

 

Having said that, the sort of 'appearances' alluded to above aren't the same as, nor are they even analogous to, those of interest to DM-fans. The latter relate to a distinction drawn between how something appears to be and how it really is, its 'essence', as it is 'in-itself'. So, although sticks look like they bend when partially immersed in water, and objects seem to grow smaller when they recede from us, neither is actually the case. Sticks don't really bend in such circumstances and objects don't shrink as they move away from observers. Even with respect to capitalism, that economic and social system might look fair to some, but no Marxist believes it really is fair. Consider another popular example: what the Sun appears to do each morning; this phenomenon is a little more complex and will be dealt with in much greater detail below. But even here, while it looks like the Sun rises in the East, it would be false to say that that represents what really happens. As we will see, what we conclude in such circumstances depends on the inertial frame of reference chosen in order to depict this phenomenon. Of course, DM-fans interpret such events in more black-and-white terms -- despite their anathematising of such rigid dichotomies elsewhere, as 'metaphysical'. That is, they hold that there is an absolute truth here, even if we never actually attain it, and that, in such instances, "the thing-in-itself" or "the-event-in-itself" exists independent of our knowledge of it/them. Not only that, they also contrast the latter with how things appear to be (as we have seen), and how that differs from how they 'really are'.

 

But there is no such contrast to be had with Type-(v) examples. With respect to a disguise, for instance, there is no such thing as 'how someone really looks without any disguise'. There is no 'thing-in-itself' here. How someone looks from a certain angle, in certain lighting conditions, as their mood changes, or as they age (etc., etc.) is all there is. Appearances vary all the time in this and other ways. There is no 'how-someone-looks-in-itself' independent of lighting conditions, the age of the individual involved, their mood, their state of health, etc., etc. As far as someone being amused is concerned, that is far too vague a term for it to be contrasted with yet another 'thing-in-itself'. What would it even mean to suppose there is such a thing as 'being-amused-in-itself'? In which case, there is no analogous contrast to be drawn here between how an individual looks and what he or she really is. Hence, there is no such thing as how someone 'really looks-in-themselves' -- if by that we mean 'how things look below the surface' or how they 'look essentially'. Below the surface, no one looks at all appealing, especially when their skin has been removed! And as soon as something looks a certain way, it ceases to be an 'essence'. The latter are creatures of thought and rationality not direct perception. That is why Idealists (and, as we have seen, many DM-theorists) never tire of telling us that 'abstractions' can't be seen, felt, heard, or tasted.

 

Of course, if we now take into account how DM-theorists depict 'objectivity' (i.e., as that which exists independent of the 'human mind', or independent of 'human consciousness'), how something looks can't be independent of human awareness, and so can't be 'objective' (in DM-terms). Looks and seemings don't exist independent of someone who experiences or perceives them, and so looks and seemings can't be part of 'objective reality', if we were to believe what DM-theorists have to say. So, in this sense, in a DM-universe, there can be no 'objective' contrast between how things look and how they really are! There might be one such for Hegel (I will pass no comment about that possibility, in this Essay), but there can't be for Dialectical Marxists who agree with Lenin about 'objectivity'. Just as soon as reference is made to how something looks or seems to be, it is no longer independent of 'the human mind', and so, according to Lenin (and other DM-theorists), it can't be 'objective'. [On this, may I refer readers to the comments at the end of the previous paragraph.]

 

[Follow the above link for passages where Lenin defined 'objectivity'. I have covered questions like this in much greater detail in Essay Thirteen Part One -- and I have also discussed the 'below the surface' metaphor more extensively in Essay Twelve Part One. Readers are directed to those two Essays for more on both. However, no one should assume from the above remarks that I accept terms like "things-in-themselves" make any sense when used in indicative sentences. But DM-theorists think they do, which is why I have used this term against them. Nevertheless, once again, I have entered into this specific topic in more detail in Note 6a.]

 

Finally on this, consider another example, The Doppler Effect, which most people who live in one of the 'advanced economies' (and elsewhere) will experience many times a year, and which is used by Astrophysicists in their study of the Universe in connection with the so-called "Red Shift", which occurs in relation to light reaching Earth from distance stars and galaxies:

 

"The Doppler effect is the perceived change in frequency of sound emitted by a source moving relative to the observer: as a plane flies overhead, the note of the engine becomes noticeably lower, as does the siren noise from a fast-moving emergency vehicle as it passes. The effect was first noted by Christian Doppler in 1842.  The effect is widely used to measure velocities, usually by reflection of a transmitted wave from the moving object, ultrasound for blood in arteries, radar for speeding cars and thunderstorms. The velocities of distant galaxies are measured using the Doppler effect (the red shift)." [Quoted from here; accessed 19/10/2024.]

 

Is this an 'objective' feature of the universe or is it merely 'subjective'? But the wavelength of light and sound is, presumably, what it is independent of any observers, so, the perceived change in the frequency of light and sound waves, for instance, is, in some sense, misleading. But instruments register this change 'objectively' when they actually measure such changes (and what they record is used to help explain how the Universe began, for example). So, this phenomenon appears to be a genuine feature of the world around us and it seems to be independent of 'human consciousness' -- but which is both misleading and 'objective'. It is genuine since this change really exists (as noted above, instruments record these changes independently of whether or not humans are capable of observing/detecting them), but it tells us something about the world that is false, if interpreted one way, true if viewed in another.

 

Of course, the above is a highly simplified description of such phenomena, which is clearly related to relative velocities and that must involve issues connected with Relativity Theory. But all that that does is complicate the issue, it doesn't materially alter the points just made. The Doppler Effect is both 'real' and an 'appearance', and so is Red Shift!

 

Be this as it may, good luck trying to fit any of this into a DM-view of 'reality', or make it consistent with Hegel's odd (and barely comprehensible) interpretation of the distinction between 'appearance' and 'reality'. Here we seem to have a 'subjective' phenomenon that is also 'objective' -- as well as an 'appearance' that also appears to be 'real'! [Irony intended.]

 

[Readers should once again note that I don't accept the validity of the philosophical use of words like "objective" and "subjective" -- for reasons set out in Essay Thirteen Part One. These terms are only being used here since DM-fans dote on them.]

 

There are other rather strange phenomena (like the above) that also seem difficult to squeeze into the a priori 'straightjacket' DM-theorists have imposed on the world, which I will simply mention but not comment upon: time dilation and length contraction. Are these 'objective' and 'subjective', too? Are they 'appearances' or are they 'real'?

 

Despite this, it might now prove opportune to contrast what Novack says above with his earlier, unequivocal warning:

 

"A consistent materialism cannot proceed from principles which are validated by appeal to abstract reason, intuition, self-evidence or some other subjective or purely theoretical source. Idealisms may do this. But the materialist philosophy has to be based upon evidence taken from objective material sources and verified by demonstration in practice...." [Novack (1965), p.17. Bold emphasis added.]

 

And yet much of what Novack has to say about "appearance" and "reality" (and, indeed, about 'dialectical logic' in general) is based on "abstract reason, intuition, self-evidence or some other subjective or purely theoretical source". In fact, the same might be said about every other DM-fan quoted at this site (when they opine on such topics).

 

A different DM-theorist, Hyman Cohen, took great exception to 'crude' interpretations of the 'contradiction' between 'essence' and 'appearance' (when responding to an article written by one, Mark Mussachia), in the following terms:

 

"Yet, if one consults a textbook of Marxist philosophy (Fundamentals of Marxist-Leninist Philosophy, Progress Publishers, Moscow [this appears to be Konstantinov (1974), pp.188-92 (no pun intended!) -- RL]), it is plain to see that essence and appearance are depicted as complex categories, correlated categories whose oppositeness does not constitute a total negation, one of the other, but a unity; they are characterised through one another." [Cohen (1980), p.120. Italic emphases in the original.]

 

The following is what we find in the above textbook (attentive readers will no doubt notice the dogmatic nature of what they are about to read (it is imposed on the facts), and hence should ask themselves whether or not what it says has been "validated by appeal to abstract reason, intuition, self-evidence or some other subjective or purely theoretical source", and then perhaps note the dearth of evidence offered in support, while also noting the fact that this is an authoritative DM-textbook, at least as far as Marxist-Leninists are concerned, not a fringe work):

 

"Essence and appearance are correlated categories. They are characterised thorough one another. Whereas essence is something general, appearance is individual, expressing only an element of essence; whereas essence is something profound and intrinsic, appearance is external, yet richer and more colourful; whereas essence is something stable and necessary, appearance is more transient, changeable and accidental. The difference between the essential and the unessential is not absolute but relative. For instance, at one time it was considered that the essential property of the chemical element was its atomic weigh. Later this essential property turned out to be the charge of the atomic nucleus. The property of atomic weight did not cease to be essential, however. It is still essential in the first approximation, essential on a less profound level (sic!), and is further explained on the basis of the charge of the atomic nucleus. Essence is expressed in its many outward manifestations. At the same time essence may not only express itself in these manifestations. When we are in the process of gaining sensory knowledge of a thing, phenomena sometimes seem to us to be not what they are in reality. This seemingness is not generated by our consciousness. It arises through our being influenced by real relationships in the objective conditions of observation. Those who thought the Sun rotated around the Earth took the seeming appearance of things for the real thing. Under capitalism the wages of the worker seem to be payment for all his work, but in reality only part of his work is paid, while the rest is appropriated by the capitalists free of charge in the form of surplus value, which constitutes the source of their profit. Thus to obtain a correct understanding of an event, to get to the bottom of it, we must critically test the evidence of immediate observation, and make a clear distinction between the seeming and the real, the superficial and the essential. Knowledge of the essence of things is the fundamental task of science. Marx wrote that if essence and appearance directly coincided, all science would be superfluous. The history of science shows that knowledge of essence is impossible without considering and analysing the various forms in which it is manifest. At the same time these various forms cannot be correctly understood without penetrating to their 'foundation', their essence." [Konstantinov (1974), pp.191-92. Bold emphases alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site; paragraphs merged.]       

 

Well, this is all rather vague and not entirely consistent (something one has come to expect of self-respecting DM-theorists!). One minute we are told that 'essence' is "profound" and "intrinsic", the next that it might not be such, but "relative" and hence not the least bit "intrinsic". At this point, a reader might well ask, somewhat mischievously: "Is there perhaps a contradiction between what appears to be the definition of 'essence' and what it 'really' is?" [I am, of course, (temporarily) using "contradiction" here in the loose and profligate way DM-fans do.] One fears the answer to that query might very well be "Yes, there is!", since the definition of "essence" seems to contradict its own 'essence'! And, far from being told (unequivocally) that 'essence contradicts appearance', we find these rather sheepish words in its place:

 

"When we are in the process of gaining sensory knowledge of a thing, phenomena sometimes seem to us to be not what they are in reality." [Ibid. Bold emphasis added.]

 

Only "sometimes"? Only "seem"? How often is this "sometimes"? And how definitive is this "seem"? Does the Sun orbit the Earth, or not? Do sticks really bend in water, or not? Do objects shrink as they recede from us, or not? Is the Earth really flat, or not? Do objects appear to shrink in size as they recede from us, or not? Are workers paid for all the hours they work, all the value they create, or not? Or do these phenomena only intermittently behave in the way they seem? Or, at other times do we see them as they 'really' are (whatever that means)? On Monday do sticks appear to bend in water but on Tuesday they don't? Do objects that recede from us shrink on Wednesdays but remain the same size the rest of the week while they do that?

 

[LEM = Law of Excluded Middle.]

 

Nevertheless, in connection with this the reader would be well advised to ignore DM-inspired criticisms of the "either-or" of 'commonsense' (supposedly enshrined in the LEM), since it looks like the above textbook has just employed it! That is because any (clear and unambiguous) answer to the following question, "Does the Sun orbit the Earth or does the Earth orbit the Sun?" must respond with one or other of these options --, either:

 

(a) The Sun orbits the Earth; or,

 

(b) The Sun doesn't orbit the Earth.

 

But not both!

 

The above DM-textbook clearly chose alternative (b) (and then (c), below), not both of them. So, the innocent-looking "seem" its author thought to use turns out to be much stronger than it appears (irony intended), since it is clear this 'seeming' (i.e., the Sun orbiting the Earth) isn't a "real thing", after all. Hence, the choice made by the author of this DM-textbook constitutes a clear, if implicit, use of the LEM.

 

"Those who thought the Sun rotated around the Earth took the seeming appearance of things for the real thing." [Ibid.]

 

(c) So, the Earth orbits the Sun. (End of story.)

 

The 'either-or of common sense' wins -- yet again.

 

[On why it will always win, see here.]

 

In which case, it is far from clear why Cohen thought it a good idea to reference the above textbook since we are now no clearer than we were before about what these two (i.e., Cohen and Konstantinov) mean. Quite the reverse in fact. What, for example, does Cohen mean by the following?

 

"[E]ssence and appearance are depicted as complex categories, correlated categories whose oppositeness does not constitute a total negation, one of the other, but a unity; they are characterised through one another." [Cohen, loc cit.]

 

But, how is the correct relation (whatever it is) between the Sun and the Earth "characterised" by the appearance that the Sun orbits the Earth, when we are now told that the reverse is the case? As we have just seen, there is an unambiguous (if implicit) "either-or" at work here, which implies that the former and the latter aren't in the end "characterised through one another". They rule each other out. If (a) is the case, (c) isn't, and vice versa.

 

(a) The Sun orbits the Earth; or,

 

(c) The Earth orbits the Sun.

 

Furthermore, the following can't (surely) be true:

 

"The difference between the essential and the unessential is not absolute but relative. For instance, at one time it was considered that the essential property of the chemical element was its atomic weigh. Later this essential property turned out to be the charge of the atomic nucleus. The property of atomic weight did not cease to be essential, however. It is still essential in the first approximation, essential on a less profound level, and is further explained on the basis of the charge of the atomic nucleus." [Konstantinov, loc cit.]

 

If that were the case, it would seem 'essence' actually depends on the choices we make, not the way things are independently of us. In that case, it is worth asking "Is 'essence' a 'social construct' or a 'real phenomenon'?

 

Cohen's comment is, therefore, far too brief, confused and enigmatic to be of much use -- while the longer passage from Konstantinov is, as we have also seen, far too vague and inconsistent to be of any use at all.

 

The same confusion is apparent in the comments advanced by a fan of Systematic Dialectics, with whom I debated these and related issues recently:

 

"Now, if you've never thought critically about how a capitalist economy works or never had the benefit of reading Marx, then all of that probably sounds like some pretty crazy sh*t. About as crazy as telling Joshua of the Hebrew Bible that the Sun is the stationary centre of the universe (or our solar system) and the Earth revolves around it. Only a madman would think such a thing. It is obvious that the Sun rises in East and sets in the West. But, in reality, the Sun rising and falling around the Earth is merely the form of appearance that the Sun takes from our immediate experience. If we took the Sun simply as it appears, never thought critically about its movements or lack thereof, then we would never be able to apprehend the nature of our solar system. Critical thought demands abstraction. We must organize the manifold objects of reality in the thought realm of our minds, which means we have to provisionally distance ourselves from the complex, concrete appearances and start with the most simple and abstract category that captures the phenomena we are attempting to understand. Hence, Marx starts with the commodity in the abstract." [Quoted from here. Bold emphasis added; spelling modified to agree with UK English. Paragraphs merged.]

 

"'[E]ssence' isn't 'in a secret world lying behind "appearances"'. It has no reality except in its appearance. However, taking the appearances to be exhaustive of reality is a mistake.... [E]ssence, necessarily expresses itself through the appearances." [Quoted from here and here; quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Bold emphases added.]

 

First, that isn't how scientific knowledge of the Solar System developed and went through a profound series of changes in the 16th and 17th centuries. As we will see in Essay Thirteen Part Two, Copernicus's ideas, for example, were motivated by two key factors: his Hermeticism and his search for mathematical simplicity:

 

"At rest, however, in the middle of everything is the sun. For in this most beautiful temple, who would place this lamp in another or better position than that from which it can light up the whole thing at the same time? For, the sun is not inappropriately called by some people the lantern of the universe, its mind by others, and its ruler by still others. [Hermes] the Thrice Greatest [Hermes Trismegistus -- RL] labels it a visible god, and Sophocles' Electra, the all-seeing. Thus indeed, as though seated on a royal throne, the sun governs the family of planets revolving around it. Moreover, the earth is not deprived of the moon's attendance. On the contrary, as Aristotle says in a work on animals, the moon has the closest kinship with the earth. Meanwhile the earth has intercourse with the sun, and is impregnated for its yearly parturition." [Copernicus, De Revolutionibus, Book 1, Chapter 10, partially quoted in Kuhn (1995), p.131, using a different translation.]

 

Thomas Kuhn added the following remarks about the work of the next important scientist in line, Johannes Kepler:

 

"Neoplatonism is explicit in Copernicus' attitude toward both the sun and mathematical simplicity. It is an essential element in the intellectual climate that gave birth to his vision of the universe. But it is often hard to tell whether any given Neoplatonic attitude is posterior or antecedent to the invention of his new astronomy in Copernicus' thought. No similar ambiguity exists with respect of the later Copernicans. Kepler, for example, the man who made the Copernican system work, is quite explicit about his reasons for preferring Copernicus' proposal, and among them is the following:

 

'[The sun] is a fountain of light, rich in fruitful heat, most fair, limpid, and pure to the sight, the source of vision, portrayed of all colours, though himself empty of colour, called king of the planets for his motion, heart of the world for his power, its eye for his beauty, and which alone we should judge worthy of the Most High God, should he be pleased with a material domicile and choose a place in which to dwell with the blessed angels…. For if the Germans elect him as Caesar who has most power in the whole empire, who would hesitate to confer the votes of the celestial motions on him who already has been administering all other movements and changes by the benefit of the light which is entirely his possession?....[Hence] by the highest right we return to the sun, who alone appears, by virtue of his dignity and power, suited for this motive duty and worthy to become the home of God himself, not to say the first mover.'" [Kuhn (1995), p.131, quoting Kepler from Burtt (1954), p.48. Bold emphases added; spelling modified to conform with UK English. (These link to PDFs.)]

 

As Frank Tipler, Professor of Mathematical Physics, pointed out:

 

"[T]he new theory of Nicolaus Copernicus which, while still committed to uniform circular motion, argued that by placing the sun at the centre instead, the apparent retrograde motion of the planets could be accounted for with greater mathematical simplicity and elegance." [Quoted from here; accessed 15/09/2020. Spelling modified to conform with UK English; bold emphasis added.]

 

The next leading scientist to advance knowledge significantly in this area, Galileo Galilei, didn't indulge in any heroic feats of 'mental abstraction', either -- even though he helped hammer the last few nails in the coffin of the old Aristotelian/Ptolemaic system. Not a bit of it; he did something overt. He peered down a telescope and recorded the fact that several planets had their own moons. The old system couldn't explain this and that meant Kepler's model (which also needed revising) was at least physically possible. [On this see, for example, Koestler (2017).]

 

So, 'the mental process of abstraction' (even if we knew what it was) played no part in these developments -- or, if they did, in support of that contention someone needs to produce Galileo's brain scan so we might finally begin to understand his words and hence what he was actually trying to tell us.

 

Second, one might well wonder how one of the above quoted passages might be rendered consistent -- i.e., how, for example, the Sun's 'apparent' motion might be harmonised with the claim that 'essence' "necessarily expresses itself through the appearances"? If the latter were the case, why did no one register the (supposed) 'expression' of 'essence' involved in this phenomenon for countless centuries? Why did it have to wait until the above scientists and philosophers revealed it to an expectant humanity? That is, why did it take so long before anyone claimed that the Earth moves relative to the Sun, not the other way round? Why did it take so long for the scientific community to arrive at this conclusion? And how does this particular 'essence' (a moving Earth) "necessarily express itself through the appearance" of its opposite -- i.e., the fact that the Earth appears to be stationary? It rather looks like the 'essence' involved in this case (whatever it is!) failed to "express itself through the appearances". Indeed, it induced (in the vast majority of human observers up to that point in history) a set of false beliefs, many of which lasted for thousands of years  -- i.e., the theory that the Earth doesn't move and sits motionless at the centre of the Universe. That is, of course, inconsistent with what we now know to be the case, -- that the Earth does move and isn't located at the centre of the Universe. In fact, it is now plain that any such 'essence' was, at best, locked away in a "secret world lying behind appearances", since it took so long for anyone to force it into the open!

 

That helps explain why there are still so many who erroneously think the Earth is flat (because, locally, it appears to be so), and who also conclude it is the Sun that hovers above our 'flat planet'. Hence, as noted earlier, given this view, 'appearances' are more like screens than they are windows -- which reminds one of the shutters we met earlier.

 

After all, didn't Heraclitus himself try tell us that "nature likes to hide"? [Kirk, et al (1999), p.192.]

 

That is, indeed, what Hegel himself claimed:

 

"The immediate Being of things is thus conceived under the image of a rind or curtain behind which the Essence is hidden." [Hegel (1975), p.163, §112. Bold added.]

 

Hegel fans have yet to explain how something "hidden" can "express itself through the appearance", or remain so well concealed that it takes a Christian Mystic to see it -- and then only after countless thousands of years when virtually everyone else saw the opposite!

 

And we have already had occasion to quote this famous remark courtesy of  Marx:

 

"But all science would be superfluous if the outward appearance and the essence of things directly coincided." [Marx (1981), p.956; Marx (1998), p.804.]

 

Not much 'shining' going on in there, it would seem!

 

Why would we need science if 'essence' shone through?

 

[In several places below I return to consider the motion of the Earth, where I aim to show that the picture painted by DM-fans isn't quite as neat and tidy as they would have us believe.]

 

On this issue (the alleged 'contradiction' between 'appearance' and 'essence'/'reality'), here is what one commentator had to say (quoted earlier):

 

"Essence shows or appears (scheint), but itself remains hidden behind a veil of Schein (appearance -- RL).... This suggests the idea of a world that is the reverse of the world of appearances, in which everything that has, in our world, a certain quality, has, in the world in itself, the opposite quality." [Inwood (1992), pp.39-40. Bold emphases alone added.]

 

At a time in his life when his ideas were being heavily influenced by ruling-class forms-of-thought (like these), Marx also expressed this (peculiar) idea rather forcefully, in the following terms:

 

"The contradiction between existence and essence, between matter and form, which is inherent in the concept of the atom, emerges in the individual atom itself once it is endowed with qualities. Through the quality the atom is alienated from its concept, but at the same time is perfected in its construction. It is from repulsion and the ensuing conglomerations of the qualified atoms that the world of appearance now emerges. In this transition from the world of essence to the world of appearance, the contradiction in the concept of the atom clearly reaches its harshest realisation. For the atom is conceptually the absolute, essential form of nature. This absolute form has now been degraded to absolute matter, to the formless substrate of the world of appearance." [Marx (1975b), pp.61-62. (This links to a PDF.) Bold emphases alone added; paragraphs merged.]

 

Here, too, is Mao:

 

"We should draw a lesson here: Don't be misled by false appearances. Some of our comrades are easily misled by them. There is contradiction between appearance and essence in everything. It is by analyzing and studying the appearance of a thing that people come to know its essence. Hence the need for science. Otherwise, if one could get at the essence of a thing by intuition, what would be the use of science? What would be the use of study? Study is called for precisely because there is contradiction between appearance and essence. There is a difference, though, between the appearance and the false appearance of a thing, because the latter is false. Hence we draw the lesson: Try as far as possible not to be misled by false appearances." [Mao (1964b), pp.165-66. Bold emphases added.]

 

However, in connection with what Mao had to say one might ask: How is the following even possible?

 

"It is by analyzing and studying the appearance of a thing that people come to know its essence." [Ibid.]

 

As should seem clear, in order to study "the appearance of a thing" it is necessary -- at least initially -- to rely on its appearance, which we have just been warned not to trust, since some 'appearances' (or is it all?) are "false". But, if it is only some that are false, how might we distinguish the false from the not-false 'appearances'? Unfortunately, Mao failed to say. In this regard, it would be no use appealing to scientific observations since they also rely on these already suspect 'appearances'. On the other hand, if no 'appearances' can be trusted, how might they convey anything reliable to anyone, never mind anything about 'essence'? And, what would be the point of "analysing" such 'dubious data inputs' -- these sketchy 'appearances' -- if they can't be trusted? All the data and information retrieved from telescopes, microscopes, magnifying glasses (and eyeglasses!), compasses, computers, cell phones, thermometers, gauges and measuring devices in general, all of it confronts us as experiential phenomena -- as 'appearances' -- which have all just been thrown under the bus. We have no way of 'leaping out of our heads' in order to 'intuit' nature directly (whatever that might mean!). No good appealing to books, articles, reports, blogs, emails or letters for any help or guidance -- and that includes Mao's own writings! -- since they, too, now confront us as 'appearances'.

 

If appearances can't be trusted, neither can a book or article that tries to tell us this!

 

[Misguided attempts to defend Mao on this issue have been subjected to sustained criticism elsewhere in this Essay.]

 

Here are several other Marxists who have also (unwisely) advanced similar opinions (in addition to passages quoted earlier, here and here):

 

"Whereas Kant stopped at contradiction, Kant being paralyzed by its omnipresence where thought was concerned, Hegel presses forward to the recognition of the profound truth of contradiction, and thus Hegel is not trapped with an incognizable essence and a perfectly cognizable appearance, as in Kant; since, for Hegel, reality can only present itself by means of contradictory oppositions, such as the opposition appearance/reality." [David DeGrood, quoted from here; bold emphasis alone added.]

 

"Elsewhere, it is the contradiction between essence and appearance that is emphasised in the dialectic approach." [Hirsch (2004), p.8. Bold added.]

 

"In his Philosophical Notebooks, Lenin, after renewed study of Hegel, explicitly breaks with reflection theory in favour of a much more dialectical theory of cognition that emphasises the contradiction between essence and appearance and establishes consciousness, not just as a reflection of the world, but also as a factor capable, through practice, of shaping it. Human knowledge, according to Lenin, depends upon an active process of abstraction, capable of distinguishing between essence and appearance, rather than passive reflection, an insight with profound consequences for the theorisation of literary production." [Quoted from here, pp.31-32. (This links to a PDF. Unfortunately, this link is now dead!) Accessed 19/08/2020. Bold emphasis alone added. I have examined John Rees's attempt to rescue Lenin's failed theory of knowledge -- which was taken apart in Essay Thirteen Part One -- by appealing to the (supposedly) more nuanced approach 'set out' in his Philosophical Notebooks [PN], in Appendix Three. Incidentally, the phrase "set out" is in 'scare quotes' since what Lenin had to say in PN is far too fragmentary, brief and obscure to characterise in any other way.]

 

"Essence refers to 'the negative reciprocal reflectedness of many capitals with one another through which they themselves, in as much as they are concretely different from one another, are posited as capitals essentially identical to one another; that is existing values that valorise themselves…. This is their identity within their difference.' Appearance refers to 'the reciprocal relation of the many capitals among themselves whereby, as capitals that are different in many concrete aspects, they oppose and compete [with each?] other in order to obtain their greatest valorisation. This, by contrast, is their difference within their identity.' [The author] is able to show -- through the Hegelian categories of repulsion and attraction, quality and quantity, one and many -- that the contradiction between essence and appearance is mediated in a more concrete form, 'as capital in its existence in-and-for-itself'." [Tony McKenna, quoted from here, accessed 19/08/2020. Bold emphases added. Tony has clearly adopted the 'bury everything under several layers of impenetrable gobbledygook' writing-style one finds all too often across much of Dialectical Marxism, but especially in the HCD-wing.]

 

"The realist shares with the positivist a conception of science as an empirically-based, rational and objective enterprise, the purpose of which is to provide us with true explanatory and predictive knowledge of nature. But for the realist, unlike the positivist, there is an important difference between explanation and prediction. And it is explanation which must be pursued as the primary objective of science. To explain phenomena is not merely to show they are instances of well-established regularities. Instead, we must discover the necessary connections between phenomena, by acquiring know-ledge of the underlying structures and mechanisms at work. Often, this will mean postulating the existence of types of unobservable entities and processes that are unfamiliar to us: but it is only by doing this that we get beyond the 'mere appearances' of things, to their natures and essences. Thus, for the realist, a scientific theory is a description of structures and mechanisms which causally generate the observable phenomena, a description which enables us to explain them.... (p.5)

 

"Marx argues that 'vulgar economics' analyses only the superficial, phenomenal or apparent features of social and economic life, and fails to penetrate to their deeper underlying substratum, essence or reality. Marx supports his view that the distinction between appearance and reality is important by an argument about science in general, and by arguments specific to political economy. First, he says that there would be no need for scientific theories unless the outward appearance of things and their inner essence did not coincide. Thus while the air that we breathe appears undifferentiated, the scientific analysis of how it is in reality shows that it is mainly comprised of nitrogen and oxygen in pro-portions four to one. No science could proceed if it did not attempt to explain appearances in terms of the reality, and if it did not show how the appearances are themselves misleading. But this interpretation of the appearance/reality distinction is fairly general and imprecise. It fails to provide Marx with criteria specific to his approach to political economy, and does not even clearly exclude 'vulgar economics'....

 

"Commodity fetishism means that reality, that is, the social relations of production, does not appear as it is. There is a gap between the appearances of capitalism and its essence or reality. It appears that social life is governed by general lawful relations between things; for example, that capital is a thing and earns its profit because of its natural productivity. However, according to Marx, any social science which merely analyses this fetishistic level of appearances is false and distorting. Rather we must analyse reality, the organization of capital and labour based on the production and appropriation of surplus value. It is this reality which differs from the appearances of capitalism and which produces the false and distorting forms in which capitalist society appears to its members. It is not that people simply misperceive the nature of capitalism. Rather it is that reality presents itself in an inverted form." [Keat and Urry (1982), pp.99-100. Bold emphases added. Although, it is important to add that Keat and Urry say regard the visual metaphor of 'Appearance and Reality' as "problematic", or even misleading -- so this looks like another mismatch between 'reality' and the appearance of that phrase! (Irony intended.)]

 

"'If the essence and appearance of things directly coincided, all science would be superfluous'. Does Marx's dictum lead to novel insights? The purpose of science is to discover the nature of reality concealed under surface appearance. Based on this definition, Marx makes the above assertion -- if things appeared exactly as they are, there would be no need for science to remove the veil of appearance. Social science, therefore, is the search for the real nature of society, underneath all of its visible, external façades. If the reality of society is easily observable in our everyday experience, then there is no need for scientific reflection on society, as Marx defines science. The idea that society has an 'appearance', which is not the same as social 'essence', forms the starting point for the Marxist discussion of ideology. Ideology is what allows a society to persist, even though the essence of that society may contain contradictions. It is important to note that the difference between appearance and reality is not due to some form of false belief or faulty vision on the part of the observer. The appearances are caused by the reality. There is no 'mistake' in the observance of society, because it is the nature of society that the essence projects a certain appearance. It is the nature of a mirage that it is an illusion, it is not a case of 'faulty vision'. A person with normal vision will still see a mirage, as it is the very essence of the mirage which creates the illusion.

 

"Marx was primarily concerned with the nature of the capitalist mode of production. The cardinal tenets of Marx's theory of the essence of capitalism are: Only expenditure of labour creates economic value, in proportion to the amount of labour expended; workers do not receive the whole value of what they produce -- capitalists enjoy profits due to surplus value, for which the worker is not paid; labour power is the only form of capital investment which creates profit. (1) The social appearance, on the other hand is: An object is worth what it can be exchanged for in the market, i.e. its exchange-value; workers appear to be paid for all of their labour; capital is seen to 'create' profit. There is clearly a marked difference between the appearance and essence of society. Marx uses the idea of 'commodity fetishism' to explain this difference. 'Commodity fetishism' is the vision of objective value in commodities especially money, as the commodity of exchange. Under a society with exchange, the only way people can gauge value is during the exchange process. For example, in the labour market, a worker will agree to a contract with an employer for a certain wage per time period. The worker feels that he is being paid for all of his work, and the employer feels that the value of the labour-power employed is worth the wage. The actual value of the labour is more than the wage, as the employer will eventually extract a surplus value when the product is sold. The cause of this commodity fetishism is the nature of the exchange process. The result is that some aspects of the appearance of society are the 'inverse' of its essence.

 

"The notion of 'inversion' is very important to Marx, as it sums up the idea that the capitalist mode of production contains contradictions. The contradiction is between the essence and appearance. Marx goes so far as to say that 'everything appears as reversed in competition'. Ideology 'conceals the contradictory essential relations...because it is based on a sphere of reality which reveals the contrary to its essential relations'. The role of ideology, therefore, is to hide the essence of society as it contradicts the appearance, which is beneficial to the ruling class at the time. As ideology is based on the 'phenomenological sphere', or the sphere of 'appearances', it fulfils its role by reinforcing the appearances of society, thus further burying the 'essence'." [Luis Avilés, quoted from here. Accessed 16/12/2016. Minor typo corrected; several  paragraphs merged. (This link now appears to be dead!)]

 

So, the theory that there is a 'contradiction' between 'essence' and 'appearance' is mainstream, right across Dialectical Marxism, and is widely accepted by DM-theorists. In which case, it seems reasonably clear that for them, 'essences' are 'hidden' and 'appearances' are in some sense, or to some extent, false or misleading.

 

However, in the last of the above passages, Luis Avilés seems to want to have his abstract cake and eat it. On the one hand, he claims that "the difference between appearance and reality is not due to some form of false belief or faulty vision on the part of the observer", on the other he then says "It is the nature of a mirage that it is an illusion, it is not a case of 'faulty vision'. A person with normal vision will still see a mirage, as it is the very essence of the mirage which creates the illusion." Other dialecticians (not quoted here) argue along similar lines. And yet, if an observer 'sees' what she thinks is water, but which is just a mirage, she is entertaining a false belief that there is water.

 

Avilés then tells us that "workers appear to be paid for all of their labour" and the "worker feels that he is being paid for all of his work...." But, is that belief true or false? [Or is it 'dialectically' both?] He adds "The actual value of the labour is more than the wage." If so, the aforementioned worker plainly held a false belief. There appears to be no other way of making sense of this.

 

Somewhat appropriately, comrades like Avilés and Mandel (analysed in detail in Appendix Four) appear to be able to hold two contradictory ideas 'in their heads' at once -- i.e., that 'appearances', or the beliefs motivated by them, aren't false even while they are false! Or, that all such ideas are false and true! We met get-out-of-jail-free cards like this in Essay Eleven Part One, where some DM-theorists try to maintain that even in the most blatant of falsehoods there is a grain of truth:

 

In addition to the above pro-DM-avoiding tactic, dialecticians (like, say, Lenin and Cornforth) also argue that no theory or proposition is either absolutely true or completely false. All are in their own way closer approximations to the truth; or, rather, are closer approximations to 'partial' or 'relative truth', stepping stones on the endless journey toward 'Absolute Truth'.

 

Quite apart from the fact that no DM-theorist really accepts this idea (on that, see below), the term "partial truth" is itself conveniently vague (as will be demonstrated in Essay Thirteen Part Two).

 

But, even if that weren't the case, and the meaning of "relative truth" were crystal clear, those who say they accept theories that are less 'partially true' (even if only provisionally) also claim that the goal should be to 'resolve' or remove (most or all of the) contradictions that remain so that they become even less 'partially true' -- which means, of course, that the above conclusions still follow. Hence, even if the DM-view of the advance of science were acceptable, a maximally true theory should contain fewer contradictions, possibly even none at all.

 

As we have already seen, Engels himself suggested that if we had access to 'Absolute Truth', contradictions would completely disappear:

 

"If one does not loiter here needlessly, but presses on farther into the immense building, one finds innumerable treasures which today still possess undiminished value. With all philosophers it is precisely the 'system' which is perishable; and for the simple reason that it springs from an imperishable desire of the human mind -- the desire to overcome all contradictions. But if all contradictions are once and for all disposed of, we shall have arrived at so-called absolute truth -- world history will be at an end. And yet it has to continue, although there is nothing left for it to do -- hence, a new, insoluble contradiction. As soon as we have once realized -- and in the long run no one has helped us to realize it more than Hegel himself -- that the task of philosophy thus stated means nothing but the task that a single philosopher should accomplish that which can only be accomplished by the entire human race in its progressive development -- as soon as we realize that, there is an end to all philosophy in the hitherto accepted sense of the word. One leaves alone 'absolute truth', which is unattainable along this path or by any single individual; instead, one pursues attainable relative truths along the path of the positive sciences, and the summation of their results by means of dialectical thinking. At any rate, with Hegel philosophy comes to an end; on the one hand, because in his system he summed up its whole development in the most splendid fashion; and on the other hand, because, even though unconsciously, he showed us the way out of the labyrinth of systems to real positive knowledge of the world." [Engels (1888), p.590. Spelling modified to agree with UK English; quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Minor typo corrected.]

 

Which clearly implies that contradictions don't really exist in 'reality'! Otherwise how could the following ever be true?

 

"[I]f all contradictions are once and for all disposed of, we shall have arrived at so-called absolute truth...." [Ibid.]

 

Anyway, as has already been suggested, whatever they might say, in practice few dialecticians accept the idea that there are no completely false theories or propositions, even if they might sometimes tell their audiences the opposite. Here, for instance, is Cornforth:

 

"Just as truths are for the most part only approximate and contain the possibility of being converted into untruths, so are many errors found not to be absolute falsehoods but to contain a germ of truth.... We should recognise, then, that certain erroneous views, including idealist views, could represent, in their time, a contribution to truth -- since they were, perhaps, the only ways in which certain truths could first begin to come to expression...." [Cornforth (1963), pp.138-39. Paragraphs merged. Bold emphasis added.]

 

Despite what Cornforth says, it would be impossible to find a "germ of truth" in any of the following:

 

(1) Ten litres of concentrated Nitric Acid applied directly to unprotected human skin dramatically improves the complexion if left there for several hours.

 

(2) "Jews, Slavs, Romanies, Arabs, Asians and Africans all belong to 'inferior, sub-human races'."

 

(3) "Capitalism is a genuine expression of eternally unchanging human nature, which is both acquisitive and selfish."

 

(4) "All women are completely happy with their oppression and are keen to be reminded of it on a daily basis."

 

(5) "Imperialism is 100% progressive everywhere, at all times, and always will be."

 

(6) "The Ku Klux Klan and the alt-right are exemplary leaders in the fight for Black Liberation and full equality for Muslims."

 

(7) In 2002, Iraq manufactured and stored more WMD than any other country in the entire history of the planet.

 

(8) The earth is supported by a colossal tortoise, on top of a huge locust, on top of a giant crab, on top of a...

 

(9) Hysteria is caused by a wandering womb.

 

(10) "Trans rights aren't human rights."

 

(11) Karl Marx was a flagrant plagiarist from Mars who copied all his best ideas from George W Bush.

 

(12) "Anyone who wanders about aimlessly for several hours crossing and re-crossing a busy main road during the day while blindfolded will live a long and happy life."

 

(13) Sherlock Holmes was in fact a nuclear physicist who lived in Atlantis, 812-756 BCE.

 

(14) The world was created about 6000 years ago from a bowl of custard by the Flying Spaghetti Monster.

 

I suspect that anyone who questioned the truth of, say, (1) would be hard pressed to find a single revolutionary who agreed with (2). Naturally, that means the negation of (2) is absolutely true (for all revolutionaries).

 

On the other hand, if they were to reject as completely false one or both of these sentences -- i.e., (1) and/or (2) -- which they should(!), they would thereby have confirmed the point at issue: that is, if either one of those sentences is completely false, then there is at least one sentence (namely (1) or (2)) that is completely false. QED.

 

And, just in case these remarks attract the attention of any brass-necked, died-in-the-wool, hardcore Hegel Honchos, who might claim that one or more of the above are 'partially true', 'partially false', they should perhaps be encouraged to consider the following sentence:

 

H1: There are absolutely no partial truths, and there never have been.

 

Now, is that 'partially' true?

 

Or, must we agree with the following two theorists?

 

"It also follows that each theory's truth -- including that produced in Marxian theory -- is in no sense the expression of the essence of some 'reality.' Assertions of that sort, as we shall point out, occur outside the Marxian theory we seek to elaborate here and in contradiction to its epistemological position. Each theory's concept of 'reality' as well as of the 'truth' about that reality is different. Their differing concepts of reality are indexes of difference among theories, as are their differing concepts of truth. Marxian theory, then, recognizes no single reality or absolute truth or epistemological standard that can serve to validate one theory as against another. For Marxian theory, validations occur within theories as they subject various statements to their differing criteria of truth. Marxian theory sees itself as one among many different theories, each of which conceptualises its reality differently and tests its conceptualisations differently. Reality for Marxian theory is a totality comprising contradictions in theory interacting with contradictions within all the other processes that constitute that totality. Marxian theory specifies that interaction as overdetermination. Marxian theory also recognizes, of course, that other theories conceptualise all these matters differently; they take different epistemological positions....

 

"Marxian theory constitutes a break from the tradition of epistemology built around the problematic handed down from Descartes, Locke, and Kant. That problematic posed the issue: How can philosophy warrant the adequacy of thought as a representation of an external reality? Philosophy, and more specifically, epistemology, was defined in terms of a task: to establish the criteria by which it could be determined to what degree any statement was adequately grounded or, in other words, true. Truth was understood as a universal and absolute quality which any statement either possessed or did not possess for all thinkers. By contrast, Marxian theory rejects that problematic, posing the issue of epistemology altogether differently. It is not sensible, in and for Marxian theory, to imagine or seek after any absolute criteria of an absolute truth. Truths are intra- rather than inter-theoretic; they are, in a very particular sense, relative to the theories in which they are constructed." [Resnick and Wolff (1987), pp.6-7; p.32. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Spelling adjusted to agree with UK English. Bold emphases and link added. Several paragraphs merged.]

 

But, is that theory absolutely true? If it is, then it is false to say that all truths are relative. In which case, the above passage can itself be discounted/ignored. On the other hand, if it is only relatively true, anything it says about itself can be discounted as self-serving, and anything it says about other theories becomes irrelevant (since whatever it says is hermetically sealed inside the theory itself -- that is what "relatively true" implies). In that case, the above passage can be discounted/ignored, once more.

 

Of course, if it is false, it can be ignored, anyway.

 

Either way, what it says can be discounted.

 

[The above is yet another example of two Marxist economists stumbling about in an discipline well outside their area of expertise -- philosophy -- and who end up refuting themselves!]

 

Independently of that, what happened to Marx, Engels, Lenin and Mao's criterion that practice is a criterion of truth? Is that only 'partially'/'relatively' true? But, if practice is a criterion of truth what justifies its truth? That can't be yet more practice, not without arguing in a circle. And if that 'something more' is a different criterion, what is it? If there is one such, what then is the point of referring to practice as the catch-all fall back option when it can't be justified without going round in circles?

 

Finally, as we will see in Essay Ten Part One, a desperate (but maybe by-now-tempered) appeal to "practice" -- an attempt made perhaps in order to help resolve these 'problems', always assuming they can be -- would still be to no avail. Practice takes place at the level of 'appearances', and one set of 'appearances' can hardly absolve another set -- that is, if they even needed absolving, to begin with!

 

[See also Note 29b.]

 

'Commonsense'

 

Issues connected with 'commonsense' clearly have a role to play in any discussion of the distinction between 'appearance' and 'reality'/'essence'. Unfortunately, few DM-theorists bother to inform their readers (with any consistency or clarity -- big surprise there, then!) what they mean by "commonsense". Lenin once claimed that "common sense = the prejudices of its time" [Lenin (1961), p.271] whatever that means! We are never told what its core beliefs -- or even what its peripheral 'prejudices', are -- let alone whether there are one or many competing ideologies/'prejudices' underpinning it. One DM-theorist who did make some attempt to address this question is the STD, Teodor Oizerman. Here he is speaking about "everyday consciousness", which I take it is meant to be the same as "commonsense" (but that might be a mistaken assumption, who can say?):

 

"Everyday consciousness is a multi-layered complex and contradictory entity composed of a multitude of perceptions, emotions and concepts that are generated and continuously reproduced by the relatively constant and familiar conditions surrounding individuals.... We encounter concepts of everyday consciousness everywhere. They are, first and foremost, empirical notions consisting partly of relative truths and partly of illusions and errors: water boils at 100oC; gold does not rust; the sun rises in the morning and sets in the evening; money in a savings bank pays interest. Proverbs are classic expressions of everyday consciousness, polished to perfection by the ages; they are the quintessence of popular wisdom ('life is not a bed of roses'), the class instinct of the oppressed and exploited..., popular fears and hopes." [Oizerman (1982), p.101. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

Ok, well one can almost hear the contempt and condescension in Oizerman's tone as he wrote that. But, what evidence was offered in support of these 'widely held, anti-working class prejudices'?

 

None at all.

 

Is anyone surprised? Sadly, the above in general represents the 'commonsense' of many on the far left.

 

[I have said much more about 'commonsense', here, and more concerning the widely held 'prejudices' on the Marxist left about workers in Essay Nine Part Two (partially quoted below). However, on this in general, see Peels and Woudenberg (2020); having said that, several of that book's contributors also tend to confuse widely held beliefs with 'commonsense'. Follow the last link for more about the difference between them.]

 

But, this is typical of the genre. DM-theorists in general skate over this entire topic -- except to register their (dismissive, even 'orthodox') disdain for 'commonsense', rather like Oizerman. In this (as much as their adherence to other aspects of ruling-class ideology) they echo and channel the condescension that has always been shown toward 'commonsense' by the average defender of the status quo, and not just DM-fans.

 

Those claims will be fully substantiated in Essay Twelve Part Seven. However, we need look no further than Engels himself; in his classic study, The Condition of the Working Class in England, he devoted an entire chapter to a consideration of "The Attitude of the Bourgeoisie Towards the Proletariat" -- i.e., Engels (1845), pp.562-83. Anyone reading that today and who listens to the average right-wing UK Tory (for example, Lee Anderson, who has just defected to the ultra-right-wing 'Reform Party'), or to a typical US Republican (a Thomas Sowell or a J D Vance, for instance) speaking about 'the poor' or 'the working class'  will see how little has changed in the last 180 years. While dialecticians would (rightly) condemn talk like this today, and in terms not dissimilar to those deployed by Engels, nevertheless, just like Engels (and other DM-classicists), their denigration of the language, thought-patterns and experience of the working class identifies them rather too closely and uncomfortably with similar attitudes displayed by card-carrying members of the ruling-class, their hangers-on and their hired 'prize-fighters'. As I have argued in Essay Nine Part Two:

 

So, in spite of what we might read in pro-DM-literature, it isn't Hegelian 'logic' which has been rotated through 180º, but workers themselves. Their thinking has been up-ended, their materialist ideas replaced by incomprehensible Idealist gobbledygook. The erstwhile subjects of history -- revolutionary workers -- must thereby be transformed into passive objects of theory. They must be intellectually neutered, theoretically knocked off their feet.

 

[Again, substitution for much of the above can be found in Part One.]

 

At this point, it is worth stressing what is not being maintained: that revolutionaries should adopt or develop a romantic or naïve view of workers and the ideas they hold --, i.e., that their thoughts aren't fragmentary or inconsistent, that racist or sexist notions can't 'enter their heads', that they unerringly know how best to further their own cause, that they possess the organisational structures required to promote or defend their interests -- or even that they always understand the nature and source of their own oppression, alienation and exploitation, etc., etc.

 

[None of the above are cast in stone, anyway! How workers transform themselves in and by struggle (with or without the aid of the revolutionary party) is already well understood by Marxists and needs no elaboration here. Even so, in Essay Twelve Part Seven, it will be shown how and why any successful intervention by revolutionaries has to be expressed in the vernacular, not the obscure jargon concocted by Hegel and other ruling-class hacks. Any who still think ordinary language is inadequate in this respect are encouraged to read this and this, and then perhaps think again. Or, failing that, contact the editors of the vast majority of revolutionary papers on earth and tell them to (i) Stop using the vernacular when communicating with workers and then (ii) Sit back and watch their circulation positively soar to record heights as a result! (Not!)]

 

Neither is it part of the case being presented here that workers have no need of a revolutionary party largely drawn from their own ranks, which has established long-term links with the proletariat forged in struggle, and which party has in turn learnt from them. [As indeed Lenin did post-1905.]

 

On the other hand, because HM represents a generalisation of workers' experience, when it is introduced to them it augments, clarifies and systematises what they already know. In that case, it doesn't need to be substituted in their heads, replacing their own ideas -- even though it might change many of those ideas for the better. As, noted in Essay Nine Part One, because HM meshes with their experience, and speaks to their exploitation, alienation and oppression, it is introduced, as it were, from the 'inside'.

 

Nevertheless, the only issue of immediate concern is the influence DM has had on the attitude revolutionaries adopt toward workers and each other. Indeed, this will involve the connection between DM and the petty-bourgeois, substitutionist mentality that is endemic among professional revolutionaries (because of their class position and the predilection they all seem to have for elitist, anti-democratic, ruling-class forms-of-thought).

 

Hence, in relation to strategy and tactics, and in connection with a theoretical understanding of the relationship between party and class, the question posed below will be whether ideas drawn from what are demonstrably ruling-class sources, which reflect the priorities of that class (e.g., mystification, esotericism, secrecy, fragmentation, control, hierarchy, arrogance and disdain), when they have been adopted and internalised by revolutionaries, may turn out to possess unsuspected substitutionist implications of their own.

 

In short, it will be shown that, among other things, dialectical concepts have been and still are being used in order to normalise, rationalise and 'justify' substitutionism.

 

[Indeed, as Essay Nine Part One demonstrated, DM is the ideology of substitutionist elements in Dialectical Marxism.]

 

[For more on that, readers are encouraged to check out to Essay Nine Parts One (link above) and Two (here and here), where these allegations have been substantiated.]

 

Finally, one of Oizerman's examples (sunrise) will be examine later in this Essay, but if we focus on the volunteered example given in the next sub-section, we might be able to make a little more sense of the broader claim that there is some sort of 'clash' or incongruity between the way things appear to be and what scientists and Philosophers have so far discovered, 'hidden below the surface of appearances' -- i.e., the supposed conflict, or 'contradiction', between 'commonsense' and 'science'.

 

In other words, what follows will address the issues raised by Item (v) from earlier, but applied more generally to the social and the natural world.

 

Hegel's decidedly odd theory is in turn connected with the undeniable fact that some things 'appear' for a short time and then disappear or fade away, like someone who:...

 

(v) Describes how another looks -- as in "Her appearance gave her away; she was clearly amused", or "His appearance changes from day-to-day; he is a master of disguise."

 

To that end, the next few sections will consider several examples drawn from nature and society that raise issues about how things look (their appearance) and whether or not they are transient to see if the distinction Hegel tried to draw (and DM-fans have unwisely appropriated) between 'appearance' and 'reality'/'essence' is itself valid and implies any sort of 'contradiction'.

 

Contradictions Supposedly Generated By Science

 

The following case in point has been deliberately chosen for its triteness and its familiarity. A more arcane or complex example would have obscured the issues involved. As noted above, other instances of this phenomenon (where 'appearances' appear to 'contradict' reality) will be considered as this Essay unfolds, as well as in other Essays at this site.

 

This volunteered example concerns the apparent incongruity that exists between the way that sticks look bent, and the fact that they do not really bend, when they are partially immersed in water. Of course, it could be objected that this phenomenon doesn't illustrate a process in nature, and so it isn't really relevant. Nevertheless, it is relatively easy to adapt the example so that that objection itself becomes irrelevant, as we will also see.

 

[On this, check out R1a, R2a, R3 and R4, below, which do manage to illustrate a process. Other instances of this alleged clash between science and 'commonsense' can be adjusted in like manner, but I will refrain from doing that here for obvious reasons. As such, they should be viewed in the same way in order to help prevent this section descending any further into recondite, scholastic pedantry.]

 

Be that as it may, this illusion, or incongruity, might be expressed as follows:

 

R1: This stick appears bent in water.

 

R2: It isn't the case that this stick appears bent in water.27

 

R1a: This stick appears to bend when immersed in water.

 

R2a: It isn't the case that this stick appears to bend when immersed in water.

 

R1 and R2, and R1a and R2a, form what appear to be contradictory pairs, but this type of incongruity isn't the sort to which Rees and other dialecticians are alluding: the alleged contradiction between appearance and reality. Plainly, R1 and R2 are both about appearances; hence, they don't illustrate the aforementioned mis-match between appearance and reality.

 

Perhaps the next two sentences will suffice?

 

R3: This stick bends when put in water.

 

R4: It isn't the case that this stick bends when put in water.

 

Again, these two seem to be contradictory, but, unfortunately, once more, they aren't what Rees and other dialecticians had in mind, either, since they fail to contrast appearance with reality. R3 and R4 merely express two contradictory propositions relating to a possible state of affairs (the same one or different). Neither is about appearances.

 

However, the following pair of sentences does attempt to draw a contrast between appearance and reality:

 

R5: This stick appears bent in water.

 

R6: It isn't the case that this stick is bent in water.28

 

The problem with the above two sentences is that they aren't contradictories since they can be both true at once, just as they can both be false at once. The truth of one doesn't imply the falsehood of the other, nor vice versa. There is therefore no logical connection between them. Nor do they even seem to be 'dialectically' connected; that is, they don't struggle with, and then turn into, each other (as they should do if the DM-classics are to be believed). Moreover, they don't imply one another (in the way that the existence of the capitalist class supposedly implies the existence of the proletariat, and vice versa -- so we are told).

 

[At this point it is worth reminding ourselves that two propositions are contradictory just in case they can't both be true and they can't both be false, at once. Not only do they have opposite truth values, the truth of one implies the falsehood of the other, and vice versa. I only mention such salient details since most DM-fans seem oblivious of them, often conflating the LEM, PB (propositional bi-polarity) and the LOC with one another -- and, indeed, all three of them with opposites, inconsistencies, absurdities, contraries, paradoxes, puzzles, quandaries, oddities, irrationalities, oppositional processes, antagonisms, opposing forces, unexpected events, alongside a whole range of unrelated states of affairs, events and assorted idiosyncrasies. (And they then imagine they are somehow uniquely qualified to pontificate about logic! I have given ample proof of this 'Dialectical Dunning-Kruger Effect' in Essay Four Part One.) In fact, they are so eager to see contradictions everywhere that they find they have to tinker with the meaning of the word, "contradiction" itself, so that (for them) it becomes synonymous with "struggle", "conflict" and "opposition". I have said much more about that confusion in Essay Eight Parts Two and Three.]

 

[LOC = Law of Non-Contradiction; LEM = Law of Excluded Middle; PB = Principle of Bivalence.]

 

It could be objected that the fact that sticks appear to bend in water prompts the naïve belief that they actually do bend, which contradicts the fact that they don't really bend when partially immersed. That incongruity, or at least the realisation such it isn't the case that sticks bend under such circumstances, could lead to the rejection of an unscientific and/or a false belief. In that sense, therefore, it could be argued that reality does indeed contradict appearances.

 

Or so it might be claimed...

 

[It is far from clear that anyone who accepts the line promoted here and here -- i.e., that appearances, or the beliefs they motivate, aren't false or 'unreal' -- can consistently advance the above argument.]

 

But, does any of this mean it is false to say that sticks still look bent in water? Clearly not. A stick will still look this way whether you're a scientist, a water dowser, or, indeed, anything inbetween. In which case, if these two sentences seem contradictory (recall, no two contradictory propositions can be true together or false together) -- and given that R6 and R5 are both true -- it would be incorrect to say that they are contradictory:

 

R5: This stick appears bent in water.

 

R6: It isn't the case that this stick is bent in water.

 

Of course, if DM-theorists reject this contention (as seems likely, which is highly likely), they must actually be trying to revise the meaning of the word "contradiction", as opposed to using that familiar term drawn from ordinary discourse. It is worth reminding ourselves that in ordinary language the verb form of this word (i.e., "to contradict") literally means "to gainsay" -- i.e., to utter or write the logical opposite of what another utters or writes. Either that, or DM-fans are attempting to revise a typographically similar-looking word (which we shall label, "contradictionH") they encountered in Hegel's writings, having confused it with a typographically-identical word (which we shall label, "contradictionL") used in FL, or even the one we use in ordinary language (which we shall label, "contradictionO"). But, since these terms are defined, or are used, differently they can't be the same. So, any 'theoretical/philosophical' remarks made by DM-fans about, or in relation to, "contradictionL" and/or "contradictionO" can't be about those terms (despite what DM-theorists clearly think), but are about, or relate to, "contradictionH", thus leaving both "contradictionL" and "contradictionO" unaffected.

 

[The word "appear" was deliberately used in the previous paragraph since we still await a clear definition of "contradictionH".]

 

So, dialecticians oscillate between a hybrid understanding of "contradiction", situated half-way between the meaning(s), or the use, it has in the vernacular and the connotations it enjoys in FL, all the while seeking to link it (somehow) with the maverick sense given this word by Hegel.29

 

Naturally, dialecticians are at liberty to make whatever revisions they deem necessary to any word they see fit, and use them as they please (not that they need my permission or my acquiescence). But any attempt to do so in this case (as part of a 'dialectical' criticism of the alleged deficiencies of FL) would have no more significance, or effect, than would a similar attempt to revise the definition of, say, "relative surplus value" in an attempt to 'prove' that because Marx ignored this 'new definition', his analysis of value was defective.

 

In connection with this, it is also worth recalling that light rays are deflected from their path when they pass between air and water, which creates the illusion that partially-immersed sticks are bent. However, if sticks didn't actually look bent in water (or if it were false to say that they appeared to bend when half immersed), that would count toward a falsification of the scientific theory that light rays themselves deviate from their path upon entering or leaving the relevant media. Tinker around with beliefs like this too much and far more serious problems will emerge that would threaten to undermine much of contemporary Physics.

 

Hence, even in this respect appearances aren't 'contradicted' by 'reality'. Far from it; they occupy an essential role in the confirmation of scientific theory (concerning light as it passes between different media). Consequently, the scientific truth that light deviates from its path under such circumstances is verified by, if not founded upon, the appearance recorded in R5! Furthermore, this isn't even a transient appearance (as noted above, it will presumably last at least as long as the human race exists). In that case, given what we discovered earlier, this can't even be an Hegelian 'appearance'.

 

R5: This stick appears bent in water.

 

It could be objected that the above constitutes an entirely specious response. The plain fact is that scientific knowledge is inconsistent with the belief that sticks bend in water. No amount of hair-splitting, spin and 're-interpretation' can minimise or explain away its significance.

 

However, that would have been an effective response if:

 

(i) The argument presented above were about beliefs and not about appearances; and,

 

(ii) It could be shown that anyone actually believed (or has ever believed) that sticks really do bend when immersed in water.

 

["Anyone", of course, doesn't include infants, those with psychological/psychiatric problems, seriously impaired vision, or those who are inebriated/high on something.]

 

That is because the pro-DM counter-response volunteered in the last but one paragraph specifically mentioned what might plausibly be believed by naïve or untrained observers. Undeniably, such a belief would be incompatible with what we know to be the case, but the DM-claim is that appearances contradict reality. It said nothing about beliefs doing that. [Anyway, the idea that a belief can contradict something that isn't a belief (i.e., that beliefs can 'contradict' 'reality' or 'the facts') is equally misguided. Beliefs can only contradict one another -- and then only if they are expressed in or by indicative sentences.]

 

Indeed, the point being made above is that, far from reality contradicting appearances, scientists themselves need appearances to be correct (or rather, for sentences expressing such beliefs to be true) in order to confirm (in this specific case) Snell's Law, and hence that they have to take account of what seem to be bent sticks. Plainly, that is because scientists have to look at objects and processes in the world, and if they were to see sticks that were partially immersed in water that didn't appear to be bent, they would either question whether the liquid concerned was even water or wonder if they were hallucinating. The same can be said about objects that seem to grow smaller when they recede from us. If they didn't appear to do that, much of the Science of Optics would have to be ditched. Again, scientists need appearances to be 100% correct (or again, for sentences expressing such beliefs to be true, and not just about receding objects, but about the changing shapes of bodies, mirages, etc., etc.), otherwise they would have to kiss goodbye to large swathes of current theory/knowledge.

 

In that case, the above pro-DM objection only seems to work by confusing appearances with beliefs. Now, it certainly isn't being questioned here whether or not propositions drawn from, or based upon, scientific investigation contradict certain beliefs held about the world (expressed in or by indicative sentences/propositions, along lines intimated above), which humans might once have accepted or to which some still give credence. But, to state the obvious, beliefs aren't the same as appearances.

 

It could be objected that the argument presented above is inconsistent. On the one hand, it is claimed that there can be no contradiction between appearances and reality, on the other it allows for the fact that there can be -- indeed, there are -- contradictions between scientific propositions and certain beliefs (expressed propositionally).

 

In which case, the above argument appears to conclude that these are contradictory:

 

B1: p.

 

B2: NN believes that not p.

 

But, it also seems to argue that these aren't contradictory:

 

B3: p.

 

B4: It appears to NN that not p.

 

How can the first pair be deemed contradictory while the second isn't?

 

Or, so it might be objected...

 

Of course, the wording of my earlier claim was specifically this:

 

B5: It certainly isn't being questioned here whether or not propositions drawn from, or based upon, scientific investigation contradict certain beliefs held about the world (expressed in or by indicative sentences/propositions, along lines intimated above), which humans might once have accepted or to which some still give credence. But, to state the obvious, beliefs aren't the same as appearances.

 

When schematic letters (of the sort employed above) have been interpreted, not p is most definitely the contradictory of p, but p itself isn't the contradictory of NN believes that not p, although it would certainly be paradoxical if NN believed that not p were the case while also accepting p itself as true. [Where "p" stands for an indicative sentence with an assertable content.]29a00

 

[That conundrum has since come to be known as Moore's Paradox, after British Philosopher, G. E. Moore, one of Wittgenstein's Cambridge tutors. I have briefly commented on this Paradox in Part One, here.]

 

Nor, when interpreted, is p the contradictory of the back end of B4 -- i.e., p isn't the contradictory of, *to NN that not p (in that particular sentential context). [The asterisk indicates a non-standard locution.]

 

B4: It appears to NN that not p.

 

In which case, B1/B2 and B3/B4 aren't comparable.

 

[B4 has been deliberately left in such a stilted form so that the point being made is easier to see. In addition, it mustn't be assumed that I believe B1 and B2 are contradictories (they aren't!); I am just seeing where a DM-counter-argument might possibly take us.]29a0

 

B1: p.

 

B2: NN believes that not p.

 

It could be argued that if we re-worded the above, they might still be analogous; perhaps in the following way:

 

B6: p.

 

B7: NN has a belief that not p.

 

B8: p.

 

B9: *NN has an appearance that not p.

 

In response to this I will merely note that these two sets of sentences can only be made to appear to be analogous (irony intended!) by a blatant misuse of language (in B9). But, human beings can no more have appearances than they can have seemings or lookings. Of course, if we had sentences in language like B10 (mirroring those like B9 -- or even B11):

 

B10: It believes to me that not p; or,

 

B11: It appears to me that not p,

 

we might be able to make some sense of this response, but we don't, and it isn't difficult to see why we don't. We form our beliefs based on all manner of contingencies, but appearances are things we undergo, or experience, like it or not -- we don't form them. Moreover, we use sentences like these: "NN believes that p", but not "NN appears that p"; "NM believes the branch secretary", but not "NM appears the branch secretary"; "NP believes he can win", but not "NP appears he can win"; "MN has lost her belief in god", but not "MN has lost her appear (sic!) in god", and so on.

 

[Concerning further complications involving belief sentences, see Note 29ao.]

 

So, appearances (still) aren't beliefs, nor are the two even analogous.

 

Nevertheless, it could be objected that while sticks might appear to bend in water, the fact is that they don't actually do so. In that sense, subjective appearances are contradicted by objective facts.

 

Or so it might once again be claimed...

 

However, this latest (proffered) DM-objection itself labours under several additional misconceptions:

 

(1) Appearances are, I take it, 'part of reality' (for want of a better phrase). No one supposes, surely, that appearances are fictional in the way that, say, The Tooth Fairy or Pixies are, or that they have been invented (like, for instance, Sherlock Holmes or Darth Vader), or even fabricated (like Fake News). It isn't as if our ancestors made up a fable that there were such things as appearances and several millennia later we have finally seen through the con. In that sense, appearances are just as 'real' as unbent sticks.

 

[Nor can an Hegelian argue that appearances are transient, while sticks aren't, so appearances aren't 'real', but sticks are. We saw that 'conceptual-trajectory' crash and burn earlier. Of course, the problem here centres on the word "real" and the profligate and incautious way it is used in Traditional Thought (and by DM-fans). I will say more about that in Essay Twelve. In the meantime, readers should consult Moore (1953), pp.216-33, and Austin (1964), pp.62-83.]29a

 

(2) Moreover, but perhaps more importantly (and, as pointed out earlier), since neither 'appearances' nor 'reality' are propositional as such, no contradiction is possible between them.

 

It could be countered that the issue here is the contradiction between essence and appearance, not between appearance and reality, which is an invention of the present Essay. [But, from the passages quoted earlier -- here, here and here -- we can see that that isn't even remotely true.]

 

Nevertheless, even if the meaning of "essence" were itself clear, it is difficult to see how there could be any such contradiction, not unless appearances and essences were also propositional. Hegelians might be able to get away with that peculiar idea (but as far as I know they haven't wandered down that blind alley, yet), since, for them, everything is Ideal. But materialists definitely can't.

 

Of course, that comment itself depends on a view of "contradiction" I don't expect dialecticians to accept; however, until they tell us what they do mean by their odd use of this word, little progress can be made. Since we have only been waiting for two hundred or so years to be informed with any clarity what dialecticians actually mean by "contradiction", it might perhaps be a little impatient for anyone to expect them to come up with a clear and unambiguous answer in the next five centuries.

 

[Not that anyone in the DM-fraternity is trying all that hard, either. (This topic is discussed in more detail in Essays Four, Five, Eight Parts One, Two and Three, and Eleven Part One.)]

 

Moreover, it is important to remember that the example being examined here concerns sticks that look bent when partially immersed in water. In that case, unless dialecticians have a theory about the 'essence' of sticks that differs from their idea/concept -- or any idea/concept of 'real sticks' -- this latest pro-DM objection must fail, too. After all, it was George Novack who argued that:

 

"A thing is truly real if it is necessary, if its appearance truly corresponds to its essence.... Materialists...locate the roots of necessity in the objective world, in the material conditions and conflicting forces which create, sustain and destroy all things. But, from the purely logical standpoint, both schools of philosophy [i.e., Idealism and Materialism -- RL] agree in connecting reality with necessity. Something acquires reality because the necessary conditions for its production and reproduction are objectively present and operative. It becomes more or less real in accordance with the changes in the external and internal circumstances of its development. It remains truly real only so long and insofar as it is necessary under the given conditions. Then, as conditions change, it loses its necessity and its reality and dissolves into mere appearance." [Novack (1971), p.86. Paragraphs merged.]29b

 

Which, more-or-less, settles things: appearances are just as much 'part of reality' as 'essences' are, if they coincide.

 

[How they manage do that with respect to bent sticks I will leave those addicted to this (bizarre) way of talking to figure out for themselves. I don't prefer this (weird) use of language since, I, for one, can make no sense of it.]

 

(3) Finally, the idea that it is merely a 'subjective experience' that sticks appear to bend when partially immersed in water is itself misleading. Not only does everyone see the same appearance (i.e., 'bent sticks' when partially immersed) -– which means it can't be subjective (or only one person would see it) -–, but this apparent bending of sticks forms the basis of 'objective' observations that confirm the scientific fact that light changes its path when passing between media. If the appearance of bent sticks were merely subjective, what then should we make of the claim that light alters its course like this? Is that subjective too? Is the 'objectivity' of science predicated on such tenuously weak 'subjective' foundations?

 

Again, exception might be taken to the idea that appearances are objective, since most philosophers and scientists appear to agree they are subjective (no irony intended). Since objectivity relates to something called "observer independence", appearances must therefore be subjective -- or so it could be argued...

 

(A) First of all, I'm not advancing any such claim here since I reject the use of metaphysical language like this; I have already pointed out that I don't prefer this peculiar way of talking. It is merely being employed here to assist in its demise. Hence, the frequent use of 'scare' quotes.

 

(B) Secondly, since it is also an appearance that (many) philosophers and scientists say they believe that appearances are subjective, it looks like that belief must itself be subjective. It plainly isn't "observer independent". In fact, as should seem reasonably clear, no observation made by scientists or philosophers -- or by anyone else, for that matter --, would or could be "observer"/"mind independent", and therefore "objective", given this decidedly strange way of talking. [Some authors think there is a way around this 'epistemological road block' (for want of a better term) -- for instance, Ruben (1979). That 'escape route' will be blocked in Essay Three Part Six.]

 

So, if 'objectivity' is understood as "observer-", or "mind-independence", it would be impossible to form an 'objective' opinion of anything -- even about 'subjectivity' itself – that is, while we humans unwisely possess 'minds', foolishly go about the place observing things and unwisely express opinions about them.

 

Indeed, as we will soon see, any attempt to classify appearances as 'subjective' (and hence not fully 'real') would totally undermine not just science, but the opinion of anyone who holds such a belief.

 

Hence, if 'objectivity' is defined as "observer-independence" (etc.), then, plainly, the notion that light bends when it passes between media (and every other such belief) can't be 'objective'. As now seems undeniable, the truth of this and every other (supposed) scientific fact depends on centuries of observation (and no little human thought, too), as much as it relies on beliefs held by other human beings. Exactly how these can be independent of one another is a mystery dialecticians have yet to explain. Eliminate the 'subjective' element from science -- if that is what it is -- and everything we believe to be 'objective' must follow it out of the window. If science dealt only with "observer-independent" realities, we wouldn't be able to establish a single 'objective' scientific fact! In such circumstances, there would be no science!

 

Of course, all this might be music to dialecticians' ears, since they already accept the theory that there is a 'dialectical interplay' between the 'objective' and the 'subjective':

 

"Logical concepts are subjective so long as they remain 'abstract,' in their abstract form, but at the same time they express the Thing-in-themselves. Nature is both concrete and abstract, both phenomenon and essence, both moment and relation. Human concepts are subjective in their abstractness, separateness, but objective as a whole, in the process, in the sum-total, in the tendency, in the source." [Lenin (1961), p.208. Italic emphases in the original.]

 

However, if that were so, we would be forced to abandon the idea that "objective" means "mind-independence", contradicting Lenin (and those who agree with him):

 

"We ask, is a man given objective reality when he sees something red or feels something hard, etc., or not? This hoary philosophical query is confused by Mach. If you hold that it is not given, you, together with Mach, inevitably sink to subjectivism and agnosticism and deservedly fall into the embrace of the immanentists, i.e., the philosophical Menshikovs. If you hold that it is given, a philosophical concept is needed for this objective reality, and this concept has been worked out long, long ago. This concept is matter. Matter is a philosophical category denoting the objective reality which is given to man by his sensations, and which is copied, photographed and reflected by our sensations, while existing independently of them. Therefore, to say that such a concept can become 'antiquated' is childish talk, a senseless repetition of the arguments of fashionable reactionary philosophy. Could the struggle between materialism and idealism, the struggle between the tendencies or lines of Plato and Democritus in philosophy, the struggle between religion and science, the denial of objective truth and its assertion, the struggle between the adherents of supersensible knowledge and its adversaries have become antiquated during the two thousand years of the development of philosophy?...

 

"As the reader sees, all these arguments of the founders of empirio-criticism entirely and exclusively revolve around the old epistemological question of the relation of thinking to being, of sensation to the physical. It required the extreme naïveté of the Russian Machians to discern anything here that is even remotely related to 'recent science,' or 'recent positivism.' All the philosophers mentioned by us, some frankly, others guardedly, replace the fundamental philosophical line of materialism (from being to thinking, from matter to sensation) by the reverse line of idealism. Their denial of matter is the old answer to epistemological problems, which consists in denying the existence of an external, objective source of our sensations, of an objective reality corresponding to our sensations. On the other hand, the recognition of the philosophical line denied by the idealists and agnostics is expressed in the definitions: matter is that which, acting upon our sense-organs, produces sensation; matter is the objective reality given to us in sensation, and so forth....

 

"'Matter is disappearing' means that the limit within which we have hitherto known matter is vanishing and that our knowledge is penetrating deeper; properties of matter are likewise disappearing which formerly seemed absolute, immutable, and primary (impenetrability, inertia, mass, etc.) and which are now revealed to be relative and characteristic only of certain states of matter. For the sole 'property' of matter with whose recognition philosophical materialism is bound up is the property of being an objective reality, of existing outside our mind." [Lenin (1972), pp.144-45, 165, 311. Bold emphases alone added, quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

"To be a materialist is to acknowledge objective truth, which is revealed to us by our sense-organs. To acknowledge objective truth, i.e., truth not dependent upon man and mankind, is, in one way or another, to recognise absolute truth." [Ibid., p.148. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"Knowledge can be useful biologically, useful in human practice, useful for the preservation of life, for the preservation of the species, only when it reflects objective truth, truth which is independent of man." [Ibid., p.157. Bold emphasis added.]

 

[I have said much more about 'objectivity' here.]

 

It is impossible to make the above comments consistent with one another.

 

[Anyone who disagrees is invited to email me with their best shot.]

 

However, if dialecticians are (bravely) prepared to contradict Lenin, much of their epistemology will go down in flames as a result, since, according to this latest turn-of-events, it seems that nature is 'objective' only if we know about it, and then only if we manage to do so in certain specific ways, making it observer-, and thought-dependent, after all!

 

It could be argued that this misconstrues Hegel's notion of objectivity; indeed, it confuses it with a much looser, modern concept. But, Hegel drew many of his ideas from Kant's Critical Philosophy and adapted them accordingly. In fact, what he says about this topic can't be separated from his system as a whole.

 

Or, so it might be maintained...

 

Be this as it may, since the above considerations will be examined in Essay Twelve Parts Five and Six, not much more will be said about this topic here. But, for present purposes, it is worth pointing out that Dialectical Marxists surely can't accept Hegel's notion of objectivity, since that would openly concede they are (in fact) Objective Idealists. In that case, until we are told exactly what they do mean when they repeat the sort of ill-considered and obscure things about 'objectivity' that Lenin (or even Hegel) came out with, little more can be done with anything they have so far said about it.

 

[It is important to remind ourselves that in MEC (quoted above), Lenin clearly meant by "objectivity" the existence of objects and processes independent of, and external to, the human mind, which doesn't appear to be what Hegel meant by this word (no pun intended) -- that is, if it is possible to determine what Hegel actually meant by anything he inflicted on his readers. I have said much more about that in Essay Thirteen Part One.]

 

[MEC = Materialism and Empirio-Criticism; i.e., Lenin (1972).]

 

In response it could be argued that an objective view of nature is one which attempts to picture it as it must be (or as it must have been) without observers, or even as it would be if there were no 'conscious minds' to observe or interact with it. That is, it aims to depict reality as it is in-itself (or, perhaps expressed in DM-terms, as it is in relation to its constantly changing nature).

 

Of course, this take on 'objectivity' would clearly undermine what Lenin said about it, since "Thing-in-Itself" doesn't mean "Thing-as-observed-by-some-mind-or-other":

 

"Logical concepts are subjective so long as they remain 'abstract,' in their abstract form, but at the same time they express the Thing-in-themselves. Nature is both concrete and abstract, both phenomenon and essence, both moment and relation. Human concepts are subjective in their abstractness, separateness, but objective as a whole, in the process, in the sum-total, in the tendency, in the source." [Lenin (1961), p.208. Italic emphases in the original.]

 

Here, Lenin appears to connect 'objective reality' with what we determine it to be (even if only partially or "relatively") when we investigate it 'dialectically' (no pun intended again!). Unfortunately, as usual, the pronouncements coming from DM-fans on this and other related topics are about as clear and perspicuous as the Nicene Creed. Hence, I leave it to others to make what they can of this interminable dialectical muddle. I can make no further sense of it.

 

Independently of that, the use of the word "picture" itself is something of a give-away. Here is Lenin descending into even greater confusion:

 

"For instance, the materialist Frederick Engels...constantly and without exception speaks in his works of things and their mental pictures or images, and it is obvious that these mental images arise exclusively from sensations. (p.32/p.41)

 

"Anybody who reads Anti-Dühring and Ludwig Feuerbach with the slightest care will find scores of instances when Engels speaks of things and their reflections in the human brain, in our consciousness, thought, etc. Engels does not say that sensations or ideas are 'symbols' of things, for consistent materialism must here use 'image', picture, or reflection instead of 'symbol', as we shall show in detail in the proper place." (p.33/p.42)

 

"To say that the purpose of science is to present a true picture of the world...means to repeat the materialist point of view. By saying so, one is admitting the objective reality of the world in relation to our knowledge, of the model in relation to the picture." (p.197/p.171)

 

"Only when we throw out the first two rungs, and only then, can we obtain a picture of the world that truly corresponds to natural science and materialism. Namely: 1) the physical world exists independently of the mind of man and existed long prior to man, prior to any 'human experience'; 2) the psychical, the mind, etc., is the highest product of matter (i.e., the physical), it is a function of that particularly complex fragment of matter called the human brain." (p.270/pp.227-28) [The first page reference is to Lenin (1972); the second to Lenin (1962) (a PDF). Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Bold emphases alone added.]

 

Puzzled readers might well wonder how a picture can be 'objective' in an 'independent-of-man' kind of way. Pictures are only such because of the observers who view them. Eliminate the observer and the 'picturing' role of science (or, indeed, of anything) must go with it. Admittedly, the physical object that constitutes a picture (i.e., in one sense of that word: the canvas, the frame, the paint, the paper, the ink, etc., etc.) won't immediately vanish if humanity and all sentient life perished (or, of course, it won't do so depending on how that itself happens!), but the verb "to picture" is transitive. Without human input, no picturing can take place. The Moon, for example, might very well exist independent of our knowledge of it, and it certainly did so long before all sentient life evolved on this planet, but it isn't a picture of anything. Nor is your favourite aunt (if you have one), no matter how many photographs you have of her. So, if Lenin wants to use the word "picture", he must abandon 'objectivity' (as he himself defines it), or tell us what he means by "picture" that doesn't imply there is an observer, and hence doesn't work transitively, in the manner indicated above, or in a way that doesn't undermine what he also says about the 'objectivity' of science.

 

That is, of course, why we find the 'Ideal Observer' -- or the use of terms that imply that 'virtual observers' exist 'somewhere' --, cropping up all over the place, supposedly witnessing events (often those that no human could possibly experience -- I will give a few examples of this presently). And that would still be the case even if such an 'observer' only featured in a 'thought-experiment' -- such as, "Imagine you are travelling on a light beam, at the speed of light"; or "Imagine you live in two-dimensional Flatland!" -- in connection with many erstwhile, 'objective' theories or descriptions of nature, or, at least, in relation to their popularisations. On that basis, the term "objective" would mean something like "observer-, but not ideal-observer-independent". In other words, science would be 'objective' only if we conveniently forget what is meant by "observer-independent".

 

It could be argued that Lenin employed the nominal form of "picture", not the verb form, so no transitivity was implied. But the nominal form of "picture" (as Lenin used it) is relational. Hence, "picture" used that way is a picture of something, and it is the human observer that does the relating. A picture, as a picture, isn't just an inert object, so to speak. The way Lenin used this noun suggests he was fully aware of this. For example:

 

"To say that the purpose of science is to present a true picture of the world...means to repeat the materialist point of view." [Ibid. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"Anybody who reads Anti-Dühring and Ludwig Feuerbach with the slightest care will find scores of instances when Engels speaks of things and their reflections in the human brain, in our consciousness, thought, etc. Engels does not say that sensations or ideas are 'symbols' of things, for consistent materialism must here use 'image', picture, or reflection instead of 'symbol'." [Ibid. Bold emphases added.]

 

"Only when we throw out the first two rungs, and only then, can we obtain a picture of the world that truly corresponds to natural science and materialism." [Ibid. Bold emphasis added.]

 

So, to repeat: One might well wonder how a picture can be 'objective' in an 'independent-of-man' kind of way. Lenin certainly failed to explain how, and, as far as can be ascertained, no DM-fan since has filled in the gaps.

 

[Again, if anyone knows differently: please email me with the details.]

 

It could still be argued that the objectivity of science is based on the following sort of counterfactual:

 

R7: Even if there were no observers, light would still bend as it passed between media.

 

Naturally, sentences like R7 won't be controverted at this site (or anywhere else, for that matter) -- although it is highly questionable whether the word "objective" is of any real help here -- but it is worth pointing out that R7 isn't relevant to the DM-theory presently being questioned. That is because, if there were no observers, appearances couldn't contradict reality -- for, in that case, there would plainly be no 'appearances' to any 'contradicting', nobody to do the 'contradicting', and no one to experience a single 'appearance' to begin with! Eliminate human observers and out go 'appearances' with them. And if there are none of them, they can't do any 'contradicting', either.

 

[I am aware that animals can legitimately be said to 'experience appearances' (if that, too, is the right phrase), but since we can't know anything about this (and probably never will!), and because DM-theorists in general totally ignore what animals experience, no more will be said about this side-issue here. I have, however, added a few comments about animals to Essay Thirteen Part Three.]

 

So, 'objectively' speaking (to adopt this confused mode of expression again, for the moment), 'appearances' can't contradict "things-in-themselves", even if they were to be counterfactually depicted in the above way. That is because neither are propositional. [On that, see Note 30.]

 

It might still be felt that there must be a contradiction between 'commonsense', 'appearances', ordinary language and scientific knowledge if the latter is to make any progress. We no longer believe many things that once seemed obvious to 'commonsense', or which appeared to be true. This clearly means that most of our former erroneous beliefs and theories have been abandoned or corrected by the progress of science, at some point.

 

Or so it might be maintained...

 

However, this latest attempt to rescue the theory that 'reality contradicts appearances' labours under another confusion -- one based on the belief that 'commonsense' and ordinary language are somehow the same. They aren't.

 

[This topic is examined in greater detail in Essay Twelve (however, some of that material has already been published here). There, it will become apparent that since no one seems to have a clear idea what the term "commonsense" means (as it is used in Philosophy), it is difficult to make much sense of the above objection.]

 

It is also worth pointing out that long before the scientific study of nature began, human beings were well aware of the fact that sticks don't bend in water. It hardly took a Newton, a Galileo or an Einstein to apprise humanity of that amazing fact! That isn't to say earlier generations were able to explain this phenomenon, but their inability to do that plainly has no bearing on the topic in hand.

 

[Several of the other 'corrections' that scientific advance has allegedly forced on 'commonsense' will be examined in the next sub-section, and then again elsewhere at this site -- particularly in Essay Twelve Part Seven.]

 

As we have just seen, this entire topic revolves around the use of two obscure terms-of-art: "objective" and "subjective". Neither of them has a clear meaning or a fixed use (when employed metaphysically), even for, or by, those who think they know what they mean! Of course, that clearly implies the distinction between these two words must itself be 'subjective' -- again, if, for the moment, we accept as legitimate this odd way of talking.

 

Be this as it may, if the theory that 'reality contradicts appearances' actually depends on this unintelligible pair of terms -- "objective" and "subjective" -- it would prove impossible to determine its veracity, at least, not until those two words have themselves been given a clear meaning, and, incidentally a 'meaning' that doesn't itself depend on a single instance of human or observer-motivated input, for that would render that 'meaning' 'subjective', too!

 

Finally, as noted above, this entire issue reduces discussion to a consideration of contradictory beliefs -– the erroneous nature of which becomes increasingly obvious as science progresses. If that is all it means, it, too, won't be controverted at this site, for there is nothing in the least bit puzzling about false beliefs, still less about those that are contradictory, or even those that have been abandoned.

 

Indeed, and alas, such beliefs are as common as grains of sand on Bondi beach.30

 

The 'Contradiction' Between Science And 'Commonsense'

 

In view of the above, perhaps we should consider examples that illustrate the alleged conflict between science and 'commonsense' (i.e., disparities that many think have actually arisen as and when scientists study nature -- which, as we have seen, is a topic often alluded to by DM-fans), in order to try to understand what the supposed 'contradiction' between 'appearance' and 'reality' is meant to be. To that end, consider the following:

 

R8: The Sun appears to rise each morning.

 

R9: It isn't the case that the Sun appears to rise each morning.

 

R10: It isn't the case that the Sun rises each morning.

 

Once more, while R8 and R9 might look contradictory, they fail to match the sort of conflict we seek (or, rather, the sort that DM-theorists require) since they're both about appearances. not the supposed clash between 'appearance' and 'reality'. In addition, there is no obvious logical connection between R10 and either one of R8 and R9. That is because the truth or falsehood of R10 has no bearing on the truth or falsehood of R8 and R9, nor vice versa. [Of course, that observation depends on what R10, for example, itself means. On that, see Note 30a.]30a

 

In fact, if the earth were stationary, and it was the Sun that moved, there would be no difference in the way this phenomenon manifested itself and hence appeared to observers. Furthermore, we surely wouldn't conclude that R10 had been contradicted if sunrise couldn't be seen one morning because of, say, fog or thick cloud -- that is, if the Sun didn't appear (to any local observers) to rise. Nor would R8 become false if, in the future, scientists changed their minds about the truth of R10 (or its corollary, the idea that the Earth revolves around the Sun, not the other way round).31

 

This recurring 'roadblock' is in fact a logical barrier. Indeed, it is more like a fatal defect in their theory that John Rees and other dialecticians have clearly overlooked; it isn't possible to form a contradiction when a proposition that expresses matters of fact is conjoined with one that reports only appearances; indeed, as we saw earlier.

 

In short, the following schematic sentences:

 

R11: It appears to be the case that p; and,

 

R12: It is not the case that p,

 

can't form a contradictory pair when interpreted in the manner specified and then conjoined (where p is once again a propositional variable) in R11c:

 

R11c: It appears to be the case that p and it is not the case that p.

 

R11 and R12 aren't even inconsistent, since they can both be true (when they have been interpreted). Consider the interpreted sentences R11a and R12a (or their more colloquial equivalents, R11b and R12b):

 

R11a: It appears to be the case that it is raining.

 

R11b: It appears to be raining. [Which is a more colloquial version of R11a.]

 

R12a: It is not the case that it is raining.

 

R12b: It isn't raining. [Which is, again, a more colloquial version of R12a.]

 

R12c: The water main next door has just burst.

 

So, observer NN, for instance, might look out of the window and truthfully utter R11b, while her companion, NM, truthfully comes out with R12b a few seconds later. Both would be speaking the truth since, unbeknown to NN, there has just been a major fracture in a neighbouring water pipe which is cascading what looks like rain high into the air over their house prompting NM to utter R12c, soon after. Even then, R11b could be true, since, in such circumstances it would still appear to be raining even when it wasn't.

 

Or, think how rain machines work in the film industry:

 

 

Video Three: How To Create The Appearance Of Rain

 

[Yes, this is yet another boringly trite example, but it has the (not inconsiderable) merit of making things clear enough even for befuddled DM-fans to get the point.]

 

Moreover, unless we subscribe to the view that facts and appearances are intelligent, or are perhaps both argumentative and belligerent -– that is, we assume they are capable of arguing among themselves or of engaging in disputation -- it would make no sense to suppose that an appearance could literally contradict (i.e., "gainsay", "speak against") a true proposition. Not only are appearances non-linguistic and non-sentient, but as far as propositions and appearances are concerned, they don't seem to oppose each other 'dialectically' in any obvious way, nor pick verbal fights with one another. They certainly don't turn into one another (which is what 'dialectical opposites' are supposed to do, so we are told by the DM-classics), nor do they cause/motivate each other to change (which is, once more, what the DM-classics tell us they all do). In addition, the existence of one doesn't imply the existence of the other (unlike the existence of the proletariat -- which is implied by, and implies in return, the existence of the capitalist class, or so we are also told).

 

Hence, even if this were a contradiction, it wouldn't be dialectical, whatever else it is.

 

In that case, this supposed contradiction makes little sense, even in DM-terms!

 

Furthermore, the apparent motion of the Sun is the same today (with respect to sunrise, at least) as it was thousands of years ago. Admittedly, we might interpret it differently today, but that doesn't affect how things still appear to observers. So, at best, any (possible) DM-'contradiction' here must be figurative if it is to apply in any meaningful way. Either that or it must depend on some sort of terminological re-definition (that has yet to be justified or explained with any clarity). If this were a genuine DM-'contradiction', something should have changed at least since Copernicus wrote what he did. That is because 'dialectical contradictions' cause change, as already noted. Has the apparent motion of the Sun each morning changed in all that time? Maybe 'into its 'opposite' (whatever that is supposed to be)? But that is again what the DM-classics tell us must happen with 'dialectical opposites' caught up in a 'dialectical contradiction' -- they are all supposed to change into their 'opposites' after 'struggling' with them. [Follow the previous link for extensive textual proof.]

 

So, has the apparent motion of the Sun each morning changed into its 'opposite'?

 

Not that anyone has noticed.

 

[Please email me with the details if you disagree.]

 

Nevertheless, it could be argued that there are key areas of scientific knowledge that do in fact contradict appearances, despite what has been argued above. It is surely true that those who relied on 'commonsense' at one time imagined that the earth was stationary, whereas scientists now know that not only does our planet rotate on its axis and orbit the Sun, the Solar System itself orbits the centre of our Galaxy, which in turn orbits the galactic cluster of which ours is a part. [Here is an amazing video of this complex motion.]

 

In which case, the following pair of propositions could well illustrate the intended contradiction here:

 

R13: The earth moves.

 

R14: It is not the case that the earth moves.

 

Even though these two sentences certainly form a contradictory pair they aren't what we are looking for -- since neither of them is about appearances.

 

So, we hit yet another non-dialectical brick wall...

 

In addition, John Rees seemed to be interested in contradictory pairs where both halves were true (or which reflect 'contradictory states of affairs/processes', or those that somehow coexist -- i.e., involving seemingly 'correct' appearances which are 'contradicted' by genuinely 'objective' underlying 'realities'), otherwise the alleged superiority of DL over FL would be illusory. That is because, as already noted, both halves of a DM-style contradiction must both be true together -- or, once more, they must reflect co-existing 'contradictory states of affairs/processes', unlike their less contentious FL-cousins.

 

[Henceforth, to save on needless repetition I will simply refer to "co-existing 'contradictory states of affairs'", but it should be assumed I mean "co-existing 'contradictory states of affairs/processes'", unless stated otherwise.]

 

Unfortunately, however, R14 is false.32

 

[This specific theme will be continued in the next sub-section.]

 

Does The Earth Move?

 

It should hardly need pointing out, but John Rees (and other DM-theorists) would hardly be interested in pairs of supposedly contradictory propositions if they thought both were false, or that when one was true the other was false. [Or even that they both failed to reflect coexistent 'contradictory states of affairs'.] But, because DM-theorists without exception fail to specify clearly what they actually do mean by "contradiction" in such circumstances (or, indeed, in any circumstances), it is impossible to say whether even that supposition is itself correct, or hopelessly wide of the mark.

 

In response to what has gone before, it could be objected that contemporary, post-Copernican Astrophysics in fact contradicts Aristotelian and Ptolemaic theories about the immobility of the Earth. Of course, that is itself a controversial interpretation of the relationship between ancient, medieval, early modern and contemporary science -– and one that isn't obviously correct. [I will explain why in Essay Thirteen Part Two.]

 

[TOR = Theory of Relativity.]

 

Be this as it may, one clear consequence of the TOR is that, with a suitable change of reference frame it is (mathematically) possible to model the Earth as stationary while the Sun orbits it. That done, the above 'contradiction' simply disappears. In which case, the only necessary 'correction' to Aristotelian/Ptolemaic Physics (in this respect) would involve the abandonment of the idea that the Earth is situated in a unique frame of reference. But science itself can neither confirm nor confute that particular metaphysical (or even theological) assumption.

 

On this specific topic, physicist, Robert Mills, had this to say:

 

"Another way of stating the principle of equivalence, a way that better reflects its name, is to say that all reference frames, including accelerated reference frames, are equivalent, that the laws of Physics take the same form in any reference frame…. And it is also correct to say that the Copernican view (with the sun at the centre) and the Ptolemaic view (with the earth at the centre) are equally valid and equally consistent!" [Mills (1994), pp.182-83. Spelling altered to conform with UK English. Bold emphasis and link added. Italic emphasis in the original.]

 

It is worth recalling that the late Professor Mills was co-inventor of Yang-Mills Theory in Gauge Quantum Mechanics, and was therefore neither a scientific novice nor a fringe crank.

 

Add to that what noted Astronomer, Fred Hoyle, had to say:

 

"Instead of adding further support to the heliocentric picture of the planetary motions the Einstein theory goes in the opposite direction, giving increased respectability to the geocentric picture. The relation of the two pictures is reduced to a mere coordinate transformation and it is the main tenet of the Einstein theory that any two ways of looking at the world which are related to each other by a coordinate transformation are entirely equivalent from a physical point of view.... Today we cannot say that the Copernican theory is 'right' and the Ptolemaic theory 'wrong' in any meaningful physical sense...." [Hoyle (1973), pp.78-79. Bold emphases added; paragraphs merged.]

 

"We now know that the difference between a heliocentric theory and a geocentric theory is one of relative motion only, and that such a difference has no physical significance. But such an understanding had to await Einstein's theory of gravitation in order to be fully clarified." [Hoyle (1975), p.416.]

 

Similarly, Nobel Laureate, Max Born, commented as follows:

 

"Thus from Einstein's point of view Ptolemy and Copernicus are equally right. What point of view is chosen is a matter of expediency. For the mechanics of the planetary system the view of Copernicus is certainly the more convenient. But it is meaningless to call the gravitational fields that occur when a different system of reference is chosen 'fictitious' in contrast with the 'real' fields produced by near masses: it is just as meaningless as the question of the 'real' length of a rod...in the special theory of relativity. A gravitational field is neither 'real' nor 'fictitious' in itself. It has no meaning at all independent of the choice of coordinates, just as in the case of the length of a rod." [Born (1965), p.345. Bold emphasis added. I owe this reference to Rosser (1967).]

 

However, this particular idea pre-dates the TOR; as Robert DiSalle notes (who also provides the background details to these and other related theoretical issues), it goes back at least to Leibniz, and maybe even Galileo:

 

"The term 'reference frame' was coined in the 19th century, but it has a long prehistory, beginning, perhaps, with the emergence of the Copernican theory. The significant point was not the replacement of the earth by the sun as the centre of all motion in the universe, but the recognition of both the earth and the sun as merely possible points of view from which the motions of the celestial bodies may be described. This implied that the basic task of Ptolemaic astronomy -- to represent the planetary motions by combinations of circular motions -- could take any point to be fixed, without sacrificing predictive power. Therefore, as Copernicus suggested in the opening arguments of On the Revolutions of the Heavenly Spheres, the choice of any particular point required some justification on grounds other than mere successful astronomical prediction. The most persuasive grounds, seemingly, were physical: we don't perceive the physical effects that we would expect the earth's motion to produce. Copernicus himself noted, however, in reply, that we can indeed undergo motions that are physically imperceptible, as on a smoothly moving ship.... At least in some circumstances, we can easily treat our moving point of view as if it were at rest.

 

"As the basic programme of Ptolemy and Copernicus gave way to that of early classical mechanics as developed by Galileo, this equivalence of points of view was made more precise and explicit. Galileo was unable to present a decisive argument for the motion of the earth around the sun. He demonstrated, however, that the Copernican view does not contradict our experience of a seemingly stable earth. He accomplished this through a principle that, in the precise form that it takes in Newtonian mechanics, has become known as the 'principle of Galilean relativity': mechanical experiments will have the same results in a system in uniform motion that they have in a system at rest. Arguments against the motion of the earth had typically appealed to experimental evidence -- e.g., that a stone dropped from a tower falls to the base of the tower, instead of being left behind as the earth rotates during its fall. But Galileo argued persuasively that such experiments would happen just as they do whether the earth were moving or not, provided that the motion is sufficiently uniform.... Galileo's account of this was not precisely the principle that we call 'Galilean relativity'; he seems to have thought that a system in uniform circular motion, such as a frame at rest on the rotating earth, would be indistinguishable from a frame truly at rest. The principle was named in his honour because he had grasped the underlying idea of dynamical equivalence: he understood the composition of motion, and understood how individual motions of bodies within a system -- such as the fall of a stone from a tower -- are composed with the motion of the system as a whole. This principle of composition, combined with the idea that bodies maintain their uniform motion, formed the basis for the idea of dynamically indistinguishable frames of reference....

 

"Leibniz, later, articulated a more general 'equipollence of hypotheses': in any system of interacting bodies, any hypothesis that any particular body is at rest is equivalent to any other. Therefore neither Copernicus' nor Ptolemy's view can be true -- though one may be judged simpler than the other -- because both are merely possible hypothetical interpretations of the same relative motions. This principle clearly defines (what we would call) a set of reference frames. They differ in their arbitrary choices of a resting point or origin, but agree on the relative positions of bodies at any moment and their changing relative distances through time...." [DiSalle (2020). Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Italic emphasis in the original, bold emphases and link added. Spelling modified to agree with UK English.]

 

[Although, DiSalle also points out that Leibniz's equivalence principle was actually inconsistent with his [Leibniz's] theory of motion. It took the TOR to sort that conundrum out.]

 

Of course, as Leibniz argued, it could always be claimed that Copernican theory is simpler than the Ptolemaic system (i.e., thereby recommending the adoption, or the wielding, of 'Ockham's Razor'), but until we receive a clear sign that nature works in accordance with our notion of simplicity (or cares a fig about it -- that is, if 'we' have any such notion), this response won't wash.

 

Here is physicist, Sabine Hossenfelder:

 

"They were so sure, they bet billions on it. For decades physicists told us they knew where the next discoveries were waiting. They built accelerators, shot satellites into space, and planted detectors in underground mines. The world prepared to ramp up the physics envy. But where physicists expected a breakthrough, the ground wouldn't give. The experiments didn't reveal anything new. What failed physicists wasn't their math; it was their choice of math. They believed that Mother Nature was elegant, simple, and kind about providing clues. They thought they could hear her whisper when they were talking to themselves. Now Nature spoke, and she said nothing, loud and clear." [Hossenfelder (2018), p.vi. Paragraphs merged; bold emphasis added.]

 

Again, this is quite apart from the fact that 'simplicity' itself is impossible to define in non-question-begging terms. For example, which is the simpler of these two formulae?

 

(1) θ = Ae-kt

 

(2) θ = At2 + Bt + C

 

Plainly, (2) is algebraically 'simpler', but (1) is 'simpler' if we judge simplicity on the basis of the number of terms employed. Naturally, the problem deciding which 'law' (when expressed mathematically, for example) is 'simpler' becomes all the more difficult as the complexity level rises. [On that, see Losee (2001), pp.228-29.] Incidentally, anyone who thinks nature always 'chooses' the simplest option available should perhaps compare contemporary High Energy Physics with Aristotelian Physics. That should disabuse them of the idea that Ockham's Razor is a sensible method for scientists to utilise -- not that there is much evidence they have ever done so. [A few years ago, Marxist Philosopher of Science, Elliott Sober, wrote a rather complex and highly technical book entitled Simplicity -- i.e., Sober (1975) --, clearly failing to realise the irony involved.]

 

Of course, the above interpretation of the relation between the Copernican and the Ptolemaic systems suffers from the serious problem of trying to explain how, if we fix the frame of reference so that the Earth is stationary while the rest of the heavens revolve around it, the 'fixed stars' manage to travel quite so far, so fast. Indeed, if they complete one revolution per day (as they must given this view), then they will have to travel many, many times faster than the speed of light to allow the stars and galaxies billions of light years distant to complete a full circuit in 24 hours. [Naturally, that assumes the 'fixed stars' are thousands, millions or billions of light years away.] Stars in our Galaxy would have to travel many thousands of times greater than the speed of light while those on the outer fringes of the observable universe would have to exceed it several billion fold.

 

Even more puzzling still: if any point anywhere can be taken as the centre of a stationary frame of reference with everything else moving in relation to it, then, for example, when someone sets off for a walk, and they are still considered stationary, while the rest of the world breezes past them (again, given this 'revised' view), one might well wonder why every other object, and especially every other human being, fails to register the acceleration that they must undergo in order to accommodate that individual's ambulatory proclivities. Or, indeed, why water in nearby canals, rivers or lakes, for instance, doesn't slosh about, why drinks in cups or glasses don't spill when anyone 'gets up' to 'leave' a bar or café. Or even why houses or flats don't collapse as if hit by an earthquake whenever anyone sets off on a sprint. And so on...

 

It won't do at this point to complain that the above aren't inertial frames of reference but involve accelerated (i.e., non-inertial) frames of reference. The fact that not all of the above experience accelerations (and the 'inertial forces' associated with them) still tells us which object(s) have changed their motion and which haven't.

 

So, let us assume that the relative motion between the ground and someone who sets off for a walk is zero before any change in motion, and that after this individual sets off it is a steady, but not now accelerating, 4 km/hr. However, after she sets off the ground isn't moving any faster relative to that individual (no matter what the mathematics of relative motion might tell us -- the ground hasn't accelerated!), that individual is moving 4 km/hr faster than before relative to the ground. In which case, even though a mathematical description of the relative velocities here can't discriminate between these two scenarios (i.e., between questions concerning which one, the earth or the walker, is now moving faster relative to the other than they were before), a physical description, and more importantly our experience of the world, most certainly can distinguish between the two. If we were to argue that the ground is now actually moving 4 km/hr faster relative to the walker than it was before, we would then be forced to conclude that the earth (not the walker) must have undergone an acceleration. But, that was actually the case with only one of the two factors involved -- the walker herself, not the ground. That is, of course, just a roundabout way of saying that we don't live in a mathematical universe (howsoever useful mathematics proves to be!); or even perhaps that the world we occupy and experience in isn't a mathematical object or structure.

 

Indeed, if we were to press such considerations much further, they could stand as an effective 'common sense' refutation of a core principle of Relativity Theory.

 

Well, we should perhaps leave such puzzles to the experts to sort out...

 

[I posted this conundrum on a physics discussion board a few years ago, but the answers I received were incomprehensible to anyone who doesn't think the universe is a mathematical object of some sort. (I certainly failed to understand them, and I have a mathematics degree!) Indeed, the ensuing discussion showed that if you know enough technical jargon, you can make anything appear to work (rather like the numerous word salads that were concocted by Medieval Theologians who tried to square Roman Catholic Theology with Aristotelian Philosophy; anyone who has read enough of that material will know exactly what I am talking about). This also illustrates how much disagreement there is among physicists over such basic issues as space, time and motion (indeed, as noted in Essay Eleven Part One and Essay Five)! A perusal of any advanced physics discussion board or forum will amply confirm this fact. For example, I have been asking Professors of Physics on Quora for the last eight years to explain what energy is (for goodness sake!). They all either ignore the question or change the subject pretty quickly. Of those who do deign to answer, each one gives a different explanation, which soon falls apart on further questioning.]

 

[On this in general, see Copleston (2003b), pp.423-32; 559-63, Kretzmann, et al (1988), and Rubenstein (2003). See also the comments and references listed earlier.]

 

Having said that, it is worth pointing out that in relation to the relative motion of heavenly bodies, the above local considerations don't apply (except, maybe, the one related to the superluminal velocity of the orbiting stars). This might now serve to illustrate the fact that a mathematical theory could even appear to be highly successful when applied to the entire universe, and might make very accurate predictions (which are subsequently confirmed by observation and measurement), but when it comes to its application to the world as we know it, or as we experience it locally, it might not seem quite so sensible, never mind believable. [Hossenfelder (2018).]

 

[QM = Quantum Mechanics.]

 

In which case, the TOR makes very poor predictions about our experience of the everyday world. [I will say much more about that in Essay Thirteen Part Two. In the meantime on this topic, readers might like to watch this video which argues (knowledgeably and convincingly!) that General Relativity implies that, contrary to appearances and everyday experience, it is the earth that rises to meet a 'falling body'; the body itself doesn't fall to earth! Make of that what you can. Added on Edit November 2024: This rather irritating video explains why! It is connected with 'gravitational time dilation'. On this, see Epstein (1985). However, in order to illustrate further a point made in Essay Eleven Part One, it is virtually impossible to find two physicists who agree about the fundamentals of QM or Relativity, here is a video by a physicist (i.e., the same scientist who made the first video to which I linked in this paragraph!) who claims this effect isn't caused by time dilation!]

 

Nevertheless, even if the above considerations represented an accurate depiction of the relation between these two theories (the Ptolemaic and the Copernican), they would still fail to be of much use to DM-fans -– that is, not unless they abandon the requirement that 'dialectical contradictions' should both be true (or that they should reflect 'co-existing contradictory states of affairs'). But, as noted earlier, both sets of propositions (concerning the Ptolemaic and the Copernican systems) can't be true at once, given contemporary science's current commitment to the superiority of the latter over the former. And should any dialecticians decide that the Equivalence Principle vindicates their approach (since it allows both systems to be regarded as equally valid), that would be no help, either. That is because it merely says the validity of each system depends on the frame of reference chosen, which in turn means that when one frame is chosen, the other option falls by the wayside (until a new frame is chosen, of course). DM-fans certainly can't appeal to the alleged contradiction between 'appearance' and 'reality' in this instance, since there is no 'reality' for anything to contradict until a reference frame has been chosen -- which, naturally, makes each separate configuration a creature of convention, and hence not the least bit 'objective' (or, at least, not 'objective' in the way Lenin defined it). It is also worth recalling that there aren't just two competing reference frames up for grabs here; any point in space (and, plainly, there are countless septillions of them!) is equally valid in this respect.

 

It might, however, be interesting to see whether or not there are any DM-theorists (who accept the Equivalence Principle) brave enough to countenance the rather startling consequences that follow from it (several of which were outlined above), as well as their opposites. Would they, therefore, be happy to accept that the stars both (really) travel many times faster than the speed of light and that they don't, at the same time? Or that when dialectician, D(1), for example, sets off from her flat to join a demonstration, she in fact remains stationary while the demonstration actually comes to her (without anyone in that demonstration noticing the subsequent acceleration as she 'set off from home' -- in the way they feel such forces when sat in a car as it accelerates/decelerates) --, and it doesn't, she moves toward it.

 

Or, even this puzzling conundrum: when comrade, D(1), who is still the centre of a suitable frame of reference, dives into a swimming pool, she remains stationary but is immediately confronted by a wall of water accelerating upwards to meet her, but with no distortion to its shape and with no new ripples. That is, every part of that body of water accelerates upwards at the same time and the same rate, behaving like a perfectly rigid body, not a liquid. Must DM-fans accept that scenario and its opposite?

 

[LEM = Law of Excluded Middle; follow the link below for more details.]

 

[Or, in such circumstances, do they apply the dreaded LEM here and reject one alternative in favour of the other? I am, of course, using the words "accelerate" and "decelerate" here as they are employed in everyday speech, not as they are defined in Physics or Applied Mathematics.]

 

Returning to saner questions: as I pointed out earlier (but in more detail in Essay Five), the only 'contradiction' that can be cobbled-together in this specific case would involve an undischarged ambiguity:

 

A1: The Earth moves.

 

A2: The Earth does not move.

 

But, this apparent 'contradiction' would vanish just as soon as the following equivocation was resolved:

 

A3: In Inertial Frame, IF(1), the Earth moves.

 

A4: In Inertial Frame, IF(2), the Earth does not move.

 

But, this is no more a contradiction than the following would be (which will be examined again, below):

 

R15: The strikers moved.

 

R16: It is not the case that the strikers moved.

 

This pair of sentences certainly looks contradictory (especially if both relate to the same strikers at the same time, and both were actually true), but that would cease to be the case when it is revealed that the said strikers were sat on a train that was travelling at 80 miles per hour. On the train, these militants could be sat perfectly still, but to an observer on a platform they would appear to be moving at speed. Since all motion is relative to an inertial frame (at least as far as the mathematics is concerned), the beliefs motivated by one set of observations would only appear to contradict those motivated by another. Hence, as soon as different frames of reference (or, perhaps, different background circumstances) are taken into account, the 'contradiction' simply disappears. This scenario would be deemed contradictory only by neurotic controversialists and confused DM-fans.

 

[Some of the latter might be tempted to respond that the above sort of contradiction isn't the type they are interested in; their focus centres on 'dialectical contradictions'. I have dealt with objections like that in Essays Five and Eight Parts One, Two and Three, where we will see that dialecticians themselves haven't a clue what a 'dialectical contradiction' is -- or if they have, they have kept that secret to themselves remarkably well for over 200 years. (By "dialectician" here I am, of course, referring to Hegel, subsequent Hegelians and DM-fans themselves -- but that doesn't mean I am conflating them all, just making the point that none of them seem to be able to say with any clarity what a 'dialectical contradiction' actually is! Indeed, academic DM-fans become rather abusive when that fact is pointed out to them.)]

 

However, if Aristotelian/Ptolemaic astronomy [APA] is now regarded by DM-theorists as 'representing' or 'reflecting appearances' (or perhaps even expressing -- now or in the past -- the 'commonsense view' of the universe), and they still hold APA true, or 'partially'/'relatively true' -- whether or not they are 'contradicted' by 'reality' -- then it seems that they must also be prepared to accept the truth, or 'partial'/'relative truth', of any number of fantastical, debunked, erroneous or otherwise misguided theories that were accepted in the past. And if that is so, they must also be prepared to accept the truth, or 'partial'/'relative truth', of what were once viewed as 'commonsense' ideas –- such as, say, the ancient belief that a pregnant woman who sees a hare will give birth to a child with a hare-lip, or, the (early modern) 'urban myth' that some women not only can, they actually have given birth to live rabbits. [Pickover (2000).] It seems they would have to accept the truth (or 'relative truth') of fables and 'urban myths' like these, and their negations! If not, and they only reject (as totally false) what is considered 'weird', that would underline, yet again, their fondness for special pleading.

 

[Or, once again, they will have (surreptitiously) applied the LEM!]

 

If we are meant to countenance DM-'contradictions' where both halves are 'true' (or they represent 'coexistent contradictory states of affairs'), as well as the strange idea that there is some truth even in the most outlandish of theories (perhaps as knowledge 'spirals' in on 'absolute truth' -- that topic has been covered in much more detail in Essay Eleven Part One; some of that material was re-posted earlier), then the above conclusions seem unavoidable.

 

Here, again, is Cornforth:

 

"Just as truths are for the most part only approximate and contain the possibility of being converted into untruths, so are many errors found not to be absolute falsehoods but to contain a germ of truth.... We should recognise, then, that certain erroneous views, including idealist views, could represent, in their time, a contribution to truth -- since they were, perhaps, the only ways in which certain truths could first begin to come to expression...." [Cornforth (1963), pp.138-39. Bold emphasis added. Paragraphs merged.]

 

But, what is even remotely true about such fanciful ideas? What, for example, was even vaguely correct about the ancient idea that angels pushed the planets in their orbits around the earth? Or, the more recent dogma that AIDS is a punishment from 'God'? If there is nothing true in outdated or offensive theories or 'propositions' such as these (or, those listed here, for example), then DM-'contradictions' can't be cobbled-together from such defective parts -- that is, should we ever be told with any clarity what a 'dialectical contradiction' actually is!

 

[Of course, anyone tempted to cling to unvarnished Hegelianism a little too enthusiastically will have to accept a radically different view of truth (i.e., they will have to regard it as the degree of conformity -- or lack of it -- between an 'object' and its 'concept'). But, as we saw in Part One of this Essay, that theory only works if another (ancient) syntactical error were (instead) correct -- i.e., the belief that concepts can be treated as objects (or the Proper Names thereof) --, and hence that such an 'object' can be put in some sort of relation with another 'object'. (More on that in Essay Twelve (when it is published in full). See also, here and here.)]

 

On the other hand, if an antiquated, obsolete or debunked theory is to be rejected because it is based on 'appearances', not 'reality', then DM-style 'contradictions' can't feature in it anywhere, after all. That is because in that case we would have alleged truths (those supposedly depicting 'reality') facing putative falsehoods (those allegedly encapsulating 'commonsense', ancient, or obsolete views of, or ideas about, 'reality'). We wouldn't have two truths, still less two 'partial truths' (i.e., those belonging to an outmoded conception confronting the less 'partially-true' ideas expressed in or by more recent scientific theories) confronting one another.

 

Howsoever alternatives like these are re-shaped or reshuffled there appear to be no winning cards in any of the hands DM-theorists have dealt, or could have dealt, themselves.

 

This means that we still don't have a DM-'contradiction', even in this relatively clear case. Nor are we ever likely to obtain one --, and that is so for the reasons set out above.

 

Even if a case could be made in favour of the idea that scientific propositions contradict indicative sentences that 'gave expression to appearances', that still wouldn't achieve all that dialecticians require of that idea. That is because (as argued at length in Essay Five) propositions that might look contradictory -- and which are both thought to be true -– would normally be disambiguated, or given a context against which they might be understood that resolved the apparent contradiction. [Follow the above link for several clear examples.]

 

And this latest assertion is no mere 'bourgeois' prejudice or diktat. Consider the following case, again, which is analogous to the previous pair:

 

R15: The strikers moved.

 

R16: It is not the case that the strikers moved.

 

As we saw earlier, when a frame of reference is supplied, the 'contradiction' simply vanishes.

 

And it won't do to complain about the trite nature of R15 and R16 --, that is, not unless (or until) DM-theorists tell us what they mean by the obscure phrase "dialectical contradiction". [Since this topic has been dealt with more fully in Essay Eight Parts One, Two and Three, no more will be said about it here.]

 

All this is quite apart from the fact that the DM-literature itself contains little other than trite examples -- e.g., boiling or freezing water, contradictory seeds, cooks who add too much salt to soup, characters who speak "prose all their lives", the differential fighting ability of Mamelukes, foxes that run away from larger animals, "cone bearings", "Yea, Yea"/"Nay, Nay", etc., etc.

 

The sad fact is that DM is Mickey Mouse Science on stilts, so DM-fans have no room to point their ideologically-compromised fingers at critics like yours truly (at least in this respect).

 

It is also quite apart from the fact that relative motion is hardly a "trite" topic in Physics!

 

As seems clear, 'apparent contradictions' aren't presented to us totally 'naked', as it were. They arise either from ambiguities inherent in our use of language or from a lack of clarity (etc.) in the original 'problem' (or so it was argued at length in Essay Five). In the above case (i.e., R15 and R16), the 'contradiction' plainly arose because of an unacknowledged change of reference frame.

 

While this makes such 'contradictions' sensitive to choice of reference frame, it wouldn't automatically imply they were dependent on 'coexistent contradictory states of affairs'. However, that was certainly not the point DM-theorists wanted to make about the 'contradictions' of interest to them. And yet, those mentioned above were either artefacts of a conventionalised choice of reference frame or they were a direct result of confused thinking/ambiguous language. They were certainly not based on 'reality' (whatever that means).33

 

Science Can't Undermine Common Sense

 

[The following material used to form part of Note 33.]

 

Ordinary Language Conflated With Common Sense

 

Philosophers and scientists often confuse ordinary language with 'commonsense', running the two together, or arguing that they (somehow) depend on each other. [In relation to this topic in general, see Peels and Woudenberg (2020).] One aspect of the (usual) complaint here appears to be that the vernacular contains or expresses 'commonsense'.

 

As we have seen in previous subsections, the 'contradiction' between 'appearance' and 'reality' is supposedly illustrated by the 'clash' between the Ptolemaic and the Copernican astronomical systems (or the latter's contemporary, more sophisticated version), that is between early modern theories that the Earth isn't sat motionless at the centre of the Universe (but rotates on its axis as it orbits the Sun), and earlier theories that appear to assert the opposite. Currently, those who tend to conflate the vernacular with 'commonsense', or who see the former infused by, or even 'contaminated' with, the latter also have in mind the supposed connection between so-called "folk theories" of nature (e.g., that the Earth is stationary while the Sun moves), human psychology (that we have beliefs and form intentions, etc., etc) and everyday language. Given this widely held view of 'commonsense', it would seem misguided or even mistaken to use words like "sunrise" if the Sun doesn't actually rise. Along with other notorious examples (some of which will be reviewed in Essay Thirteen Part Two), this is supposed to show that ordinary language still contains words and concepts based on, or derived from, defunct metaphysical, religious or quasi-scientific myths, fables, ideas, beliefs and doctrines. [At this point, Dialectical Marxists tend to add to that list ideological factors that have also had a significant impact in this respect.] On all sides, this is taken to mean that the vernacular is defective, at least when used in areas that impinge on topics that are the special reserve of science, philosophy and political theory.

 

[On this in general, see Lecercle and Riley (2004), Lecercle (2006), pp.164-72, Voloshinov (1973), Collins (1999, 2000, 2003, 2004), Doherty (2000), Holborow (1999), McNally (2001, 2004), Parrington (1997), Barrett (1991). But the literature on this is vast and includes work published by (and about) Foucault, Vygotsky, Althusser, Voloshinov, and Orwell, among many others. I have dealt with many of these authors and their ideas in Essay Thirteen Part Three. It is important to add that (at this site), use of the word "commonsense" is restricted to its theoretical and philosophical meaning (obscure though that is!), while the phrase "common sense" is employed in its ordinarily sense -- as in, for example, "Use your common sense! Only an idiot would put her hand in a lion's cage!". Whether or not there is any connection at all between these two widely differing uses/meanings will be put to one side for now.]

 

Notwithstanding the above, even if such (apparent) incongruities had anything to do with common sense, that would still fail to show the vernacular depended upon, or even encapsulated, outmoded scientific, metaphysical or ideological beliefs and theories. This can be seen from the fact that all of us (scientists included!) still employ terms like "sunrise", despite our acceptance of post-APA theories of the Universe. We aren't to suppose that when scientists, for example, use the word "sunrise" they do so ignorantly, ironically, duplicitously, or thoughtlessly.

 

Moreover, unless scientists and philosophers used -- and already understood -- terms taken from ordinary language, they could scarcely begin to correct common sense, always assuming that it needed correcting, or even that that is what scientists or philosophers in fact do, or wished to do.

 

[On this topic, see Baz (2012), Button, et al (1995), Cowley (1991), Cook (1979, 1980), Ebersole (1967, 1979a, 1979b), Hacker (1982a, 1982b, 1987), Hallett (2008), Hanfling (1984, 1989, 2000), Peels and Woudenberg (2020), Ryle (1960), Macdonald (1938), Stebbing (1958) and Stroud (2000). This issue will be discussed in much greater detail in Essays Twelve Part Seven and Thirteen Part Two. Since writing this, I have come across a somewhat similar approach to the line promoted at this site in Frank (1950), Chapter Seven.]

 

Nevertheless, a much more revealing fact about ordinary language -– and one all too easily missed -- is that all of us can readily form, and utter, the negations of sentences that contain (supposedly) obsolete notions -- like those about sunrise (illustrated below). Consider, for instance, the following hackneyed example (quoted earlier):

 

"As we know appearances can be deceptive. Each day the sun appears to circumnavigate the earth, when the reality is that the earth travels around the sun. We therefore need to penetrate the veil of appearance in order to reveal the reality that is disguised within." [Quoted from here.]

 

In relation to this we can clearly form/utter the following pair of sentences:

 

S1: The Sun rises in the morning.

 

S2: It isn't the case that the Sun rises in the morning.

 

First of all, the fact that we can form the negation of every indicative empirical sentence capable of being written or uttered (in every language on the planet that has the relevant vocabulary), like the two illustrated above, demonstrates that the vernacular is neither a theory nor is it dependent upon one. That is because -- to use another argument I owe to Peter Geach (although I have since seen a somewhat similar remark in Keat and Urry (1982))33a -- no viable theory could countenance the negation of all its empirical propositions, as ordinary language readily does.

 

Naturally, this claim is somewhat controversial -- but, only for those intent on depreciating or denigrating ordinary language.

 

[Ordinary language will be defended in depth in Essay Twelve Part Seven; some of that material has already been posted here.]

 

Second, scientific theories extend, develop and even replace ordinary words, using typographically similar terms that possess new meanings (such as "time", "space", "wave", "solid" and "spin", etc.), which meanings have almost invariably been modified by suitable re-definitions -- or they have been analogically or metaphorically re-configured. In addition, scientists introduce technical terms that weren't previously present in the vernacular but which subsequently make their appearance in ordinary speech -- such as "electricity", "protein", "placebo" and "radar" (as in "It's not even on my radar!"). Or which, in many cases, might not translate across into the vernacular -- such as "allele", "superposition" and "2,4-Dinitrophenylhydrazine". But, unless revisions and innovations like these had been, or could be, linked to ordinary language and practice at some point, at some level or in some way, their meaning would be completely unclear, if not entirely indeterminate, even to the scientist(s) who coined them. For example, consider the etymology of "protein":

 

"1844, from French protéine, coined 1838 by Dutch chemist Gerhard Johan Mulder (1802-1880), perhaps on suggestion of Berzelius, from Greek prōteios 'the first quality,' from prōtos 'first' (see proto-) + -ine (2). Originally a theoretical substance thought to be a constituent of food essential to life, further studies of the substances he was working with overthrew this, but the words protein and proteid continued to be used in international work on the matter and also for other organic compounds; the modern use as a general name for a class of bodies arose in German. The confusion became so great a committee was set up in 1907 to sort out the nomenclature, which it did, giving protein its modern meaning ('class of organic compounds forming an important part of all living organisms') and banishing proteid." [Quoted from here; accessed 28/04/2024. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Italic emphases in the original. Two links added.]

 

[A more detailed history of the introduction of this term can be found in Vickery (1950).]

 

Or, "allele":

 

"1931 in genetics, from German allel, abbreviation of allelomorph 'alternative form of a gene' (1902), coined from Greek allel- 'one another' (from allos "other;" from PIE root *al- (1) "beyond") + morphē "form," a word of uncertain etymology." [Quoted from here; accessed 28/04/2024. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Link and italic emphases in the original.]

 

Readers will no doubt have noticed that these words had originally been linked with, or came from, familiar ordinary terms that were already in common use. That would have to be the case if the one coining them wanted to be understood. Naturally, that doesn't imply the meaning of such terms won't or can't change over the years -- or even perhaps immediately. An excellent example of that is how the word "electron" changed markedly after it was coined by George Stoney in 1891 (which topic will be considered in more detail in Essay Thirteen Part Two); it was introduced in:

 

"1891 by Irish physicist George J. Stoney (1826-1911) from electric + -on, as in ion (q.v.)." [Quoted from here; accessed 28/04/2024. Links and emphases in the original.]

 

And concerning "electric" itself (concerning which the same comments could be made), we read:

 

"1640s, first used in English by physician Sir Thomas Browne (1605-1682), apparently coined as Modern Latin electricus (literally 'resembling amber') by English physicist William Gilbert (1540-1603) in treatise 'De Magnete' (1600), from Latin electrum 'amber,' from Greek ēlektron 'amber' (Homer, Hesiod, Herodotus), also 'pale gold' (a compound of 1 part silver to 4 of gold); which is of unknown origin. Originally the word described substances which, like amber, attract other substances when rubbed. Meaning 'charged with electricity' is from 1670s; the physical force so called because it first was generated by rubbing amber. In many modern instances, the word is short for electrical. Figurative sense is attested by 1793. Electric light is from 1767." [Quoted from here; accessed 28/04/2024. Emphases in the original; five links added.]

 

If that weren't the case, it would mean theories that employed such terms would be incomprehensible. Which might be part of the reason why many leading scientists tell us, for instance, that no one understands Quantum Mechanics:

 

"Those who are not shocked when they first come across quantum theory can't possibly have understood it." Niels Bohr

 

"If you are not completely confused by quantum mechanics, you do not understand it." John Wheeler

 

"Quantum mechanics makes absolutely no sense." Roger Penrose

 

"There was a time when the newspapers said that only twelve men understood the theory of relativity. I do not believe there ever was such a time. There might have been a time when only one man did, because he was the only guy who caught on, before he wrote his paper. But after people read the paper a lot of people understood the theory of relativity in some way or other, certainly more than twelve. On the other hand, I think I can safely say that nobody understands quantum mechanics…. I am going to tell you what nature behaves like. If you will simply admit that maybe she does behave like this, you will find her a delightful, entrancing thing. Do not keep saying to yourself, if you can possibly avoid it, 'but how can it be like that?' because you will get 'down the drain,' into a blind alley from which nobody has yet escaped. Nobody knows how it can be like that." [Feynman (1992), p.129. Bold emphases added.]

 

 

Video Four: "Nobody Understands Quantum Mechanics"

 

Clued-in physicists already seem to be fully aware of the fact that the language they use presents, or even generates, serious problems. Here, for example, is leading Physicist, the late David Peat:

 

"It hasn't been a great couple of years for theoretical physics. Books such as Lee Smolin's The Trouble with Physics and Peter Woit's Not Even Wrong embody the frustration felt across the field that string theory, the brightest hope for formulating a theory that would explain the universe in one beautiful equation, has been getting nowhere. It's quite a comedown from the late 1980s and 1990s, when a grand unified theory seemed just around the corner and physicists believed they would soon, to use Stephen Hawking's words, 'know the mind of God'. New Scientist even ran an article called 'The end of physics'. So what went wrong? Why are physicists finding it so hard to make that final step? I believe part of the answer was hinted at by the great physicist Niels Bohr, when he wrote: 'It is wrong to think that the task of physics is to find out about nature. Physics concerns what we can say about nature.' At first sight that seems strange. What has language got to do with it? After all, we see physics as about solving equations relating to facts about the world -- predicting a comet's path, or working out how fast heat flows along an iron bar. The language we choose to convey question or answer is not supposed to fundamentally affect the nature of the result.

 

"Nonetheless, that assumption started to unravel one night in the spring of 1925, when the young Werner Heisenberg worked out the basic equations of what became known as quantum mechanics. One of the immediate consequences of these equations was that they did not permit us to know with total accuracy both the position and the velocity of an electron: there would always be a degree of irreducible uncertainty in these two values. Heisenberg needed an explanation for this. He reasoned thus: suppose a very delicate (hypothetical) microscope is used to observe the electron, one so refined that it uses only a single photon of energy to make its measurement. First it measures the electron's position, then it uses a second photon to measure the speed, or velocity. But in making this latter observation, the second photon has imparted a little kick to the electron and in the process has shifted its position. Try to measure the position again and we disturb the velocity. Uncertainty arises, Heisenberg argued, because every time we observe the universe we disturb its intrinsic properties.

 

"However, when Heisenberg showed his results to Bohr, his mentor, he had the ground cut from under his feet. Bohr argued that Heisenberg had made the unwarranted assumption that an electron is like a billiard ball in that it has a 'position' and possesses a 'speed'. These are classical notions, said Bohr, and do not make sense at the quantum level. The electron does not necessarily have an intrinsic position or speed, or even a particular path. Rather, when we try to make measurements, quantum nature replies in a way we interpret using these familiar concepts. This is where language comes in. While Heisenberg argued that 'the meaning of quantum theory is in the equations', Bohr pointed out that physicists still have to stand around the blackboard and discuss them in German, French or English. Whatever the language, it contains deep assumptions about space, time and causality -- assumptions that do not apply to the quantum world. Hence, wrote Bohr, 'we are suspended in language such that we don't know what is up and what is down'. Trying to talk about quantum reality generates only confusion and paradox. Unfortunately Bohr's arguments are often put aside today as some physicists discuss ever more elaborate mathematics, believing their theories to truly reflect subatomic reality. I remember a conversation with string theorist Michael Green a few years after he and John Schwartz published a paper in 1984 that was instrumental in making string theory mainstream. Green remarked that when Einstein was formulating the theory of relativity he had thought deeply about the philosophical problems involved, such as the nature of the categories of space and time. Many of the great physicists of Einstein's generation read deeply in philosophy.

 

"In contrast, Green felt, string theorists had come up with a mathematical formulation that did not have the same deep underpinning and philosophical inevitability. Although superstrings were for a time an exciting new approach, they did not break conceptual boundaries in the way that the findings of Bohr, Heisenberg and Einstein had done. The American quantum theorist David Bohm embraced Bohr's views on language, believing that at the root of Green's problem is the structure of the languages we speak. European languages, he noted, perfectly mirror the classical world of Newtonian physics. When we say 'the cat chases the mouse' we are dealing with well-defined objects (nouns), which are connected via verbs. Likewise, classical physics deals with objects that are well located in space and time, which interact via forces and fields. But if the world doesn't work the way our language does, advances are inevitably hindered. Bohm pointed out that quantum effects are much more process-based, so to describe them accurately requires a process-based language rich in verbs, and in which nouns play only a secondary role.... Physics as we know it is about equations and quantitative measurement. But what these numbers and symbols really mean is a different, more subtle matter. In interpreting the equations we must remember the limitations language places on how we can think about the world...." [Peat (2008), pp.41-43. Bold emphases and several links added; quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Several paragraphs merged.]

 

While I don't want to suggest I agree with everything Peat has to say about the nature of language (or even scientific language!), his comments clearly show that (some) leading scientists are at least aware there is a problem here. [A point also brought out rather well throughout Becker (2018).]

 

[Admittedly, Peat concurs with Bohm when the latter suggests that we need to learn from Native American languages, many of which seem to have a rather peculiar grammar, but it is to be wondered how a culture that has produced no science or technology of any note has much (in this respect) to teach one that has. (Again, this topic will be pursued in more detail in Essay Thirteen Part Two, to be published sometime in 2025 or 2026.) Nor is it at all clear what it means to say that language contains certain assumptions. In fact, as this sub-section of the present Essay aims to show, that isn't the case. Having said that, it is important to add that when I say Native American culture has produced "no science or technology of any note", I don't mean to disparage, demean or depreciate that culture! Plainly, Native Americans wouldn't have survived had they failed to develop any scientific ideas or any technology, nor would they have flourished for centuries without sophisticated and diverse forms of culture. Clearly, they managed all three (and much else besides!). What I am alluding to is the vastly superior scientific knowledge and technology that has been enabled by the growth of capitalism -- even if the class war has greatly abused, deflected and distorted the latter --, upon which the very possibility of socialism and human emancipation are predicated. As impressive, amazing and unique as Native American culture (in all its forms) was, and still is, a socialist economy and society can't be built on it. Not that a socialist society would eradicate that culture; in fact, it will protect, preserve and enhance it.]

 

Third (returning to the case in point), the view promoted here means that the word "sunrise" is no more problematic than "nightfall" or "daybreak" are. No one imagines (it is to be hoped!) that the use of "nightfall" commits anyone to a "folk theory" of the susceptibilities of darkness to the law of gravity, or that "daybreak" suggests mornings are brittle. Or, indeed, that the use of such terms reflects a defunct or obsolete scientific theory, or even that they 'encapsulate common sense'. Consider the word "solstice" (from the Latin solstitium -- meaning "point at which the sun seems to stand still"). Even though that word is an echo of the old Geocentric Theory of the solar system, no one imagines that when Astronomers (currently) use this word they are secretly -- or inadvertently -- committed to the now defunct Ptolemaic Theory.

 

Indeed, and to change the example, no one (certainly no scientist) believes that when someone catches the 'flu (or influenza) there is some sort of cosmic influence at work, even though, as matter of fact, the original meaning of this word (derived from the medieval Latin, influentia) was based on an ancient, mystical theory about there being just such a stellar influence. Still less would anyone be willing to accept the idea that when someone is described as "hysterical", that implies they have a wandering womb (even though this word was originally based on an obsolete 'scientific' theory about 'wandering wombs' -- taken from the Greek, hysteria, or womb, from which we also get the word "hysterectomy"). Nor do psychologists these days believe that "lunatics" are sensitive to phases of the Moon (while it is now clear that few, if any, mental healthcare professionals currently use this term, until recently they certainly did), or even that phlegmatic individuals have a superabundance of phlegm, and so on. In fact, if the term "Big Bang" were to be understood as carelessly as critics of common sense interpret "sunrise", it would suggest scientists are committed to the view that the origin of the Universe was not only rather loud, it had been witnessed by some form of sentient life -- not to mention the erroneous idea that sound can travel across a vacuum! [Or even 'across' whatever the original primordial 'atom' that gave rise to the universe was embedded in as it 'exploded'.]

 

[On "influenza", type that word in this search box. On hysteria, see here and here. Of course, since the 'Big Bang' is also supposed to be the origin of space and time, there was nowhere for the sound, if there had been any, to travel. Nor, indeed, anywhere for the bang to happen! However, if there were no space before the 'Big Bang' (that is, if space had actually been created by that 'Bang'), there could be no location for it either. I won't pull on that highly controversial thread in this Essay!]

 

On "lunacy", we read this (from the BBC):

 

"In folklore, a full moon is associated with insanity -- hence the word lunacy -- werewolves and all manner of unpleasant happenings. However, when psychologists and statisticians have looked into the matter, a lunar influence on the human brain and behaviour remains elusive. Overwhelmingly they have failed to discover a correlation between the timing of a full moon and events such as assaults, arrests, suicides, calls to crisis centres, psychiatric admissions, poisonings and vehicle accidents. Eric Chudler, who has compiled a long list of the research says: 'Most of the data -- and there have been many studies -- find that there is not an association between the phase of the moon and any of those abnormal behaviours.' Many believers of the full moon myth work in law enforcement and health professions. Police officers and hospital staff frequently witness horrific and upsetting events. Mr Chudler suggests that when these traumatic things happen, workers are much more likely to notice a full moon shining in the sky than they are to register more modest half or quarter moons. Consequently, they only make a connection with accidents or crimes when the moon is at its most obvious and symbolically significant." [Quoted from here. Paragraphs merged; quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Link and bold emphasis added.]

 

But, that doesn't stop ordinary speakers using the words "lunacy" and "lunatic" (often colloquialised as the 'politically incorrect', "Looney"; in fact, here's a Monty Python video entitled "Spot the Looney!"), and this they do (often or in general) while being unaware of the connection between the phases of the Moon and madness, etc.

 

In addition to the terms already mentioned, there are many scientific words in use today that are themselves derived from what was, in each case, an unrelated or even obsolete use of language. For example: "Oxygen" (derived from the original Greek meaning "acid"); "Mercury" from the Latin version of the Greek 'god' Hermes; "Quark" (coined by Murray Gell-Mann from Finnegans Wake -- and are Quarks really "coloured"?); "Law" ("layer, measure, stroke", derived from Jurisprudence); "Atom" (meaning "indivisible"); "Acid" (meaning "of the taste of vinegar", "sour" or "sharp to the taste"); "Alkali" (Arabic, "the ashes of a plant"); "Algebra" (Arabic, "reunion of the broken parts", or "the reduction"); "Alcohol" (Arabic, al-kuhul, "powdered antimony", or eye-makeup), "Flow" (Old High German, flouwen, "to rinse"); "Force" (Latin, "strength, courage, fortitude; violence, power, compulsion"); "Root", used in Mathematics (part of a plant); "Matrix" also used in mathematics (from the Latin for "mother" or "womb"); "Vector" (again from the Latin, vehere, "to carry"); "Missing Link" (from The Great Chain of Being), "Planet" (late Latin, planeta, or "wanderer"), "vaccine" (from vacca, cow), "inoculate" (from the Latin, inoculatus, "to graft a bud" onto a tree or shrub), and as we have just seen, "electricity" comes from the Greek word for amber -- ἤλεκτρον -- "electron", but no one supposes it still carries that connotation. And here is a video that explains the origin of the names of elements in the Periodic Table:

 

 

Video Five: Origin Of The Names Of Elements In

The Periodic Table

 

[Concerning The Great Chain of Being, see Lovejoy (1964). On this topic in general, see Crosland (2006) and Danziger (1997).]

 

And how many who use the titles of days of the week, or even those of several months of the year (at least in English), believe in the 'gods' and/or the 'pagan' celebrations after which they have all been named?

 

Fourth, the idea that words are capable of encapsulating ancient beliefs or defunct theories implies that 'meanings' are somehow able to track, accompany or follow words down the centuries as if glued to them by some sort of 'semantic adhesive'. This would further imply that when a word had gained an original, specific meaning, it would always connote that meaning no matter when it was subsequently used or, indeed, for what it purpose was actually employed -- even many centuries later. But, that would also suggest words were quasi-intelligent beings, whose denotations and connotations were hard-wired into 'their memories' and couldn't be altered or modified by subsequent users or uses.

 

[It would be decidedly odd to see DM-fans accept the theory that there are unchanging meanings like this hard-wired into certain words, especially since many seem to think that not even the letter "A" can remain stable from moment-to-moment, never mind an entire word and its meaning! (This topic was covered in Part One, here. On those (allegedly) morphoholic letter "A"s, see Essay Six.)]

 

Howsoever these metaphors are interpreted they clearly imply that users must have the meanings of certain words dictated to them by those words themselves, or even that each user somehow 'catches' that meaning when young, rather like the way they might pick up a virus from a parent, sibling, friend or carer. Given such a scenario, each speaker would remain 'infected with these unchanging meanings' for the rest now of their life. If that were case, it would look like 'something' had taken over and controls that speaker's brain and now governs her thought and speech. Learning a language would then be more like contracting a disease, or even like being 'possessed', rather than a socially-acquired skill. Meaning in language wouldn't be a function of communal life, social interaction or collective labour --, or even the physical existence of human beings and their relationship with the material world and each other. It would be a function of the 'social'/'psychological' life of words and their 'disembodied meanings'. Hence, as noted above, the claim that words still carry their ancient or obsolete meanings about with them would amount to their fetishisation. In effect, that would humanise symbols while de-humanising humans!

 

So, piled on top of the alienation inflicted on humanity by class-division and the class war there would be this added alienation of their control over their own language! Discourse and meaning would now be the creation of extra-human forces, echoing ancient myths that language and meaning were gifts of the 'gods'. [On this novel form of linguistic fetishisation, see also here.]

 

[The recent widespread infatuation with Richard Dawkins's 'memes' also trades on a pernicious form of the fetishisation myth. On the serious weaknesses of this aspect of Dawkins's 'theory' (never mind the rest of it!), see McGrath (2005). Cf., also Essay Thirteen Part Three, here. Any who object to my referencing McGrath's book -- which defends Theism -- should also point a few fingers at DM-fans who look to Hegel, a character with a similar aim in mind. Of course, I am only recommending McGrath's case against 'memes', which seems to me pretty conclusive, not his Theology! Update October 2024: So, it isn't surprising to see Dawkins now promote and praise as "utterly superb" a book by far right Tory ideologue, Douglas Murray, which argues in favour of the Nazi-inspired, Great Replacement Theory.]

 

Admittedly, TAR's general point appears to be that while science presents us with an 'objective' view of the world, ordinary 'commonsense' operates at the level of 'subjective appearance':

 

"But Hegel is also difficult for reasons that are not the result of character and circumstance. His theories use terms and concepts that are unfamiliar because they go beyond the understanding of which everyday thought is capable. Ordinary language assumes that things and ideas are stable, that they are either 'this' or 'that.' And, within strict limits, these are perfectly reasonable assumptions. Yet the fundamental discovery of Hegel's dialectic was that things and ideas do change…. And they change because they embody conflicts which make them unstable…. It is to this end that Hegel deliberately chooses words that can embody dynamic processes…. It is the search to resolve…contradictions that pushes thought past commonsense definitions which see only separate stable entities." [Rees (1998), pp.45, 50. Paragraphs merged. ]

 

"The important thing about a Marxist understanding of the distinction between the appearance of things and their essence is twofold: 1) by delving beneath the mass of surface phenomena, it is possible to see the essential relations governing historical change -- thus beneath the appearance of a free and fair market transaction it is possible to see the exploitative relations of class society, but, 2) this does not mean that surface appearances can simply be dismissed as ephemeral events of no consequence. In revealing the essential relations in society, it is also possible to explain more fully than before why they appear in a form different to their real nature. To explain, for instance, why it is that the exploitative class relations at the point of production appear as the exchange of 'a fair day's work for a fair day's pay' in the polished surface of the labour market." [Ibid., p.187. Bold emphases alone added.]

 

In the above, Rees argues that while 'commonsense' might be perfectly adequate when confined its own legitimate sphere of application (one imagines this is meant to be everyday life), it is nevertheless inadequate when it is employed in technical areas or in circumstances that involve change (especially complex change connected with social development of the class war).

 

Here are my remarks (taken from Essay Four Part One) about the first of the above two passages (slightly edited):

 

Concerning the alleged limitations of ordinary language, John Rees expressed himself as follows:

 

"Ordinary language assumes that things and ideas are stable, that they are either 'this' or 'that'. And, within strict limits, these are perfectly reasonable assumptions. Yet the fundamental discovery of Hegel's dialectic was that things and ideas do change…. And they change because they embody conflicts which make them unstable…. It is to this end that Hegel deliberately chooses words that can embody dynamic processes." [Rees (1998), p.45.]

 

The problem with this passage is that it gets things completely the wrong way round. It is in fact our use of ordinary language that enables us to speak about change, movement and development. Complex philosophical jargon (especially terminology invented by Hegel) is completely useless in this regard, since it is wooden, static and of indeterminate meaning, despite what Rees asserts.

 

[Any who think differently are invited to reveal precisely which set of Hegelian terms is able do what the words listed below (or their equivalent in German) already achieve for us, only better.]

 

As is well-known (at least by Marxists), human beings managed to progress because of their interaction with nature and their consequent development of the forces and relations of production, both constrained by the class war. In which case, ordinary language -- the result of collective labour -- couldn't fail to have a range of words with the logical and semantic multiplicity that allowed its users to speak about changes of almost limitless complexity, rapidity and duration.

 

This is no mere dogma; it is easily confirmed. Here is a greatly shortened list of ordinary words (restricted to modern English, but omitting simple and complex tensed participles and auxiliary verbs) that allow speakers to talk about changes of almost unbounded complexity, swiftness and scope:

 

Vary, alter, adjust, adapt, amend, make, produce, revise, rework, advise, administer, allocate, improve, enhance, deteriorate, depreciate, edit, bend, straighten, weave, merge, dig, plough, cultivate, sow, reap, twist, curl, turn, tighten, fasten, loosen, relax, ease, tense up, slacken, fine tune, bind, wrap, pluck, carve, rip, tear, mend, perforate, repair, puncture, renovate, restore, damage, impair, scratch, diagnose, mutate, metamorphose, transmute, sharpen, hone, modify, modulate, develop, upgrade, appear, disappear, expand, contract, constrict, constrain, shrivel, widen, lock, unlock, swell, flow, glide, ring, differentiate, integrate, multiply, divide, add, subtract, simplify, complicate, partition, unite, amalgamate, fuse, mingle, disseminate, connect, entwine, unravel, link, brake, decelerate, accelerate, fast, slow, swift, rapid, hasty, protracted, lingering, brief, heat up, melt, freeze, harden, cool down, flash, shine, glow, drip, bounce, cascade, drop, pick up, fade, darken, wind, unwind, meander, peel, scrape, graze, file, scour, dislodge, is, was, will be, will have been, had, will have had, went, go, going, gone, return, lost, age, flood, swamp, overflow, precipitate, percolate, seep, tumble, plunge, dive, float, sink, plummet, mix, separate, cut, chop, crush, grind, shred, slice, dice, saw, sew, knit, spread, coalesce, congeal, fall, climb, rise, ascend, descend, slide, slip, roll, spin, revolve, circulate, bounce, oscillate, undulate, rotate, wave, splash, conjure, quick, quickly, slowly, instantaneously, suddenly, gradually, rapidly, briskly, hurriedly, absolutely, lively, hastily, inadvertently, accidentally,  carelessly, really, energetically, lethargically, snap, drink, quaff, eat, bite, devour, consume, swallow, gulp, gobble, chew, gnaw, digest, ingest, excrete, absorb, join, resign, part, sell, buy, acquire, prevent, block, avert, avoid, forestall, encourage, invite, appropriate, lose, find, search, pursue, hunt, track, explore, follow, cover, uncover, reveal, stretch, distend, depress, compress, lift, put down, fetch, take, bring, carry, win, ripen, germinate, conceive, gestate, abort, die, rot, perish, grow, decay, fold, empty, evacuate, drain, pour, fill, abduct, abandon, leave, abscond, many, more, less, fewer, steady, steadily, jerkily, intermittently, smoothly, awkwardly, expertly, very, extremely, exceedingly, intermittent, discontinuous, continuous, continual, emit, push, pull, drag, slide, jump, sit, stand, run, sprint, chase, amble, walk, hop, skip, slither, crawl, limp, swim, fly, hover, drown, submerge, immerse, break, abrogate, dismiss, collapse, shatter, split, interrupt, charge, retreat, assault, squash, adulterate, contaminate, purify, filter, clean, raze, crumble, erode, corrode, rust, flake, demolish, dismantle, pulverise, atomise, disintegrate, dismember, destroy, annihilate, extirpate, flatten, lengthen, shorten, elongate, crimple, inflate, deflate, terminate, finish, initiate, instigate, augment, replace, undo, redo, analyze, synthesise, articulate, disarticulate, reverse, repeal, abolish, enact, quash, throw, catch, hour, minute, second, instant, moment, momentary, invent, devise, teach, learn, innovate, forget, rescind, boil, freeze, thaw, cook, liquefy, solidify, congeal, neutralise, evaporate, condense, dissolve, process, mollify, pacify, calm down, excite, enrage, inflame, protest, object, challenge, confirm, deny, repudiate, reject, refute, expel, eject, repel, attract, remove, overthrow, expropriate, scatter, distribute, equalise, surround, gather, admit, acknowledge, hijack, assemble, attack, counter-attack, charge, repulse, defeat, strike, occupy, picket, barricade, revolt, riot, rally, march, demonstrate, mutiny, rebel, defy, resist, lead, campaign, educate, agitate, organise...

 

[In each case, where there is a noun form of a word its verb form has been listed (for instance, "object" as in "to object"). Moreover, where I have listed the word "ring", for example, I also intend cognates of the verb "to ring" -- like "ringing" and "rang". I have also omitted many nouns that imply change or development, such as "river", "runner", "wind", "lightning", "tide", "cloud" and "fire". Anyone who didn't know such words implied changing processes in the world -- that rivers flow, fires burn, runners run, tides ebb and flow or winds blow -- would simply have advertised their lack of comprehension of English (or whatever language theirs happened to be), compounded by a seriously defective, possibly even dangerous, knowledge of the world. So, not knowing that fires burn or rivers flow, for example, could endanger someone's life. In addition, several of the above also have verb forms, such as "fired" or "winding". Other nouns also imply growth and development, such as "tree", "flower", "mouse", "day",  "human being". Anyone who thought "human being", for instance, reflected a 'fixed and changeless' view of the world would probably be regarded as suffering from some sort of learning disability. Either that or they would perhaps be thought in the grip of a rather odd philosophical theory of some description.]

 

Naturally, it wouldn't be difficult to extend this list until it contained literally thousands of entries -- on that, see here and here --, all capable of depicting countless changes in limitless detail (especially if it is augmented with words drawn from mathematics, science and HM). It is only a myth put about by Hegel and DM-theorists (unwisely echoed by Rees and others -- such as Woods and Grant) that ordinary language can't depict change adequately, since it is supposedly dominated by 'the abstract understanding', a brain module helpfully identified for us by Hegel without a scrap of supporting evidence, a brain scan or even the use of a consulting couch. By way of contrast, ordinary language performs this task far better than the incomprehensible and impenetrably obscure jargon Hegel invented in order to fix something that wasn't broken.

 

Dialecticians like Rees would have us believe that because of the alleged shortcomings of the vernacular only the most recondite and abstruse terminology concocted by Hegel -- the meaning of much of which is still unclear, even to Hegel scholars! -- is capable of telling us what we already know, and have known for tens of thousands of years, that things change!

 

Indeed, we read the following (about ancient cosmology):

 

"Now, to understand the power of sacred cities and cosmic shrines we have to understand the power of the cosmos. The ancients recognised that there is really only one thing taking place in the universe, one expression of transcendental power, and that is change. Day transforms into night. Each night alters the shape of the moon. Seasons change. Seeds sprout into the light and gradually grow into mature plants that flower and blow to seed. Through metamorphosis, tadpoles become frogs, and caterpillars become moths. Our lives change.... The world changes.... Everything changes, but for the ancients, change occurred in an ordered and oriented world." [Krupp (1997), p.17. Paragraphs merged; bold emphases added.]

 

It is preposterous, therefore, to suppose that the ability to express change hadn't been incorporated into language many thousands of years before 'Being' inflicted Hegel and his crazy ideas on humanity.

 

Of course, as Rees himself implicitly concedes, Hegel's jargon has had to be 'translated' into 'ordinary-ish' sorts of words for the rest of us to be able to gain even a glimmering of the obscure message it supposedly conveys -- that was the point of Rees's précis of a key Hegelian 'deduction', which many other Hegel scholars have also 'translated' for us (and which will be discussed in detail Essay Twelve Part Five, summary here); cf., Rees (1998), pp.49-50 --, the aim of which was, apparently, to reveal that we can't possibly understand change without such assistance!

 

[Although an earlier version of this 'derivation' was published in Hegel (1977), Hegel's more 'mature' attempt to 'obtain' 'Nothing' from 'Being', and then 'Becoming' from the 'relation' between those two, appeared in Hegel (1999), pp.82-108. As noted above, just like Rees, others have tried to make this incomprehensible derivation 'comprehensible', for example: Burbidge (1995), pp.38-45; Carlson (2007), pp.9-53; Hartnack (1997), pp.11-19; Kaufmann (1978), pp.199-203; and Marcuse (1973) pp.129-34).]

 

But, if we already have ordinary terms (like those listed above) that enable us to talk about and comprehend change, what need is there for Hegel's obscure terminology?

 

Conversely, if, according to Rees, ordinary language is inadequate when it is faced with the task of 'translating' Hegel's observations into something we can understand, then how would anyone be able to grasp what Hegel supposedly meant, or even determine whether he meant anything at all? Why translate Hegel into the vernacular if the latter can't cope?

 

On the other hand, if we are capable of comprehending Hegel's obscure ideas only when they have been rendered into ordinary-ish sorts of terms, why do we need his convoluted jargon to reveal to us what it now turns out our language was quite capable of expressing to begin with -- when (on this supposition) it must have been adequate enough for just such a successful re-casting of these very ideas (by commentators like Rees) for the rest of us to grasp? After all, that is why they chose to translate it.

 

If ordinary language enables its users to capture what Hegel meant, in what way is the vernacular defective? Alternatively, if it can't do this, then how might we ever understand Hegel? In that case, if Hegel were correct, no one (including Hegel himself!) would be able to understand Hegel! That is because, ex hypothesi, his words would then be incapable of being translated in terms that anyone could comprehend.

 

Conversely, once more, if Hegel's words are translatable in terms we can understand, that must mean we already have the linguistic resources available to us to comprehend change perfectly well, thank you very much.

 

In which case, the following dilemma now faces Hegel-fans:

 

(a) If we suppose Hegel were correct (that ordinary terms can't adequately capture change), no one would be able to understand Hegel; or,

 

(b) If we suppose Hegel were mistaken -- and we are capable of understanding him enough to be able to say even that much -- no one need bother, since the vernacular would in that case be perfectly adequate on its own.

 

Either way, Marxists would be well-advised to avoid this obscure waffler like the plague....

 

Here is John Rees again:

 

"Hegel is also difficult for reasons that are not the result of character and circumstance. His theories use terms and concepts that are unfamiliar because they go beyond the understanding of which everyday thought is capable. Ordinary language assumes that things and ideas are stable, that they are either 'this' or 'that'. And, within strict limits, these are perfectly reasonable assumptions. Yet the fundamental discovery of Hegel's dialectic was that things and ideas do change…. And they change because they embody conflicts which make them unstable…. It is to this end that Hegel deliberately chooses words that can embody dynamic processes…. It is the search to resolve…contradictions that pushes thought past commonsense definitions which see only separate stable entities." [Rees (1998), pp.41-50. Bold emphasis added.]

 

Contrary to what Rees asserts, ordinary language not only doesn't, it can't assume anything. Plainly, it is human beings who assume things and they do so by means of the language they use. Unless language had the capacity to allow for the possible truth or the possible falsehood of these assumptions, and that of their negations, no assuming could even begin. That is, of course, because assumptions can be correct as well as incorrect. [Admittedly, it could be argued that Rees was employing metonymy here. Maybe so, but the point still stands. Language isn't an autonomous system; it takes human beings to give it life.]

 

Moreover, the rich and diverse vocabulary available to ordinary speakers also allows for the assumption (but it is far more than just this!) that objects can and do change -- and in complex ways, too. Indeed, ordinary language enables its users to speak about and study a wide variety of changes in seemingly limitless detail. A long list of just some of the words available in the vernacular that enable this was given earlier.

 

Hence, and despite what Rees says, the sophisticated nature of ordinary language permits the formation of the following sentences that depict change with ease:

 

H78: This protest is increasing in size as we watch.

 

H79: That case is becoming too heavy for the children to carry.

 

H80: This venue is now too small for our meetings.

 

H81: This spider's web is beginning to disintegrate.

 

H82: This train is being re-painted.

 

H83: That light over there is defective; it keeps flickering.

 

H84: This is how to lose members rapidly: spout dialectics at them.

 

H85: This dispute is no longer about working conditions.

 

H86: This entire continent is moving closer to Asia.

 

H87: That is how to break an egg.

 

H88: This is how to change workers' minds.

 

H89: This π-bond breaks in less than 5 nanoseconds if the molecule is rapidly heated.

 

H90: In an instant the pickets had re-grouped ready for the next police charge.

 

Many of the above sentences are somewhat stilted because they have been deliberately tailored to use the words "this" and "that" (i.e., the form of words that Rees employed to caricature the vernacular), in order to show that "things and ideas" aren't "assumed" to be stable -- contrary to his assertion. However, the above list of examples at least demonstrates that even using Rees's implausible and highly restricted phraseology, ordinary language is capable of expressing material changes (especially if it is augmented with words drawn from science and mathematics), something Hegel's tortured prose can't emulate -- that is, not without raiding the vernacular, or aping the protocols of ordinary discourse, to assist it do just that.

 

Even given this highly limited and constrained form of language, the above list of sentences can easily be extended. Of course, if the full range of words and phrases available to ordinary speakers were called upon (H90 being just one such example), it would be possible to form an indefinitely large set of sentences of far greater sophistication than anything dreamt of in Hegel's work, picturing changes of every imaginable type.

 

This shows that ordinary language is capable of depicting (and thus permitting the explanation of) change in the real world far better than any philosophical theory yet devised.

 

Now, this isn't something that a sophisticated user of English (like John Rees) should have to have pointed out to him -- even though my having to do so is a sad reflection of the intellectual decay that 'dialectical thought' induces in those held in its thrall.

 

Hence, it is a little rich of Rees proclaiming the superiority over the vernacular of language employed by Hegel -- and later, DM -- since, it now transpires that if, per impossible, DM were 'true', change would be impossible.

 

[These specific claims will be examined in greater detail in Essay Twelve Part Seven; however, as noted above, some of that material has already been posted here.]

 

Scientists Can't Afford To Undermine Common Sense

 

[This material also used to appear in Note 33.]

 

Following on from what Rees had to say about science, it could be argued that because appearances can be and often are deceptive, scientific knowledge has to be based on theories that go beyond, or even behind, the phenomenal world in order to reveal its underlying "essence". These 'deeper realities' must be capable of explaining not only why appearances are what they are but also why they look the way they do. This once again echoes what Marx had to say:

 

"But all science would be superfluous if the outward appearance and the essence of things directly coincided." [Marx (1981), p.956; Marx (1998), p.804.]

 

[I have commented on that all-too-brief remark in Essay Twelve Part One. ]

 

Be this as it may, it is undeniable that scientists have to rely on their activity in this world -- the world of 'appearances' -- to test, refine and confirm their hypotheses or improve their theories. No matter how sophisticated, technical or "elegant" a given hypothesis/theory happens to be, at some point researchers will have to interface with the ordinary world in order to confirm, refute, refine, test or modify it. In which case, scientists have to do one or more (but in some instances, possibly even most) of the following: read dials and meters, carefully mix substances, perform measurements, record and check data, design, handle or calibrate instruments, conduct surveys, look down microscopes, telescopes or other optical devices, collect samples, write code or programme a computer, consult a computer screen, construct (physical or 'virtual') models, research the relevant literature, communicate with colleagues, compose reports, formulate and use equations, attend conferences and seminars, publish papers, articles and books, etc., etc. These have to be carried out if a theory is to become anything other than speculative, tentative or remain merely hypothetical, let alone accepted as established fact or as valid by the profession as a whole. Clearly, every single one of these activities and performances takes place in the ordinary phenomenal world and has to be carried out by ordinary, albeit highly qualified and expertly trained, individuals/teams.

 

These are non-negotiable facts that confront every single scientist.

 

All such socially-conditioned, communally-sanctioned and professionally-mandated practices take place in this world, the world of phenomena, and it is what enables the intelligent and efficient prosecution of scientific research, and with that the advancement of knowledge (albeit seriously diverted, distorted and mis-used by capitalist priorities and interests). In addition, the vernacular not only enables the education and socialisation of aspiring scientists, it underpins the skills necessary for the comprehension and performance of all standardised laboratory-, field- and research-techniques, as well as the design of surveys, questionnaires, experiments, excavations and expeditions, etc., etc. This overall background even lies behind the writing of every summa vitae (résumé), job reference, employment application, research post, transfer- and grant-request. [With a few modifications, the same protocols will still apply in a socialist society.] While on the one hand mundane aspects of our material and social existence like these also facilitate successful inter-communication between scientists, on the other they provide a readily available and fertile source of the metaphors, analogies, figures of speech and models that breathe life into the vast majority of scientific hypotheses, theories, reports and papers.

 

Every single one of the above procedures and routines is constrained and regulated by the same conventions and protocols that govern everyday behaviour, speech and reasoning, which are in turn mediated by familiar, mundane physical skills and practices, all of which are once again materially-, socially-, and historically-conditioned.

 

Every single one takes place in the phenomenal world of 'appearances'.

 

[On this see, Arib and Hesse (1986), Baake (2003), Brown (2003), Cantor (1987), Fahnestock (2002), Gould (1988), Griffiths (2001), Gross (1996), Guttenplan (2005), Hesse (1966), Keller (1995, 2002), Kuhn (1993), Leatherdale (1974), Lynch (1996), MacCormac (1976), Polanyi (1962), Ravetz (1996), pp.69-244, Way (1994), White (1996b), and Young (1985).]

 

In which case, scientists can't afford to risk undermining the constraints imposed on them by the phenomenal, natural or social world, just as they can't afford to depreciate ordinary language and everyday practice for fear that by sawing away at the branch upon which they are all collectively sat, they risk their own catastrophic fall.

 

 

Figure Eight: I Came, I Saw, I...

 

Can 'Appearances' Be Trusted?

 

It could be objected at this point that Rees's account doesn't imply that appearances can't be trusted; indeed, as noted above, he actually argued that his own analysis:

 

"…does not mean that surface appearances can simply be dismissed as ephemeral events of no consequence. In revealing the essential relations in society, it is also possible to explain more fully than before why they appear in a form different to their real nature. To explain, for instance, why it is that the exploitative class relations at the point of production appear as the exchange of 'a fair day's work for a fair day's pay' in the polished surface of the labour market." [Rees (1998), p.187. Bold emphases alone added.]

 

Other dialecticians concurs. Here, for example, is Ernest Mandel:

 

"But for Marx, the materialist dialectician, the distinction between 'essence' and 'appearance' in no sense implies that 'appearance' is less 'real' than 'essence'. Movements of value determine in the last analysis movements of prices; but Marx the materialist would have laughed at any 'Marxist' who suggested that prices were 'unreal', because in the last analysis determined by value movements." [Mandel (1976), p.20. Bold emphasis added; minor spelling mistake corrected. Mandel's detailed argument will be carefully dissected in Appendix Four.]

 

But, as pointed out in more detail earlier, the second highlighted clause in Rees's comment implies that the surface phenomena in Capitalist society are different from their underlying form, which, of course, means appearances can't be relied upon. That accounts for the use of the word "real" by both Rees and Mandel.

 

Indeed, Mandel half admits this anyway:

 

"For these 'appearances' themselves are neither accidental nor self-evident. They pose problems, they have to be explained in their turn, and this very explanation helps to pierce through new layers of mystery and brings us again nearer to a full understanding of the specific form of economic organization which we want to understand. To deny this need to reintegrate 'essence' and 'appearance' is as un-dialectical and as mystifying as to accept 'appearances' as they are, without looking for the basic forces and contradictions which they tend to hide from the superficial and empiricist observer." [Ibid. Bold emphasis added.]

 

Why would 'appearances' pose any "problems" if they could be trusted or simply taken at face value? Why would they need "explaining" if they were exactly as they appeared to be? How come "empiricists" interpret 'appearances' erroneously when we were told 'appearances' are fine just as they are? How can prices be as "real" as value if they mislead so many?

 

Consequently, to return to earlier examples: the suspicion that 'appearances' might not be "real" (or "fully real") could motivate the belief that just as, say, the Sun appears to rise in the morning (but doesn't really do so), just as sticks look as if they bend when partially immersed in water (but they don't really deform in this way), just as objects seem to shrink in size when they recede from us (when they don't really grow smaller), and just as tables and chairs give the impression that they are solid (when they are really 'composed' mostly of 'empty space'), so the surface appearance of Capitalism only seems to be fair when 'underneath' it really isn't fair at all. In that case, it is clear that even for those who talk and think like the above DM-theorists, or who use similar language, 'appearances' can't actually deliver a true or reliable picture of reality. In that case, it looks like Rees and Mandel's own dalliance with the word "real" itself appears to be misleading. When we "scratch below the surface" of what they are trying to say, we see how misleading their words actually are! What they appear to be saying fails to match what we know they really mean. [Heavy-handed irony intended!]

 

That is why no one believes that deep down objects change their shape as they walk round them, that the Sun is really the same size as the Moon, or that ships slowly sink below the waves when they sail over the horizon. And, presumably, it is also why only deeply confused or compromised (reformist?) 'socialists' believe Capitalism really is fair. Or that price is a reliable and accurate expression of value. Certainly neither Rees nor Mandel genuinely believe any of that.

 

Moreover, the objection that Rees doesn't really believe that appearances are deceptive implies that his own distinction between surface phenomena and (all those underlying) 'real essences' is itself pointless.  Indeed, his overall argument would make no sense unless he believed that appearances were deceptive-in-themselves. Otherwise, why try to isolate or identify underlying "essences" if surface phenomena have never, or won't ever, mislead anybody? Why delve 'deeper' if Capitalism not only looks fair, it can also be regarded as essentially fair (given this way of talking)? And, why try to explain to workers that their wages represent only a fraction of the value they produce (or the time they have spent working) if what they are paid actually represents a 'fair slice of the cake'? [The same (with qualification) could also be said of Mandel's take on this.]

 

Why repeatedly quote these famous words if you think 'surface appearances' are never 'deceptive' or are always reliable?

 

"But all science would be superfluous if the outward appearance and the essence of things directly coincided." [Marx (1981), p.956; Marx (1998), p.804.]

 

[Note that I am most decidedly not promoting the idea that appearances are deceptive since only human beings (or what they produce in writing, speech or art, for example) can literally be deceptive. Quite the reverse, in fact. I am merely drawing out the untoward consequences of this family of confused ideas, metaphors, analogies and metaphysical fairytales that DM-theorists have unwisely imported in Marxism. However, further consideration of this specific topic would take us too far into HM, an area largely avoided in these Essays (for reasons outlined in Essay One).]

 

Doubtless, several of the above assertions might still attract criticism from some quarters. However, any such critics can console themselves with the thought that the resolution of issues like this may only take place in the phenomenal world -– that is, in this world of appearances, ordinary language, written documents and everyday computer screens. Hence, if the superiority of science and dialectics may only be established by a defence prosecuted precisely here, in the world of 'unreliable' appearances and 'untrustworthy' ordinary language -- using books, articles, newspapers, spoken and written words, argumentation, observation, experimentation and the like --, then any criticisms of the points made above must surely self-destruct. If those who advance any such criticisms are only able to convince others of the correctness of what they have to say by arguing that no one can really trust what they read, see or hear -- except, of course, they can trust the physical form of the argument that had just been used to express those very doubts (and which also appear to have been given a convenient 'exemption certificate' in this respect) --, then self-destruct they will.

 

If phenomena are untrustworthy, then any phenomenal statement of that 'fact' must be unreliable, too.

 

And, it is little use referring sceptical onlookers to the 'dialectical' interplay between "appearance" and underlying "essence" (as we saw Novack attempt to do earlier, and as Mandel also intimated), since the first half of that alleged "interplay" is defective -- because it is predicated on a series of logical blunders -- while the second half readily self-destructs, as we have seen time and again.

 

That is, of course, quite apart from the fact that the alleged 'dialectical interplay' also takes place in 'the world of appearances', which means that it is manifestly incapable of turning any such 'phenomenological dust' into 'epistemological gold' just because DM-fans think it can.

 

[It is worth recalling at this point that I am employing words like "phenomena" and "phenomenological" here to refer to the 'deliverances of the senses'. I don't prefer this way of talking, and, once more, it is only being used here in order to assist in its demise. Those two quoted words do not, and nor should they be taken to imply, I am promoting, advocating or recommending Phenomenalism, directly or indirectly, explicitly or implicitly. Again, I reject all philosophical theories, including Phenomenalism, as incoherent non-sense.]

 

Taking A Rise Out Of The Sun?

 

Returning to the main theme of this section of the Essay: if scientists themselves understand the meaning of the word "rise" (in S1, for example, repeated below), then they can't simply re-define it to suite themselves, perhaps under the mistaken belief that such a revision would help uncover its 'real' meaning. To see that this is indeed so, consider again the following remark:

 

"As we know appearances can be deceptive. Each day the sun appears to circumnavigate the earth, when the reality is that the earth travels around the sun. We therefore need to penetrate the veil of appearance in order to reveal the reality that is disguised within." [Quoted from here.]

 

As well as this pair of sentences:

 

S1: The Sun rises in the morning.

 

S2: It isn't the case that the Sun rises in the morning.

 

If the word "rises" in S1 or S2 doesn't mean what we ordinarily take it to mean, then anyone (scientist or philosopher) using sentences like these wouldn't in fact be clarifying or correcting ordinary language; they would be attempting to change, modify or even replace it.

 

Worse still, if the word "rises" in S1 or S2 doesn't mean what we ordinarily take it to mean, then those two sentences would be incomprehensible, since they would now contain at least one word ("rise") that no one seems to understand (in this context).

 

It might be wondered how it could be true that "no one seems to understand" the verb "rise" (in such a context)? Of course, every competent speaker of English (or, indeed, other languages that possess an equivalent verb) knows how to use this word in ordinary life, and hence understands it. What is being claimed here isn't that no one understands this word as it is used in such circumstances, only that in this case, with specific reference to S1 and S2 (but, not in relation to other, unrelated sentences), if "rises" doesn't mean what we ordinarily take it to mean, here (and if no one ever succeeds in informing us what its 'alternative'/'real meaning' is in these two sentences, in this context), then S1 and S2 must be incomprehensible, since, in this specific instance, they would contain at least one word ("rises") that no one understands, in this context. If so, S1 and S2 might just as well have been:

 

S1a: The Sun schmises in the morning.

 

S2a: It isn't the case that the Sun schmises in the morning.

 

On the other hand, if the word "rises" in S2 is to be understood in a new, and as-yet-unspecified, manner -- or even in a technical sense (indicated by 'scare' quotes in S2b) --, then S2b would no longer be the contradictory of S1, and so couldn't be used to 'clarify' or 'correct' it. Either way, it isn't possible to correct ordinary language in this way.

 

[Why this tactic will always fail, no matter how it is spun or re-packaged, was explained in detail, here.]

 

S1: The Sun rises in the morning.

 

S2b: It isn't the case that the Sun 'rises' in the morning.

 

[S2: It isn't the case that the Sun rises in the morning.]

 

It could be argued that it is perfectly clear what "rises" means in this context: it refers to what we see in the morning on a cloudless day, if we look to the East.

 

But what we see is also consistent with the earth being stationary while the Sun moves (relative to it).

 

Again, it could be countered that the point is that post-Renaissance science has established that the Sun doesn't actually rise; the horizon falls (relative to the Sun) as the Earth rotates. This means that anyone objecting in this way clearly means by "the Sun rises in the morning" that "the earth falls away in the morning", and hence that the "the Sun only appears to rise in the morning".

 

In which case, this use of "rise" in the clause, "appears to rise", doesn't mean what we ordinarily take it to mean, after all, and we are back where we were a few paragraphs ago.

 

Rees also claimed that underlying reality contradicts appearances:

 

"There is a deeper reality, but it must be able to account for the contradiction between it and the way it appears." [Rees (1998), p.188.]

 

Again, that is a clear echo of this famous comment by Marx:

 

"Vulgar economy actually does no more than interpret, systematise and defend in doctrinaire fashion the conceptions of the agents of bourgeois production who are entrapped in bourgeois production relations. It should not astonish us, then, that vulgar economy feels particularly at home in the estranged outward appearances of economic relations in which these prima facie absurd and perfect contradictions appear and that these relations seem the more self-evident the more their internal relationships are concealed from it, although they are understandable to the popular mind. But all science would be superfluous if the outward appearance and the essence of things directly coincided." [Marx (1981), p.956; Marx (1998), p.804. Bold emphasis alone added.]

 

[However, on this passage see my remarks, here.]

 

Although Rees doesn't himself use S1 or S2 [repeated below], they might nevertheless serve to illustrate the alleged conflict he seems to have in mind. If so, it could be argued that these two sentences reveal that theories concerning the apparent motion of the Sun were in fact contradicted by later advances in science, which therefore confirm the limitations of 'commonsense'.

 

The problem with this reading of S1 and S2 -- expressed in S3 and S4 -- is that (as noted several times already) these two sentences don't contradict one another; nor do they even depict a 'contradictory state of affairs'. That is because, given such an interpretation, S3 reports that the Sun appears to rise. But, if appearances were deceptive, and it appears to be the case that the Sun rises (even if it doesn't), then both of the following (i.e., S3 and S4) could be true:

 

S3: The Sun appears to rise in the morning.

 

S4: The Sun does not rise in the morning.

 

[S1: The Sun rises in the morning.

 

S2: It isn't the case that the Sun rises in the morning.]

 

But, we have been here already, too.

 

Perhaps the worry exercising DM-theorists might be brought out by means of the following 'argument':

 

S5: The Sun appears to rise.

 

S6: Therefore, the Sun does rise.

 

S7: But, modern science shows that the Sun does not rise.

 

S8: Therefore, the Sun does not rise.

 

S9: Hence, the Sun both rises and does not rise. [From S6 and S8.]

 

S10: S9 is a contradiction, and so it is false.

 

S11: If S8 is still held true, then based on the falsehood of S9, S6 is also false.

 

It looks like S9 might be the contradiction DM-theorists require. The idea here appears to be that while phenomena might lead us to accept one set of beliefs, the development of science has forced us to adopt an 'opposite', or even 'contradictory', set. Once again, the conclusion seems to be that scientific knowledge contradicts 'commonsense' and ordinary language. [I have discussed this topic in much greater detail in Interlude One of Essay Eleven Part One. Readers are directed there for more details.]

 

Of course, DM-theorists -- if they were to accept this line of reasoning -- will have to abandon one or both of the following:

 

(1) Contradictions are true, or they reflect coexistent contradictory states of affairs.

 

[The (logical) opposite of (1) was used in S10 to derive the falsehood of S6.]

 

(2) Reality itself is contradictory.

 

On the contrary, the continued acceptance of (1) would mean that DM-theorists who claim that scientific knowledge contradicts 'commonsense' also believe that both 'incorrect' and 'correct' theories/beliefs are true. Clearly, if that were the case, it would completely halt the advance of scientific knowledge. If mythical tales and supposedly erroneous 'folk' theories were all true (even though they 'contradict' fact and/or theory), then there would seem to be no point anyone bothering with scientific research. On that basis, we would have to accept as true the 'fact' that the Earth sits stationary at the centre of the Universe and the fact that it is in motion on the periphery of the Galaxy. Naturally, it would then be impossible to agree that science provides an 'objective' account of reality if the opposite of what scientists believe to be the case is also the case.

 

Some might respond by pointing out that earlier it was argued that the Ptolemaic view of the universe is just as valid as the Copernican. The above remarks now seem to suggest the opposite. Which is it to be?

 

In reply, it is worth adding that wherever the truth happens to lie, no sane individual would hold both of the above theories true at the same time. If a scientist wants to use or accept one approach, he or she won't use or accept the other at the same time, otherwise irredeemable confusion would ensue. Anyway, that specific example is somewhat unique; we certainly wouldn't be this accommodating with other scientific theories that are (supposedly, or even genuinely) in competition with ancient beliefs/dogmas. For example, no one -- it is to be hoped(!) -- accepts the literal truth of the Biblical account of creation and Darwin's theory of descent through modification and natural selection, or the Humoral Theory and the Germ Theory of disease, etc., etc.

 

Finally, it should to be recalled that I am not airing my views here, merely highlighting the insurmountable obstacles that confront DM-theorists if they insist on sticking to the ideas they inherited from Hegel (upside down or 'the right way up') and Traditional Philosophy on this score.

 

Despite these 'difficulties', S5-S11 present serious problems of their own:

 

S5: The Sun appears to rise.

 

S6: Therefore, the Sun does rise.

 

S7: But, modern science shows that the Sun does not rise.

 

S8: Therefore, the Sun does not rise.

 

S9: Hence, the Sun both rises and does not rise. [From S6 and S8.]

 

S10: S9 is a contradiction, and so it is false.

 

S11: If S8 is still held true, then based on the falsehood of S9, S6 is also false.

 

There are at least three problems with the above 'argument', namely:

 

[1] S5 doesn't imply S6, which means that S9 can't be derived from S5-S8.

 

[2] S9 isn't a contradiction -- it is far too ambiguous. [Similar equivocations were highlighted, here.]

 

[3] If all phenomenal reports are to be subjected to this sort of test (or this level of scrutiny), then it might prove impossible to show that S7, for instance, is itself true. That is because the validation of S7 would require extensive reliance on other phenomenological reports, all of which would be susceptible to the same level of destructive/sceptical analysis.

 

[The above considerations are quite apart from the fact that S7, for example, is a phenomenal object itself (it is, after all, a physical object on your screen!), and is therefore 'untrustworthy' -- or what it says is unreliable -- but only given this odd way of characterising 'appearances'. Again: if all appearances are deceptive, so is any sentence that attempts to assert this! On the other hand, if only some appearances are deceptive, how do we distinguish between them without relying on anything in the phenomenal world, and hence on appearances themselves?]

 

In which case, S9-S11 can't be derived from these premisses. So, this supposed reductio is defective from start to finish.

 

It could be objected that in a perfectly ordinary sense the following two sentences are contradictory (when they have been interpreted):

 

Z1: It appears to be φ-ing.

 

Z2: No, it isn't φ-ing.

 

[Where "φ" stands for a verb clause or phrase, such as "rain"; so, "φ-ing" would become "raining".]

 

Consider this ordinary language interpretation of Z1 and Z2:

 

Z1a: "It appears to be raining."

 

Z2a: "No, you're mistaken, it isn't raining." [Which is perhaps a more colloquial version.]

 

Or, consider this example:

 

Z3: "The Sun appears to be moving."

 

Z4: "No, you're mistaken, the Sun isn't moving." [Which is also perhaps a more colloquial version.]

 

Anyone who uttered Z2a (or, indeed, Z4) would be correcting (i.e., gainsaying -- speaking against) anyone who uttered Z1a (or Z3), thus contradicting them.

 

This shows that the earlier claim that "It isn't possible to form a contradiction from a proposition that expresses matters of fact with one that reports an appearance" is itself false.

 

Or, so it could be argued...

 

Of course, Z4 is false anyway, since the Sun is moving relative to the Galaxy; in which case, it isn't too clear that Z3 and Z4 will be of much use to DM-apologists, especially since the obvious reply to anyone who tried to correct Z3 by means of Z4 would be to respond as follows:

 

Z5: "Well, I didn't say it was moving, only that it appears to be -- and it still appears to be moving, despite what you say."

 

So, Z3 and Z4 aren't contradictories since they can both be true (and can both be false) at once. That is, of course, because of the equivocal nature of verbs like "move" and "appear".

 

[In Essay Five we saw that the word "move" was rather complex and had many different meanings (even in mathematics, science and philosophy), most of which have been ignored by those who (still!) rashly buy into Hegel's theory that motion is 'contradictory'.]

 

The same sort of response applies to Z1a and Z2a:

 

Z6: "Well, I didn't say it was raining, only that it appears to be -- and it still appears to be raining, despite what you say." [Compare this with what was said earlier about rain machines.]

 

[Z1a: "It appears to be raining."]

 

[Z2a: "No, you're mistaken, it isn't raining."]

 

Hence, this still remains the case: It isn't possible to form a contradiction from a proposition that expresses matters of fact with one that reports an appearance.

 

[Anyone who thinks differently is invited to email me with their best shot.]

 

'Contradictory' Capitalism?

 

Putting the natural sciences to one side for now, Rees and other DM-theorists often cite examples drawn from (a 'dialectical' version of) HM to illustrate the alleged clash between "essence" and "appearance".

 

[Several other such examples were analysed in Essay Eight Part Two, here, here and here.]

 

Perhaps an examination of the cases they cite might help clarify the point DM-theorists are trying to make?

 

Rees's argument, for instance, proceeds as follows (a similar approach to this question by Ernest Mandel has been moved to Appendix Four):

 

"The important thing about a Marxist understanding of the distinction between the appearance of things and their essence is twofold: 1) by delving beneath the mass of surface phenomena, it is possible to see the essential relations governing historical change -- thus beneath the appearance of a free and fair market transaction it is possible to see the exploitative relations of class society, but, 2) this does not mean that surface appearances can simply be dismissed as ephemeral events of no consequence. In revealing the essential relations in society, it is also possible to explain more fully than before why they appear in a form different to their real nature. To explain, for instance, why it is that the exploitative class relations at the point of production appear as the exchange of 'a fair day's work for a fair day's pay' in the polished surface of the labour market.... There is a deeper reality, but it must be able to account for the contradiction between it and the way it appears." [Rees (1998), pp.187-88. Bold emphases alone added; paragraphs merged.]

 

This passage makes it plain that while Capitalism appears on the surface to be fair (but surely only to non-Marxists and anti-socialists!), its underlying 'essence' is exploitative, or, at least, its 'essential relations' may be described in these terms. Hence, in that sense it could be claimed that appearances do indeed contradict reality.

 

Or, so it might be argued...

 

Unfortunately, Rees's example isn't even a contradiction, howsoever much we might deplore what it seems to express. [Why that is so has been explained more fully here. On the highly misleading metaphor that certain truths, or even "essences", somehow lie "below the surface", see here.]

 

Perhaps the above remarks are a little too hasty, or even dismissive? In that case it might prove helpful if Rees's argument were rephrased so that the alleged contradiction he seems to see there becomes much more obvious, perhaps along the following lines:

 

R17: Capitalism appears to be fair.

 

R18: It isn't the case that Capitalism appears to be fair.

 

This pair of sentences certainly looks contradictory, but as we saw above, since both are about 'appearances' -- not about the alleged clash between 'reality' and 'appearances' -- they aren't what Rees intended.34

 

Well, maybe then the following will do in their place?

 

R19: Capitalism is exploitative.

 

R20: It isn't the case that Capitalism is exploitative.

 

This pair also seems contradictory, but once again, these two sentence won't do either since they fail to counterpose 'appearance' with 'reality' -- they are both about 'reality' which isn't where Rees thought there was a contradiction.

 

We seem to be going round in circles again, like we did earlier.

 

Independently of the above, a clearer understanding of Rees's intentions might be achieved by considering the relation he says exists between (i) "essence" and "appearance" and (ii) "subjective" and "objective" views of 'reality':

 

"[F]or Lenin practice overcomes the distinction between subjective and objective and the gap between essence and appearance." [Ibid., pp.190-91.]

 

This suggests these rather elusive DM-'contradictions' arise between a "subjective" and an "objective" view of the world. But, even if that were the case, what precisely is the contradiction, even here? And how do 'subjective contradictions' (or those that result for a 'subjective' view if the world) power the universe, never mind the class war?

 

Perhaps the following 'argument' might help clarify Rees's intentions:

 

R21: Capitalism appears to be fair.

 

R22: That leads people (including workers) to think it is fair.

 

R23: Hence, Capitalism is fair. [Or, so they conclude.]

 

R24: But, revolutionary theory and practice convince others that Capitalism isn't fair.

 

R25: Therefore, Capitalism isn't fair. [Or, so they conclude.]

 

R26: Consequently, Capitalism is both fair and not fair. [From R23 and R25.]

 

R27: However, the contradiction in R26 implies that R23 can't be true (based on the truth of R25).

 

R28: Therefore, Capitalism isn't fair.35

 

Ignoring the fact that the above argument is hopelessly invalid, its (intended) message looks reasonably clear: the 'objectivity' of revolutionary theory (expressed in R24) 'makes plain' the contradiction in R26.

 

Admittedly, R26 is an incorrect statement of the results of this argument, which should have been something like this:

 

R26a: Consequently, some think capitalism is fair while others believe it isn't.

 

However, even if that were the case, the supposed contradiction here still isn't between 'appearance' and 'reality', but between certain beliefs held about both -- or perhaps even between the inferences that could be drawn from either by different individuals.

 

Anyway, few people (and certainly no revolutionaries) believe that capitalism is both fair and not fair at the same time (as R26 seems to imply). Anyone who devotes some thought to this question will either agree with R23 or with R25, but not both at once. Indeed, that is why R28 would be held true by socialists. However, DM requires both R23 and R25 (and hence R26) to be true at once (or, for both to reflect 'coexistent contradictory states of affairs'). But, we have been here several times already.36

 

It could be objected that the appearances referred to above prompt the false belief that Capitalism is fair, which is contradicted by the fact that it isn't, and that is what creates the intended contradiction. But, no one is questioning the fact that there are all sorts of contradictory beliefs in people's heads. What is at issue here is:

 

(a) Whether R22 and R28 can both be (unequivocally and unambiguously) held true together; and,

 

(b) Whether 'appearances' contradict 'reality';

 

both of which have yet to be established.37

 

Hence, it doesn't look like we can construct a clear example of the sort of contradiction Rees had in mind -- even when we use his own example!

 

Nevertheless, this latest impasse introduces yet another, and perhaps even more serious, problem facing DM-theorists: if 'appearances' are finally acknowledged to be (in some respects or in some way) deceptive --, or, at least, not entirely, or not fully, accurate (or even not fully 'real') --, or they are said to be limited in some (as yet unspecified) way or are misleading to some extent, how can anything of value be learnt from them, or by means of them? Worse still, if revolutionary practice takes place at the level of 'appearances', how could any such practice act as a test of the 'objectivity' of Marxist theory itself?

 

The next few sections will attempt to resolve these unexpected 'difficulties'.

 

Adrift In A Sea Of 'Appearances'

 

'Dialectical' Practice Can't Be 'Objective'

 

The contribution revolutionary practice makes to the validation (or otherwise) of DM will be examined in greater detail in Essays Ten Part One and Nine Part Two, but for present purposes it is worth pointing out that practice can't in fact test 'objectivity' in the way DM-supporters seem to imagine. Nor can it even be 'objective', and that isn't just because the word "objective" is itself hoplessly vague. As noted above, it is because practice clearly takes place at the level of 'appearances', which, according to dialecticians can't be anything other than 'subjective'.38

 

Admittedly, some Marxists claim that there is such a thing as "theoretical practice", but even there, its results can only surface in the 'world of appearances' -- not to mention the physical objects any such practice has to utilise. Hence, in order for there to be any such 'theoretical practice', books, articles, computer screens, sheets of paper, pens (etc., etc.) have to be accessed, used, read or written, all of which are 'trapped' in the everyday 'world of appearances'. Unless we believe in telepathy, or are committed to the bizarre idea that theoretical propositions live in an 'abstract world', accessible to the 'mind' alone, and aren't embodied or expressed in anything material -– that is, that they are never, and can't ever be, written down, typed or spoken about, let alone mulled over during soliloquy -– the deflationary conclusion that theoretical propositions are as material as sticks and stones seems undeniable.

 

[Of course, if the opposite were the case (i.e., if theoretical propositions lived an 'abstract world', accessible to the 'mind' alone, and weren't embodied or expressed in anything material), and DM-fans were to accept such a conclusion as part of their theory, that would make them dualists, whether they realised it or not!]

 

Plainly, that is because abstract objects (and any words used to express them) must make some form of an appearance in the phenomenal world at some point, or be forever unknown to us. In the real world, even theoretical propositions have to be written down or uttered in a public language, and that immediately places them in the vice-like grip of all those 'unreliable'/'deceptive' 'appearances'.

 

[MEC = Materialism and Empirio-Criticism (i.e., Lenin (1972); PN = Philosophical Notebooks (i.e., Lenin (1961).]

 

[John Rees made some attempt to address concerns like these by arguing (correctly) that Lenin's theory had progressed markedly (and 'dialectically') between the writing of MEC and PN. I have critically reviewed what he (Rees) had to say in Appendix Three.]

 

Are All 'Appearances' False?

 

Exception might be taken to the above comments since they seem to imply that dialecticians regard appearances as unreliable, misleading or false. Some might object that that is itself highly misleading -- even though, as we are about to see, Herbert Marcuse, for example, openly admits appearances are false. Earlier, we saw other DM-supporters say more-or-less the same -- for instance, here and here.

 

On the contrary, it could be maintained that dialecticians (or, perhaps, the majority of them) don't believe this of appearances. Indeed, the following passage from TAR underlines this (alleged) fact:

 

"[T]his does not mean that surface appearances can simply be dismissed as ephemeral events of no consequence. In revealing the essential relations in society, it is also possible to explain more fully than before why they appear in a form different to their real nature. To explain, for instance, why it is that the exploitative class relations at the point of production appear as the exchange of 'a fair day's work for a fair day's pay' in the polished surface of the labour market.... There is a deeper reality, but it must be able to account for the contradiction between it and the way it appears." [Rees (1998), p.187-88. Bold emphasis alone added; paragraphs merged.]

 

But if, as the aforementioned passages also say, superficial appearances aren't in fact a guide to deeper "essences" -- indeed they "contradict" them --, then they must be deceptive at some point or to some extent. That is especially so if the vast majority of human beings misread them or are misled by them and it takes 'clued-in DM-fans' to disabuse them of their false beliefs or misguided opinions. If, as even Rees admits, the exploitative relations in Capitalism aren't really as they seem, and "appear in a form different from their real nature", then what they reveal can't be anything other than misleading (at least to non-Marxist observers), and hence false. There is no other way of reading this passage. [The entire topic has been discussed more fully here.]

 

But, it is worth asking again: In what sense do 'appearances' "contradict...deeper reality"? Do they' struggle with and then turn into any such "deeper reality" (which is what the DM-classics tell us all such 'dialectical opposites' must do)? If so, DM-theorists have been remarkably coy about the details. Furthermore, do 'appearances' and 'deeper reality' imply one another -- such that the existence of one implies the existence of the other (rather like the existence of the proletariat is said to imply the existence of the capitalist class)? That can't be correct, for if it were, it would mean that before sentient life evolved the existence of 'deeper reality' must have implied, even back then(!), that there were 'appearances', somewhere, for non-sentient objects and processes to 'generate' so that they always have, and always will, 'contradict' all these 'deeper realities'. According to DM-theorists themselves, 'dialectical opposites' can't exist alone; they have to exist in united ('interpenetrated') pairs. Here, for example, is Engels:

 

"The law of the interpenetration of opposites.... [M]utual penetration of polar opposites and transformation into each other when carried to extremes...." [Engels (1954), pp.17, 62.]

 

"Dialectics has proved from the results of our experience of nature so far that all polar opposites in general are determined by the mutual action of the two opposite poles on one another, that the separation and opposition of these poles exists only within their unity and inter-connection, and, conversely, that their inter-connection exists only in their separation and their unity only in their opposition." [Ibid., p.72.]

 

"For a stage in the outlook on nature where all differences become merged in intermediate steps, and all opposites pass into one another through intermediate links, the old metaphysical method of thought no longer suffices. Dialectics, which likewise knows no hard and fast lines, no unconditional, universally valid 'either-or' and which bridges the fixed metaphysical differences, and besides 'either-or' recognises also in the right place 'both this-and that' and reconciles the opposites, is the sole method of thought appropriate in the highest degree to this stage. Of course, for everyday use, for the small change of science, the metaphysical categories retain their validity." [Ibid., pp.212-13.]

 

"Further, we find upon closer investigation that the two poles of an antithesis positive and negative, e.g., are as inseparable as they are opposed and that despite all their opposition, they mutually interpenetrate. And we find, in like manner, that cause and effect are conceptions which only hold good in their application to individual cases; but as soon as we consider the individual cases in their general connection with the universe as a whole, they run into each other, and they become confounded when we contemplate that universal action and reaction in which causes and effects are eternally changing places, so that what is effect here and now will be cause there and then, and vice versa." [Engels (1976), p.27.]

 

"And it is just as impossible have one side of a contradiction without the other, as it is to retain the whole of an apple in one's hand after half has been eaten." [Engels (1891b), p.496. Bold emphasis added.]

 

The online version renders the above passage slightly differently:

 

"And one cannot have one side of this contradiction without the other, any more than a man has a whole apple in his hand after eating half." [Quoted from here.]

 

Mao also made the same point:

 

"The fact is that no contradictory aspect can exist in isolation. Without its opposite aspect, each loses the condition for its existence. Just think, can any one contradictory aspect of a thing or of a concept in the human mind exist independently? Without life, there would be no death; without death, there would be no life. Without 'above', there would be no 'below'; without 'below', there would be no 'above'. Without misfortune, there would be no good fortune; without good fortune, these would be no misfortune. Without facility, there would be no difficulty; without difficulty, there would be no facility. Without landlords, there would be no tenant-peasants; without tenant-peasants, there would be no landlords. Without the bourgeoisie, there would be no proletariat; without the proletariat, there would be no bourgeoisie. Without imperialist oppression of nations, there would be no colonies or semi-colonies; without colonies or semicolonies, there would be no imperialist oppression of nations. It is so with all opposites; in given conditions, on the one hand they are opposed to each other, and on the other they are interconnected, interpenetrating, interpermeating and interdependent, and this character is described as identity. In given conditions, all contradictory aspects possess the character of non-identity and hence are described as being in contradiction. But they also possess the character of identity and hence are interconnected. This is what Lenin means when he says that dialectics studies 'how opposites can be and how they become identical'. How then can they be identical? Because each is the condition for the other's existence. This is the first meaning of identity.

 

"But is it enough to say merely that each of the contradictory aspects is the condition for the other's existence, that there is identity between them and that consequently they can coexist in a single entity? No, it is not. The matter does not end with their dependence on each other for their existence; what is more important is their transformation into each other. That is to say, in given conditions, each of the contradictory aspects within a thing transforms itself into its opposite, changes its position to that of its opposite. This is the second meaning of the identity of contradiction. Why is there identity here, too? You see, by means of revolution the proletariat, at one time the ruled, is transformed into the ruler, while the bourgeoisie, the erstwhile ruler, is transformed into the ruled and changes its position to that originally occupied by its opposite. This has already taken place in the Soviet Union, as it will take place throughout the world. If there were no interconnection and identity of opposites in given conditions, how could such a change take place?" [Mao (1937), pp.337-39. Bold emphases alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site; several paragraphs merged. Three minor typos corrected; missing words "and how they become", present in the published version, but absent on-line, have been added. I have informed the Marxist Internet Archive (MIA) of these errors.]

 

This was underlined by MIST, Ira Gollobin:

 

"Opposites in a thing are not only mutually exclusive, polar, repelling, each other; they also attract and interpenetrate each other. They begin and cease to exist together.... These dual aspects of opposites -- conflict and unity -- are like scissor blades in cutting, jaws in mastication, and two legs in walking. Where there is only one, the process as such is impossible: 'all polar opposites are in general determined by the mutual action of two opposite poles on one another, the separation and opposition of these poles exists only within their unity and interconnection, and, conversely, their interconnection exists only in their separation and their unity only in their opposition.' In fact, 'where one no sooner tries to hold on to one side alone then it is transformed unnoticed into the other....'" [Gollobin (1986), p.113; quoting Engels (1891a), p.414. Bold emphases added.]

 

In which case, if the above theorists are to be believed, there couldn't have been a capitalist class without a proletarian class. The one can't exist without the other. If so, how could 'appearances' exist before sentient life evolved? Or are we to suppose that 'deeper reality' wasn't 'contradicted' until sentient life emerged? That is, are we to imagine that 'deeper reality' existed for countless billions of years all on its own, in a 'non-contradicted state', only to be 'contradicted' when the first sentient organisms evolved? But, if 'deeper reality' existed alone for billions of years, that would make the relation between it and 'appearances' non-dialectical, and hence unchanging. Why then did it change? If all change is the result of just such 'dialectical contradictions', and there were none in this case, how and why the change?

 

While odd ideas like this might sit well with maverick Hegelian Idealists, or even run-of-the-mill Theists, it can't possibly do so for hard-headed materialists. Least of all DM-fans.

 

Once more, none of this makes sense, even in DM-terms!

 

It could be objected that if there were no sentient life, there would be no appearances and hence no contradiction of the sort described above. Maybe not, but in what way does the existence of 'underlying reality' imply the existence of 'surface appearances' so that one of them can't exist without the other -- again, like the proletariat can't exist without the capitalist class, nor vice versa (so we are told)? Both would have to co-exist and imply one another if this were a 'dialectical contradiction' (and if the DM-classics were to be believed). If 'underlying reality' existed long before sentient life evolved (or it wouldn't have evolved!), then it plainly could exist without there being any 'appearances' to do all that 'contradicting'. If so, that means this 'contradiction' can't be 'dialectical', whatever else it is --, otherwise, once more, this couldn't happen. Compare the supposed possibility that there was an 'underlying reality' before there were any 'appearances' to 'contradict' it with the following suggestion: There was a time when there was a proletariat but no capitalist class, or there was a capitalist class but no proletariat. For DM-fans, is either of these even conceivable? One suspects not.

 

In which case, the anti-DM conclusions drawn above still appear to be valid.

 

Again, it could be argued that DM-theorists reject such a simple-minded view of the relation between appearance and reality; they hold there is a dialectical interplay between theory and practice, and hence between appearance and reality. This means that even though thought depends on appearances for its immediate content, it nevertheless ascends by means of abstraction, or critical analysis/synthesis (subsequently tested and confirmed in practice) to a more adequate (less partial or less relative), theoretical and concrete understanding of the world. This process is also rooted in previously accepted, relatively true theory, which in turn isn't set in stone. In the long-run, this method yields a more accurate account of the real processes at work in Capitalism (and in nature). At each stage, thought returns to the original world of experience where, after again being tested in practice, its content may be viewed in a more all-rounded, increasingly concrete manner. The progressive refinement of cognition along such lines renders any conclusions that have been drawn (and tested) in this manner, objective --, or, at least, it means they are increasingly objective (even if such results are still only partially or relatively true). Hence, appearances needn't be regarded as merely subjective, contrary to what is suggested above. Their connection with underlying reality allows them to be viewed in a different, more complex, inter-connected, less one-sided light, allowing revolutionaries to understand why things seem the way they do and why most individuals view them in the manner they do.

 

Or, so it might be argued...

 

However, that doesn't explain what the 'contradiction' is supposed to be here, even in DM-terms!

 

Ignoring that rather annoying 'problem' for the present, and despite the fanfare, the undeniable fact is that the old conservative adage, "A fair day's pay for a fair day's work", couldn't serve as a guiding principle for a single revolutionary writing agitational leaflets no matter how many casuistical hoops dialectical sloganeers might try to force it through.

 

That is because at no stage in the execution of the above 'dialectical somersaults' would it be correct to say, think, or even imply that Capitalism isn't exploitative. No matter how many impressive or intricate 'dialectical gyrations' were expertly performed only the most naïve of militants would automatically believe the boss of a profitable company who said that she "couldn't afford" the latest pay demand from the strike committee.

 

In that case, and in practice once more, no revolutionary would regard the beliefs prompted by the 'superficial appearances' of Capitalist society as anything other than false or self-serving. Certainly, no Marxist -- that is, this side of a major sell-out -- believes Capitalism is ultimately "fair", and then acts in accord with that belief.39

 

Anyway, the pro-DM-rejoinder (from a few paragraphs back) seems to rely on the assumption that thoughts and theories aren't themselves 'appearances' -– i.e., that they aren't expressed in a public language, or don't surface in an open arena in a physical form of some sort. In fact, when reading DM-texts on the 'dialectical method' one gets the distinct impression that each complex 'dialectical fouetté' -- like those Rees mentions above (and in Appendix Three; "dialectical fouetté" is, of course, my phrase, not his!) -- takes place in a internal 'mental-', or 'psychic-sports-arena' (as it were), where concepts and abstractions are put through their paces in private. And not just that. It very much looks like 'dialectical moves' like these have to be performed afresh each time inside each socially-isolated, dialectical cranium.

 

[That was one of the main themes of Part One (and earlier sections of this Essay): the idea that DM-epistemology, for all its pretensions to the contrary, is trapped in a bourgeois individualist 'isolation cell'. The general principles underlying the social nature of language and knowledge will be addressed again in much more detail in Essays Twelve Part One and Thirteen Part Three.]

 

Hence, as noted above, it is difficult to resist the conclusion that 'the process of abstraction' is something that adepts learn to perform as socially-isolated individuals, in their own private inner sanctum, their heads. Certainly, we have yet to encounter anything in the 'abstractionist literature' that suggests the following picture is misguided: in order for DM-fans to agree what any of their general words mean there must exist synchronised teams of dialecticians all chanting in unison the latest verbal application of their most recent 'dialectical conjuring trick', or the production of their latest 'abstraction' -- perhaps under the watchful eye of a team leader in the shape of Alan Woods, Gerry Healy, Bob Avakian, Ernest Mandel, George Novack, Bertell Ollman, or even Chris Cutrone (to name just six). How else do Dialectical Marxists imagine they are capable of coordinating their individual 'abstractive endeavours' so they are able to decide whether or not the 'abstractions' generated by Abstractor A are the same as those of Abstractor B, the same as those of Abstractor C, the same as those of Abstractor D, the same as those of Abstractor E, the same as..?

 

We are never told how any of these Intrepid Abstractors know whether or not their 'abstractions' concur with those of the rest of the Abstractive Community, so any such 'coordination' -- if it happens -- remains just as mysterious as the 'process' itself. In fact, no two dialecticians would be able to determine whether or not their socially-isolated 'feats of mental abstraction' actually converged on the same target, let alone the right target. [On that, see here and here. In fact, as we saw earlier, in such circumstances, there could be no such thing as "correct" or "right".]

 

An appeal to a publicly accessible language here (in order to establish some level of shared meaning across the above Abstractors) would be to no avail, either -- as pointed out earlier, too. Moreover, since the use of any such language takes place in this 'unreliable world of appearances', recourse to it would be rather like trying to ascertain your correct height by placing the flat of your hand on the top of your head, but doing nothing more.

 

[Once again: in the above it was assumed for the purpose of argument that DM-epistemology and the 'dialectical theory of abstraction' were both, prima facie, true --  or even comprehensible.]

 

In short, the superficial gestures DM-theorists make in the general direction of their (avowed) belief in the social nature of language and knowledge are at odds with their pronouncements on this and related topics. Given their own theory, knowledge and language can't be social products; they are the result of the abstractive activities of socially-, and epistemologically-isolated individuals, none of whom would in the end mean the same by their words as anyone else involved in this 'dialectical pantomime'.

 

[Why that is so is explained here.]

 

Conversely, of course, if language and knowledge are accepted as social products, abstractionism becomes a non-starter. [On that, see here.]

 

In both Parts of this Essay we have witnessed several dialecticians reporting -- verbally or in print -- on the results of their own self-confessed, 'internal investigations' (since they all describe, or characterise, 'abstraction' in terms of inner 'mental processes'). Indeed, in this respect, they have no choice. They have to do one or other of these (i.e., report on their ideas verbally or in print), or keep their ideas to themselves. Moreover, they have to do all that reporting in this 'world of appearances', too. Short of there being a 'hot-line' connecting one 'dialectical brain' to the next (or there exist some form of 'dialectical telepathy'), there is no way that the contents of any one of these 'inner abstractive-gymnasiums' might be available to any others in the same Abstractive Community for comparisons to be made, let alone validation or confirmation.

 

So, in order to compare their 'ideas and abstractions', dialecticians have to record or express their 'inner deliberations' in this material world, in some form or other, where 'unreliable appearances' still reign supreme.

 

In that case, and if we were to believe what we are told about this 'untrustworthy world of appearances' and its 'subjective' nature, no DM-proposition could ever be or become "objective", in any sense of that word -- but, certainly not in any way consistent with what Lenin had to say about 'objectivity'.

 

Of course, it could be countered that even if DM-propositions surface in the world of appearances, that doesn't affect their content, what they are about -- and hence surfacing in the world of appearances can't affect their validity.

 

But, anyone who wants to ascertain what any such propositions are about, or determine the validity of their content, has to rely on what appears before them, on the page or in person (in a lecture hall, or in conversation, for example), or while watching a video --, all of which must take place in this 'sketchy world of appearances'. As should now seem clear, what Dialectical Marxists claim they can 'see', 'read' or even conclude about such content will only appear to be this, or only appear to be that. How could it be otherwise? Does anyone have direct access to the brain processes of a single DM-theorist? On the other hand, if they are somehow capable of ascertaining what this content really is, then, if DM-epistemology is to be believed, what this content really is must also 'contradict' what 'appears' in front of them. If not -- i.e., if there is no contradiction here -- i.e., between what this content really is and what 'appears' in front of each DM-fan -- this theory must be defective to its core. Naturally, this means no one need pay DM any heed --, or, even worse, try to put it into practice.

 

[Although such considerations might help account for the last hundred or so years of the almost unremitting failure of Dialectical Marxism.]

 

There is no way around this major obstacle -- or, there is none for those who have unwisely bought into the ancient, ruling-class distinction between 'appearance' and 'reality'.

 

[The words "see" and "read" above are encased in 'scare' quotes for reasons set out in detail in Essay Thirteen Part One -- since, if Lenin is to be believed, all that DM-fans have available to them are 'images' of the world (and hence 'images' of books and articles about DM) -- not the world itself. Readers are directed to that Essay for proof. In Appendix Three, I have dealt with John Rees's unsuccessful (and surprisingly weak) attempt to rescue Lenin from the solipsistic black hole into which he had dropped himself in MEC.]

 

Furthermore, even if it were true that 'the process of abstraction' takes place in 'the mind', unless DM-theorists are prepared to accept a quasi-Cartesian account of thoughts (whereby the latter somehow guarantee their own veracity, as opposed to merely appearing to do so), not even such an inner, 'dialectical detour' will succeed in grounding a single DM-abstraction in 'objectivity' (again, if we really have to use the jargon).39a Hence, without postulating the existence of abstractions that are self-authenticating and thoughts that are self-certifying (which would therefore require no support from practice or evidence), these 'inner phenomena', these 'inner representations', can't obviate or diminish the need to make a validating entrance in the world of suspect 'appearances'.40

 

Unfortunately, however, inside the alleged 'inner chamber of the mind', a 'thought' is no less an appearance than the deliverances of the senses. Even for the most solipsistically-incarcerated of individuals, their thoughts only appear to them to be thus and so.

 

In which case, even if such 'thoughts' were 'self-certifying', they would still only appear to be such.40a

 

Hence, individual dialecticians can no more certify their own ideas and 'abstractions' than they can certify their own exam results, their own divorce or their own world record. 

 

But, what about the unsupported claim (above) that thoughts are also appearances?

 

Presumably the following -- or what they can be used to express -- would be counted as examples of thought, at some level:

 

T1: "That stick is bent in the water", said the philosopher.

 

T2: NN thought a stick was bent until she realised it was partly immersed in water.

 

T3: NM thought he had won the vote until the result of the recount was announced.

 

On the basis of these (and countless other examples one could think of), it would be difficult to deny that thoughts are either 'appearances' or are part of the 'world of appearances'. In fact, the above are not only about appearances, they are appearances themselves.

 

It could be argued that appearances are usually associated with sense perception, which is what (fundamentally) distinguishes them from thoughts. In response it is worth pointing out that T3, for instance, isn't about 'sensations', it is about how things appeared to NM at a certain point during a re-count, and perhaps afterwards. So, T3 records a reported appearance that prompted NM's thoughts, and he was wrong. What appeared to be the case, what was thought to be true, turned out not to be so.

 

Of course, what has dominated Traditional Thought is a certain paradigm/metaphor that has held Philosophers (and amateur metaphysicians) in its grip for countless centuries. This paradigm/metaphor is integral to an entire family of theories that picture 'thoughts' as inner, shadowy 'mental' events, states, processes or episodes, which somehow represent things to us 'internally' and 'directly', or which form the basis of our beliefs about, and our knowledge of, the world. Fundamental to this complex paradigm is an associated metaphor that pictures 'the mind' as a (sort of) computational device that 'processes data' sent its way by the senses. This approach was subsequently based on (yet-to-be-indentified) neurological or psychological structures, networks and pathways located and operating in the CNS. The 'output' of these 'internal processes' is then supposed to be accessible only to the individual concerned, who thereby has a unique perspective on, and an immediate awareness of, that 'output'. Since Descartes introduced the term, this entire ensemble is now called "consciousness". [I have said more about that obscure term in several places in Essay Thirteen Part Three, but especially here.]

 

This then a core belief the vast majority of contemporary theorists have inherited from Descartes --, and, ultimately, from Plato himself:

 

"Descartes's view of the nature of mind endured much longer than his view of matter. Indeed among educated people in the West who were not professional philosophers it is still the most widespread view of the mind. Most contemporary philosophers would disown Cartesian dualism but even those who explicitly renounce it are often profoundly influenced by it. Many people, for instance, go along with Descartes in identifying the mental realm as the realm of consciousness. They think of consciousness as an object of introspection; as something we see when we look within ourselves. They think of it as an inessential, contingent matter that consciousness has an expression in speech and behaviour. Consciousness, as they conceive it, is something to which each of us has direct access in our own case. Others, by contrast, can only infer to our conscious states by accepting our testimony or making causal inferences from our physical behaviour." [Kenny (1992), p.2. Bold emphases added; paragraphs merged.]

 

"In philosophy, ever since Plato, the mainstream opinion has been that the mind is the organ of thought; thinking is what the mind is for, and we act as we do because we think what we do." [Fodor (2011), p.24. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"Philosophical reflection on human nature, on the body and soul, goes back to the dawn of philosophy. The polarities between which it fluctuates were set out by Plato and Aristotle. According to Plato, and the Platonic-Christian tradition of Augustine, the human being is not a unified substance, but a combination of two distinct substances, a mortal body and an immortal soul. According to Aristotle, a human being is a unified substance, the soul (psuchē) being the form of the body. To describe that form is to describe the characteristic powers of human beings: in particular, the distinctive powers of intellect and will that characterize the rational psuchē. Modern debate on this theme commences with the heir to the Platonic-Augustinian tradition: namely, the Cartesian conception of human beings as two one-sided things, a mind and a body. Their two-way causal interaction was invoked to explain human experience and behaviour.

 

"The greatest figures of the first two generations of twentieth-century neuroscientists, e.g., Sherrington, Eccles and Penfield, were avowed Cartesian dualists. The third generation retained the basic Cartesian structure, but transformed it into brain–body dualism: substance dualism was abandoned, but structural dualism retained. For neuroscientists now ascribe much the same array of mental predicates to the brain as Descartes ascribed to the mind, and conceive of the relationship between thought and action, and experience and its objects, in much the same way as Descartes -- essentially merely replacing the mind by the brain. The central theme of our book was to demonstrate the incoherence of brain–body dualism, and to disclose its misguided crypto-Cartesian character. Our constructive aim was to show that an Aristotelian account, with due emphasis on first- and second-order active and passive abilities and their modes of behavioural manifestation, supplemented by Wittgensteinian insights that complement Aristotle's, is necessary to do justice to the structure of our conceptual scheme and to provide coherent descriptions of the great discoveries of post-Sherringtonian cognitive neuroscience." [Bennett and Hacker (2008), pp.240-41. Bold emphases and links added. Italics in the original.]

 

"The second critical aspect of the Cartesian Paradigm was the creation of the private realm of consciousness that flowed from the new scientific withdrawal of soul from the material world. Ideas existed in consciousness only (and animals did not and could not) have them. Because there seemed to be a New World of consciousness, it invited exploration and study with a special tool for making the voyage, introspection. Thus was created the idea of a science devoted to consciousness, psyche-logos, the science of the soul.... What I want to point out here is a more basic problem for psychology defined according to the Cartesian framework: It makes doing psychology as a science nearly impossible...." [Quoted from here; accessed 18/05/2024; bold emphases added.]

 

"...[V]irtually no philosopher doubted, from the time of Locke until roughly 1914, that, whatever concepts and ideas were, they were clearly mental objects of some kind. And no large-scale and comprehensive demolition job was done against this particularly wide-spread and influential philosophical misconception until Wittgenstein produced his Philosophical Investigations...." [Putnam (1975b), p.7. Bold emphasis added.]

 

[Er..., what was that again about the "ideas of the ruling class..."?]

 

As Essay Thirteen Parts One and Three show, DM-theorists have bought into this pseudoproblem, with its associated view of 'the mind', 'consciousness', 'cognition' and 'thought' -- they just have a different theory that attempts to account for all four. As such, their theory not only arose out of, it remains locked in, the Platonic-Christian-Cartesian-Paradigm of 'the mind', 'consciousness', 'cognition' and 'thought' -- which motivates the belief that 'thoughts' are internal, private and individually-experienced phenomena. That explains why Traditional Theorists define 'the process of abstraction' in terms of private mental acts (and that includes DM-theorists themselves, as we have seen, here and here). Indeed, it is also why it seems obvious to many that since appearances arise from sensation, they can't be 'thoughts' (nor visa versa).

 

Here is Plato laying the foundations of this theory of 'the mind' -- i.e., that 'thought' is like 'the soul' in private conversation with itself (i.e., it engages in what later came to be known as "inner speech") -- in a conversation between Socrates and Theaetetus:

 

"Soc. But must not the mind, or thinking power, which misplaces them, have a conception either of both objects or of one of them?


"Theaet. Certainly.


"Soc. Either together or in succession?


"Theaet. Very good.


"Soc. And do you mean by conceiving, the same which I mean?


"Theaet. What is that?


"Soc. I mean the conversation which the soul holds with herself in considering of anything. I speak of what I scarcely understand; but the soul when thinking appears to me to be just talking -- asking questions of herself and answering them, affirming and denying. And when she has arrived at a decision, either gradually or by a sudden impulse, and has at last agreed, and does not doubt, this is called her opinion. I say, then, that to form an opinion is to speak, and opinion is a word spoken, -- I mean, to oneself and in silence, not aloud or to another: What think you?

 

"Theaet. I agree." [Plato (1997e), p.210. However, I have used Benjamin Jowett's on-line version, not the one found in Plato (1997e). Bold emphases added.]

 

Similar ideas were expressed in another of Plato's dialogues, the Sophist (in this case, the exchange is between an Eleatic Stranger and Theaetetus):

 

"Str. And therefore thought, opinion, and imagination are now proved to exist in our minds both as true and false.


"Theaet. How so?


"Str. You will know better if you first gain a knowledge of what they are, and in what they severally differ from one another.


"Theaet. Give me the knowledge which you would wish me to gain.


"Str. Are not thought and speech the same, with this exception,
that what is called thought is the unuttered conversation of the soul with herself?


"Theaet. Quite true."
[Plato (1997b), pp.287-88. Once again, I have quoted Benjamin Jowett's on-line version, not Plato (1997b). Bold emphases added.]

 

[Details concerning other Ancient Greek thinkers who adopted similar ideas can be found in Sorabji (2004), pp.205-26. I have covered this topic more extensively in Essay Thirteen Part Three, here. Readers are directed there for more details.]

 

But, what takes place in this 'internal world' is uncheckable, which means that whatever each individual experiences there (that is, if they do!) may only appear to be this or appear to be that. They have no independent way of checking any of it. Again, that would be like trying to establish your own truthfulness by asking yourself a series of questions.

 

So, given both the Ancient and post-Cartesian way of picturing human cognition, 'appearances' now turn out to be shadowy, inner 'entities' ('reflections', 'images', 'impressions', etc., etc.) that can only be inspected by an 'internal eye' of some sort. If so, sensation as such can't be what distinguishes 'appearances' from 'thoughts'. On this view, both 'thoughts' and 'appearances' are privately experienced and internally processed -- interpreted as events or states hidden away in the 'recesses of the mind'. In that case, it looks like the only difference between 'thoughts' and 'appearances' is that the latter seem to 'arrive from the outside' while the former are supposedly generated 'internally', under our control (to a limited extent). Nevertheless, given this view of 'appearances', the belief that there is an 'outside', which is capable of acting as a source of anything, let alone sensory 'inputs', is itself based on another set of 'appearances', which, plainly, undermines this assumed difference, making both 'thoughts' and 'appearances' 'internal' events, processes and states, after all.

 

[Again, I have said much more about this in Essay Thirteen Parts One and Three. Note once more: I am not reporting on my own beliefs here, merely pointing out the absurd consequences of accepting ruling-class forms-of-thought, in this case the distinction between 'appearance' and 'reality'/'essence'.]

 

Moreover, as we have also seen, the supposition that 'thoughts' are under our (possibly limited) control trades on a further misconception: that there is something 'internal' to each of us that is separate from our 'thoughts', which is also independent of our conscious control and is thereby capable of regimenting or regulating our 'thoughts' for us. Hence, given this view, our 'thoughts' are both under our control and aren't under our control, since such control has been has delegated to an 'autonomous regulator' that ultimately runs the show.

 

We just think what we think is under our control.

 

That helps explain why:

 

(i) Leibniz ended up with all those autonomous Monads, which were a law unto themselves and which meant his thoughts weren't really his, but were put there by 'God';

 

(ii) Hegel was led by the nose as 'God' (almost parasitically) unfolded 'His' ideas in Hegel's brain, living rent-free in his head -- or those ideas self-developed outside of control by either of them, Hegel or 'God'; and,

 

(iii) DM-theorists, caught up in the confusion they inherited from Hegel, talk the way they do; i.e., when what they say about the 'process of abstraction' results (somewhat fittingly) in two inconsistent interpretations: that the process itself both is and isn't under our conscious control. [One specific example of this Dialectical Muddle is examined in detail in Appendix One.]

 

This overall idea in turn trades on what has come to be called 'the homunculus fallacy' (a caricatured version of which was recently animated in Pixar's cartoon, Inside Out -- and again in 2024, with Inside Out 2), which is clearly no solution. Whatever 'it' supposedly is that controls our 'thoughts', 'it' must face the same insoluble problems the 'mind' and its 'thoughts' already imply, generating another infinite regress.

 

Earlier, we saw this approach to knowledge is in the end predicated on two further (implicit) assumptions; either:

 

(a) Ideas are 'minds' themselves, capable of self-direction; or,

 

(b) 'The mind' is in effect an internal, 'bourgeois individual', different from the Christian/Cartesian 'soul' in name alone.

 

Without doubt materialists will reject the dualism that underpins this way of picturing 'the mind' -- unfortunately, however, there is no consistent way for DM-theorists to do so.

 

[Why that is the case is covered in detail in Essay Thirteen Part Three (link a few paragraphs back), where the neo-Cartesian theory that 'mental events' are 'internal objects and processes', upon which DM-theories of cognition depend, has been subjected to sustained and destructive criticism.]

 

On the other hand, if the existence of self-interpreting and auto-confirming thoughts are part of DM-epistemology (in fact, as we have seen, there is a clear echo of both in Hegel's system, but as far as I can determine, no Marxist dialectician has gone the whole hog here in agreeing with Hegel -- although some appear to have gone half-hog in that direction, for example, here and here), and thoughts were then considered to be no part of 'the world of appearances' (contrary to what was concluded above), they would be no different from the 'intelligent ideas' we met earlier in this Essay.

 

Furthermore, a belated appeal to 'inter-subjectivity' can't validate this part of DM, either. That is because, if this theory were 'true', the reports advanced by other individuals (about their 'internally-processed abstractions', etc.) would likewise surface in this 'unreliable world of appearances', to be promptly be 'contradicted' by all those 'underlying essences', as, indeed, would any opinion expressed about one or both, for or against.

 

Once more, until a clear account of the nature of "thoughts" and "appearances" (as these terms are understood by DM-theorists) is forthcoming (and which doesn't depend on the Platonic/Christian/Cartesian 'soul', nor any 'equivalent' doctrine), it is impossible to determine whether or not they are the same or different, or only appear to be the one or the other.

 

However, as seems reasonably clear, if DM-theorists continue to argue along traditional lines, and agree with Hegel about this ('whole hog' or 'half hog' -- recall that Hegel linked both the 'contingent' and the 'ephemeral' with 'appearances', and human 'thought' is certainly 'ephemeral' and as 'contingent' as any individual who entertains a single 'thought'), it would make a mockery of the materialist flip they claim to have inflicted on his system, for such 'thoughts' would then be little different from those mysterious Hegelian 'Ideas'/'Concepts'. Except they would now be trapped in, and defined by, a psychologically-isolated, socially-fragmented version of Hegel's mind/concept in 'self-development'. Hence, if dialecticians still want to distinguish 'thought' from 'appearance', there seems to be no way of doing so that distances them from all those Platonic/Cartesian/Hegelian 'self-developing', 'self-certifying' (even 'semi-divine') 'Ideas'. And, if that is the case, any subsequent referral back to the 'empirical world' for testing and validation would be an empty gesture. Why bother to test a 'god-like' 'thought'? Did Moses even think to check the Ten Commandments or the creation story in the Book of Genesis?

 

[Moving even higher up the Cosmic Pecking Order: did Gerry Healy ever substantiate a single thing he said -- except by quoting Holy DM-writ, of course (i.e., Hegel, Engels, Lenin and Trotsky)? And, it goes without saying, we all know Bob Avakian doesn't need to check anything at all. (Perish the thought!) But, the situation is even worse than this might suggest, since not even 'God' can side-step how things appear to 'Him' to be. Even for the 'Absolute Idea', at The End of Time, as the Final Judgement-Day Bell tolls, things will merely appear to be as history has delivered them to 'Him'/'Her'/'It'. Once again: Even if 'appearances' ever managed to coincide with 'essence' on that fateful, Definitive Day, they would still only appear to do so. After all, it would be just another 'brute fact' about how 'The Absolute' so happens to string ideas together.]

 

Finally, we can console ourselves with the further thought (no pun intended!) that whoever rejects the above conclusions must do so in 'this world of appearances', or stay forever silent. Even Hegel's system is only accessible to those who can read, speak or hear. That is because his writings (indeed, anyone's writings) confront us now, and always will, as phenomenal objects.

 

And, in this world, the physical universe, 'appearances' reign supreme.

 

Any appearance to the contrary is, of course, entirely illusory...

 

Dialectics Engages Auto-Destruct Mode

 

Furthermore, thoughts and theories can be every bit as mistaken as beliefs based on appearances often are (if we insist on picturing knowledge in such a peculiar way).41 For example, the thought that sticks bend when immersed in water is no less (potentially) misleading than is any appearance to that effect.

 

[That is partly what lay behind the point made earlier about contradictory beliefs.]

 

The history of science is littered with erroneous and radically false or mistaken beliefs and theories. With respect to DM, the situation is, if anything, far worse. Given the DM-theory that knowledge depends on an infinite, asymptotic convergence on an ever-elusive Absolute or Ideal Limit, it is little different from extreme scepticism. [That accusation was substantiated in Essay Ten Part One, here.] If so, there is an extremely high probability that even the soundest-seeming DM-claim only appears to be correct, or the very latest, 'best' and 'well-confirmed' DM-'abstraction' only looks authentic, when neither are. That is especially so in relation to a theory that promotes the belief that 'appearances' are deceptive since they not only fail to match 'reality', they somehow 'contradict' it --, as we are about to find out.42

 

Unfortunately, just as soon as the virus-like distinction between 'appearance' and 'reality' is introduced into the equation, the downfall of any theory that lays out a welcome mat for it is all but guaranteed. Indeed, for that theory, the hour of its birth is the hour of its death.

 

Even more ironic: this is one idea that actually does 'self-develop', but not in a positive or encouraging direction. Nor, indeed, in a way DM-theorists will find at all appealing. In fact, such an idea soon engages self-destruct mode. For if nothing in epistemology is indubitable -- save we revert to those comforting 'Cartesian certainties' (which, anyway, only seem to be secure and only appear to be reliable to those who think that ideas are somehow capable of interpreting and validating themselves, when they aren't; after all, even Descartes required 'God' to validate his 'clear and distinct' ideas!) --, then the superiority of 'thought' over 'sensation', 'essence' over 'accident' and 'reality' over 'appearance' turns out to be no less illusory -- but, only given this crazy way of picturing human cognition and the growth of knowledge.

 

In which case, alongside misleading phenomena we now have to contend with even more dubious DM-theories and their associated, uncheckable 'abstractions'. And, like it or not, these increasingly suspect theories are totally incapable of providing a secure basis for any attempt to explain of the "true nature" of all those equally shaky 'appearances'. If an apparently correct -- possibly incorrect -- theory, which is incapable of guaranteeing an accurate interpretation of 'misleading phenomena', a demonstrably defective theory (such as DM) stands no chance.

 

Oscillate dialectically as much as you like -- between 'thought' and 'appearance', 'essence' and 'accident', 'reality' and 'illusion', 'fact' and 'fantasy' -- loop the 'dialectical loop' all day long, it matters not. Traditional concepts like these -- i.e., "essence", "reality", "appearance", "theory", "objectivity", and their ilk -- are forever lost in this 'shadowy world' of misleading 'semblances'.43

 

So, it now clear that the 'dialectical circuit' locks DM in a steady orbit around permanently questionable 'appearances'. Hence, for any given DM-theorist who employs problematic concepts like these, the supposed route that leads to the formation of abstract theory and back again (via practice), as a way of delving behind phenomena in order to uncover hidden "essence", is forever blocked. For just as soon as a single DM-abstraction is penned, typed, thought about or spoken, it enters and then remains trapped in this world of 'faded simulacra'.

 

In response, it could be objected that, contrary to the above dialecticians locate the process of abstraction in thought. That links it with theory and hence (at least intentionally) with essence, not appearance. So all those earlier, anti-DM conclusions are completely misguided.

 

But, that pro-DM-rebuttal is itself misconceived, for 'thought' (as DM-theorists themselves view it) only becomes objective in practice. 'Thought' doesn't become 'objective' if it remains confined to an inner, mental or 'abstract antechamber'. It has to enter the phenomenal world via expression (in language), subsequently confirmed in practice. Minimally, a DM-'thought' (at the very least) has to be vocalised, typed or written down if it is to be acted upon or tested and thereby be allowed mature into 'objectivity' (where possible sand howsoever 'relative' it is). Unfortunately, given this way of depicting the 'process of abstraction' and its growth into 'objectivity', it has to manifest itself in 'extra-mental reality', in the phenomenal world we see around us -- it has to emerge into a world where 'appearances' are both judge and jury. In that case, any material representation or expression of a DM-'thought' -- and any attempt to test it in practice -- must negotiate its peace with them.

 

Unfortunately once more, given the traditional approach to cognition and the growth of knowledge (outlined above), the world of 'appearances' is an unsympathetic, unforgiving and unrelenting taskmaster.

 

Moreover, if the (additional) restrictions that DM places on 'thought' are now taken into account (i.e., the requirement that theories must be tested in practice), there turns out to be no way of corroborating a single DM-proposition -- at least, none that hasn't already been compromised by the 'reality'/'appearance' distinction (briefly described in the last few paragraphs). That would be all the more so if the 'asymptotic approach' metaphor is thrown in for good measure -- which, as we have also seen, reveals that DM collapses into a radical form of scepticism. Furthermore, as we also discovered was the case with 'thought', confirmation isn't self-certifying, either. It, too, has to be carried out in this 'vale of appearances', where practice also takes place. Hence, any test of a theory must be carried out there, in the 'unreliable world of appearances'. If so, practice, even if it were a test of truth, can't provide DM-epistemology with a 'get-out-of-any-need-to-appeal-to-appearances-free' card.

 

Negotiate this rusty old DM-banger around as many dialectical bends as you like, it makes no difference. It still ends-up wrapped around the same old post of 'untrustworthy appearances'.

 

[Apologies are owed the reader for all these mixed metaphors!]

 

 

Figure Nine: Dialectics 0 - Reality 1

 

And that is just one more reason why genuine materialists distrust the Idealist nostrums DM-fans have unwisely imported into Marxism, courtesy of that Hermetic Harebrain, Hegel. Indeed, as we have discovered, this dialectical muddle is a direct consequence of the appropriation of ideas that grew out of Traditional Metaphysics. In the present case, it involves ideas associated with the 'appearance'/'reality' and 'essence'/'appearance' distinctions.

 

Naturally, that doesn't mean an HM-analysis of Capitalism, for example, is incapable of distinguishing between genuinely exploitative relations and the false beliefs workers (and others) form of them --, nor does it prevent a successful explanation being given why workers form, or accept, contradictory ideas as a result.44 But, it does mean that revolutionaries may successfully do so only when the confused, class-compromised categories of Traditional Philosophy and DM are completely abandoned.

 

And good riddance, too...

 

Appendix One

 

Ollman's Traditionalism

 

Initial Disappointment

 

[This used to form part of Note 24.]

 

I have added the following extended criticism of a core section of one of Bertell Ollman's books -- i.e., Ollman (2003), pp.59-112; the material also appears in Ollman (1993), pp.23-83 -- because several comrades recommended it as an excellent exposition of the 'process of abstraction'.

 

[A recent example of this can be found here, where I have also posted several objections. (Unfortunately, those links now appear to have died!)]

 

In the above book Ollman outlined his interpretation of Marx's use of "abstraction" (and its cognates), however, Ollman's readers will surely be forgiven their acute sense of disappointment that, after the opening fanfare (i.e., to the effect that 'abstraction' is a key concept in Marx's analysis of Capitalism -- in fact, the word "abstraction" and its cognates appear over 590 times in Ollman's book alone, which is far more times than Marx used the term in all three volumes of Das Kapital!), no actual account is given of the 'process' itself, that is, over and above the usual, by-now-familiar handful of superficial gestures and vague references to 'mental acts' and 'mental constructs' that are somehow involved.

 

Here, for instance, is Ollman's opening salvo:

 

"First and foremost, and stripped of all qualifications added by this or that dialectician, the subject of dialectics is change, all change, and interaction, all kinds and degrees of interaction. This is not to say that dialectical thinkers recognize the existence of change and interaction, while non-dialectical thinkers do not. That would be foolish. Everyone recognizes that everything in the world changes, somehow and to some degree, and that the same holds true for interaction. The problem is how to think adequately about them, how to capture them in thought. How, in other words, can we think about change and interaction so as not to miss or distort the real changes and interactions that we know, in a general way at least, are there (with all the implications this has for how to study them and to communicate what we find to others)? This is the key problem addressed by dialectics, this is what all dialectics is about, and it is in helping to resolve this problem that Marx turns to the process of abstraction." [Ollman (2003), pp.59-60. Bold emphasis added. We also found out in Part One of Essay Three that Andrew Sayer's attempt to characterise the 'process of abstraction' was no less disappointing.]

 

But, we have already seen that neither dialecticians nor their 'theory' can actually explain change. Indeed, it turns out that if DM were true, change would be impossible (why that is so is explained in Essays Five through Eight Part Three, but especially here and here). In addition, it has also been shown (throughout much of  Essay Three Parts One and Two), that no sense can be made of the 'process of abstraction', either (that is, what little is known about it). So, the question remains: Has Ollman anything new to add that might turn the tide of theory back in favour of this easily discredited intellectual fossil, this left-over from Ancient Greek philosophical confusion?

 

Well, apparently not, since all he has to offer are a few pages of trite observations about what he thinks we all do when we allegedly engage in 'the process of abstraction' (supported by no evidence at all -- either quoted, cited or referenced), allied with what he thinks scientists engage in when they formulate their theories (again, supported, not by evidence, just a lively imagination).

 

[The serious philosophical difficulties that confront any attempt to define change in general (let alone construct 'abstract ideas' about it) have been be exposed below.]

 

The Highly Secretive, Mysterious, Privatised 'Process Of Abstraction'

 

The above remarks might appear a little hasty and unfair to Ollman, so, in response, it would be wise to examine in greater detail what he actually had to say about this 'process' in order to see if those comments are as prejudicial and peremptory as they might seem (to some). Here, then, is part of what he did say:

 

"In his most explicit statement on the subject, Marx claims that his method starts from the 'real concrete' (the world as it presents itself to us) and proceeds through 'abstraction' (the intellectual activity of breaking this whole down into the mental units with which we think about it) to the 'thought concrete' (the reconstituted and now understood whole present in the mind) (Marx (1904), pp.293-94; this is a reference to A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy -- RL). The real concrete is simply the world in which we live, in all its complexity. The thought concrete is Marx's reconstruction of that world in the theories of what has come to be called 'Marxism.' The royal road to understanding is said to pass from the one to the other through the process of abstraction." [Ibid., p.60. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site, as they have been in all the other passages quoted from this source. Referencing conventions changed to agree with those adopted at this site; bold emphases added.]

 

He has repeated these ideas, or something like them, more recently:

 

"If Marx's philosophy of internal relations provides us with an ontology that consists of processes and relations, the epistemology associated with it addresses the problem of how to learn about such a reality without getting overwhelmed with our findings. Marx resolves this problem with the process of abstraction, or way of singling out, or focusing on, and setting up a provisional boundary around some part(s) of the processes and relations that have come to his attention. While the qualities we perceive with our five senses really exist as parts of nature, the conceptual distinctions that tell us where one 'thing' ends and the next one begins, both in space and across time, are also social and mental constructs. However great the influence of what the world is on where we draw these boundaries, it is ultimately we who draw them, and people in different cultures and from different philosophical traditions, and/or with different goals in mind, will draw them different, whether a little or a lot. There are several other senses in which Marx uses the term 'abstraction,' but for our purposes this is the most important one." [Ollman (2019), p.99. Bold emphases added; quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

So, according to Ollman, abstraction is a method by means of which we aim to break down the "real concrete" into manageable "mental units", which can be used to "think about" the world and then presumably theorise about it). But, how we actually do this is passed over in total silence.

 

No surprise there, then...

 

If we all do it, it should be child's play to set out how we perform this universal trick. Or so my readers might naively think...

 

But, Ollman is following a well-trodden path whereby those who claim there is such a 'process' remain tight-lipped about how we actually go about 'processing abstractions' in our 'minds'.

 

If someone aims to tell you how to bake a cake, assemble a bunk bed, mix a cocktail or build a house, they will also provide you with a detailed description of the steps you need to take, in what order they should be performed and what implements/tools/skills you will need, etc., etc. Here, for instance, is a one such that sets out how to bake a cake, with all the steps and ingredients in plain view. Anyone who checks the latter will see no hand-waving, no side-stepping, no boorish attempts to deflect, no obscure jargon, in place of actual instructions. But, in well over two thousand years we have yet to be given even one step (never mind a series of steps) that explains how to abstract anything 'in the head', laid out for us by those who seem to think we are all natural abstractors. [Added On Edit October 2024: Having said that, I have just discovered a recent attempt made in this direction -- Laurence and Margolis (2012). I will say more about this failed endeavour in Interlude One.] And, even if we were, it should still be possible to set out in detail the steps taken when anything has been 'abstracted', just as, say, speech therapists can specify in detail the steps we take when we pronounce a given phoneme -- here are just a few examples of that. Again, readers will see no hand-waving or attempts to deflect. But the 'abstractionist community' is totally silent on this, and have been for centuries. When pressed in debate to specify the steps that need to be taken we witness little other than animated hand-waving, partisan special pleading and repeated attempts to deflect from DM-fans.

 

How odd...

 

[Anyone who disagrees with the above rather sweeping generalisation is invited to email me with the contrary details.]

 

Interlude One: Failed Attempt To Show There Actually Is A 'Process Of Abstraction'

 Under Construction...

 

 

~~~~~~oOo~~~~~~

 

In addition, it is difficult to see how this 'process' can begin with the "real concrete", since anything thought to be "concrete" ("real", or otherwise) can only be declared to be such at the end of an infinite epistemological journey:

 

"'Fundamentally, we can know only the infinite.' In fact all real exhaustive knowledge consists solely in raising the individual thing in thought from individuality into particularity and from this into universality, in seeking and establishing the infinite in the finite, the eternal in the transitory…. All true knowledge of nature is knowledge of the eternal, the infinite, and essentially absolute… The cognition of the infinite…can only take place in an infinite asymptotic progress." [Engels (1954), pp.234-35. Bold emphasis alone added; paragraphs merged.]

 

"The identity of thinking and being, to use Hegelian language, everywhere coincides with your example of the circle and the polygon. Or the two of them, the concept of a thing and its reality, run side by side like two asymptotes, always approaching each other but never meeting. This difference between the two is the very difference which prevents the concept from being directly and immediately reality and reality from being immediately its own concept. Because a concept has the essential nature of the concept and does not therefore prima facie directly coincide with reality, from which it had to be abstracted in the first place, it is nevertheless more than a fiction, unless you declare that all the results of thought are fictions because reality corresponds to them only very circuitously, and even then approaching it only asymptotically…. In other words, the unity of concept and phenomenon manifests itself as an essentially infinite process, and that is what it is, in this case as in all others." [Engels to Schmidt (12/03/1895), in Marx and Engels (1975b), pp.457-58, and Marx and Engels (2004), pp.463-64. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"Cognition is the eternal, endless approximation of thought to the object." [Lenin (1961), p.195. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"Shachtman obviously does not take into account the distinction between the abstract and the concrete. Striving toward concreteness, our mind operates with abstractions. Even 'this,' 'given,' 'concrete' dog is an abstraction because it proceeds to change, for example, by dropping its tail the 'moment' we point a finger at it. Concreteness is a relative concept and not an absolute one: what is concrete in one case turns out to be abstract in another: that is, insufficiently defined for a given purpose. In order to obtain a concept 'concrete' enough for a given need it is necessary to correlate several abstractions into one -- just as in reproducing a segment of life upon the screen, which is a picture in movement, it is necessary to combine a number of still photographs. The concrete is a combination of abstractions -- not an arbitrary or subjective combination but one that corresponds to the laws of the movement of a given phenomenon." [Trotsky (1971), p.147. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Paragraphs merged.]

 

As I then proceed to argue in Part One (slightly edited):

 

[Concerning concrete objects], consider a familiar enough example of one possible candidate: a cat. Is each of these furry mammals a concrete particular? DM-theorists would perhaps want to argue that a single cat isn't such until it has been comprehended against a background of all its interconnections, these being infinite in number. But, that would surely mean nothing could ever be viewed as a concrete particular, which in turn implies that nothing would be a concrete particular unless an Ideal Observer (or, Abstractor) viewed it against just such an infinite back-drop. This now suggests that concrete objects are only concrete in the Ideal limit. Here is Lenin again:

 

"A tumbler is assuredly both a glass cylinder and a drinking vessel. But there are more than these two properties and qualities or facets to it; there are an infinite number of them, an infinite number of 'mediacies' and inter-relationships with the rest of the world…. [I]f we are to have true knowledge of an object we must look at and examine all its facets, its connections and 'mediacies'. That is something we cannot ever hope to achieve completely, but the rule of comprehensiveness is a safeguard against mistakes and rigidity…. [D]ialectical logic requires that an object should be taken in development, in change, in 'self-movement' (as Hegel sometimes puts it). This is not immediately obvious in respect of such an object as a tumbler, but it, too, is in flux, and this holds especially true for its purpose, use and connection with the surrounding world." [Lenin (1921), pp.92-93. Bold emphases alone added; paragraphs merged.]

 

Perhaps this is what Lenin meant when he argued as follows:

 

"Logical concepts are subjective so long as they remain 'abstract,' in their abstract form, but at the same time they express the Thing-in-themselves. Nature is both concrete and abstract, both phenomenon and essence, both moment and relation. Human concepts are subjective in their abstractness, separateness, but objective as a whole, in the process, in the sum-total, in the tendency, in the source." [Lenin (1961) p.208. Bold emphasis alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

If that is the case with respect to familiar feline occupants of the universe, it would seem that the more we know about them the more Ideal they should appear to be! Abstract cats; who would have thought?

 

That can't be right. And yet it looks like that is the clear implication of this rather odd approach to knowledge....

 

On the other hand, if this approach is correct, it looks like the class of concrete objects would: (i) Only ever have aspiring, but never successful, members, or it would (ii) Look increasingly ephemeral, resembling a metaphysical version of the Cheshire Cat -- the more we knew about this class, or this Cheshire Cat, the less substantial it would appear to be....

 

Worse still, both of these terms (i.e., "abstract" and "concrete") appear to be abstract themselves. Neither would pass, for example, TAR's 'gastronomic test': "no one has ever eaten, tasted, smelt, seen or heard" either of these 'concepts'. [Rees (1998), p.131.] To be sure, when vocalised or committed to paper these two words are material objects in their own right, but that fact alone can't ground 'the content' of either of them in the material world, nor can it legitimate their use. If it could, we should all have to start believing in "God" just as soon as that word had been spoken aloud or written down somewhere.

 

Far worse than that: according to Lenin it now seems that no one could even "eat (etc.)" a single concrete object:

 

"But there are more than these two properties and qualities or facets to [any material object]; there are an infinite number of them, an infinite number of 'mediacies' and inter-relationships with the rest of the world…. [I]f we are to have true knowledge of an object we must look at and examine all its facets, its connections and 'mediacies'. That is something we cannot ever hope to achieve completely…. [D]ialectical logic requires that an object should be taken in development, in change, in 'self-movement' (as Hegel sometimes puts it). This is not immediately obvious in respect of such an object as a tumbler, but it, too, is in flux, and this holds especially true for its purpose, use and connection with the surrounding world." [Lenin (1921), pp.92-93. Italic emphases in the original; paragraphs merged.]

 

If not even an everyday tumbler is concrete unless it has been set against, and then interlinked with, an "infinite number of mediacies", who is there alive that could swear truthfully that a tumbler is in fact concrete? Assuming these connections are "infinite", then no matter how many interconnections we set up for it, there will always be an infinite number still left to connect, leaving any judgement we make about it stranded infinitely far from the truth with an infinitely high probability of being false.

 

[The response that only 'relevant' connections should be considered in this regard has been batted out of the park in Essay Ten Part One, here.]

 

Clearly, whatever applies to tumblers applies equally well to things we think we can eat; perhaps they aren't concrete, either? In that case, TAR's 'gastronomic, touchy-feely test' fails to pick out even concrete objects! If so, how it can be used to test whether something is 'abstract' or 'concrete', or distinguish the one from the other, is far from clear, to say the least.

 

Of course, it could be argued that whether we know it or not, concrete objects are still concrete for all that. But are they? Who says? And where is the infinite body of knowledge which would be needed to substantiate a 'cosmically' bold (abstract) claim such as that? Moreover, if Lenin is right that "all truth is concrete, never abstract", then the abstract claim that "whether we know it or not, concrete objects are still concrete" can't itself be true.

 

Such are the 'consolations' of 'dialectics'.

 

For example: Is, say, the apple you might pluck from a tree or buy in a shop now actually interconnected with everything in reality? Lest an impatient dialectician is tempted to snap back a hasty "Yes, of course it is!" in response to such an impertinent question, it is worth pointing out that that fact (if it is one) could never itself be confirmed, but must either be imposed on the said apple or accepted as an article of faith. In that case, whatever it is that dialecticians now claim they know about allegedly concrete objects (like that apple) must, it seems, be foisted on them, too, since no one at present would or could ever be justified in calling anything "concrete" unless they had pointed to the infinite number of "mediacies" Lenin insisted were required to that end, or had actually gathered that amount of evidence in support of such a hyper-bold contention:

 

"But there are more than these two properties and qualities or facets to [any material object]; there are an infinite number of them, an infinite number of 'mediacies' and inter-relationships with the rest of the world…. [I]f we are to have true knowledge of an object we must look at and examine all its facets, its connections and 'mediacies'. That is something we cannot ever hope to achieve completely…." [Ibid., bold added.]

 

Do we have this much information about apples?

 

Could we cope with it even if we had?

 

Again, if Lenin were right that "all truth is concrete, never abstract", then the abstract claim that the aforementioned apple is "actually interconnected with everything in reality" can't itself be true -- whenever it is asserted this side of the completion of the above infinitary task.

 

If we can't even eat a 'concrete apple', how is it possible to begin with the 'concrete'? Only when the above 'infinite journey' has been completed (which, of course, can't happen), will anyone be able to say with certainty that a dog, a table or even an apple is 'concrete'. This is one of the least appreciated consequences of trying to 'invert' Hegelian Idealism: material reality may only be 'comprehended' by beginning at the end!

 

Wherever the truth lies (and good luck trying to extract a clear answer on this or any other issue connected with 'dialectics' from a DM-fan!), we have seen that the way the 'process of abstraction' has consistently been characterised by Traditional Theorists (like Ollman) means it is an individualised, 'mental' skill that (as we have also shown) completely undermines the social nature of knowledge and language.

 

Just like Ollman, Andrew Sayer's attempt to characterise this 'process' reveals that he, too, thinks it is an individualised, private skill in relation to which we all seem to be 'natural' experts:

 

"The sense in which the term ['abstract' -- RL] is used here is different [from its ordinary use -- RL]; an abstract concept, or an abstraction, isolates in thought a one-sided or partial aspect of an object." [Sayer (1992), p.87. In a footnote, Sayer adds "My use of 'abstract' and 'concrete' is, I think, equivalent to Marx's" (p.277, note 3). Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Bold emphasis alone added. The page numbers are completely different in the Second Corrected Edition, i.e., Sayer (2010), p.59 and p.187, respectively.]

 

As was the case with Ollman -- and, indeed, everyone else who has written about this obscure 'process' (many of whom have been quoted in both Parts of Essay Three) --, we aren't told by Sayer how anyone manages to do this, still less why it doesn't result in the construction of a 'private language'.

 

Indeed, this is something Ollman himself pointed out:

 

"What, then, is distinctive about Marx's abstractions? To begin with, it should be clear that Marx's abstractions do not and cannot diverge completely from the abstractions of other thinkers both then and now. There has to be a lot of overlap. Otherwise, he would have constructed what philosophers call a 'private language,' and any communication between him and the rest of us would be impossible. How close Marx came to fall into this abyss and what can be done to repair some of the damage already done are questions I hope to deal with in a later work...." [Ollman (2003), p.63. Bold emphasis added.]

 

Well, it remains to be seen if Professor Ollman can solve a problem that has baffled everyone else for centuries -- that is, of those who have even so much as acknowledged it exists!

 

It is to Ollman's considerable credit, therefore, that he is at least aware of it.

 

In fact, Ollman is the very first dialectician I have encountered (in nigh on thirty years) who even acknowledges this 'difficulty'!

 

[Be this as it may, I have devoted Essay Thirteen Part Three to an analysis of this topic; the reader is referred there for more details. Update November  2024: After over 21 years waiting there is still no sign of Ollman's 'solution' to this 'problem'. Certainly, no attempt is made in Ollman (2019) to address this 'problem', let alone solve it. Nor is there any indication that others have risen to this challenge on his behalf -- or that a single DM-fan (since Ollman raised this issue) regards it as a 'difficulty' that even needs addressing! One Academic Marxist with whom I debated this very topic a few years ago completely ducked the issue and showed no sign he was aware of it, never mind how to deal with it. Nor was he cognisant of the serious challenge 'abstractionism' poses for anyone who at least says they accept the social nature of language and knowledge.]

 

Of course, none of this fancy footwork would be necessary if Ollman acknowledged that even though Marx gestured in its direction HM doesn't need this obscure 'process', and the fact that Marx's emphasis on the social nature of knowledge and language completely undercuts abstractionism.

 

[Nor does Ollman appear to take into consideration Marx's own refutation of this 'process' (in The Holy Family). In fact, he doesn't even mention it.]

 

Nevertheless, the few things Ollman does say about this topic hardly inspire much confidence:

 

"In one sense, the role Marx gives to abstraction is simple recognition of the fact that all thinking about reality begins by breaking it down into manageable parts. Reality may be in one piece when lived, but to be thought about and communicated it must be parcelled out. Our minds can no more swallow the world whole at one sitting than can our stomachs. Everyone then, and not just Marx and Marxists, begins the task of trying to make sense of his or her surroundings by distinguishing certain features and focusing on and organizing them in ways deemed appropriate. 'Abstract' comes from the Latin, 'abstrahere', which means 'to pull from.' In effect, a piece has been pulled from or taken out of the whole and is temporarily perceived as standing apart. We 'see' only some of what lies in front of us, 'hear' only part of the noises in our vicinity, 'feel' only a small part of what our body is in contact with, and so on through the rest of our senses. In each case, a focus is established and a kind of boundary set within our perceptions distinguishing what is relevant from what is not. It should be clear that 'What did you see?' (What caught your eye?) is a different question from 'What did you actually see?' (What came into your line of vision?). Likewise, in thinking about any subject, we focus on only some of its qualities and relations. Much that could be included -- that may in fact be included in another person's view or thought, and may on another occasion be included in our own -- is left out. The mental activity involved in establishing such boundaries, whether conscious or unconscious -- though it is usually an amalgam of both -- is the process of abstraction.

 

"Responding to a mixture of influences that include the material world and our experiences in it as well as to personal wishes, group interests, and other social constraints, it is the process of abstraction that establishes the specificity of the objects with which we interact. In setting boundaries, in ruling this far and no further, it is what makes something one (or two, or more) of a kind, and lets us know where that kind begins and ends. With this decision as to units, we also become committed to a particular set of relations between them -- relations made possible and even necessary by the qualities that we have included in each -- a register for classifying them, and a mode for explaining them. In listening to a concert, for example, we often concentrate on a single instrument or recurring theme and then redirect our attention elsewhere. Each time this occurs, the whole music alters, new patterns emerge, each sound takes on a different value, etc. How we understand the music is largely determined by how we abstract it. The same applies to what we focus on when watching a play, whether on a person, or a combination of persons, or a section of the stage. The meaning of the play and what more is required to explore or test that meaning alters, often dramatically, with each new abstraction. In this way, too, how we abstract literature, where we draw the boundaries, determines what works and what parts of each work will be studied, with what methods, in relation to what other subjects, in what order, and even by whom. Abstracting literature to include its audience, for example, leads to a sociology of literature, while an abstraction of literature that excludes everything but its forms calls forth various structural approaches, and so on." [Ollman (2003), pp.60-61. Bold emphases added. Minor typo corrected; several paragraphs merged.]

 

As far as can be ascertained, that is all Ollman has to say about the 'process of abstraction' as such -- as opposed to lengthy comments about how Marx (supposedly) employed it.

 

Now, anyone reading through the above passage will surely conclude that Ollman has totally forgotten about the social nature of knowledge, just as they will note he has confused paying attention, or paying heed, with abstraction. Sure, he gestured in the direction of acknowledging the social nature of knowledge -- for instance, with his comment that we must factor in "group interests, and other social constraints", but how this helps turn an individual 'aptitude' into a socially-conditioned skill is left entirely unclear. That isn't at all surprising since it is impossible to pull this trick off. For example, how would it be possible for Abstractor A to ensure that she has abstracted anything in the same way as Abstractor B, or even had obtained the same results? As we have just seen, Ollman himself made a note of this 'problem' -- but failed to address, let alone solve, it. As such then it stands in the way of any ascent from the abstractions an individual might construct to an account being given of the social nature and origin of knowledge. Again, this should astonish few given the additional fact that this 'process' itself depends on a major concession to Bourgeois Individualism, as we have also seen. This theory implies that all that the above two abstractors have to work with are their own individual, subjective attempts to derive their own 'abstractions'. Indeed, all they have is their own private take even on "group interests, and other social constraints", and the same goes for everyone else in the this yet-to-be-identified social "group".

 

As now seems clear, neither Abstractor A nor Abstractor B has any way of comparing their results with those arrived at by each other, nor anyone else.

 

[In reply at this point it would be no good appealing to a shared language, either, for reasons set out here and here. However, since this overall topic has already been covered (in detail) here and here, I won't rake over it any more in this Appendix.]

 

Independently of that, much of what Ollman focuses on isn't under our conscious control:

 

"We 'see' only some of what lies in front of us, 'hear' only part of the noises in our vicinity, 'feel' only a small part of what our body is in contact with, and so on through the rest of our senses. In each case, a focus is established and a kind of boundary set within our perceptions distinguishing what is relevant from what is not. It should be clear that 'What did you see?' (What caught your eye?) is a different question from 'What did you actually see?' (What came into your line of vision?)." [Ibid.]

 

But, 'abstraction', at least as Ollman and other DM-theorists seem to conceive it, is supposed to be under our conscious control. It is something we not only do, we intend to do it. For example, as we will see, dialecticians (en masse) tend to focus on a specific concept that Marx himself dealt with -- "the population" -- which they also try to force through a series of 'dialectical hoops'. But, since the above passage deals with 'processes' that aren't always under our conscious control, much of it appears to have nothing to do with 'abstraction' in the 'dialectical' sense of that word.

 

Of course, it could be argued that in the last analysis the 'process of abstraction' isn't under our conscious control (i.e., it is involuntary, rather like belief-formation), but if that were the case, much of what Ollman and others have to say about this 'process' would become even more obscure. The question is "Was Marx consciously 'abstracting' when he spoke about this 'process' applied to 'the population'?" If not, what sort of 'intellectual exercise' was he describing in when he wrote the following?

 

"It seems correct to begin with the real and the concrete…with e.g. the population…. However, on closer examination this proves false. The population is an abstraction if I leave out, for example, the classes of which it is composed. These classes in turn are an empty phrase if I am not familiar with the elements on which they rest…. Thus, if I were to begin with the population, this would be a chaotic conception of the whole, and I would then, by further determination, move toward ever more simple concepts, from the imagined concrete towards ever thinner abstractions until I had arrived at the simplest determinations. From there the journey would have to be retraced until I had finally arrived at the population again, but this time not as the chaotic conception of a whole, but as a rich totality of many determinations and relations…. The latter is obviously scientifically the correct method. The concrete is concrete because it is the concentration of many determinations, hence the unity of the diverse." [Marx (1973), pp.100-01. Bold emphases added.]

 

It seems impossible to interpret the above highlighted words as if they depicted an involuntary, or non-voluntary, psychological event (i.e., one not under his conscious control, something that just ran through Marx's mind like pain perception, a headache, a daydream or a hypnotic episode -- or even most emotions -- for example). If that were so --, and it is worth underlining that the above passage is widely regarded among dialecticians as a paradigm example of the 'process of abstraction' in action --, the conclusion seems inescapable: this 'process' is voluntary (i.e., it is (supposedly) under our conscious control) and intentional (i.e., we (reputedly) know what we are doing when we 'abstract something' and it is goal-directed -- that is, there is a (hypothetical) point to such 'mental activity', an aim we have in mind when we so indulge).

 

[As noted above, I will return to consider this passage in more detail, later.]

 

None of this should be taken to mean that we can't intentionally focus on something in our line of sight, or in our immediate surroundings -- or that, to some extent, we can't selectively 'shut out'/'block' certain sounds, events or 'objects' --, but when Ollman says "We 'see' only some of what lies in front of us, 'hear' only part of the noises in our vicinity, 'feel' only a small part of what our body is in contact with, and so on through the rest of our senses", he isn't speaking about intentional behaviour, but about episodes that aren't, or aren't always, under our conscious control. So, once again, it seems that what Ollman has to say in the above passage can't be used to illustrate 'the process of abstraction dialectically' -- or, at least, not without undermining other things he says or implies about this 'process'.

 

Again, an appeal to a public language here (as a way out of this impasse) would be to no avail since this theory undermines the very possibility that there is or could be any such language. That is because it bases language acquisition, as well as meaning in language, on 'the process of abstraction' itself. In which case, anyone who accepts this theory can hardly appeal to language to bail it out -- at least, not without arguing in a circle.

 

[I have explained why the 'process of abstraction' also forms part of a (bourgeois individualist) theory of meaning here, here and here -- and hence why it is inconsistent with the standard Marxist theory that language and knowledge are both social.]

 

As noted above, this entire approach is entangled in, and has been compromised by, post-Renaissance, bourgeois individualist theories of language, cognition and the formation of knowledge, which picture them as dispositions, aptitudes and skills we all activate, acquire or learn as socially-, and psychologically-isolated individuals. Given that view, we are later supposed to bring the results of these individually-shaped dispositions, aptitudes and skills back into society (acting as 'social atoms') in order to compare, or share, the 'contents of our minds' with those that others have also brought with them into this 'market place of ideas' in 'the same way'. Given this family of theories, the individual is ranked first in the epistemological pecking order (as it were), the social last. Hence, given this approach, we act and learn as 'social atoms', first, and then attempt to transform ourselves into 'social molecules', second. This is the abstractionist version of Margaret Thatcher's, "There is no such thing as society". No wonder Ollman expressed genuine concerns about abstraction and the formation of a private language, since that would be a direct result of this theory, just as it is of much else that surfaced in post-Renaissance Epistemology.

 

[There is more on this in Essay Thirteen Part Three. As we have also found out, the two major wings of post-Renaissance thought -- Rationalism and Empiricism -- depend on and promote Bourgeois Individualism, and thereby the formation of private languages. What was that again about the "ideas of the ruling class"...? I keep forgetting.]

 

As Meredith Williams pointed out in relation to Vygotsky's theory (whose ideas are, alas, highly influential among dialecticians):

 

"Vygotsky attempts to combine a social theory of cognition development with an individualistic account of word-meaning.... [But] the social theory of development can only succeed if it is combined with a social theory of meaning." [Williams (1999b), p.275. Bold emphasis added.]

 

Williams could in fact be talking about any randomly-selected Dialectical Marxist who has written on this subject (including Ollman).

 

Again, these comments might still seem a little too hasty, so we will have to wait to see how (or if) Ollman manages to dig himself out of this particular, bourgeois-individualist hole. [As of November 2024, there is no sign he has even attempted so to do!]

 

Independently of this, Ollman has surely confused the capacity we have for concentrating on certain aspects of the world and our environment with the 'process of abstraction' itself. So, to take his example, when we attend a concert we might indeed concentrate on the soloist, for instance, but we don't abstract him or her. Concentrating on a musician doesn't result in the production of abstract particulars, abstract general ideas or the Proper Names thereof, which the 'process of abstraction' is typically supposed to do. How is focussing on a soloist connected with anything general? In fact it seems to do the opposite; it means we concentrate on a single item in out environment, not the general. What would a 'general soloist' even look/sound like? In fact, focusing on one part or one aspect of an orchestra seems a long way from ascending from the particular (the 'real concrete'?) to the general (the 'thought concrete'?), which is how Ollman pictures the 'process itself, as we saw earlier:

 

"In his most explicit statement on the subject, Marx claims that his method starts from the 'real concrete' (the world as it presents itself to us) and proceeds through 'abstraction' (the intellectual activity of breaking this whole down into the mental units with which we think about it) to the 'thought concrete' (the reconstituted and now understood whole present in the mind) (Marx (1904), pp.293-94; this is a reference to A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy -- RL). The real concrete is simply the world in which we live, in all its complexity. The thought concrete is Marx's reconstruction of that world in the theories of what has come to be called 'Marxism.' The royal road to understanding is said to pass from the one to the other through the process of abstraction." [Ollman (2003), p.60. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site; bold emphases added.]

 

In what way does focusing on a soloist, for example, actually illustrate this 'process', even if we believed in it?

 

It might be objected that this is precisely where abstraction kicks in.

 

Quite apart from still being in the dark about this 'process' -- how it actually works, as opposed to a few vague references to it -- what exactly is gained by saying any of this that the word "concentrate" hasn't already achieve for us? What extra feature does the alleged 'process of abstraction' now add? Again, Ollman doesn't say. In fact, this 'crucially important process' stalls at that point. It has nowhere to go and nothing to work with (as the earlier sections of this Essay have demonstrated). Again: does listening to a concert produce a single abstract particular? Or one 'abstract general idea'? Or even the Proper Name thereof? What 'abstract general idea' has anyone ever cobbled-together by listening to a Beethoven or a Mozart concert? If anyone has ever managed to do this, Ollman unwisely failed to pass the details on to his readers.

 

This is quite apart from the fact that even when we concentrate on the soloist, for instance, the rest of the orchestra doesn't become silent or disappear. But, that is the exact opposite of what is supposed to happen when we 'succeed' in 'abstracting' something. When we allegedly abstract the general concept, CAT, from the individual cat, Tiddles -- or from an array of cats -- what happened to its individual colour, its smell, its fleas (if it has any)? They all vanish like an icicle in boiling water -- but not like the rest of the orchestra.

 

As Frege noted (in his review of Husserl's Philosophy of Arithmetic -- quoted earlier):

 

"Abstraction

 

"The author himself finds a difficulty about the abstraction that provides the general concept of the collective. He says (p.84):

 

'The peculiarities of the individual contents that are collected...must be completely abstracted from, but at the same time their connection must be maintained. This seems to involve a difficulty, if not a psychological impossibility. If we take the abstraction seriously, then the individual contents vanish, and so, naturally, does their collective unity, instead of remaining behind as a conceptual extract. The solution is obvious. To abstract from something simply means: not to attend to it specially.' 

 

"The kernel of this explanation is obviously to be found in the word 'specially'. Inattention is a very strong lye; it must be applied at not too great a concentration, so that everything does not dissolve, and likewise not too dilute, so that it effects a sufficient change in the things. Thus it is a question of getting the right degree of dilution; this is difficult to manage, and I at any rate have never succeeded.... [Detaching our attention] is particularly effective. We attend less to a property, and it disappears. By making one characteristic after another disappear, we get more and more abstract concepts…. Inattention is a most efficacious logical faculty; presumably this accounts for the absentmindedness of professors. Suppose there are a black and a white cat sitting side by side before us. We stop attending to their colour, and they become colourless, but are still sitting side by side. We stop attending to their posture, and they are no longer sitting (though they have not assumed another posture), but each one is still in its place. We stop attending to position; they cease to have place, but still remain different. In this way, perhaps, we obtain from each one of them a general concept of Cat. By continual application of this procedure, we obtain from each object a more and more bloodless phantom. Finally we thus obtain from each object a something wholly deprived of content; but the something obtained from one object is different from the something obtained from another object -- though it is not easy to say how." [Frege (1980), pp.84-85. Bold emphases alone added; several paragraphs merged.]

 

Of course, no one begins with such skills (in this case, an ability to listen attentively to classical music). We all have to be socialised into acquiring any such, just as we have to be taught what our words mean (or we have to be shown by repeated use and example). We can see this from the way that individuals from other cultures focus on different aspects of their surroundings, especially with respect to music. [On that see, for instance, Wong, et al (2012). This something Ollman admits anyway -- pp.13-14.] In relation to music we all have to develop 'trained ears'. Rather like beer and Marmite, love of music we might never have heard before is an acquired taste -- or in this instance, an acquired ear -- and even then, it's not for everyone. So, even if there were such a 'process of abstraction', it wouldn't be needed, for we already have the skills necessary to advance knowledge using these socially-acquired, socially-taught, socially-reinforced skills, propensities and capacities. Moreover, the latter possess the not inconsiderable advantage that they follow from, but do not undermine, the social nature of language and knowledge. [In fact, they are predicted on both.] All are learned, developed, tested and performed in the open, in social contexts. [Of course, after they have been acquired they can be performed in private, just as after we all learn to speak, we can engage in private, even silent, episodes of soliloquy -- on this, see Squires (1974).] Which means that they can not only be checked in the open they can be shared. By way of contrast, abstraction (supposedly) takes place in a hidden, inner world where the bourgeois individual holds sway -- and where testing has no jurisdiction and sharing thereby becomes impossible.

 

Someone might object that we manage to do many things in our heads -- such as mental arithmetic -- but that doesn't mean we can't know or share the results or make sense of them. The same is the case with abstraction.

 

Or so it could be argued...

 

There are several problems with that attempted rebuttal (the following material is also relevant to an earlier discussion regarding 'thought experiments' and idealisation is science):

 

[1] I have devoted much of Essay Thirteen Part Three [Sections (2) through (6)] to undermining the idea that we 'do' anything at all 'in our heads'/'brains'. Readers are directed there for more details. [That isn't to say that nothing happens in our heads, only that we do not do anything there. When was the last time you intentionally activated a specific brain cell or re-directed an electric impulse between neurons? On whether or not we use our brains, see here.]

 

[2] Even if it were true that 'mental arithmetic' is performed 'in the head', it in no way resembles the 'process of abstraction'. With 'mental arithmetic' we aren't dealing with symbols that have been 'abstracted into existence' in the way that supporters of abstractionism imagine is the case with the words they use. For example, how on earth would it be possible to abstract into existence the number two? You would need to be able to count to two correctly first so that you knew you were abstracting the right number to begin with and hadn't mistaken it for, say, three! How would it be possible to abstract zero? Or negative numbers? Or a real number, like π? Or a Hermite Polynomial and an Abelian Group?

 

[Readers mustn't confuse "the number zero" with "nothing", for, as Blaise Pascal pointed out, if "zero" meant the same as "nothing" then 1 and 10 would be the same since, on this assumption, they would both be one followed by nothing. If so, zero can't be 'abstracted' from nothing. It can't be what every example of nothing has in common -- since it has nothing to do with nothing [Irony intended.] If it were what every instance of nothing had in common, one would equal ten! In fact, if we really must talk this way, any single (assumed) instantiation of nothing in our imagination (or wherever) would also instantiate the number one -- in such circumstances, there would be one such 'instantiation of nothing'! For there to be zero instantiations of nothing there would be no instantiation of it; that is, it would fail to be an instantiation. (In the foregoing I am not conceding that it makes any sense to say that there can be an instantiation of nothing, only that there would have to be one such if nothing were to be abstracted from it! So, supporters of abstractionism would have to countenance that possibility and then explain how 'one instantiation' doesn't connote one, not zero. In which case, it is impossible to 'abstract nothing', or zero!)]

 

[3] The meaning of the symbols used and the legitimacy of the operations employed in mental arithmetic were established in the open long before anyone calculated anything 'in their head' (even if that is where we supposedly did it!). That isn't so with 'abstraction'. The meaning of any of the terms that are (allegedly) handled in 'the mind'/'head' during the 'process of abstraction' (again, assuming for the moment that that were possible) are fixed by the process itself., by their use. And that has already been established in and by the community and by mathematicians, in the open. In addition, we have no clue what 'operations' are being used by each lone abstractor (they either can't or they simply refuse to tell us!), nor have we any idea if these are legitimate 'operations', yield the 'right result' or even if there are any 'right' results for them to obtain, to begin with(!) --, unlike mental arithmetic.

 

Here is Frege on the very idea that numbers, for example, can be abstracted (this was also quoted earlier):

 

Frege's sharpest criticisms were reserved for those of his day who imagined that mathematical concepts could be created, or perhaps apprehended, by a 'process of abstraction' --, in particular, the views of the 19th century mathematician and mystical Platonist, Georg Cantor, and his followers:

 

"We may begin here by making a general observation. When negroes from the heart of Africa see a telescope or pocket watch for the first time, they are inclined to credit these things with the most astounding magical properties. Many mathematicians react to philosophical expressions in a similar manner. I am thinking in particular here of the following: 'define' (Brahma), 'reflect' (Vishnu), 'abstract' (Shiva). The names of the Indian gods in brackets are meant to indicate the kind of magical effects the expressions are supposed to have. If, for instance, you find that some property of a thing bothers you, you abstract from it. But if you want to call a halt to this process of destruction so that the properties you want to see retained should not be obliterated in the process, you reflect on these properties. If, finally, you feel sorely the lack of certain properties in the thing, you bestow them on it by definition. In your possession of these miraculous powers you are not far removed from the Almighty. The significance this would have is practically beyond measure. Think of how these powers could be put to use in the classroom: the teacher has a good-natured but lazy and stupid pupil. He will then abstract from the laziness and the stupidity, reflecting all the while on the good-naturedness. Then by means of a definition he will confer on him the properties of keenness and intelligence. Of course so far people have confined themselves to mathematics. The following dialogue may serve an illustration:

 

'Mathematician: The sign √(−1) has the property of yielding -1 when squared.

 

'Layman: This pattern of printer's ink on paper? I can't see any trace of this property. Perhaps it has been discovered with the aid of a microscope or by some chemical means?

 

'Mathematician: It can't be arrived at by any process of sense perception. And of course it isn't produced by the mere printer's ink either; a magic incantation, called a definition, has first to be pronounced over it.

 

'Layman: Ah, now I understand. You expressed yourself badly. You mean that a definition is used to stipulate that this pattern is a sign for something with those properties.

 

'Mathematician: Not at all! It is a sign, but it doesn't designate or mean anything. It itself has these properties, precisely in virtue of the definition.

 

'Layman: What extraordinary people you mathematicians are, and no mistake! You don't bother at all about the properties a thing actually has, but imagine that in their stead you can bestow a property on it by a definition -- a property that the thing in its innocence doesn't dream of -- and now you investigate the property and believe in that way you can accomplish the most extraordinary things!'

 

"This illustrates the might of the mathematical Brahma. In Cantor it is Shiva and Vishnu who receive the greater honour. Faced with a cage of mice, mathematicians react differently when the number of them is in question. Some…include in the number the mice just as they are, down to the last hair; others -- and I may surely count Cantor amongst them -- find it out of place that hairs should form part of the number and so abstract from them. They find in mice a whole host of things besides which are out of place in number and are unworthy to be included in it. Nothing simpler: one abstracts from the whole lot. Indeed when you get down to it everything in the mice is out of place: the beadiness of their eyes no less than the length of their tails and the sharpness of their teeth. So one abstracts from the nature of the mice. But from their nature as what is not said; so one abstracts presumably from all their properties, even from those in virtue of which we call them mice, even from those in virtue of which we call them animals, three-dimensional beings -- properties which distinguish them, for instance, from the number 2.

 

"Cantor demands more: to arrive at cardinal numbers, we are required to abstract from the order in which they are given. What is to be understood by this? Well, if at a certain moment we compare the positions of the mice, we see that of any two one is further to the north than the other, or that both are to the same distance to the north. The same applies to east and west and above and below. But this is not all: if we compare the mice in respect of their ages, we find likewise that of any two one is older than the other or that both have the same age. We can go on and compare them in respect of their length, both with and without their tails, in respect of the pitch of their squeaks, their weight, their muscular strength, and in many other respects besides. All these relations generate an order. We shall surely not go astray if we take it that this is what Cantor calls the order in which things are given. So we are meant to abstract from this order too. Now surely many people will say 'But we have already abstracted from their being in space; so ipso facto we have already abstracted from north and south, from difference in their lengths. We have already abstracted from the ages of the animals, and so ipso facto from one's being older than another. So why does special mention also have to be made of order?'

 

"Well, Cantor also defines what he calls an ordinal type; and in order to arrive at this, we have, so he tells us, to stop short of abstracting from the order in which the things are given. So presumably this will be possible too, though only with Vishnu's help. We can hardly dispense with this in other cases too. For the moment let us stay with the cardinal numbers.

 

"So let us get a number of men together and ask them to exert themselves to the utmost in abstracting from the nature of the pencil and the order in which its elements are given. After we have allowed them sufficient time for this difficult task, we ask the first 'What general concept…have you arrived at?' Non-mathematician that he is, he answers 'Pure Being.' The second thinks rather 'Pure nothingness', the third -- I suspect a pupil of Cantor's -- 'The cardinal number one.' A fourth is perhaps left with the woeful feeling that everything has evaporated, a fifth -- surely a pupil of Cantor's -- hears an inner voice whispering that graphite and wood, the constituents of the pencil, are 'constitutive elements', and so arrives at the general concept called the cardinal number two. Now why shouldn't one man come out with the answer and the other with another? Whether in fact Cantor's definitions have the sharpness and precision their author boasts of is accordingly doubtful to me. But perhaps we got such varying replies because it was a pencil we carried out our experiment with. It may be said 'But a pencil isn't a set.' Why not? Well then, let us look at the moon. 'The moon is not a set either!' What a pity! The cardinal number one would be only too happy to come into existence at any place and at any time, and the moon seemed the very thing to assist at the birth. Well then, let us take a heap of sand. Oh dear, there's someone already trying to separate the grains. 'You are surely not going to try and count then all! That is strictly forbidden! You have to arrive at the number by a single act of abstraction....' 'But in order to be able to abstract from the nature of a grain of sand, I must surely first have looked at it, grasped it, come to know it!' 'That's quite unnecessary. What would happen to the infinite cardinals in that case? By the time you had looked at the last grain, you would be bound to have forgotten the first ones. I must emphasise once more that you are meant to arrive at the number by a single act of abstraction. Of course for that you need the help of supernatural powers. Surely you don't imagine you can bring it off by ordinary abstraction. When you look at books, some in quarto, some in octavo, some thick, some thin, some in Gothic type and some in Roman and you abstract from these properties which distinguish them, and thus arrive at, say, the concept 'book', this, when you come down to it, is no great feat. Allow me to clarify for you the difference between ordinary abstraction and the higher, supernatural, kind.

 

"With ordinary abstraction we start out by comparing objects a, b, c, and find that they agree in many properties but differ in others. We abstract from the latter and arrive at a concept Φ under which a and b and c all fall. Now this concept has neither the properties abstracted from nor those common to a, b and c. The concept 'book', for instance, no more consists of printed sheets -- although the individual books we started by comparing do consist of such -- than the concept 'female mammal' bears young or suckles them with milk secreted from its glands; for it has no glands. Things are quite different with supernatural abstraction. Here we have, for instance, a heap of sand...." [Frege (1979), pp.69-71. Unfortunately, the manuscript breaks off at this point. Italic emphases in the original. Links added; quotation marks altered and passage reformatted to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

As I point out below, 'the process of abstraction' itself (supposedly) determines the meaning of the 'abstractions' -- or the words used to represent/express any such 'abstractions' --, so obtained. That isn't the case with 'mental arithmetic'. [However, as we have seen, DM-theorists regularly conflate words with whatever they are supposed to represent.] Unless the individual doing these calculations 'in her head' already understood the public, shared meaning of number words, how to employ them, and had been trained in the correct use of mathematical operations, she wouldn't be able to do any arithmetic, let alone any 'in her head'. We don't learn these skills individualistically, or assign our own meaning to number words and mathematical operations, piecemeal or by our own efforts. We are taught them, in the open, just as we are taught what they mean. In addition, we are subsequently tested in the open to see if we have understood these terms and operations correctly, and how to use them.

 

[Once more, to imagine otherwise would be to accept some form of bourgeois individualism, which would also, of course, undermine the social nature of language, knowledge, and now, mathematics!]

 

That is why all (who have the required arithmetical skills) are capable of comprehending the results of 'mental arithmetic'; they already understand the language of mathematics before anyone tries to do any. That isn't the case with the (supposed) formation of 'abstractions'.

 

[4] There is no social training that enables each individual to perform successfully 'the process of abstraction'; it is a quintessentially individualistic process that each intrepid abstractor has to teach herself/himself -- or which they somehow engage in 'naturally'. As I have pointed out already (slightly modified):

 

Is there a Philosophers' Rule Book to guide us? Is there an Abstractionist's Algorithm we all unconsciously (or even consciously) 'follow', somehow programmed into each of us at birth (or is it at conception)? Do we have access to a set of tried-and-tested instructions we all implicitly appear, not just to know about, but how to use/implement? Are we all instinctive abstractors, or do we need training? Are there any YouTube videos or websites that explain this process, step-by-step? [A comprehensive Google search will return a negative answer on both counts. If anyone disagrees and has found one (or even several!), please email me with the details (and links), and I'll delete much of Parts One and Two of Essay Three! Update October 2024: Since writing this, I have discovered one attempt to describe the 'process of abstraction' -- Laurence and Margolis (2012). I will say more about this failed attempt in Interlude One.] And, if it turns out that there are metaphysical disrobing protocols that determine the order in which Tiddles's qualities are to be removed from, or attributed to, her -- so that this process might be executed correctly by the entire Community of Intrepid Abstractors -- when and where did they learn them? On the other hand, if there are none, how might each aspiring abstractor know whether or not they had abstracted Tiddles the same way each time?

 

Do we all keep a (secret) Abstractor's Diary? An internal log of what we did the last time we thought about that cat -- or any cat?

 

Even if there were clear -- let alone plausible -- answers to such questions, another annoying 'difficulty' would soon block our path: it would still be impossible for anyone to check a single one of these 'abstractions' to see if they tallied with those 'produced' by anyone else -- or, for that matter, whether or not they had 'abstracted' them correctly. In fact, the word "correct" can gain no grip in such circumstances -- since, as Wittgenstein pointed out, whatever seems correct will be correct. [That would be like buying two copies of the same edition of a newspaper (on the same day) to check if the first copy had got a certain story 'right'.] But, for something to be correct it needs to be checked against a standard that isn't dependent on the subjective impression of the one doing the checking, or that relies on the very same source. And yet in relation to this 'process' and its supposed results, there is no such standard. Given this theory, everyone's notion of a cat will be private to that individual. They have no way of checking their 'abstractions' with those 'arrived at' by anyone else, which means, of course, there can be no standard, 'abstract cat' to serve as an exemplar, and hence nothing by means of which anyone's 'abstractions' might be deemed 'correct'.

 

And those strictures apply to the 'abstractions produced' by each individual abstracter. So, Abstracter E will have no way of knowing whether or not her own 'abstractions' were correct, or if they were the same as, or were different from, those 'arrived at' yesterday or even a few seconds earlier, by her! Again, it is no use appealing to memory here, since the meaning of the word "memory" is subject to the very same strictures.

 

[Of course, for anyone who accepts the HF no memory could be trusted, anyway....]

 

[HF = Heraclitean Flux.]

 

It could be objected (indeed, it has been objected by the likes of A. J. Ayer -- e.g., Ayer (1971), replied to by Rhees (1971)), that such doubts (about memory, for example) would also apply to any external or social check on the meaning or veracity of the words we use. If memory in general is thrown into question, how would anyone be able to remember the meaning of any of their words? That would appear to undermine all social theories of language and knowledge.

 

That objection misses the point. No one (other than those who accept the HF) is questioning memory, only the theory that there is a 'process of abstraction' which tells us what our words (especially general words like "memory") mean. Reject that idea, along with the traditional philosophical approach to such questions (for the reasons set out in both Parts of Essay Three, as well as Essay Twelve Part One), take Marx's advice to return to the ordinary language of the working class, and watch such pseudoproblems simply disappear....

 

Naturally, this means that there is no way this obscure process can form the basis of 'objective' science (and that remains the case even if we were to substitute "idealisation" for "abstraction"). Plainly, that is because:

 

(i) No one has access to the results of anyone else's 'mental machinations' (or 'idealisations');

 

(ii) There appear to be no rules governing the production of these 'abstractions' --, or, indeed, governing the entire 'process' itself; and, as we have just seen,

 

(iii) There is no standard of right, here.

 

By way of contrast, in the real world, agreement is invariably achieved in and by the use of publicly accessible, general terms that are already in common use, words that were present in the vernacular long before a single one of us was a twinkle in our (hypothetical) ancestral abstractors' eye.

 

[Note: I am not questioning scientific idealisation, only the claim that it is a private, internal, 'mental process'.]

 

One obvious reply to the above might be that we abstract by concentrating only on those factors that are "relevant" to the enquiry at hand. But, what are these "relevant factors"? And who decides? How might they be specified before any such enquiry even begins? Surely, in order to know what is "relevant" to the successful process of, say, 'abstracting a cat', one would already have to know how to use the general term "cat", otherwise:

 

(a) The 'abstractor' involved would have no idea what the target of her intended abstractive endeavours actually was supposed to be; and,

 

(b) The accuracy of any 'abstractions' that might emerge as a result would rightly be called into question, alongside several more such concerning the competency of the abstractor herself.

 

If the abstractor in question doesn't already know how to use the word "cat", what faith can be put in anything she subsequently 'abstracts', or even reports about these 'abstractions'? On the other hand, if each intrepid abstractor already knows how to use the word "cat" (in order to 'abstract' the 'right' object), one might well wonder what the point is of trying to 'abstract' that furry mammal in the first place? It would seem to be about as pointless as checking to see if you know your own name by looking it up in a telephone directory or on the Internet.

 

[Anyway, we have already seen that the 'process of abstraction' requires knowledge of the very concepts being 'abstracted' before they were 'abstracted', vitiating the entire exercise.]

 

Again, in response it could be argued that past experience guides us. But, how does it do that? Can any of us recall being asked about, or made to study, the heroic deeds of intrepid abstractors from the days of yore? Does past experience transform itself into a sort of personal Microsoft Office Assistant -- or these days, maybe, Cortana -- if we hit the right internal 'Help' key? But, what kind of explanation would that be of the supposedly intelligent 'process of abstraction' if it requires such a guiding hand? And where on earth did this 'inner PA' receive its training?

 

Once more, it could be objected that in the investigation of, say, the biology of cats, it is important for scientists to find out what these animals have in common with other members of the same species, family, order, class and phylum, so that relevant generalisations might be made about them. In order to do that, zoologists disregard (or attribute) certain features common to cats and concentrate on those they share with other mammals, vertebrates, living organisms, and so on --, be they morphological, ecological, behavioural, genetic or biochemical (etc.). Clearly, in each case, and at each stage, greater abstraction is required.

 

Or, so a response might try to maintain...

 

Nevertheless, if this is what "abstraction" means, it is surely synonymous with a publicly accessible and checkable set of behavioural/linguistic skills and performances, similar in all but name to description, analysis and classification (etc.). It has nothing to do with a 'private, internal skill' we are all supposed not only to possess, but also to be able to utilise effortlessly and correctly -- namely, an ability to polish rough and ready particulars into smooth general concepts. If abstraction were an occult (i.e., a hidden), inner process, then, as noted above, no two people would agree over the general idea of, say, a mammal, let alone a cat. All would have their own idiosyncratic inner, but intrinsically un-shareable and un-checkable, exemplars.

 

Again, one response to this could be that while we might use language to facilitate the transition from a private to the public arena, that doesn't impugn our abstractive skills. Unfortunately, that objection introduces topics discussed at length in Essay Thirteen Part Three, so readers are directed there for more details.

 

Nevertheless, a few preliminary remarks are worth making in response.

 

Human beings have generally managed to agree on what animals they consider belong to, say, the Class Mammalia -- i.e., especially individuals who possess the necessary education and qualifications, who also show they have the required linguistic and organisational skills/competency. We might even join with Hilary Putnam and call this a legitimate division of linguistic labour (although, without implying any acceptance of his other ideas concerning 'essentialism'). However, this doesn't include individuals who possess unspecified and mysterious 'abstractive powers'. So, for example, trainee zoologists don't gain their qualifications by demonstrating to their teachers and examiners an expertise in the 'inner dissection' or 'internal processing' of 'mental images', 'ideas' and 'concepts'. The same is true of qualified and practising zoologists. In fact, and on the contrary, they all have to demonstrate their mastery of highly specialised techniques, relevant terminology and current theory, which skills they are required to exhibit publicly, showing they are capable of applying them in appropriate circumstances and in a manner specified by, and consistent with, the standards and expectations laid down by their teachers, their adjudicators, their colleges and their professions. [On the ordinary and scientific use of such terms, see Dupré (1993), pp.15-84.]

 

The widespread illusion that we are all experts in the 'internal dismemberment' of images, ideas or concepts is now, and has always been, motivated by a further set of confusions, which also arose out of Traditional Philosophy: the belief that the intelligent use of general words depends on some sort of internal, naming, representing, 'reflecting' or processing ritual/ceremony. [On this, see the references cited in Essay Thirteen Part Three.] In effect, this once more amounts to the belief that, despite appearances to the contrary, all words are names, and that meaning something involves an 'inner act of meaning', 'naming' or 'representing', which matches words to specific images, sensations, processes or ideas 'in the mind/brain'. This paradigm certainly dominated Lenin's theory in MEC, as well as the rather fragmentary ideas Marx and Engels expressed on this topic, and, as usual, this idea originated in Ancient Greece (this was partially quoted earlier):

 

"The essence of the theory of Ideas lay in the conscious recognition of the fact that there is a class of entities, for which the best name is probably 'universals', that are entirely different from sensible things. Any use of language involves the recognition, either conscious or unconscious, of the fact that there are such entities; for every word used, except proper names -- every abstract noun, every general noun, every adjective, every verb, even every pronoun and every preposition -- is a name for something of which there are or may be instances." [Ross (1961), p.225. Bold emphasis added.]

 

[MEC = Materialism and Empirio-Criticism (i.e., Lenin (1972).]

 

At work here are several other inappropriate metaphors, which in turn trade on the further idea that 'consciousness' functions rather like an internal theatre, TV or computer display. The latter are now refined perhaps with analogies drawn against Microsoft Windows or some other programme of the same sort, where 'the mind' is often pictured as "modular" -- operated, no doubt, by an internal analogue of a computer geek, skilled at 'clicking' on the right internal 'icons', or 'apps', at the right moment, filing items in the right folders, setting-up useful and efficient 'networks', etc., etc. Given this family of metaphors, understanding is modelled on the way we ordinarily look at pictures and computer monitors, but now applied to 'internal representations', with each of us employing the equivalent of an 'inner eye' to appraise whatever is projected onto some sort of 'internal flat screen'.

 

[Again, this set of wildly inappropriate metaphors underpins Pixar's recent film, Inside Out (and again in 2024, Inside Out 2), which is itself based on an 'Homunculus', a 'little-man-in-the-head' Theory of Mind, briefly considered earlier, but in more detail in Essay Thirteen Part Three.]

 

These tropes are a faint echo of Plato's theory of 'knowledge by acquaintance', expressed in and by his Allegory of the Cave. [On that, see Appendix B of Essay Eight Part Two.]

 

[Of course, Plato's tropes were intended to make a different set of points, but for present purposes his focus on vision is the relevant factor here.]

 

As we have seen, contemporary, bourgeois versions of this (hackneyed) family of ideas regard knowledge as the passive processing of 'representations' in the 'mind' of each socially-isolated, lone abstractor -- although among Dialectical Marxists, this approach to knowledge is further augmented by a series of gestures made toward practice coupled with the active engagement of the individual 'mind' involved -- examined in Appendix Three. Nevertheless, both views of knowledge acquisition still picture it as a form of acquaintance, in relation to which the reasoning appears to be little more complex than this: just as we all know our friends by personal acquaintance, or by sight, so we all know the contents of our minds (all those 'concepts', 'images' and 'abstractions') by 'internal acquaintance' and 'inner sight'.

 

This once again reminds us why Traditional Theorists argue that knowledge is some sort of relation between the Knower and the Known. In this case, we are the Knowers and our own (internal) ideas are the Known. This has the unfortunate consequence of trapping dialecticians in their own solipsistic dungeon!

 

[5] Once more, it is no use referring to the existence of a public language to try to circumvent the sceptical results obtained above, as argued in Part One:

 

An appeal to the existence of a public language would be to no avail, either. Again, if each abstractor 'processes' their 'abstractions' in the privacy of their own heads, no one would be able to tell whether Abstractor A meant the same as Abstractor B by his or her use of the relevant words (or the relevant 'concepts' -- like "Substance", "Being", "Nothing", "The Population", "abstract labour", etc., etc.) drawn from the vernacular, or elsewhere. Definitions would be no help, either, since, just like memory, they also employ 'abstractions' -- so, they, too, would be subject to the same awkward questions. For how could Abstractor A know what Abstractor B means by any of the abstract terms she has processed without access to her 'mind'? Abstractor B can't point to anything which is 'the meaning' of a single abstraction she might be trying to define, so she can't use an ostensive definition to help Abstractor A understand what she means (even if meanings could be established that way). No particular, or no singular term, can give the meaning of any abstraction or abstract term under scrutiny (as those who accept this theory intend, not as I have criticised it -- so I am not contradicting my claim that these abstractions are really the Proper Names of abstract particulars). That being so, the same 'difficulties' would confront the general terms supposedly employed in any definition used to that end, and so on...

 

Nor would it be it any use an objector pointing to a series of correct results that might result from an individual having 'worked something out in their head', and, because of that arguing that the abstractive process must be valid if we are able to obtain consistently correct solutions like this while engaging in mental arithmetic. That is because 'correct answers' are, or have been, declared to be such in the public domain by reference to socially-sanctioned rules and procedures, which are also enabled by the competent use of publicly acquired skills by those who have shown a level of mastery in handling such communally-ratified methods and techniques. 'Correct results' aren't certified by each individual who engages in bouts of mental arithmetic, nor are any of the steps used to produce correct answers. They entire system in which 'correct results' may be ascertained has been developed, refined and authenticated over many centuries in the above manner. So, even if there were a 'process of abstraction', and even if mental arithmetic were performed 'in the head', both would be predicated on publicly-acquired and publicly-ratified skills and techniques already in use, not the other way round. So, a stream of correct answers generated by someone engaging in mental arithmetic fails to validate abstractionism. 'Correct answers' in fact confirm the opposite, they underscore the social nature of mathematics and the publicly acquired skills necessary to engage in bouts of mental arithmetic, to begin with

 

[6] Finally, in connection with this overall topic, a few years ago I posted the following material over at the Soviet Empire Forum (here re-written, modified and re-edited -- links added):

 

The meaning of the abstract nouns, verbs and adjectives obtained via the 'process of abstraction' is established by the results of that process itself.

 

"The notion of a universal and with it the celebrated problem of universals was invented by Plato.... The distinction of particulars and universals is complemented in many doctrines since Plato with the distinction and division of labour between the senses and the reason or intellect, or understanding. According to these doctrines, what is given to the bodily senses is merely particular, and the understanding or reason alone apprehends, or constructs or derives, the universal. Many philosophers take the problem of universals to be that of the meaning of general terms without realising that what makes the meaning of general terms a problem is the very concept of a universal." [Cowley (1991), p.85. Spelling modified to agree with UK English. Bold emphasis added.]

 

So, for example, the word "cat" no longer relates to cats in the real world but to an 'abstract particular', 'cat', that emerges as a result of this 'process'. Sure, given this theory, the word "cat" is supposed to 'reflect' cats in 'reality' -- or, on some accounts, their 'essence' -- , but whether or not it manages to do this, the abstract general term (or what it designates) is what gives the (real) meaning of the word "cat". The fury animal asleep on a mat or the one chasing a mouse outside does not. We can see this from the fact that if and when either cat dies, the meaning of "cat" doesn't die with them. That would still be the case even if all cats were to die; the word "cat" would keep its meaning and that meaning would be given by the 'abstract concept', 'CAT', designated by the abstract/common noun, "cat".

 

[I am, of course, summarising this theory and attempting to render it plausible, but that shouldn't be taken to imply I accept a single word of it! The same comment applies to much of what follows.]

 

The same is the case with "population" and "value". What Dialectical Marxists mean by, say, "value" is given by the process of abstraction applied to the ordinary common noun "value", so that the 'dialectical meaning' of the processed noun, "valueD", is no longer the same as the meaning of its ordinary, typological twin -- the vernacular, "valueV". The 'dialectical word', "valueD", now applies to the abstraction, 'VALUE' (which, because it is 'dialectical', has no fixed meaning; the way that works has yet to be explained by DM-advocates). How this then reflects what supposedly occurs or exists in the economy is to be determined by the 'new meaning' it has just acquired. "Value" now becomes the Proper Name of 'VALUE', and denotes this novel abstract particular,  with "valueD" supposedly 'reflecting' this 'abstract, if changing, fact'.  

[An abstract particular is like a genuine particular (such as the chair you are now sat on (if you are), the screen you are looking at -- or even you), to which we can, if we so choose, give a Proper Name or pick out by the use of a singular term (such as a definite description -- e.g., in this case, "The screen you are now looking at"); except, 'abstract particulars' don't exist in the world around us. They are, however, still capable of being designated by the use of Proper Names or other singular terms (such as "The Form of the Good", "Cathood", "The Population", or "value").]

In Plato's theory these abstract particulars were the 'Forms'. In Aristotle's, they were 'Universals'. In other systems they were variously 'Concepts', 'Categories' or 'Ideas' supposedly named by abstract general nouns or adjectives (or even nominalised verbs -- a term to be explained presently). This helped motivate the parallel idea that all words are in fact names -- they name the ideas, concepts or categories we all supposedly have in our heads (or they name objects and processes in the 'extra-mental' world), all of which we comprehend (perhaps more fully) at the end of the hypothesised, 'process of abstraction', and by any subsequent confirmation/revision in practice.

This means that this 'process' was a spin-off of the idea that we are only able to understand anything if all our words name something (in the world or in our heads). Given this theory, Proper Names/Proper Nouns (like "Plato", "Socrates", "George W Bush") are relatively easy to grasp; they name the individual idea we supposedly have of the person or object involved --, or, indeed, they name those individuals or objects themselves (out there in the world). But general words don't seem to name anything tangible. What does "cat" name? Or "value"? "Cat" can't name all the cats we have met, since that would mean one person's understanding of "cat" would be different from everyone else's, and the word would change its meaning as we met new cats. Hence, philosophers invented the 'process of abstraction' so they could explain what all of us name when we talk about cats -- i.e., what the general noun "cat" supposedly designates --, which, as we have seen, was then taken to be the Form/Universal, 'CAT', Cathood, or the Essence of Cat. So, "Cat" became the Proper Name of Cathood/CATHOOD, or even its 'essence'. Subsequently, the same became the case with "commodity", "population" and "value", in Marx's later work. That had to be so since their meaning can't be ascertained by actually pointing to, or at, anything in society, either. These terms were now supposedly capable of depicting something 'below the surface of appearances', something much more complex, accessible to thought alone. In that case, these terms (or the 'vague concepts' they supposedly stand for or represent) have to be 'mentally processed' by each lone abstractor if they are to be understood more fully, or less vaguely. This meant that the 'real' (non-vague) meaning of these general nouns had now to be ascertained -- or, rather, their meaning must be fixed -- by the 'process of abstraction' itself, and in no other way.

 

With this approach, out of the window went any commitment to the social nature of language and meaning.

So, given this view, we are all supposed to be able to discover or ascertain the 'real meaning' of these abstractions as individuals, by one or other of the following methods, depending on whether the traditional (non-Marxist) theorist involved in spinning this yarn was an Empiricist or a Rationalist.

(A) For Empiricists, we attain the general idea of 'cat' by a process of subtraction (which we do 'in our heads') until we reach that general idea, something all cats supposedly share; this is basically Locke's theory, for example. The 'process of abstraction' yields the 'real', or perhaps the 'nominal', essence of the item concerned. [A real essence is what is supposed to exist in the outside world independently of us -- what philosophers these days might call a de re essence. A nominal essence is just the name we supposedly give to 'things', which might or might not actually, or fully, reflect anything in reality -- what philosophers these days would call a de dicto essence.]
 

(B) For the Rationalist, however, we arrive at our knowledge of these 'forms' or 'concepts' by the 'light of reason' (in effect, we supposedly think 'God's thoughts' after 'him') --, or, according to Plato, we recall the Forms we met in our earlier existence, in Heaven, which we had subsequently forgotten about as a result of the shock of being born. For the German Idealists, we apply general terms to objects we meet in experience by a 'law of cognition', as Lenin might have put it.

 

Marx described this process as follows:

 

"If from real apples, pears, strawberries and almonds I form the general idea 'Fruit', if I go further and imagine that my abstract idea 'Fruit', derived from real fruit, is an entity existing outside me, is indeed the true essence of the pear, the apple, etc., then -- in the language of speculative philosophy -- I am declaring that 'Fruit' is the 'Substance' of the pear, the apple, the almond, etc. I am saying, therefore, that to be an apple is not essential to the apple; that what is essential to these things is not their real existence, perceptible to the senses, but the essence that I have abstracted from them and then foisted on them, the essence of my idea -- 'Fruit'. I therefore declare apples, pears, almonds, etc., to be mere forms of existence, modi, of 'Fruit'. My finite understanding supported by my senses does of course distinguish an apple from a pear and a pear from an almond, but my speculative reason declares these sensuous differences inessential and irrelevant. It sees in the apple the same as in the pear, and in the pear the same as in the almond, namely 'Fruit'. Particular real fruits are no more than semblances whose true essence is 'the substance' -- 'Fruit'." [Marx and Engels, The Holy Family.]

 

All very mysterious...

[By the way, to nominalise a verb is to turn it into a noun. For example, in place of "Socrates runs" we would obtain "Socrates is a runner". So, plainly, "Socrates" names Socrates, or our idea of him, and "runner" (now a noun) names the general category or class, 'Runner', or our idea of it, to which he supposedly belongs. 'RUNNER' is now an abstract particular, and the abstract noun "Runner" becomes its Proper Name, or it designates the 'class of runners' to which Socrates is said to belong (depending, once again, on the theorist spinning this yarn). In addition, according to the Identity Theory of Predication (which Hegel borrowed from Medieval Roman Catholic Theologians), the verb "is" in fact 'names' 'the identity relation' (or it just designates 'IDENTITY'), which we are now supposed to imagine exists between our idea of Socrates and our idea of the class or category of runners to which we have just assigned him -- or even an identity between the actual Socrates and that class itself. So, the sentence "Socrates runs" has now been transformed into a list of nouns, "Socrates" "Identity" and "Runner" (via "Socrates is a runner"). The significance of that transformation will soon emerge.]

 

However, the original generality expressed by terms like "cat", "runner" or even "value" has now been lost -- since a class is a particular.

 

[Added on Edit: The above topic was covered in detail in Part One; the argument presented in support has been summarised here.]

For both wings of Traditional Philosophy, howsoever we finally arrive at these abstract terms, the result (supposedly) defines the (real) meaning of the words we ordinarily use to describe objects and processes -- relating to 'concepts' or 'ideas' in our heads, in the world, in the economy, in Platonic Heaven or wherever they might happen to be located.

 

So, this approach became a theory of meaning.

[Ian Hacking's book, Why Does Language Matter To Philosophy? -- i.e., Hacking (1975) -- describes this tradition in relatively few pages and with admirable clarity.]


As Bertell Ollman points out, the problem with this is that the 'process of abstraction' (howsoever it is conceived) means we all end up constructing our own private language. As a result, we all mean something different by the words we have just processed, making communication impossible. [That is just one reason why Wittgenstein criticised the idea of a private language, alongside the theory that all words are names, in his Philosophical Investigations
(Wittgenstein (2009)).]

 

"What, then, is distinctive about Marx's abstractions? To begin with, it should be clear that Marx's abstractions do not and cannot diverge completely from the abstractions of other thinkers both then and now. There has to be a lot of overlap. Otherwise, he would have constructed what philosophers call a 'private language,' and any communication between him and the rest of us would be impossible. How close Marx came to fall into this abyss and what can be done to repair some of the damage already done are questions I hope to deal with in a later work...."

 

[That comes from Ollman's The Dance of the Dialectic, quoted earlier.]

What Marx and Engels did (at least in some of their work) was to invert this picture: They argued that language is primarily a means of communication, not representation (as philosophical tradition would have us believe -- i.e., the old theory held that these 'abstractions' were represented in our heads and supposedly reflect something, somewhere, even if it wasn't always clear what that 'something' is, or where that 'somewhere' was). Hence, if we want to understand how language works, we must begin with the fact that we use it to communicate, which will in turn imply our explanation of language and meaning will have to adapt to this changed perspective. Anything else would undermine the social nature of language and threaten human intercommunication.

Wittgenstein picked this idea up in his conversations with the Marxist economist, Piero Sraffa (Gramsci's friend), and it completely revolutionised his approach to language. He adopted what he called an 'anthropological', human-centred, social view of discourse.

According to this new perspective we are all socialised by our carers, siblings, peers and teachers how to use language -- largely by example, instruction and correction. We don't decide for ourselves what the words of our shared language mean by a 'process of abstraction', or in any other way. That was the 'old approach' to language acquisition which naturally appealed to bourgeois individualist philosophers (e.g., Descartes, Locke, Berkeley and Hume). That is still the case; it remains the leading theory of language, which explains the dominant influence of cognitive psychology on contemporary theories of mind and language. Even Chomsky has fallen into this trap, with his openly Cartesian approach to these topics. In this way it is still the "ruling idea" in the field. Marx and Wittgenstein's approach is almost totally ignored, if not contemptuously dismissed -- and, alas, it is also totally disregarded by those who claim to be Marxists!

 

[Of course, the above Marxists will reject that accusation, but their theories of cognition show that, in practice, that accusation is well-deserved -- indeed, as these two Parts of Essay Three, alongside Essays Twelve Part One and Thirteen Part Three, amply confirm.]

So, given this novel, Marx/Wittgenstein approach to language, we are all taught what our words mean, we don't teach ourselves what they mean -- 'in our heads', or anywhere else, for that matter. Hence, this change of emphasis, and perspective, begins with the social and proceeds from there. It doesn't begin with the individual. At a stroke, this re-orientation eliminates all the classic problems associated with abstractionism and representationalism....

By way of contrast, the old approach to language and meaning ends up completely undermining discourse, as Professor Lowe explains:

 

"What is the problem of predication? In a nutshell, it is this. Consider any simple subject-predicate sentence, such as..., 'Theaetetus sits'. How are we to understand the different roles of the subject and the predicate in this sentence, 'Theaetetus' and 'sits' respectively? The role of 'Theaetetus' seems straightforward enough: it serves to name, and thereby to refer to or stand for, a certain particular human being. But what about 'sits'? Many philosophers have been tempted to say that this also refers to or stands for something, namely, a property or universal that Theaetetus possesses or exemplifies: the property of sitting. This is said to be a universal, rather than a particular, because it can be possessed by many different individuals.

"But now we have a problem, for this view of the matter seems to turn the sentence 'Theaetetus sits' into a mere list of (two) names, each naming something different, one a particular and one a universal: 'Theaetetus, sits.' But a list of names is not a sentence because it is not the sort of thing that can be said to be true or false, in the way that 'Theaetetus sits' clearly can. The temptation now is to say that reference to something else must be involved in addition to Theaetetus and the property of sitting, namely, the relation of possessing that Theaetetus has to that property. But it should be evident that this way of proceeding will simply generate the same problem, for now we have just turned the original sentence into a list of three names, 'Theaetetus, possessing, sits.'

"Indeed, we are now setting out on a vicious infinite regress, which is commonly known as 'Bradley's regress', in recognition of its modern discoverer, the British idealist philosopher F. H. Bradley. Bradley used the regress to argue in favour of absolute idealism...." [Lowe (2006).]

 

So, traditional theory reduces all words to nouns (in fact, to Proper Nouns), and hence all such sentences to lists of names, and lists say nothing.

 

[Again, I have explained in detail how that works in Essay Three Part One.]

This means that my main criticism of abstractionism is not so much that we would or wouldn't know what our words mean...it is that it would make it impossible for anyone to say anything at all if it were true! All our (subject/predicate) sentences would fall apart as mere lists of names.

None of that happens when we take Marx's advice:

 

"We have shown that thoughts and ideas acquire an independent existence in consequence of the personal circumstances and relations of individuals acquiring independent existence. We have shown that exclusive, systematic occupation with these thoughts on the part of ideologists and philosophers, and hence the systematisation of these thoughts, is a consequence of division of labour, and that, in particular, German philosophy is a consequence of German petty-bourgeois conditions. The philosophers have only to dissolve their language into the ordinary language, from which it is abstracted, in order to recognise it, as the distorted language of the actual world, and to realise that neither thoughts nor language in themselves form a realm of their own, that they are only manifestations of actual life." [The German Ideology, bold added.]

 

Note that Marx specifically connects the traditional theory with the philosophically individualistic lives of the theorists who invented it (i.e., petty-bourgeois, early modern philosophers, from Hobbes to Hegel), and he also links it with abstraction and that in turn with a distortion of language.

This germ of an idea was taken up by Wittgenstein and was used by him to revolutionise philosophy, so that, if correct, his method would bring to an end 2500 years of empty, self-important speculation. It also meant that the old 'ruling ideas' (e.g., abstractionism and representationalism) can gain no grip and should therefore be rejected by Marxists.

My work is (partly) aimed at bringing this revolution back into Marxism itself.

 

It should never have left.

 

[7] In which case, an appeal to mental arithmetic would be no help at all in trying to make sense of the 'process of abstraction'. When we engage in mental arithmetic we employ words and symbols that already have a publicly accepted and established meaning (and, as we have seen, meanings that can't themselves have been obtained by abstraction). In addition, we employ mathematical operations we had already been taught how to use correctly before even attempting to work something out 'in our heads'. So, such operations were validated before they could even be used to do any mental arithmetic. The 'process of abstraction' depends on the reverse of this happening; that 'process' supposedly fixes the meaning of the terms that emerge at the end -- but in effect it empties them of meaning, as we have also just seen, since they are now "distorted" words, according to Marx. Furthermore, as we have seen, too, there is no way that a given abstractor can know that the new meanings they have given to the terms 'abstracted into existence' are the same as, or are different from, anyone else's -- or are the same as, or are different from, those they 'abstracted' yesterday, or even an hour earlier. Finally, unlike the operations used in mathematics, the 'process of abstraction' and the methods employed can't have been validated before they were used, since, beyond a few vague gestures, no one seems to know what this 'process' actually is.

 

Karl Marx's Magic Trick

 

Ollman then informs his readers that Marx employed four different senses of "abstraction" -- for example, in relation to:

 

(i) The division of the world into manageable "mental constructs";

 

(ii) The results of the process itself;

 

(iii) The difference between a deficient or ideological use of certain concepts; and,

 

(iv) The employment of this method in Das Kapital. [Ollman (2003), pp.61-62.]

 

It is, of course, undeniable that Marx used the word "abstract" and its cognates, and he certainly imagined he had employed this 'process' in his later work, but there nothing in his writings to show that he actually abstracted a single thing. And that isn't just because the 'process' itself is impossible to carry out -- let alone describe in detail, or with any clarity --, it is because of what he himself had to say about it. As we are about to discover, the passage usually quoted in support of the claim Marx used 'the process of abstraction' actually fails to do so. Here it is:

 

"It seems correct to begin with the real and the concrete…with e.g. the population…. However, on closer examination this proves false. The population is an abstraction if I leave out, for example, the classes of which it is composed. These classes in turn are an empty phrase if I am not familiar with the elements on which they rest…. Thus, if I were to begin with the population, this would be a chaotic conception of the whole, and I would then, by further determination, move toward ever more simple concepts, from the imagined concrete towards ever thinner abstractions until I had arrived at the simplest determinations. From there the journey would have to be retraced until I had finally arrived at the population again, but this time not as the chaotic conception of a whole, but as a rich totality of many determinations and relations…. The latter is obviously scientifically the correct method. The concrete is concrete because it is the concentration of many determinations, hence the unity of the diverse." [Marx (1973), pp.100-01.]

 

As noted in Part One of this Essay:

 

In fact, Marx doesn't actually do what he says he does in this passage; he merely gestures at doing it, and his gestures are about as substantive and convincing as the hand movements of stage magicians. That isn't to disparage Marx. Das Kapital is perhaps one of the greatest books ever written; but it would have been an even more impressive work if he had omitted what few (superficial) examples there remain of methods employed in traditional thought.

 

[Yes, I know the first quotation above is from the Grundrisse, not Das Kapital! The point is that he did at least talk about abstraction in the latter, but without ever once explaining what went on 'in his head', or how he ever managed to 'abstract' a single concept.]

 

What Marx actually did was put familiar words to use in new ways, thus establishing new concepts that enabled him to understand and explain Capitalism with startling depth and clarity. Anyone who reads the above passage can actually see him doing it. They don't need to perform a brain scan on Marx (even if that were possible and he were still alive!), or submit him to a series of psychometric tests to follow his argument. Nor do they even have to re-create these alleged 'abstractions' -- which they would certainly have to do if the 'process of abstraction' were something we all do privately in our heads, or one we should have to emulate in order to follow his 'private thoughts'. [Earlier, I substantiated my claim Marx also believed that the 'process of abstraction' was performed 'in the head' with quotations from his contemporaneous writings.] And they definitely can't duplicate his moves here since he failed to say what he had actually done, privately, with the concepts/words he targeted or used. Nor did he specify how he had 'mentally processed' the latter -- if in fact he had done so! Indeed, his 'instruction' how to go about 'abstracting' the 'population' are even less useful than John Lennon's famous remark that in order to find the USA all you had to do was turn left at Greenland. In that case, no one who reads Marx now is in any position to copy him in this respect, since he left no usable details. That, of course, indicates Marx didn't in fact do what he thought he had done, or proposed to do, otherwise, careful thinker that he was, he would have specified the required steps. Even more significantly: no one since has been able to reconstruct, reverse engineer or emulate these mythical 'mental moves', or show that any of their own gestures in that direction are exactly the same as Marx's, or even that they yield the same results as those allegedly achieved by him (indeed, as noted earlier).

 

In fact, it is quite apparent from the above passage that Marx had forgotten about his own refutation of this very process! [On that, see here and the next sub-section.] Or, if he had latterly repudiated that earlier refutation, he nowhere explained what was wrong with it. Nor have subsequent Marxists!

 

Marx merely says it "seems correct" if we begin with "the real and the concrete…with e.g. the population...", and he notes that the latter term is abstract if we omit "the classes of which it is composed." Marx then suggests that we proceed as follows:

 

"[B]egin with the population, [but] this would be a chaotic conception of the whole, and...then, by further determination, move toward ever more simple concepts, from the imagined concrete towards ever thinner abstractions until [we have] arrived at the simplest determinations." [Ibid.]

 

From there we then:

 

"[R]etrace the journey] until [we have] finally arrived at the population again, but this time not as the chaotic conception of a whole, but as a rich totality of many determinations and relations…. The latter is obviously scientifically the correct method. The concrete is concrete because it is the concentration of many determinations, hence the unity of the diverse." [Ibid.]

 

But, what "simpler concepts" are these? Marx failed to say and no one since has filled in the gaps. And he left it entirely mysterious exactly what the criterion is here supposed to be of a "simpler concept". Is class "simpler" than population? Or, vice versa? In fact, and notoriously, Marx left no detailed rules informing his readers even how he understood the word "class". Volume Three of Das Kapital famously breaks off at that point. As I noted in Essay Eight Part Two (here), subsequent Marxists have been struggling for over a hundred years to do what Marx failed to do: decide exactly who belongs to the proletariat and hence who belongs to the capitalist class (alongside other intermediate classes). If, after 150 years, we are still far from clear about this core distinction, and Marx failed to describe with any clarity what the composition of each class is (had he done so we wouldn't still be arguing over basics a century-and-a-half later!), how can anyone claim with any confidence that Marx had actually done what he said he had done in the above passage --, or that it is possible for anyone to do it in public, let alone in private, 'in their heads'?

 

We can't even do it in the open, for goodness sake!

 

And problems like this apply in equal measure to the "thinner" abstractions Marx mentioned -- about which he was also tight lipped. What are these "thinner" abstractions? What makes one abstraction "thinner" than the next? Is he referring to the extension of a set? If so, is a set with fewer members "thinner" than one with more? If that were so, "female over eighty" would have fewer members and be "thinner" than "female under forty". Is something like that what he meant? But those numbers could change (and if we accept the HF, they will change!), invalidating the 'abstraction'. In that case, "male under twenty" might have fewer members than "male between twenty and thirty" in 1850, but more in 1870. How are such questions to be settled if all you have are these hidden, 'mental processes' to hand? Indeed, how would it be possible to decide which sets have fewer, more than, or the same number as any other set just by thinking about them? In that case, if this is what Marx meant by "thinner", what has it got to do with the 'process of abstraction'? Do social scientists just sit around all day forming 'mental abstractions' when they want to determine the demographic profile of a given society? Or do they do actual surveys, in the open? Indeed, when Marxists these days write books and articles on the class composition of a given economy, they don't just 'retreat into their heads' or 'mull things over in secret'. They rely on published data, which has in turn been collected in the open, in a public arena, not ascertained by the sort of 'mental gymnastics' described in the above passage.

 

Furthermore, what counts as the "simplest determinations"? How on earth do we know they are the "simplest"? Indeed, what counts as a "simplest determination"? Worse still: how do we know there actually are any "simplest determinations", to begin with? What if analysis can (legitimately) proceed indefinitely? How can we rule that possibility out? Where do we stop? And how might we ascertain, concerning any two randomly-selected abstractors, that they will always stop at the same point if this all takes place secretly, 'in the head'?

 

In the last 150 years, has a single DM-fan asked questions like these about this famous passage, never mind bothered to answer them?

 

[If anyone knows the answer to that one, please email me with the details. I personally haven't seen anyone do this in the thirty-seven years I have been a revolutionary socialist. DM-supporters just quote and re-quote this passage as it if were unquestioned Holy Writ, failing to note it appears in a manuscript Marx chose not to publish. There is nothing like it in Das Kapital itself.]

 

So, as I suggested earlier, Marx's verbal flourishes are no more substantive than the hand gestures of stage magicians. In which case, it is difficult to understand why Dialectical Marxists have relied quite so heavily on this particular passage, and who have also failed to ask the sort of questions posed above, given its lack of detail and tantalising vagueness. We aren't even told what a "determination" is, for goodness sake! Is it the same as an Hegelian 'determination'? Or does it have a different meaning? If so, what is it, and where exactly does Marx explain the difference?

 

Of course, none of this is even remotely surprising. As we have repeatedly seen, abstractionists (typically) become super-vague when it comes to specifying the details of this mysterious 'process' -- and anyone who questions these champion DM-prevaricators can expect much hand waving and deflection in response. Not even Marx, genius though he was, is clear about any of this! That is why, after 2400 years of this Ancient Greek metaphysical fairy-tale going nowhere -- that is, other than motivate the sort of vague gestures that theorists like Ollman come out with --, no one seems quite able to say what this 'process' actually is, let alone what its results turn out to be!

 

By way of contrast, the actual method Marx employed (as noted above: we can physically see him using it on the page right in front of us -- i.e., indulging in an intelligent and novel, if imprecise, use of language) is how the greatest scientists have always behaved. In their work they present evidence and construct arguments in the open, in a public domain, using a public language, even if it is accompanied by an innovative use of words -- all of which can be checked, examined and questioned (or built upon) by anyone who cares to do so.

 

That can't be done with Ollman's mythical "mental constructs".

 

The Young Marx And Engels Torpedo 'Abstractionism'

 

Marx and Engels's earlier words are surely a more reliable guide to what he actually ended up doing in Das Kapital than the vague language that appeared (the once!) in the Grundrisse (quoted earlier):

 

"The ordinary man does not think he is saying anything extraordinary when he states that there are apples and pears. But when the philosopher expresses their existence in the speculative way he says something extraordinary. He performs a miracle by producing the real natural objects, the apple, the pear, etc., out of the unreal creation of the mind 'the Fruit'…. It goes without saying that the speculative philosopher accomplishes this continuous creation only by presenting universally known qualities of the apple, the pear, etc., which exist in reality, as determining features invented by him, by giving the names of the real things to what abstract reason alone can create, to abstract formulas of reason, finally, by declaring his own activity, by which he passes from the idea of an apple to the idea of a pear, to be the self-activity of the Absolute Subject, 'the Fruit.'" [Marx and Engels (1975), p.60. Bold emphases alone added.]

 

"For philosophers, one of the most difficult tasks is to descend from the world of thought to the actual world. Language is the immediate actuality of thought. Just as philosophers have given thought an independent existence, so they had to make language into an independent realm. This is the secret of philosophical language, in which thoughts in the form of words have their own content. The problem of descending from the world of thoughts to the actual world is turned into the problem of descending from language to life. We have shown that thoughts and ideas acquire an independent existence in consequence of the personal circumstances and relations of individuals acquiring independent existence. We have shown that exclusive, systematic occupation with these thoughts on the part of ideologists and philosophers, and hence the systematisation of these thoughts, is a consequence of division of labour, and that, in particular, German philosophy is a consequence of German petty-bourgeois conditions. The philosophers would only have to dissolve their language into the ordinary language, from which it is abstracted, to recognise it as the distorted language of the actual world, and to realise that neither thoughts nor language in themselves form a realm of their own, that they are only manifestations of actual life." [Marx and Engels (1970), p.118. Bold emphases alone added. Several paragraphs merged.]

 

In the above passage, the 'process of abstraction' is shown up for what it is: a systematic capitulation to philosophical confusion based on a distortion of ordinary language.

 

Ollman Misconstrues Change

 

Ollman now offers his readers the following (highly clichéd, but no less vague) remarks about 'change':

 

"Beginning with historical movement, Marx's preoccupation with change and development is undisputed. What is less known, chiefly because it is less clear, is how he thought about change, how he abstracted it, and how he integrated these abstractions into his study of a changing world. The underlying problem is as old as philosophy itself. The ancient Greek philosopher, Heraclitus, provides us with its classic statement when he asserts that a person cannot step into the same river twice. Enough water has flowed between the two occasions so that the river we step into the second time is not the same river we walked into earlier. Yet our common sense tells us that it is, and our naming practice reflects this view. The river is still called the 'Hudson', or the 'Rhine' or the 'Ganges'. Heraclitus, of course, was not interested in rivers, but in change. His point is that change goes on everywhere and all the time, but that our manner of thinking about it is sadly inadequate. The flow, the constant alteration of movement away from something and toward something else, is generally missing. Usually, where change takes place very slowly or in very small increments, its impact can be safely neglected. On the other hand, depending on the context and on our purpose in it, even such change -- because it occurs outside our attention -- may occasionally startle us and have grave consequences for our lives." [Ollman (2003), p.64. Bold emphases and link added.]

 

Although Ollman claims Marx "abstracted" change, he forgot to say exactly how or where he did this, or even what it means to "abstract" change, in the first place. What is common to every conceivable example of change? Ollman neglected to inform his readers about that not insignificant detail, too.

 

Among professional philosophers a perspicuous, non-trivial definition of change has yet to be agreed upon (Mortensen (2020)). And, after over 2400 years, we aren't even close! An appeal to something called, 'Cambridge Change' (a term coined by Peter Geach, in Geach (1968) pp.13-14, reprinted in Geach (1969), pp.71-72) also proves to be a dead end, as we are about to find out.

 

Despite this, we might still try to define change in the following way (along lines suggested by 'Cambridge Change'):

 

W1: Let Γ be the set of predicates 'true of' A at t1, where A goes proxy for a singular term designating some object (with "object" defined as "anything to which a singular term can legitimately be applied" -- that might sound circular, but it isn't), and tm is a temporal variable (for m Z+).

 

[Z+ is the set of Positive Integers and "" stands for "belongs to". The verb phrase "true of" has been put in scare quotes since Γ will only be capable of being 'true of A' when both variables have been interpreted. The same comment applies to "false of", used below.]

 

W2: Let Γ comprise the following elements: {P1, P2, P3..., Pi..., Pn-1, Pn} (for n Z+). [Where Pk goes proxy for legitimate, distinct predicate expressions.]

 

W3: For A to change, then, at a minimum:

 

(i) Let Pj be 'true of' A at t2 and Pj be 'false of' A at t1; or,

 

(ii) Let Pj be 'false of' A at t2 and Pj be 'true of' A at t1 (where t2 > t1). [Here, ">" stands for "later than", and Pj Γ.]

 

[Colloquially, W3 reads as follows: At a minimum: (i) Let something be 'true of' A at a later time that was 'false of' it earlier, or (ii) Let something be 'false of' A at a later time that was 'true of' it earlier.]

 

The problem with this attempt to define change is that (what would rightly be regarded as) superficial relational predicates, which become 'true of' A, will imply it had changed when it clearly hadn't done so.

 

So, if the new predicate 'true of' A were "NN thought about ξ", yielding "NN thought about A" -- or the new predicate that had been 'true of' A, but was now 'false of' A, were "NM wrote about ζ", yielding "NM wrote about A" --, then, while both of these would satisfy the above definition, implying A had changed, they wouldn't actually mean A had changed because of that. Otherwise we would have to argue that if someone began to think about, say, the Crab Nebula, that would mean it had changed simply because someone on earth had thought about it! Or that if someone else stopped writing about Engels at, say, 12:13:27 on May 17, 2023, when she had been writing about him a few seconds earlier, Engels himself had changed!

 

[The use of Greek letters like those employed above was explained here.]

 

Obviously, this definition of "change" is unacceptable, but no one has come up with a better, non-question-begging or generally accepted alternative. So, despite what dictionaries might tell you, there is currently no (philosophical) definition of change!

 

[I won't enter into why we don't actually need a philosophical definition of change -- or even why one can't be found no matter how hard we try -- in this Essay, or at this site.]

 

Now, it is reasonably clear that Marx, genius though he was, didn't solve this 'problem', which has dogged Traditional Thought for over two thousand years, but it is even clearer still that Ollman hasn't, nor did he point his readers to where he thinks Marx (or anyone else) might have done so. In that case, the question remains: how is it possible to form an 'abstract concept of change', if, after over two thousand years, we still lack a workable, or acceptable, definition of 'it'? What can possibly have been 'abstracted' if we have no clear idea what we are aiming for? Or even where to begin, for goodness sake!?

 

With that in mind, we might further ask: Precisely which examples of change are we to count as relevant? Which of them will settle where we can even begin to 'abstract' the supposed 'concept of change'? Are social changes to be lumped together with changes in nature? Are local changes on this planet to be equated with those halfway across the universe? Are recent changes to be associated with those that took place billions of years ago, which we will never experience (or even know about)? Are complex and simple changes to be compared? Are the above examples (of 'intentional/relational change') also to be taken into account in this respect? That is, those concerning A? If someone simply mentions a distant galaxy, have they 'magically' changed it? What about other instances of change? Does, say, a tree in Chicago change if an apple hits the ground in Tokyo? According to DM-fans, everything is interconnected, so that tree must change if an apple falls somewhere half-way across the globe. So, does the Sun change if you scratch your head? What about someone -- call her, "NN" -- who is second in line in a queue on the phone -- or she is on a waiting list for a flat, college course or organ transplant --, and NM, who was first in line ahead of her, drops out. NN will now be first in line, but has she actually changed just because of that?

 

We might be tempted to reply with a firm "Yes" to some, or even all, of those questions -- but what do they have in common with, say, a leaf changing colour, a child having her hair cut or someone just thinking about Karl Marx? If we can't say what these and many other examples one can think of have in common (and which don't also allow the ridiculous conclusions we met earlier in relation to A to be drawn), what chance is there that there is an 'abstract concept of change' that applies to every single instance of it, past, present and future? Or, one that we are all equally capable, not just of arriving at, but agreeing over? And then that each of us manages to 'abstract', separately, successfully, and correctly, 'in our heads'?

 

[Bearing in mind the fact that no sense can be made of a 'correct abstraction' in such circumstances. (On that, see here.) Moreover, these problems won't go away by the simple expedient of ignoring them -- a tactic beloved of DM-fans with whom I have debated such topics in the past. (I have covered possibilities like these -- as well as those that involve the obscure DM-concept, 'internal relations' --, in much more detail in Essay Eleven Parts One and Two, here and here.)]

 

Be this as it may, we saw in Essay Six that Heraclitus got himself into a terrible mess over the criteria of identity for mass nouns and count nouns in his attempt to 'show' that change was universal, based solely on his thoughts about stepping into a river! In relation to which we read the following:

 

"Among the best-known fragments is Heraclitus' claim usually given as 'one cannot step into the same river twice' which is actually translated from the Greek as 'In the same river we both step and do not step, we are and are not' meaning that, since the waters of a river are constantly in motion, one cannot ever experience the same waters across one's feet.... In this same way, life is also in constant motion and one should not expect any aspect of it to remain still for one's personal pleasure." [Quoted from here; accessed 14/08/2023. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

Engels concurred:

 

"When we consider and reflect upon nature at large or the history of mankind or our own intellectual activity, at first we see the picture of an endless entanglement of relations and reactions in which nothing remains what, where and as it was, but everything moves, changes, comes into being and passes away. This primitive, naive but intrinsically correct conception of the world is that of ancient Greek philosophy, and was first clearly formulated by Heraclitus: everything is and is not, for everything is fluidis constantly changing, constantly coming into being and passing away." [Engels (1976), p.24. Bold emphasis added.]

 

But, Heraclitus had a legitimate excuse. He lived at a time when little was known (let alone had been concluded) about this terminological difference. Indeed, I have been told that the distinction between mass and count nouns doesn't actually exist in the Greek language. Nevertheless, even though I have yet to verify that supposed fact, no Greek speaker would try to count cabbage or chalk, although they would happily count cabbage heads or sticks of chalk. Nor would they even attempt to weigh bodies (that isn't a typo!) when asked how many supporters were sat inside a coach on their way to a UK Premier League football (soccer) match, but they would try to count them. [Trite examples like these illustrate the stark difference between count and mass nouns and how we all handle them in everyday life, irrespective of any (philosophical) theories we might hold.] That excuse is no longer available, so Ollman's breezy conclusions (which were clearly based on little or no awareness of contemporary work in this area -- follow the "mass noun" link above for more details) are far less easy to absolve.

 

Now, had Heraclitus said that it was impossible to step into the same body of flowing water twice he might have had a point. Despite what he did say, it is quite easy to step into the same river. [On that, see here.] Indeed, without that particular option not even Heraclitus could test his own 'theory' (or even imagine such a test being performed in his 'mind's eye'), for he wouldn't be able to recognise the same river to test it on, let alone assert anything about it! And, of course, the word river legitimately applies to bodies of water that typically flow, so anyone using the word "river" would already know that they flow, otherwise they would be using that word with no comprehension of its meaning. In which case, Ollman is mistaken when he says:

 

"The underlying problem is as old as philosophy itself. The ancient Greek philosopher, Heraclitus, provides us with its classic statement when he asserts that a person cannot step into the same river twice. Enough water has flowed between the two occasions so that the river we step into the second time is not the same river we walked into earlier. Yet our common sense tells us that it is, and our naming practice reflects this view. The river is still called the 'Hudson', or the 'Rhine' or the 'Ganges'." [Op cit., bold added.]

 

But, if the above bodies of water are called rivers, that implies they change and flow, and naming them doesn't alter that fact. As if names can't be applied to changing objects! Who thinks that calling a hurricane "Katrina" means it doesn't change? Who in their left mind thinks that calling a huge conflagration, "The Camp Fire", means that it won't kill them if they don't get out of its way? [Ollman sort of half admits this, anyway, below.]

 

[The 'relative stability' of language defence was neutralised in Essay Six, so there is little point anyone appealing to it.]

 

Nevertheless, Ollman nowhere even so much as questions Heraclitus's semi-divine ability to extrapolate from a single observation about stepping into a river to what must be true, right across the entire universe, for all of time!

 

He continues:

 

"In contrast to this approach, Marx set out to abstract things, in his words, 'as they really are and happen,' making how they happen part of what they are (Marx and Engels (1964), p.57) [Ollman is here referencing the German Ideology; i.e., Marx and Engels (1976), p.31, see below -- RL] Hence, capital (or labour, money, etc.) is not only how capital appears and functions, but also how it develops; or rather, how it develops, its real history, is also part of what it is. It is also in this sense that Marx could deny that nature and history 'are two separate things' (Marx and Engels (1964), p.57). In the view which currently dominates the social sciences, things exist and undergo change. The two are logically distinct. History is something that happens to things; it is not part of their nature. Hence, the difficulty of examining change in subjects from which it has been removed at the start. Whereas Marx, as he tells us, abstracts 'every historical social form as in fluid movement, and therefore takes into account its transient nature not less than its momentary existence' (My emphasis (i.e., Ollman's emphasis -- RL)) (Marx (1958), p.20) [Ollman is here referencing Das Kapital Volume One; i.e., Marx (1996), p.20, see below -- RL]." [Ollman (2003), p.65. Spelling adjusted to conform with UK English. Referencing conventions altered to agree with those adopted at this site. Italic emphases in the original.]

 

But, as we have also seen (in Essay Three Part One), abstraction may only penetrate to the heart of things if 'reality' itself were abstract (i.e., if it were Ideal).

 

The MECW edition renders the above passages from The German Ideology as follows:

 

"The premises from which we begin are not arbitrary ones, not dogmas, but real premises from which abstraction can only be made in the imagination. They are the real individuals, their activity and the material conditions under which they live, both those which they find already existing and those produced by their activity. These premises can thus be verified in a purely empirical way." [Marx and Engels (1976), p.31. Bold emphasis added.]

 

I can't find the second passage to which Ollman refers on this particular page, or on any surrounding pages, of The German Ideology. Here is the third, from Das Kapital:

 

"...[B]ecause it regards every historically developed social form as in fluid movement, and therefore takes into account its transient nature not less than its momentary existence; because it lets nothing impose upon it, and is in its essence critical and revolutionary." [Marx (1996), p.20.]

 

Of course, in the first passage Marx refers to abstraction that "can only be made in the imagination", but he pointedly failed to tell us how that might actually be done, and neither does Ollman. What is more, Ollman's 'below the surface' metaphor explains nothing, either (on that, see here).

 

Doubtless, social development and the growth of science might be able to tell us how things "really are" (depending, of course, on what is meant by that phrase), or even how they "actually change", but they certainly can't do either by means of abstraction, for that 'process' deprives language of its capacity to express generality. Even if we were to assume that 'the process of abstraction' could do all that Ollman claims for it, DM would be the very last theory that scientists would turn to for assistance --, since, if it were true, change would be impossible!

 

So, all this labour has brought forth not even so much as an abstract mouse!

 

"The mountain labor'd, groaning loud, on which a num'rous gaping crowd of noodles came to see the sight, when, lo! a mouse was brought to light!" [Phaedrus, IV, XXIV.]

 

Ollman devotes the next few pages to listing, and then commenting on, several of the abstract terms he claims Marx used (whereas Marx doesn't appear to call them "abstract"!), in the course of which he makes the following (more substantive) point:

 

"Before concluding our discussion of the place of change in Marx's abstractions, it is worth noting that thinking in terms of processes is not altogether alien to common sense. It occurs in abstractions of actions, such as eating, walking, fighting, etc., indeed whenever the gerund form of the verb is used. Likewise, event words, such as 'war' and 'strike', indicate that to some degree at least the processes involved have been abstracted as such. On the other hand, it is also possible to think of war and strike as a state or condition, more like a photo than a motion picture, or if the latter, then a single scene that gets shown again and again, which removes or seriously underplays whatever changes are taking place. And unfortunately, the same is true of most action verbs. They become action 'things.' In such cases, the real processes that go on do not get reflected -- certainly not to any adequate degree -- in our thinking about them. It is my impression that in the absence of any commitment to bring change itself into focus, in the manner of Marx, this is the more typical outcome." [Ollman (2003), p.67. Bold emphases added.]

 

Ollman is absolutely right to point out that ordinary language contains numerous words that can be, and typically are, used to depict change, but he, like all too many others, confuses the vernacular with "common sense". Moreover, he seems content merely to assert that "thought" assumes or concludes many of the words we use to speak about change actually mange to depict states or conditions (when no such 'assuming' or 'concluding' takes place -- or, if it does, Ollman failed once again to provide any evidence or argument in support), which, if it were true, would undermine a feature of language he had only just mentioned -- the fact that the vernacular contains countless action words (on that, see below).

 

That is, of course, the problem with abstraction and reification; but neither of the latter two is (obviously) related to "common sense". And yet, if what Ollman says does indeed happen (in connection with ordinary language), that itself would be another regrettable result of the same syntactic errors and miss-steps that originally motivated philosophers and grammarians in Ancient Greece, highlighted in Part One of this Essay, and which have now re-surfaced in 'Marxist dialectics'!

 

In that case, if "common sense" is at fault, so too is DM! On the other hand, if ordinary language hadn't been deliberately distorted in this way (and if we took seriously the advice Marx and Engels offered earlier), the action verbs to which Ollman refers wouldn't end up being twisted and abused in such a Philistine way. Indeed, as pointed out in Essay Four (quoted earlier):

 

As is well-known (at least by Marxists), human beings managed to progress because of their interaction with nature, later constrained by the class war and the development of the forces of and relations of production. In which case, ordinary language -- the result of collective labour -- couldn't fail to have invented a array of words with the logical and semantic multiplicity that allowed its users to speak about changes of almost limitless complexity, speed and duration.

 

This is no mere dogma; it is easily confirmed. Here is a greatly shortened list of ordinary words (restricted to modern English, but omitting simple and complex tensed participles and auxiliary verbs) that allow speakers to talk about changes of almost unbounded complexity, rapidity, or scope:

 

Vary, alter, adjust, adapt, amend, make, produce, revise, rework, advise, administer, allocate, improve, enhance, deteriorate, depreciate, edit, bend, straighten, weave, merge, dig, plough, cultivate, sow, reap, twist, curl, turn, tighten, fasten, loosen, relax, ease, tense up, slacken, fine tune, bind, wrap, pluck, carve, rip, tear, mend, perforate, repair, puncture, renovate, restore, damage, impair, scratch, diagnose, mutate, metamorphose, transmute, sharpen, hone, modify, modulate, develop, upgrade, appear, disappear, expand, contract, constrict, constrain, shrivel, widen, lock, unlock, swell, flow, glide, ring, differentiate, integrate, multiply, divide, add, subtract, simplify, complicate, partition, unite, amalgamate, fuse, mingle, disseminate, connect, entwine, unravel, link, brake, decelerate, accelerate, fast, slow, swift, rapid, hasty, protracted, lingering, brief, heat up, melt, freeze, harden, cool down, flash, shine, glow, drip, bounce, cascade, drop, pick up, fade, darken, wind, unwind, meander, peel, scrape, graze, file, scour, dislodge, is, was, will be, will have been, had, will have had, went, go, going, gone, return, lost, age, flood, swamp, overflow, precipitate, percolate, seep, tumble, plunge, dive, float, sink, plummet, mix, separate, cut, chop, crush, grind, shred, slice, dice, saw, sew, knit, spread, coalesce, congeal, fall, climb, rise, ascend, descend, slide, slip, roll, spin, revolve, circulate, bounce, oscillate, undulate, rotate, wave, splash, conjure, quick, quickly, slowly, instantaneously, suddenly, gradually, rapidly, briskly, hurriedly, absolutely, lively, hastily, inadvertently, accidentally,  carelessly, really, energetically, lethargically, snap, drink, quaff, eat, bite, devour, consume, swallow, gulp, gobble, chew, gnaw, digest, ingest, excrete, absorb, join, resign, part, sell, buy, acquire, prevent, block, avert, avoid, forestall, encourage, invite, appropriate, lose, find, search, pursue, hunt, track, explore, follow, cover, uncover, reveal, stretch, distend, depress, compress, lift, put down, fetch, take, bring, carry, win, ripen, germinate, conceive, gestate, abort, die, rot, perish, grow, decay, fold, empty, evacuate, drain, pour, fill, abduct, abandon, leave, abscond, many, more, less, fewer, steady, steadily, jerkily, intermittently, smoothly, awkwardly, expertly, very, extremely, exceedingly, intermittent, discontinuous, continuous, continual, emit, push, pull, drag, slide, jump, sit, stand, run, sprint, chase, amble, walk, hop, skip, slither, crawl, limp, swim, fly, hover, drown, submerge, immerse, break, abrogate, dismiss, collapse, shatter, split, interrupt, charge, retreat, assault, squash, adulterate, contaminate, purify, filter, clean, raze, crumble, erode, corrode, rust, flake, demolish, dismantle, pulverise, atomise, disintegrate, dismember, destroy, annihilate, extirpate, flatten, lengthen, shorten, elongate, crimple, inflate, deflate, terminate, finish, initiate, instigate, augment, replace, undo, redo, analyze, synthesise, articulate, disarticulate, reverse, repeal, abolish, enact, quash, throw, catch, hour, minute, second, instant, moment, momentary, invent, devise, teach, learn, innovate, forget, rescind, boil, freeze, thaw, cook, liquefy, solidify, congeal, neutralise, evaporate, condense, dissolve, process, mollify, pacify, calm down, excite, enrage, inflame, protest, object, challenge, confirm, deny, repudiate, reject, refute, expel, eject, repel, attract, remove, overthrow, expropriate, scatter, distribute, equalise, surround, gather, admit, acknowledge, hijack, assemble, attack, counter-attack, charge, repulse, defeat, strike, occupy, picket, barricade, revolt, riot, rally, march, demonstrate, mutiny, rebel, defy, resist, lead, campaign, educate, agitate, organise...

 

[In each case, where there is a noun form of a word its verb form has been listed (for instance, "object" as in "to object"). Moreover, where I have listed the word "ring", for example, I also intend cognates of the verb "to ring" -- like "ringing" and "rang". I have also omitted many nouns that imply change or development, such as "river", "runner", "wind", "lightning", "tide", "cloud", and "fire". Anyone who didn't know such words implied changing processes in the world -- that rivers flow, fires burn, runners run, and winds blow -- would merely underline their lack of comprehension of English (or whatever language theirs happened to be), compounded by a dangerously defective knowledge of the world. Not knowing that fires burn, for example, would endanger life. In addition, several of the above also have verb forms, such as "fired" or "winding". Other nouns also imply growth and development, such as "tree", "flower", "mouse", "day",  "human being". Anyone who thought "human being", for example, reflected a 'fixed and changeless' view of the world would perhaps be regarded as suffering from some form of learning disability; either that, or they were in the grip of an off-the-wall philosophical theory of some sort.]

 

Naturally, it wouldn't be difficult to extend this list until it contained literally thousands of entries -- on that, see here and here --, all capable of depicting countless changes in limitless detail (especially if it is augmented with words drawn from mathematics, science and HM). It is only a myth put about by Hegel and DM-theorists (unwisely echoed by Rees, and others -- such as Woods and Grant) that ordinary language can't depict change adequately, since it is supposedly dominated by 'the abstract understanding', a brain module helpfully identified for us by Hegel without a scrap of supporting evidence, still less a brain scan. By way of contrast, ordinary language performs this task far better than the incomprehensible and impenetrably obscure jargon Hegel invented in order to fix something that wasn't broken.

 

If the above verbs are put in the present continuous tense (e.g., as flowing, burning, running, turning, organising, dissolving, crumbling..., etc.), and then placed in a sentential context (e.g., "The cops are running away from the strikers", "Management's resolve is crumbling", "The strike committee is still organising the picketing", etc., etc.) -- or, indeed, more complex present tenses are used (e.g., the present iterative or frequentative) --, only those woefully ignorant of language would conclude the following alongside Ollman:

 

"On the other hand, it is also possible to think of war and strike as a state or condition, more like a photo than a motion picture, or if the latter, then a single scene that gets shown again and again, which removes or seriously underplays whatever changes are taking place.... And unfortunately, the same is true of most action verbs. They become action 'things.' In such cases, the real processes that go on do not get reflected -- certainly not to any adequate degree -- in our thinking about them." [Ollman  (2003), loc cit.]

 

If some workers are striking, or a war is being fought, who, still in command of their senses, would conclude that a "state or condition" (and one that "removes or seriously underplays whatever changes are taking place"), not a process, was being described, or even implied?

 

Moreover, it isn't too clear what an "action 'thing" is supposed to be. Perhaps Ollman means that most action verbs can also be thought of as depicting states or conditions, but, since dialecticians like Ollman make a virtue out of abstraction, a 'process' that openly freezes verbs and predicate expressions into the Proper Names of Abstract Particulars, we would be well advised to take such comments with more than a pinch of non-dialectical salt.

 

[For a much more nuanced, clearer and comprehensive account of state, activity and performance verbs than the one attempted by Ollman -- which offered a decidedly amateurish and risibly superficial 'analysis' of this grammatical form --, see, for example, Kenny (1963), pp.151-86, Kenny (1975), and Hacker (2007), pp.90-160.]

 

'Internal Relations' To The Rescue?

 

Ollman then veers off at a tangent and begins a consideration of "internal relations" (a 'concept' that will be destructively analysed in Essay Four Part Two), which 'allows' him to advance several wild and unsubstantiated claims about Marx's method. In the course of which he made the following remark:

 

"The view held by most people, scholars and others, in what we've been calling the common sense view, maintains that there are things and there are relations, and that neither can be subsumed in the other. This position is summed up in Bishop Butler's statement, which G. E. Moore adopts as a motto: 'Everything is what it is, and not another thing,' taken in conjunction with Hume's claim, 'All events seem entirely loose and separate' (Moore, (1903), title page; Hume (1955) p.85 (see the References for further details; the first relates to Moore (1959) -- RL)). On this view, capital may be found to have relations with labour, value, etc., and it may even be that accounting for such relations plays an important role in explaining what capital is; but capital is one thing, and its relations quite another. Marx, on the other hand, following Hegel's lead in this matter, rejects what is, in essence, a logical dichotomy. For him, as we saw, capital is itself a Relation, in which the ties of the material means of production to labour, value, commodity, etc., are interiorized as parts of what capital is. Marx refers to 'things themselves' as 'their interconnections' (Marx and Engels (1950), p.488 -- Briefwechsel Volume 3 -- RL). Moreover, these relations extend backward and forward in time, so that capital's conditions of existence as they have evolved over the years and its potential for future development are also viewed as parts of what it is." [Ollman (2003), p.69. Spelling modified to agree with UK English; bold emphasis alone added. Referencing conventions altered to conform with those adopted at this site. Links added.]

 

So, on the basis of a short, enigmatic quotation from Butler (!), and a brief comment by Hume (highlighted in bold), Ollman somehow thinks he is able to tell us what the "common sense" view is! Are we meant to take this seriously? Is this cutting-edge philosophy? In Essay Seven Part One, I labelled superficial 'evidential displays' like this -- which typically feature in all forms of Dialectical Marxism --, "Mickey Mouse Science". However, in that Essay I only accused LCDs of indulging in this 'sport', but here we see a card-carrying HCD indulging, too. And Ollman isn't alone; other HCDs do likewise. [That allegation will be substantiated in Essay Twelve.]

 

[LCD = Low Church Dialectician; HCD = High Church Dialectician; follow those links for an explanation. LEM = Law of Excluded Middle.]

 

As we saw in Part One, Ollman is only able to confuse relations with "things" because of yet another linguistic sleight-of-hand (whereby nominalised and particularised relational expressions have been transformed into the Proper Names of Abstract Particulars). As a result, Ollman thinks he can (legitimately!) blur the distinction between "things" and "relations" -- thus perpetuating Marx's error in this respect, one that is easily rectified if we jettison such Hegelian gobbledygook. Hence, Ollman is simply echoing an assertion he copied from Marx: that Capital is a relation. Of course, what Marx means is that in order to understand Capitalism, it isn't enough just to look at "things", but at their interconnections, their history, their mutual development, and so on. If that is what Marx intended, I have no problem with it! And yet they [Marx and Ollman] fail to explain why that makes Capital a relation. The latter is merely asserted on the basis, one assumes, that dialectics requires the rejection of stark, black-and-white dichotomies, such as those between 'things' and 'relations'. That in turn is itself predicated on a Hegelian rejection of the LEM. I have dealt with that peculiar, self-defeating idea in Essay Nine Part One; readers are directed there for more details.

 

Independently of that, if Capital were a relation, it could have no relations of its own. On the other hand, if it were an object or system of some sort, it could.

 

Here is an example of a relation, represented by the relational expression, "ξ is larger than ζ":

 

Y1: A is larger than B. [Where "A" and "B" stand for singular terms -- i.e., Proper Names or Definite Descriptions.]

 

Y2: Ψ(ξ,ζ).

 

[I have explained the use of symbols like these, here.]

 

Plainly, the relation here is A being larger than B. It is far from clear how that relation itself can also be comprised of relations, or how that relation itself can be related to anything. Whatever A or B stand for might themselves be composed of relations, or be defined in terms of them, but how can the relation itself -- i.e., how the verb phrase "is larger than" expresses (when embedded in a grammatical sentence) can be composed of, or related to, anything? A relational expression (which, as the phrase suggests, expresses the intended relation) reflects a connection between the relata involved, it isn't itself composed of anything. Asking what a relation is made of is as nonsensical as asking what tallness and largeness are composed of. Or, indeed, what either are themselves related to.

 

Here is something -- a workers' picket line -- that is composed of relations (expressed by a series of relational expressions):

 

Y3: The picket was formed by w1, stood next to w2, stood next to w3..., stood next to wi..., stood next to wn-1, stood next to wn. [Where wk stands for the Proper Name of a worker, one of the said pickets.]

 

While it is easy to see how Capital as an economic and social system is comprised of relations, somewhat analogous to the situation depicted in Y3 (but in a far more complex way, obviously!), dialecticians like Ollman have yet to explain how Capital can be a relation while also being composed of relations, like we saw with Y1-Y3. Who, still in command of their senses, is going to ask what "stood next to" is itself made of? Or what further relations comprise the relation "stood next to"? Or even what "stood next to" is itself related to? But that would be the equivalent of asking what further relations comprise the relation that Capital is already said to be. Perhaps Ollman means Capital expresses a relation held between this and that? [Where the 'this' and the 'that' might themselves be complex structures or processes in their own right, and have their own relations.] Or that Capital began to exist when human beings entered into, set up, or established certain relations? Again, I have no problem with that! But, even then it is still hard to see how Capital can also be a relation. Nothing Ollman and other 'fans-of-the-dialectic' have so far said makes the supposed dual nature of Capital (in this sense) any the clearer -- i.e., that it is a relation and that it is comprised of relations.

 

Ollman (and other HCDs) may be content with this way of talking about relational (and/or substantival) expressions, but his (or their) only defence would once again involve an appeal to the misguided syntactical segue mentioned earlier, which reifies relational expressions so that they become objects in their own right, or the Proper Names thereof. Sliding between these two -- for example, between a set of relational expressions and the Proper Name, "Capital" (which names an identifiable 'object', system or process, or even a set of relations between such) -- 'allows' DM-theorists to imagine Capital can be comprised of relations and be a relation at the same time. We also saw (here) that this (defective) approach to the denotation of relational and nominal/substantival expressions is what lies behind the verbal tricks Hegel thought he could pull in order to befuddle his readers (and he evidently succeeded beyond his wildest dreams!). Such verbal tricks are analogous to the equally suspect word juggling that 'underpins' Anselm's notorious Ontological Argument, and are thereby no less contemptible.

 

It seems, therefore, that those who accept this view of the nature of Capital -- the alleged 'relation', not the book(!) -- can only appeal to the following considerations in support:

 

(i) A rather simple-minded view of "common sense"; backed up by,

 

(ii) An evidential display that makes Creationist propaganda look both substantial and convincing in comparison; allied with,

 

(iii) An idiosyncratic interpretation of the logic of relational expressions; all of which confusions are further compounded by,

 

(iv) A Philistine view language; based on,

 

(v) A seriously flawed criticism of the LEM.

 

[The reader will no doubt have noticed that this is precisely the accusation that was advanced at the beginning of Essay Three Part One, and will be repeated many times as the Essays at this site unfold. Moves like those Ollman tries to pull are a hallmark of ruling-class forms-of-thought -- what I have also called Linguistic Idealism [LIE]. That is, a belief that theories concerning fundamental features of nature and society (valid for all of space and time -- or, in this case, valid for at least one Mode of Production) can be inferred from language and 'thought' alone. Such moves mean that those who have bought into this way of reasoning also think they need provide little or no evidence in support (after all, why look for any of the latter if truth flows directly from language/thought?). But that is what we have just seen Ollman do in connection with his superficial analysis of change (and any of the verbs associated with it), followed by his risible appeal to what Hume and Butler had to say in an attempt to substantiate a few hasty conclusions about "common sense"! This overall approach to language and knowledge will be criticised at length in Essay Twelve Parts One to Seven (some of which material has already been published here, here and here).]

 

Having said all that, it might be possible to clear up the above confusion by arguing that there are two different meanings of the word "capital": "Capital1" and "Capital2". The first of these relates to Capital as a system, or part of a system, of relations, while the second relates to Capital as a relation itself. However, I know of no Dialectical Marxist who views this word in that way (if anyone does, please email me the details), so I will say no more about this or pass any opinion whether or not it is a viable option.

 

This is yet another hole DM-fans have dug themselves into; it is up to them to extricate themselves from it.

 

Welcome To The Desert Of The Reification

 

It could be objected that Ollman actually rejects many of the above criticisms, for example, with words like the following:

 

"In order to forestall possible misunderstandings it may be useful to assert that the philosophy of internal relations is not an attempt to reify 'what lies between.' It is simply that the particular ways in which things cohere become essential attributes of what they are. The philosophy of internal relations also does not mean -- as some of its critics have charged -- that investigating any problem can go on forever (to say that boundaries are artificial is not to deny them an existence, and, practically speaking, it is simply not necessary to understand everything in order to understand anything); or that the boundaries which are established are arbitrary (what actually influences the character of Marx's or anyone else's abstractions is another question); or that we cannot mark or work with some of the important objective distinctions found in reality (on the contrary, such distinctions are a major influence on the abstractions we do make); or, finally, that the vocabulary associated with the philosophy of internal relations -- particularly 'totality,' 'relation,' and 'identity' -- cannot also be used in subsidiary senses to refer to the world that comes into being after the process of abstraction has done its work." [Ollman (2003), p.72. Bold emphasis added.]

 

But, that is precisely what Ollman himself does (i.e., "attempt to reify" 'abstractions'); a few bluff denials in no way alters that fact. Moreover, as we have seen (here and here), it isn't possible to halt, or even slow down, the 'dialectical juggernaut' as it careers off the road into the infinite beyond, or neutralise the (fatal) criticism that, if this 'theory' were true, it would indeed be necessary to "understand everything in order to understand anything".

 

If Ollman were right (that "the particular ways in which things cohere become essential attributes of what they are"), he would it impossible to resist effectively the following argument:

 

L1: For any given object or process, H(1), its "essential" nature must be connected (in an as-yet-unspecified way) with some other object or process, H(2), which in turn must likewise depend on H(3)..., which in turn must depend on H(i)..., which in turn must depend on H(n-2), which in turn must depend on H(n-1), which in turn must depend on H(n). [For indefinitely large n.]

 

L2: In that case, in order fully to understand H(1) it is necessary to understand H(2), H(3)..., H(i)..., H(n-2), H(n-1) and H(n).

 

L3: However, if H(n) can't be fully understood without fully understanding H(n-1), and H(n-1) can't be fully understood without fully understanding H(n-2), then, by (n-1) applications of this rule, H(1) can't be fully understood until H(2) through H(n) are fully understood.

 

L4: Hence, nothing can be fully understood until everything is fully understood. QED.

 

In response, it won't do to try to substitute "understood" for "fully understood", either. Or, to be a little clearer, that ploy might have had a chance of succeeding if the "attributes" to which Ollman refers hadn't been described as "essential". If they are "essential", then they are essential to understanding anything to which they supposedly belong, relate or "cohere". Anything less than full understanding in that case would surely threaten their status as "essential" factors. Indeed, how would anyone know they are "essential" attributes if they didn't fully understood them? Without compete knowledge (which must surely accompany full understanding) it might turn out that what had been deemed "essential" wasn't "essential", after all. In fact, we have already seen DM-theorists concede the point that what were at one time considered "essential" properties lose that status as knowledge grows:

 

"Essence and appearance are correlated categories. They are characterised thorough one another. Whereas essence is something general, appearance is individual, expressing only an element of essence; whereas essence is something profound and intrinsic, appearance is external, yet richer and more colourful; whereas essence is something stable and necessary, appearance is more transient, changeable and accidental. The difference between the essential and the unessential is not absolute but relative. For instance, at one time it was considered that the essential property of the chemical element was its atomic weigh. Later this essential property turned out to be the charge of the atomic nucleus. The property of atomic weight did not cease to be essential, however. It is still essential in the first approximation, essential on a less profound level (sic!), and is further explained on the basis of the charge of the atomic nucleus." [Konstantinov (1974), p.191. Bold emphasis added.]

 

The same is also true with what used to be considered the "essential" nature of an acid. As I pointed out in Essay Twelve Part One (in connection with Wittgenstein's distinction between what he called "criteria" and "symptoms"):

 

[At this point] it is worth directing the reader's attention to a distinction Wittgenstein drew between what he called criteria and symptoms. [This links to a PDF.] Because of that distinction, what might at first sight appear to be an empirical proposition -- or, indeed, what had once been regarded as an empirical proposition --, could in fact assume a radically different role or logical status.

 

Symptoms are those facts which we regard as lending support to, or which tend to confirm the truth of, say, an hypothesis or tentative statement, whereas a criterion supplies conclusive proof, or helps provide such proof, of its truth -- or, indeed, of the proper application of an expression, such as "water" (with or without the use of other relevant criteria); or criteria help determine whether a given sentence or claim can even count as true, or whether an object has been, or can be, classified correctly.

 

Hence, a plane figure possessing three straight intersecting edges would be a criterion for something to count as a triangle (or for calling it one), whereas a pavement being wet would merely be a symptom that supported a claim, or which lent credence to the supposition, that it had been raining in the vicinity. On the other hand, wetness would now be one of the criteria that could/would be employed in order to decide if a certain liquid was water (but it wouldn't be the only criterion, of course). However, the absence of wetness on its own would provide conclusive proof that the liquid in question wasn't water. So, for example, liquid Mercury doesn't feel wet to human skin, just cold. However, other obvious properties of Mercury would clearly distinguish it from water well before it was allowed anywhere near unprotected skin.

 

[Naturally, that depends on how "wet" is itself to be defined. If it is taken to mean that a certain liquid contains water, then the above criterion would more closely resemble a colloquial tautology. It should go without saying, however, that the everyday meaning of "wet" must be distinguished from the scientific term, "wetting".]

 

Furthermore, what had once been regarded as a symptom could later become a criterion. For example, the observation that acids turned certain substances red was once regarded by medieval dyers and painters as an interesting fact about acids. That quirk was originally viewed, therefore, as a symptom. Later, this peculiar fact about acids was employed by Robert Boyle as a way of detecting, or of deciding upon, the presence of acids. It thus became a criterion -- later used universally in connection with, for instance, Litmus Paper.

 

[Although, apparently, the first recorded use of Litmus was by Spanish Alchemist Arnaldus de Villa Nova -- cf., Brock (1992), p.178. See also here.]

 

Of course, we use other pH-Indicators these days, but that just means this criterion has (or these criteria have) now become more varied and complex. The distinction itself still remains valid -- indeed, as Peter Hacker notes:

 

"It is true that we can, in certain cases, transform an empirical proposition into a rule or norm of representation by resolving to hold it rigid.... It was an empirical discovery that acids are proton donors, but this proposition was transformed into a rule: a scientist no longer calls something 'an acid' unless it is a proton donor, and if it is a proton donor, then it is to be called 'an acid', even if it has no effect on litmus paper. The proposition that acids are proton donors...has been 'withdrawn from being checked by experience but now serves as a paradigm for judging experience'. [This is a quotation from Wittgenstein (1978), p.325 -- RL.] Though unassailable, so-called necessary truths are not immutable; we can, other things being equal, change them if we so please.... But if we change them, we also change the meanings of their constituent expressions...". [Hacker (1996), p.215. Link added.]

 

So, the "essential" nature of an acid is no longer taken to be the fact that it neutralises a base or changes the colour of Litmus Paper.

 

The following dusty old (Stalinist) DM-textbook also defined acids in 'essentialist' terms that no longer apply:

 

"An acid has many properties, but the most essential is its ability to combine with an alkali or a metal and form a salt. In a word the most essential qualities are those which a thing manifests in relation to 'its other,' to its opposite." [Shirokov (1937), p.272. Bold emphasis added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

As I then point out in Essay Eight Part Three:

 

But, modern definitions of acids don't characterise acids in such a simplistic way. The Brønsted-Lowry definition says that acids are proton donators, while the Lewisian definition tells us that an acid is an electron-pair acceptor. Admittedly, bases are still defined as the 'opposite' of each of these, but acids and alkali's are no longer defined in terms of each other, but in terms of a third item (or, rather, a third and a fourth term, if we lump the lot together). [On this, see Zumdahl (1989), pp.654-56 and Shriver and Atkins (2001), pp.143-76.]

 

Of course, that assumes there are 'essences' to begin with (which idea with be destructively criticised in Essay Thirteen Part Two -- until then, the reader is directed here for more details), but even if 'essences' do exist (in some shape or form), it looks like they change, or are often discarded(!) to be replaced by another 'essence', which sometimes suffers the same fate a few years later, as we learn more. Clearly this means the previous 'essence' wasn't in fact essential; it's an odd sort of 'essence' that actually turns out not to be essential, after all!

 

Naturally, this means that until we have complete knowledge/understanding we will never really know the 'essential nature' of anything, and that in turn means:

 

L5: Nothing can be fully understood until everything is fully understood.

 

But, given the ephemeral nature of these 'essences', which are all too easily 'benched', this means we will never fully understand anything.

 

[I hasten to add once more that this isn't my view of knowledge; I am merely drawing out the absurd consequences of the DM-Epistemology. I have said much more about this topic, here and here. We have also seen that no sense can be made of DM-theorists' own use of words such as "totality" or "identity" -- on that, see here, here and here.]

 

Finally, simply denying these implausible consequences of the neo-Hegelian Horror Show outlined above won't wash, either -- that is, no more than it would if George Berkeley tried to deny he was an Idealist.

 

Brain Scans Required?

 

Ollman continues:

 

"Once we recognize the crucial role abstraction plays in Marx's method, how different his own abstractions are, and how often and easily he re-abstracts, it becomes clear that Marx constructs his subject matter as much as he finds it. This is not to belittle the influence of natural and social (particularly capitalist) conditions on Marx's thinking, but rather to stress how, given this influence, the results of Marx's investigations are prescribed to a large degree by the preliminary organization of his subject matter. Nothing is made up of whole cloth, but at the same time Marx only finds what his abstractions have placed in his way. These abstractions do not substitute for the facts, but give them a form, an order, and a relative value; just as frequently changing his abstractions does not take the place of empirical research, but does determine, albeit in a weak sense, what he will look for, even see, and of course emphasize. What counts as an explanation is likewise determined by the framework of possible relationships imposed by Marx's initial abstractions. So far we have been discussing the process of abstraction in general, our main aim being to distinguish it from other mental activities. Marx's own abstractions were said to stand out in so far as they invariably include elements of change and interaction, while his practice of abstracting was found to include more or less of each as suited his immediate purpose. Taking note of the importance Marx gave to abstractions in his critique of ideology, we proceeded to its underpinnings in the philosophy of internal relations, emphasizing that it is not a matter of this philosophy making such moves possible -- since everybody abstracts -- but of making them easier, and enabling Marx to acquire greater control over the process. What remains is to analyze in greater detail what actually occurs when Marx abstracts, and to trace its results and implications for some of his major theories." [Ollman (2003), pp.73-74. Bold emphases added; paragraphs merged.]

 

But, we have yet to be told what Marx's 'abstractions' are, or how Ollman could possibly know anything about them if, as he says, they are "mental activities" or the product thereof! Has he exhumed Marx's body and held a séance over what remains of the corpse? Maybe he has access to a time machine, travelled back to the 1870s and performed a brain scan on Marx (always assuming the relevant equipment can accompany him on his journey, and he took a powerful enough battery with him)? But, they seem to be the only ways he could possibly learn anything about the alleged "mental activities" engaged in by Marx. In that case, the following words appear to be little more than hot air:

 

"What remains is to analyze in greater detail what actually occurs when Marx abstracts, and to trace its results and implications for some of his major theories." [Ibid.]

 

It could be argued that we should begin with Marx's actual results on the page and then, perhaps, 'reverse engineer' the mental method or psychological processes by which he must have obtained the results he did. Of course, as with 'mental arithmetic', 'reverse engineering' only works because engineers and scientists already understand the processes involved, which they can specify in detail, in advance, and they can do so in the open, in a public language. That is what allows them to 'run the film in reverse', as it were. But, we (still) have no idea what the 'processes' involved here are. And Ollman has been as tight-lipped about it as other DM-theorists always have. In that case, it isn't possible to 'reverse engineer' the production of a single 'abstraction' -- no more than we can 'reverse engineer' something equally mysterious/fictional: telepathy.

 

Furthermore, as we have also seen, it is little use appealing to the language Marx used since that can't tell us anything about those hidden "mental activities", either. Nor would it show that Marx had actually indulged in this yet-to-be-explained 'process of abstraction' -- that is, over and above his use of the word "abstract" from time-to-time. Even he failed to tell us with any clarity what he meant by this 'process' or what he had done 'in his head'! Without doubt, Marx must have given thought to what he was writing about, but that has nothing to do with the 'process of abstraction', since Marx had to use familiar words drawn from a public language in order to do all that thinking. And the language he employed to that end already possessed general terms with established meanings that weren't themselves the product of 'abstraction' -- that is, not unless they had been subjected to the sort of distortion exposed in Part One, and which Marx himself had both criticised and condemned.

 

But, is it even true that "everybody abstracts"? As this Essay has shown, not only is there no evidence they do, no one seems to be able to tell us what they are all supposed to be able to do while they are allegedly involved in doing it! Which is odd in itself. If we all engage in this 'process', why can no one tell us what it is we are all supposed to be able to do? For example, we all engage in walking for much of our lives -- or at least those physically capable. There are expert anatomists and physiologists who can tell us in detail what we all do when we so indulge (here, for example, is an entire YouTube channel, with dozens of videos devoted to this and other movements we all engage in on a daily basis), and most us can also give some account of what we do when we ambulate. Even robots can be programmed to walk, too. But, not one single believer in the 'process of abstraction' (DM-fan or otherwise) in the last 2500 years seems able to say, beyond a few vague gestures, what we are all supposed to do when we intentionally fire up these 'mental processes'.

 

[Added on Edit October 2024: As noted earlier, since the above was first written I have managed to locate a relatively recent attempt to explain this 'process' -- Laurence and Margolis (2012). I will say more about that failed attempt in Interlude One.]

 

Nor can anyone work out how the heroic "mental activities" of Abstractor A could possibly agree with those of Abstractor B, or, indeed, how it is possible for anyone to check even their own results.

 

Ollman now advances the following remarks:

 

"The process of abstraction, which we have been treating as an undifferentiated mental act, has three main aspects or modes, which are also its functions vis-à-vis the part abstracted on one hand and the system to which the part belongs and which it in turn helps to shape on the other. That is, the boundary setting and bringing into focus that lies at the core of this process occurs simultaneously in three different, though closely related, senses. These senses have to do with extension, level of generality, and vantage point. First, each abstraction can be said to achieve a certain extension in the part abstracted, and this applies both spatially and temporally. In abstracting boundaries in space, limits are set in the mutual interaction that occurs at a given point of time. While in abstracting boundaries in time, limits are set in the distinctive history and potential development of any part, in what it once was and is yet to become. Most of our examples of abstraction so far have been drawn from what we shall now call 'abstraction of extension.'

 

"Second, at the same time that every act of abstraction establishes an extension, it also sets a boundary around and brings into focus a particular level of generality for treating not only the part but the whole system to which it belongs. The movement is from the most specific, or that which sets it apart from everything else, to its most general characteristics, or what makes it similar to other entities. Operating rather like a microscope that can be set at different degrees of magnification, this mode of abstraction enables us to see the unique qualities of any part, or the qualities associated with its function in capitalism, or the qualities that belong to it as part of the human condition (to give only the most important of these levels of generality). In abstracting capital, for example, Marx gives it an extension in both space and time as well as a level of generality such that only those qualities associated with its appearance and functioning as a phenomenon of capitalism are highlighted (i.e., its production of value, its ownership by capitalists, its exploitation of workers, etc.). The qualities a given capital may also possess as a Ford Motor Company assembly line for making cars or as a tool in general -- that is, qualities that it has as a unique object or as an instance of something human beings have always used -- are not brought into the picture. They are abstracted out. This aspect of the process of abstraction has received least attention not only in our own discussion but in other accounts of dialectics. In what follows, we shall refer to it as 'abstraction of level of generality.'

 

"Third, at the same time that abstraction establishes an extension and a level of generality, it also sets up a vantage point or place within the relationship from which to view, think about, and piece together the other components in the relationship; meanwhile the sum of their ties (as determined by the abstraction of extension) also becomes a vantage point for comprehending the larger system to which it belongs, providing both a beginning for research and analysis and a perspective in which to carry it out. With each new perspective, there are significant differences in what can be perceived, a different ordering of the parts, and a different sense of what is important. Thus, in abstracting capital, Marx not only gives it an extension and a level of generality (that of capitalism), he also views the interrelated elements that compose it from the side of the material means of production and, simultaneously, transforms this configuration itself into a vantage point for viewing the larger system in which it is situated, providing himself with a perspective that influences how all other parts of the system will appear (one that gives to capital the central role). We shall refer to this aspect of abstraction as 'abstraction of vantage point.' By manipulating extension, level of generality, and vantage point, Marx puts things into and out of focus, into better focus, and into different kinds of focus, enabling himself to see more clearly, investigate more accurately, and understand more fully and more dynamically his chosen subject." [Ollman (2003), pp.74-75. Bold emphases added.]

 

But words like this are just empty terms until we are told what this 'process' actually is -- other than that it is a "mental act" --, especially since we have even less of an idea what all these 'abstractions' are supposed to be that somehow 'emerge' at the end. This of course means the distinctions Ollman wants to draw here are about as useful as the intricate classification of angels concocted by Medieval Theologians.

 

Independently of this, how Ollman knows so much about abstraction when neither he nor anyone else has access to the mental gyrations of other intrepid abstractors (and who is also annoyingly vague even about what goes on 'in his own head', let alone Marx's!), is no less of a mystery. The very best Ollman can do is tell us about the "three main aspects or modes" of his own abstractions (and, as we saw in a previous sub-section, he can only tell us about the 'abstractions' he is currently aware of, not those he held yesterday or even a few minutes earlier!), if 'abstractions' are indeed the result of these yet-to-be-described-let-alone-identified "mental acts". Of course, it is quite clear what Ollman is doing when he tells us about the 'abstractions' Marx supposedly accessed and employed: he is relying on what Marx committed to paper. He clearly isn't relying on a single one of those (imagined) "mental acts". In other words, he, like the rest of us, has focused on the publicly available writings Marx left behind. But, what that has to do with this 'inner process of abstraction' is still completely unclear.

 

Be this as it may, Ollman's distinctions might turn out to be of some use in an analysis of Capitalism. I will pass no comment on that possibility, except to note that, as we saw in Part One, the 'process of abstraction' destroys generality, it doesn't express it or even provide theorists with a "level of generality". Hence, it would be wise to maintain healthy scepticism about that what Ollman has to say will help in any way. However, if Ollman's distinctions do turn out to be of some use in the analysis of Capitalism, that will clearly be because:

 

(i) He uses general terms drawn from a publicly-accessible language; he doesn't use abstractions as such (because their meaning is forever lost to us since they are based on "mental acts", about which he can know nothing); and because,

 

(ii) He nowhere asks his readers to scan his brain in order to comprehend his own (or even Marx's) 'abstractions'. In fact, Marx took care to explain what he was trying to do -- again, he did so in an open arena, using a public language -- in the shape of the copious writings he left behind. That is, of course, what allows his readers understand (or, in some cases, try to understand) his words, which they couldn't do if they paid attention to his 'mental deliberations' while ignoring what he had actually committed to paper.

 

Once again, actions speak louder than abstractions.

 

Here is Ollman, once more:

 

"As regards the abstraction of extension. Marx's general stand in favour of large units is evident from such statements as, 'In each historical epoch, property has developed differently and under a set of entirely different social relations. Thus, to define bourgeois property is nothing else than to give an exposition of all these social relations of bourgeois production.... To try to give a definition of property an independent relation, a category apart, an abstraction and eternal idea, can be nothing but an illusion of metaphysics and jurisprudence' (Marx (n.d.), p.154; this is a reference to The Poverty of Philosophy -- RL). Obviously, large abstractions are needed to think adequately about a complex, internally related world." [Ibid., pp.75-76. Bold emphasis added; spelling modified to agree with UK English. Referencing conventions altered to conform with those adopted at this site.]

 

But, the passage Ollman quotes can't be about Marx's 'abstractions', and that isn't just because it fails to mention "mental acts", it is because Marx himself repudiates these mythical 'objects' in the very work Ollman quoted! It is also worth recalling that Marx's rejection agrees with what we discovered earlier about his opinion of this backwater of Ancient Greek fantasy. The following passage is also from The Poverty of Philosophy -- which Ollman (mysteriously!) failed to quote:

 

"Is it surprising that everything, in the final abstraction…presents itself as a logical category? Is it surprising that, if you let drop little by little all that constitutes the individuality of a house, leaving out first of all the materials of which it is composed, then the form that distinguishes it, you end up with nothing but a body; that if you leave out of account the limits of this body, you soon have nothing but a space -- that if, finally, you leave out of account the dimensions of this space, there is absolutely nothing left but pure quantity, the logical category? If we abstract thus from every subject all the alleged accidents, animate or inanimate, men or things, we are right in saying that in the final abstraction the only substance left is the logical categories. Thus the metaphysicians, who in making these abstractions, think they are making analyses, and who, the more they detach themselves from things, imagine themselves to be getting all the nearer to the point of penetrating to their core…." [Marx (1978), p.99.]

 

Pointedly ignoring that repudiation, Ollman continues:

 

"The specifics of Marx's position emerge from his frequent criticisms of the political economists for offering too narrow abstractions (narrow in the double sense of including too few connections and too short a time period) of one or another economic form. Ricardo, for example, is reproached for abstracting too short a period in his notions of money and rent, and for omitting social relations in his abstraction of value (Marx (1968), p.125; Marx (1971), p.131 -- these are references to Theories of Surplus Value, Parts Two and Three -- RL). One of the most serious distortions is said to arise from the tendency among political economists to abstract processes solely in terms of their end results. Commodity exchange, for example, gets substituted for the whole of the process by which a product becomes a commodity and eventually available for exchange (Marx (1973), p.198 -- this is a reference to the Grundrisse -- RL). As Amiri Baraka so colourfully points out: 'Hunting is not those heads on the wall' (Baraka (1966), p.73). [This is now Baraka (2009), p.200 -- RL.] By thinking otherwise for the range of problems with which they are concerned, the political economists avoid seeing the contradictions in the capitalist-specific processes that give rise to these results." [Ollman (2003), p.76. Spelling modified to conform with UK English; referencing conventions altered to agree with those adopted at this site. Minor typos corrected; bold emphases and link added.]

 

And yet, Marx's criticisms aren't aimed at any supposed 'abstractions' (which, even if they did exist, would once more be the product of hidden, unspecified "mental acts"), but at the tendency classical economists have of concentrating on "results", in parallel with a penchant for substituting "commodity exchange...for the whole of the process by which a product becomes a commodity and eventually available for exchange." Similarly, Ricardo is taken to task for fixating on "too short a period in his notions of money and rent, and for omitting social relations...". In this respect, Marx plainly relied on what these economists had published in the open. He didn't once think to speculate about what might have gone on in their heads.

 

[Of course, it was Ollman who inserted the word "abstracting", here, but since that 'process' is, once again, based on a range of nondescript "mental acts", he (seriously) can't have meant this, otherwise Marx couldn't have advanced the criticisms he did. And that is because, once more, Marx didn't once attempt to 'read the minds' of other economists.]

 

And, as far as those alleged "contradictions" are concerned, until we are told what they are, Ollman might just as well have written the following for all the good it does:

 

"By thinking otherwise for the range of problems with which they are concerned, the political economists avoid seeing the schmontradictions in the capitalist-specific processes that give rise to these results." [Edited misquotation of ibid.]

 

[As we will see in Essay Twelve, Ollman's attempt to 'define' "contradiction" (pp.17-18) turns out to be worse than no help at all.]

 

Now, other than examine the passage quoted in the next sub-section, I don't plan to chisel away at the other things Ollman has to say over the next thirty-five or so pages of his book (i.e., pp.77-112), not just because that would make this Essay tedious in the extreme, but because they add nothing substantive to his attempt to explain what 'abstractions' actually are (although they do contain a large amount of material about Marx's alleged use of this 'process', the nature of which neither Marx nor Ollman cared to explain!) -- as readers are invited to check for themselves. There, Ollman advances a series of familiar claims about other areas of dialectics (which have been critically-examined elsewhere at this site, some of which will be raked over again in Essay Twelve), but he has little more to add concerning the nature of 'abstraction', certainly nothing which makes this mysterious 'process' any clearer, more comprehensible or even remotely plausible.

 

Ollman Versus The Critics

 

In which case, the following passage is all the more unfortunate:

 

"Is there any part of Marxism that has received more abuse than his dialectical method? And I am not just thinking about enemies of Marxism and socialism, but also about scholars who are friendly to both. It is not Karl Popper, but George Sorel in his Marxist incarnation who refers to dialectics as 'the art of reconciling opposites through hocus pocus,' and the English socialist economist, Joan Robinson, who on reading Capital objects to the constant intrusion of 'Hegel's nose' between her and Ricardo (Sorel (1950), p.171; Robinson (1953), p.23 -- references given at the end of this Essay -- RL). But perhaps the classic complaint is fashioned by the American philosopher, William James, who compares reading about dialectics in Hegel -- it could just as well have been Marx -- to getting sucked into a whirlpool (James (1978), p.174 -- again, reference given at the end -- RL)." [Ollman (2003), p.59. Referencing conventions modified to conform with those adopted at this site. Italic emphasis in the original; links added.]

 

In view of the continual slide into confusion and error that bedevils 'dialectics' -- exposed at this site --, it is now plain that the above critics weren't anywhere near harsh enough!

 

As I pointed out in Essay One:

 

Another aspect of the defensive approach adopted by dialecticians is the fact that few of them fail to point out that hostile critics of Dialectical Marxism always seem to attack 'the dialectic'. This then allows them to brand all such detractors as "bourgeois apologists", which in turn means that whatever the latter say can safely be ignored as, 'plainly', partisan and ideological.

 

[This is the DM-equivalent of the Roman Catholic Church's old Index of Forbidden Books.]

 

But, it has surely escaped their attention that the reason 'the dialectic' is attacked by friend and foe alike is that it is by far-and-away the weakest and most lamentably feeble area of traditional 'Marxist Philosophy'. Far from it being an "abomination" to the bourgeoisie (even though the State Capitalist rulers of Eastern Europe, the former USSR, Maoist China and North Korea are, or were, rather fond of it, as are those sections of the bourgeoisie that publish books and articles on dialectics, or, indeed, on 'Marxist Philosophy'), 'the dialectic' has in fact helped visit an abomination on revolutionary socialism.

 

So, our enemies attack dialectics precisely because they think they have found our Achilles Heel.

 

Whereas, revolutionaries (like the present writer) criticise it for the opposite reason: to rid Marxism of its Achilles Heel.

 

Admittedly, Trotsky tried to respond to general criticisms of 'the dialectic' coming in from former believers (for want of a better term), along the following lines:

 

"Anyone acquainted with the history of the struggles of tendencies within workers' parties knows that desertions to the camp of opportunism and even to the camp of bourgeois reaction began not infrequently with rejection of the dialectic. Petty-bourgeois intellectuals consider the dialectic the most vulnerable point in Marxism and at the same time they take advantage of the fact that it is much more difficult for workers to verify differences on the philosophical than on the political plane. This long known fact is backed by all the evidence of experience." [Trotsky (1971), p.94.]

 

But, Trotsky's rebuttal works both ways, for if it is difficult for workers to verify the "differences" he mentions, then that clearly allows others (such as party leaders, party hacks and party theorists) to manipulate workers with ideas they don't understand (that isn't to disparage workers -- no one understands DM), or can't check. And, far from it being the case that only workers find it hard to defend this 'theory'/'method' -- or even understand it, for goodness sake(!) -- DM-theorists themselves have shown that they, too, don't understand it (as these Essays have also repeatedly demonstrated, particularly this one)! That isn't because it is a difficult theory to grasp; it is because it is based on incomprehensible Hegelian gobbledygook (upside down and the 'right way up').

 

However, as the Essays published at this site also show, there is now no good reason to cling to these vague and confused DM-fantasies, even though there are easily identifiable psychological and ideological motivating factors that help explain why they are, have been, and will continue to be embraced by the DM-faithful.

 

Hence, the conclusion is inescapable: petty-bourgeois and de-classé revolutionaries maintain their commitment to this misbegotten, mystical set of ideas for contingent psychological, opportunist and ideological reasons, and for no other. [Again, I have fully substantiated those accusations in Essay Nine Parts One and Two.]

 

[The "Ah, but what about 1917?" reply/defence has also been neutralised, here.]

 

The class origin and current class position of comrades like Trotsky works against them, as well. After all, they, too, aren't above (i.e., they aren't exempt from) Marx's declaration that:

 

"It is not the consciousness of men that determines their existence, but their social existence that determines their consciousness." [Marx (1987), p.263.]

 

[The "Ah, but that's just crude reductionism!" riposte has also been neutralised, here.]

 

So, Ollman's attempt to explain 'the process of abstraction' -- particularly as Marx is alleged to have used it -- was completely wasted effort. I have absolutely no idea why I was directed to this work, except to conclude that those who recommended it have clearly given this entire topic little or no critical scrutiny.

 

Appendix Two: Plato And Aristotle

 

The Link Between 'The Soul', 'Rationality' And A 'Well-Ordered' City 

 

In his dialogue, the Republic, Plato makes an explicit connection between the following five factors: the 'natural order', the 'rational order of the soul', a 'well ordered/just city' and the class structure of society. The following discussion takes place between Socrates, Adeimantus and Glaucon -- Plato's older brother--, beginning with Socrates (bold emphases added):

 

We will not, I said, be over-positive as yet; but if, on trial, this conception of justice be verified in the individual as well as in the State, there will be no longer any room for doubt; if it be not verified, we must have a fresh enquiry. First let us complete the old investigation, which we began, as you remember, under the impression that, if we could previously examine justice on the larger scale, there would be less difficulty in discerning her in the individual. That larger example appeared to be the State, and accordingly we constructed as good a one as we could, knowing well that in the good State justice would be found. Let the discovery which we made be now applied to the individual -- if they agree, we shall be satisfied; or, if there be a difference in the individual, we will come back to the State and have another trial of the theory. The friction of the two when rubbed together may possibly strike a light in which justice will shine forth, and the vision which is then revealed we will fix in our souls.

 

That will be in regular course; let us do as you say.

 

I proceeded to ask: When two things, a greater and less, are called by the same name, are they like or unlike in so far as they are called the same?

 

Like, he replied.

 

The just man then, if we regard the idea of justice only, will be like the just State?

 

He will.

 

And a State was thought by us to be just when the three classes in the State severally did their own business; and also thought to be temperate and valiant and wise by reason of certain other affections and qualities of these same classes?

 

True, he said.

 

And so of the individual; we may assume that he has the same three principles in his own soul which are found in the State; and he may be rightly described in the same terms, because he is affected in the same manner?

 

Certainly, he said.

 

Once more then, O my friend, we have alighted upon an easy question -- whether the soul has these three principles or not?

 

An easy question! Nay, rather, Socrates, the proverb holds that hard is the good.

 

Very true, I said; and I do not think that the method which we are employing is at all adequate to the accurate solution of this question; the true method is another and a longer one. Still we may arrive at a solution not below the level of the previous enquiry.

 

May we not be satisfied with that? he said; -- under the circumstances, I am quite content.

 

I too, I replied, shall be extremely well satisfied.

 

Then faint not in pursuing the speculation, he said.

 

Must we not acknowledge, I said, that in each of us there are the same principles and habits which there are in the State; and that from the individual they pass into the State? -- how else can they come there? Take the quality of passion or spirit; -- it would be ridiculous to imagine that this quality, when found in States, is not derived from the individuals who are supposed to possess it, e.g. the Thracians, Scythians, and in general the northern nations; and the same may be said of the love of knowledge, which is the special characteristic of our part of the world, or of the love of money, which may, with equal truth, be attributed to the Phoenicians and Egyptians.

 

Exactly so, he said....

 

Must we not then infer that the individual is wise in the same way, and in virtue of the same quality which makes the State wise?

 

Certainly.

 

Also that the same quality which constitutes courage in the State constitutes courage in the individual, and that both the State and the individual bear the same relation to all the other virtues?

 

Assuredly.

 

And the individual will be acknowledged by us to be just in the same way in which the State is just?

 

That follows, of course.

 

We cannot but remember that the justice of the State consisted in each of the three classes doing the work of its own class?

 

We are not very likely to have forgotten, he said.

 

We must recollect that the individual in whom the several qualities of his nature do their own work will be just, and will do his own work?

 

Yes, he said, we must remember that too.

 

And ought not the rational principle, which is wise, and has the care of the whole soul, to rule, and the passionate or spirited principle to be the subject and ally?

 

Certainly.

 

And, as we were saying, the united influence of music and gymnastic will bring them into accord, nerving and sustaining the reason with noble words and lessons, and moderating and soothing and civilizing the wildness of passion by harmony and rhythm?

 

Quite true, he said.

 

And these two, thus nurtured and educated, and having learned truly to know their own functions, will rule over the concupiscent, which in each of us is the largest part of the soul and by nature most insatiable of gain; over this they will keep guard, lest, waxing great and strong with the fullness of bodily pleasures, as they are termed, the concupiscent soul, no longer confined to her own sphere, should attempt to enslave and rule those who are not her natural-born subjects, and overturn the whole life of man?

 

Very true, he said.

 

Both together will they not be the best defenders of the whole soul and the whole body against attacks from without; the one counselling, and the other fighting under his leader, and courageously executing his commands and counsels?

 

True.

 

And he is to be deemed courageous whose spirit retains in pleasure and in pain the commands of reason about what he ought or ought not to fear?

 

Right, he replied.

 

And him we call wise who has in him that little part which rules, and which proclaims these commands; that part too being supposed to have a knowledge of what is for the interest of each of the three parts and of the whole?

 

Assuredly.

 

And would you not say that he is temperate who has these same elements in friendly harmony, in whom the one ruling principle of reason, and the two subject ones of spirit and desire are equally agreed that reason ought to rule, and do not rebel?

 

Certainly, he said, that is the true account of temperance whether in the State or individual.

 

And surely, I said, we have explained again and again how and by virtue of what quality a man will be just.

 

That is very certain.

 

And is justice dimmer in the individual, and is her form different, or is she the same which we found her to be in the State?

 

There is no difference in my opinion, he said.

 

Because, if any doubt is still lingering in our minds, a few commonplace instances will satisfy us of the truth of what I am saying.

 

What sort of instances do you mean?

 

If the case is put to us, must we not admit that the just State, or the man who is trained in the principles of such a State, will be less likely than the unjust to make away with a deposit of gold or silver? Would any one deny this?

 

No one, he replied.

 

Will the just man or citizen ever be guilty of sacrilege or theft, or treachery either to his friends or to his country?

 

Never.

 

Neither will he ever break faith where there have been oaths or agreements?

 

Impossible.

 

No one will be less likely to commit adultery, or to dishonour his father and mother, or to fail in his religious duties?

 

No one.

 

And the reason is that each part of him is doing its own business, whether in ruling or being ruled?

 

Exactly so.

 

Are you satisfied then that the quality which makes such men and such states is justice, or do you hope to discover some other?

 

Not I, indeed.

 

Then our dream has been realized; and the suspicion which we entertained at the beginning of our work of construction, that some divine power must have conducted us to a primary form of justice, has now been verified?

 

Yes, certainly.

 

And the division of labour which required the carpenter and the shoemaker and the rest of the citizens to be doing each his own business, and not another's, was a shadow of justice, and for that reason it was of use?

 

Clearly.

 

But in reality justice was such as we were describing, being concerned however, not with the outward man, but with the inward, which is the true self and concernment of man: for the just man does not permit the several elements within him to interfere with one another, or any of them to do the work of others, -- he sets in order his own inner life, and is his own master and his own law, and at peace with himself; and when he has bound together the three principles within him, which may be compared to the higher, lower, and middle notes of the scale, and the intermediate intervals -- when he has bound all these together, and is no longer many, but has become one entirely temperate and perfectly adjusted nature, then he proceeds to act, if he has to act, whether in a matter of property, or in the treatment of the body, or in some affair of politics or private business; always thinking and calling that which preserves and co-operates with this harmonious condition, just and good action, and the knowledge which presides over it, wisdom, and that which at any time impairs this condition, he will call unjust action, and the opinion which presides over it ignorance.

 

You have said the exact truth, Socrates.

 

Very good; and if we were to affirm that we had discovered the just man and the just State, and the nature of justice in each of them, we should not be telling a falsehood?

 

Most certainly not.

 

May we say so, then?

 

Let us say so.

 

And now, I said, injustice has to be considered.

 

Clearly.

 

Must not injustice be a strife which arises among the three principles -- a meddlesomeness, and interference, and rising up of a part of the soul against the whole, an assertion of unlawful authority, which is made by a rebellious subject against a true prince, of whom he is the natural vassal, -- what is all this confusion and delusion but injustice, and intemperance and cowardice and ignorance, and every form of vice?

 

Exactly so.

 

And if the nature of justice and injustice be known, then the meaning of acting unjustly and being unjust, or, again, of acting justly, will also be perfectly clear?

 

What do you mean? he said.

 

Why, I said, they are like disease and health; being in the soul just what disease and health are in the body.

 

How so? he said.

 

Why, I said, that which is healthy causes health, and that which is unhealthy causes disease.

 

Yes.

 

And just actions cause justice, and unjust actions cause injustice?

 

That is certain.

 

And the creation of health is the institution of a natural order and government of one by another in the parts of the body; and the creation of disease is the production of a state of things at variance with this natural order?

 

True.

 

And is not the creation of justice the institution of a natural order and government of one by another in the parts of the soul, and the creation of injustice the production of a state of things at variance with the natural order?

 

Exactly so, he said.

 

Then virtue is the health and beauty and well-being of the soul, and vice the disease and weakness and deformity of the same?

 

True.

 

And do not good practices lead to virtue, and evil practices to vice?

 

Assuredly.

 

Still our old question of the comparative advantage of justice and injustice has not been answered: Which is the more profitable, to be just and act justly and practise virtue, whether seen or unseen of gods and men, or to be unjust and act unjustly, if only unpunished and unreformed?

 

In my judgment, Socrates, the question has now become ridiculous. We know that, when the bodily constitution is gone, life is no longer endurable, though pampered with all kinds of meats and drinks, and having all wealth and all power; and shall we be told that when the very essence of the vital principle is undermined and corrupted, life is still worth having to a man, if only he be allowed to do whatever he likes with the single exception that he is not to acquire justice and virtue, or to escape from injustice and vice; assuming them both to be such as we have described?

 

Yes, I said, the question is, as you say, ridiculous. Still, as we are near the spot at which we may see the truth in the clearest manner with our own eyes, let us not faint by the way.

 

Certainly not, he replied.

 

Come up hither, I said, and behold the various forms of vice, those of them, I mean, which are worth looking at.

 

I am following you, he replied: proceed.

 

I said, The argument seems to have reached a height from which, as from some tower of speculation, a man may look down and see that virtue is one, but that the forms of vice are innumerable; there being four special ones which are deserving of note.

 

What do you mean? he said.

 

I mean, I replied, that there appear to be as many forms of the soul as there are distinct forms of the State.

 

How many?

 

There are five of the State, and five of the soul, I said.

 

What are they?

 

The first, I said, is that which we have been describing, and which may be said to have two names, monarchy and aristocracy, accordingly as rule is exercised by one distinguished man or by many.

 

True, he replied.

 

But I regard the two names as describing one form only; for whether the government is in the hands of one or many, if the governors have been trained in the manner which we have supposed, the fundamental laws of the State will be maintained.

 

That is true, he replied.

 

Such is the good and true City or State, and the good and true man is of the same pattern; and if this is right every other is wrong; and the evil is one which affects not only the ordering of the State, but also the regulation of the individual soul.... [Plato (1997f), 435b-449a, pp.1066-77. However, I have used the on-line translation here.]

 

In Plato's, The Laws, Book X, [i.e., Plato (1997g)], the above considerations are interlinked with piety shown toward the 'gods' and the 'ordered nature of the Cosmos'. I won't quote that material here; it will be posted in Essay Twelve Part Two.

 

Contemporary Mystics are still referencing these Ancient Mystics -- i.e., Plato, Aristotle and Heraclitus -- in this regard, for example:

 

"Greek philosophy emerged through speculation on the cosmic myths that symbolically revealed the divine order of the universe. From these speculations on the cosmic order arose the various notions of the elements, the planetary motions and mathematics, and these notions were related to the question of the human order and the order of society. It was understood that the human order was distinct from that of the immortal gods, yet also distinct from biological necessity. Human nature dwelled in a region between the immortal and the mortal, open to eternity yet projected into time, apprehending the unchanging yet compelled to adapt to the ever-changing. In the primordial myths the order of nature (physis) and human law (nomos) arose together and were bound together. The order of nature and the order of the city resided in the rule of the gods, and this order could be observed in the harmony and proportion found throughout the Earth and the heavenly motions. The cosmos was filled with intelligence and with reason (nous), and every part and every motion attended the good of the whole....

 

"In this way, Greek philosophy originated in meditation on cosmic myth, the primordial apprehension of the whole, with a view to affirming its truth through reason. And this meditation takes the form of the question: how may the human being and society live in accord with the cosmic good? What is the appropriate life of the human person or citizen? It is at once a rational and a religious question. For the Greek philosophers, questions of the explanation of things are secondary to this essential question that awakens questioning in the first place. Philosophical enquiry is not a precursor to the scientific explanation of things, because explanation is not a final end in itself, while the question of how should life be lived is. And so Greek philosophy, even in its weaker or degenerate forms, for example, with the sophists whom Plato frequently challenges in the dialogues, always remains concerned with the relation of the divine cosmic order and the order of society or the polis. The polis and the cosmos are bound together, just as the polis and the soul are bound together. Greek society drifted into political decline as it forsook these connections.

 

"In their acts of resistance to the disorder of the age, Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle experienced and explored the movements of a force that structured the psyche of man and enabled it to resist disorder. To this force, its movements, and the resulting structure, they gave the name nous. As far as the ordering structure of his humanity is concerned, Aristotle characterized man as the zoon noun echon, as the living being that possesses nous.

 

"And it is with a view to restoring these connections that Plato and Aristotle enquired into the nature of the polis and the question of the relation between nature (physis) and law (nomos). Thus Heraclitus says 'Those who speak with understanding must hold fast to what is common to all as a city holds fast to its law (nomos), and even more strongly. For all human laws (anthropeoi nomoi) are fed by the one divine law (theois nomos). It prevails as much as it will, and suffices for all things with something to spare'. Hence the nature of the polis and the divine law that sustains it cannot be separated without causing harm." [Quoted from here. Bold emphases alone added.]

 

The above remarks connect ratio and proportion with the 'cosmic order'; i.e., with issues concerning how, in an 'ordered cosmos', everything is held together in proportion, in a specific ratio (from which comes our word, "rationality" -- and on which theory was based "The music of the spheres", a topic that will also be explored in Essay Twelve Part Two; on that, see James (1995)).

 

However, in relation to this topic in general, see Williams (1973) and Ferrari (2005) -- see also Kenny (1969).

 

Still Under Construction

 

Appendix Three: John Rees Attempts To Rescue Lenin

 

[This Appendix is also still under construction.]

 

John Rees made a valiant attempt to resolve the serious problems Lenin's Theory of Knowledge created, and then bequeathed to the movement in general -- at least in so far as it had been expounded in MEC --, analysed in detail in Essay Thirteen Part One.

 

One of the main problems with Lenin's (earlier) theory was his obsessive reliance on "images" as the sole source of his (and anyone else's) knowledge of the 'outside world' (see the proof texts quoted below). Despite several attempts made by subsequent DM-theorists (such as Sean Sayers and David-Hillel Rubin) to defend Lenin, this has meant his theory is no better than those advanced by the Subjective Idealists and Immanentists he was criticising in the same book. His theory suffered from all their fatal defects, but this time they were hidden behind flowery rhetoric and appeals to authority, fortified by bombast and no little distortion. This left Lenin in the same predicament as the latter theorists -- as we discovered in Essay Thirteen Part One (and in Essay Ten Part One). The result was that his theory either dropped Lenin into a bottomless solipsistic hole with no way out, or it set him adrift on a trackless ocean of extreme scepticism with no map to guide him and no engine, sail or paddle to help him make progress.

 

In response it could be argued that John Rees has successfully managed to show that Lenin's later, more sophisticated, 'dialectical' theory (set out in PN) carried no such implications. Indeed, Lenin's more nuanced theory in PN might help repair the gaping holes in his earlier theory, and hence prevent it from languishing in one or other of the two philosophical dead ends mentioned above.

 

[Sayers's attempt to defend Lenin will be examined in Appendix Five and Rubin's in Part Six of Essay Three.]

 

Background Details

 

In order to show that Rees's defence fails, it might prove helpful to re-cap a few of the points made in Essay Thirteen Part One:

 

Several critics of the claim that if Lenin were correct, humanity would only ever have 'images', have objected that that isn't Lenin's position, nor is it even remotely like it. However, when asked precisely what these 'other elements of knowledge' are or might be that have been omitted or ignored, they grow suspiciously quiet....

 

In fact, Lenin had the following to say about sensation, knowledge and 'images':

 

"Our sensation, our consciousness is only an image of the external world...." [Lenin (1972), p.69. Bold emphasis added. Notice the use of "only" here.]

 

"All knowledge comes from experience, from sensation, from perception. That is true. But the question arises, does objective reality 'belong to perception,' i.e., is it the source of perception? If you answer yes, you are a materialist. If you answer no, you are inconsistent and will inevitably arrive at subjectivism, or agnosticism, irrespective of whether you deny the knowability of the thing-in-itself, or the objectivity of time, space and causality (with Kant), or whether you do not even permit the thought of a thing-in-itself (with Hume). The inconsistency of your empiricism, of your philosophy of experience, will in that case lie in the fact that you deny the objective content of experience, the objective truth of experimental knowledge...." [Ibid., p.142. Bold emphases alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

So, Lenin has just told us that:


"Our sensation, our consciousness is only an image of the external world...." [Ibid.,
p.69. Bold emphasis added.]

 

And:

 

"All knowledge comes from experience, from sensation, from perception." [Ibid., p.142. Bold emphasis added.]

 

Hence, if "all knowledge comes from...sensation", and sensation is an "image of the external world", the only conclusion possible is that, according to Lenin, all we have as a basis for our knowledge of 'the external world' are 'images', even if they have been derived from "perception"/"sensation".

 

Lenin then proceeded to underline the point:

 

"For instance, the materialist Frederick Engels -- the not unknown collaborator of Marx and a founder of Marxism -- constantly and without exception speaks in his works of things and their mental pictures or images..., and it is obvious that these mental images arise exclusively from sensations. It would seem that this fundamental standpoint of the 'philosophy of Marxism' ought to be known to everyone who speaks of it, and especially to anyone who comes out in print in the name of this philosophy.... Engels, we repeat, applies this 'only materialistic conception' everywhere and without exception, relentlessly attacking Dühring for the least deviation from materialism to idealism. Anybody who reads Anti-Dühring and Ludwig Feuerbach with the slightest care will find scores of instances when Engels speaks of things and their reflections in the human brain, in our consciousness, thought, etc. Engels does not say that sensations or ideas are 'symbols' of things, for consistent materialism must here use 'image,' picture, or reflection instead of 'symbol,' as we shall show in detail in the proper place." [Ibid., pp.32-33. Bold emphases added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

"[S]ensation is an image of the external world...." [Ibid., p.56. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"The doctrine of introjection is a muddle, it smuggles in idealistic rubbish and is contradictory to natural science, which inflexibly holds that thought is a function of the brain, that sensations, i.e., the images of the external world, exist within us, produced by the action of things on our sense-organs." [Ibid., p.95. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"The sole and unavoidable deduction to be made from this -- a deduction which all of us make in everyday practice and which materialism deliberately places at the foundation of its epistemology -- is that outside us, and independently of us, there exist objects, things, bodies and that our perceptions are images of the external world." [Ibid., p.111. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"Thus, the materialist theory, the theory of the reflection of objects by our mind, is here presented with absolute clarity: things exist outside us. Our perceptions and ideas are their images." [Ibid., p.119. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"For the materialist the 'factually given' is the outer world, the image of which is our sensations." [Ibid., p.121. Bold emphasis added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

"This is either an idealist lie or the subterfuge of the agnostic, Comrade Bazarov, for sense-perception is not the reality existing outside us, it is only the image of that reality." [Ibid., p.124. Bold emphasis alone added.]

 

"The fundamental distinction between the materialist and the adherent of idealist philosophy consists in the fact that the materialist regards sensation, perception, idea, and the mind of man generally, as an image of objective reality." [Ibid., p.320. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"What has annoyed this most worthy 'recent positivist'? Well, how could he help being annoyed when he immediately realised that from Haeckel's standpoint all the great doctrines of his teacher Avenarius -- for instance, that the brain is not the organ of thought, that sensations are not images of the external world, that matter ('substance') or 'the thing-in-itself' is not an objective reality, and so forth -- are nothing but sheer idealist gibberish!?" [Ibid., p.428. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Link and bold emphases added.]

 

There doesn't appear to be much wiggle room here. Lenin clearly believed that sensations are images of the 'external world'. He repeatedly says things like this: "Our sensation, our consciousness is only an image of the external world..." and "[S]ensation is an image of the external world...." [Both quoted above.]

 

[However, it might well be wondered how an itch, a noise, or a smell could be an 'image', or what they could possibly be an 'image' of --, and he is quite clear that sensation (or perception), and hence 'images', are our only source of knowledge.]

 

Admittedly, Lenin did make some attempt to argue that we validate these 'images' by means of practice:

 

"Verification of these images, differentiation between true and false images, is given by practice." [Ibid., p.119. Bold emphasis added.]

 

But, as has already been pointed out, if Lenin is to be believed, all we have are images of practice, and hence no 'objective' way of distinguishing reliable from unreliable, valid from invalid 'images' of the latter. Unless human beings were somehow capable of 'leaping out of their heads', 'by-passing their sensory organs', there would be no way of escaping from the 'epistemological prison' Lenin has just constructed for himself.

 

Others have tried to argue that Lenin believed we have direct access to the outside world via our senses (otherwise known as Direct Realism -- we see this defence attempted in, for example, Goldstick (1980)) -- which theory supposedly by-passes all these 'images'. Well, Lenin might or might not have believed this (even though there is precious little textual support for such an interpretation; there is far more in support of the view that Lenin was a rather confused Representational Realist, of sorts -- but on this, see my comments earlier in this Essay concerning one passage from MEC some have quoted in support of the claim that Lenin accepted this form of Realism), the question is: how could he possibly know we have such 'direct access' if all we have are 'images' to guide us and rely on?

 

Again, Lenin might have sincerely believed he possessed eyes, ears, skin and other sense organs, and that they connected him with 'objective reality outside of himself', but, if his theory is correct, all he actually had were images of these organs, and hence images of the 'external world'.

 

Here he is again:

 

"This is either an idealist lie or the subterfuge of the agnostic, Comrade Bazarov, for sense-perception is not the reality existing outside us, it is only the image of that reality." [Ibid., p.124. Bold emphasis alone added.]

 

There is no hint in the above of any such 'direct access to reality'. Indeed, Lenin has inserted a layer of 'images' between himself and the 'outside world', the existence of which can now only be taken as an act of faith. Because Lenin has built a screen of 'images' between himself and the 'outside world', there is no way around, or through, this barrier. He is forever trapped behind it.

 

It could be objected that Lenin had in fact anticipated the above 'problem' since he quoted a reply to it that had already been offered by Engels:

 

"Now, this line of reasoning seems undoubtedly hard to beat by mere argumentation. But before there was argumentation there was action. Im Anfang war die That (sic). And human action had solved the difficulty long before human ingenuity invented it. The proof of the pudding is in the eating. From the moment we turn to our own use these objects, according to the qualities we perceive in them, we put to an infallible test the correctness or otherwise of our sense-perceptions. If these perceptions have been wrong, then our estimate of the use to which an object can be turned must also be wrong, and our attempt must fail. But if we succeed in accomplishing our aim, if we find that the object does agree with our idea of it, and does answer the purpose we intended it for, then that is positive proof that our perceptions of it and of its qualities, so far, agree with reality outside ourselves....

 

"And whenever we find ourselves face to face with a failure, then we generally are not long in making out the cause that made us fail; we find that the perception upon which we acted was either incomplete and superficial, or combined with the results of other perceptions in a way not warranted by them.... So long as we take care to train and to use our senses properly, and to keep our action within the limits prescribed by perceptions properly made and properly used, so long we shall find that the result of our action proves the conformity...of our perceptions with the objective...nature of the things perceived. Not in one single instance, so far, have we been led to the conclusion that our sense-perceptions, scientifically controlled, induce in our minds ideas respecting the outer world that are, by their very nature, at variance with reality, or that there is an inherent incompatibility between the outer world and our sense-perceptions of it." [Ibid., pp.118-20. Bold emphases alone added. Lenin is here quoting the Introduction to the English Edition of Engels (1892), p.381 (this links to a PDF). Bold emphases alone added.]

 

About which Lenin then remarked:

 

"Thus, the materialist theory, the theory of the reflection of objects by our mind, is here presented with absolute clarity: things exist outside us. Our perceptions and ideas are their images. Verification of these images, differentiation between true and false images, is given by practice." [Ibid., p.119. Bold emphasis added.] 

 

However, as noted above, Lenin made the mistake (which Engels didn't) of inserting a veil of 'images' between himself and the world, which he has yet to prove actually exists. He even reiterates the claim that originally created this 'problem': "Our perceptions and ideas are their images." Admittedly he also added that "[v]erification of these images, differentiation between true and false images, is given by practice", but no amount of observation, practice or science can remove this screen, since all Lenin now has are 'images' of science, 'images' of practice and 'images' of their supposed results.

 

How anyone is able to check and see, or otherwise discover, whether or not an "object [agreed] with [their] idea of it" when all they have are 'images' of said 'object', and no way of accessing 'it' independently of sensation (according to his own words), Lenin unwisely kept to himself.

 

[The difficulties Engels's theory itself faces are different from Lenin's, but they are equally insurmountable; they will be exposed in Essay Three Part Six, when it is published. Spoiler: Just like Lenin, Engels failed to explain how anyone could possibly find out "that the object does agree with our idea of it", so that they were able validly to conclude that "our perceptions...agree with reality outside ourselves". No good appealing to further practice in support, since, even on this theory, all anyone has are 'perceptions of practice'. Unless there were some way to access 'reality' that bypassed all the 'perceptions' that had just been inserted between 'the knower' and 'the known', appeal can't be made to "practice", "success" or even "science". They all exist or take place in a world Engels signally failed to prove exists. So, like Lenin, all Engels could fall back on was his unsubstantiated faith that there is such a world. This recurring 'problem' ought to suggest (to Dialectical Marxists) that this entire approach to cognition and the source of knowledge is defective from top to bottom. But, once more, this self-imposed predicament should hardly surprise a single DM-fan while they insist on taking philosophical advice from a Christian Mystic (upside down or the 'right way up'!).]

 

In which case, Lenin remains trapped behind a wall of 'images' all of his own making....

 

One of the few recognisably philosophical arguments to be found anywhere in MEC (aimed at countering the theories promoted by Idealists and Phenomenalists, etc.) is the following:

 

"Our sensation, our consciousness is only an image of the external world, and it is obvious that an image cannot exist without the thing imaged, and that the latter exists independently of that which images it. Materialism deliberately makes the 'naïve' belief of mankind the foundation of its theory of knowledge." [Ibid., p.69. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"The image inevitably and of necessity implies the objective reality of that which it 'images.'" [Ibid., p.279. Bold emphasis added.]

 

That's it! On the basis of this half-formed, quasi-argument Lenin hoped to counter philosophical theories some still regard as definitive -- especially when they are set against the sophomoric version of naïve realism Lenin tried to advance in MEC.

 

[I hasten to add that I don't consider the aforementioned philosophical theories in any way definitive! In fact, I regard all philosophical theories as incoherent non-sense. Again, I am merely drawing attention to Lenin's self-defeating approach to such questions in MEC.]

 

Before we consider whether or not Lenin's argument is successful in its own right, it is worth pointing out (to those dialecticians who question the deliverances of 'commonsense' -- which I take to be more-or-less the same as "naïve realism" referred to by Lenin --, and who also regale us with the 'appearance'/'reality' distinction) that 'commonsense' can't in fact be called into question if it is to act as a basis for Lenin's theory of knowledge.

 

[Those who think this an unfair criticism of Lenin should read on before they draw that rather hasty conclusion.]

 

Despite this, and given the other complexities that DM introduces, Lenin's alleged foundation stone soon starts to crumble into dust. According to DM-epistemology, knowledge depends on the completion of an infinite process before the very first thing can be known about anything in the DM-"Totality" with anything other than infinite uncertainty.

 

As we have seen (follow the previous link for proof), this approach to knowledge means that nobody is in any position to determine what even a simple tumbler is before everything about everything is already known.

 

In reply, it could be argued that the above anti-DM counter-claim is just another unfair caricature of dialectical epistemology. But, it is worth remembering that anyone who objects on those lines is similarly in no position to assert it successfully until we are given a clear (and non-defective) account of DM-epistemology. After only 150+ years, we are still waiting.

 

Indeed, given DM-epistemology, no one would be in any position to assert that the above anti-DM counter-claim is unfair and know they were speaking the truth until they too had completed the aforementioned infinite ascent of 'Epistemological Mount Olympus'.

 

This means that all forms of 'dialectical knowledge' are permanently trapped in this sceptical quagmire -- that is, if Engels and Lenin are to be believed.

 

[The above seemingly controversial claims were fully substantiated in Essay Ten Part One. Readers are directed there for more details.]

 

Despite this, it is worth reflecting on the sort of response that, say, a Phenomenalist might make to Lenin's assertion that his theory begins with the "naïve" beliefs of ordinary folk, and builds from there:

 

"The 'naïve realism' of any healthy person who has not been an inmate of a lunatic asylum or a pupil of the idealist philosophers consists in the view that things, the environment, the world, exist independently of our sensation, of our consciousness, of our self and of man in general. The same experience (not in the Machian sense, but in the human sense of the term) that has produced in us the firm conviction that independently of us there exist other people, and not mere complexes of my sensations of high, short, yellow, hard, etc. -- this same experience produces in us the conviction that things, the world, the environment exist independently of us. Our sensation, our consciousness is only an image of the external world, and it is obvious that an image cannot exist without the thing imaged, and that the latter exists independently of that which images it. Materialism deliberately makes the 'naïve' belief of mankind the foundation of its theory of knowledge." [Ibid., pp.68-69. Bold emphases alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

She (the supposed Phenomenalist) might wonder what, for instance, the word "image" is doing in such prosaic surroundings. Indeed, she might even suggest that if we were to ask the average human being about their knowledge of the world, the word "image" would appear nowhere in the reply.

 

Hence, not only is the aforementioned dialectical meander through infinite epistemological space counter-productive (since it implies infinite and permanent ignorance of everything and anything), it begins in the wrong place! 'Commonsense' and/or "naïve realism" -- whatever they are -- neither start nor end with 'images'.

 

[Admittedly, certain forms of phenomenalist psychology might do so, but 'commonsense' does not. Or, if it does, we still await the proof. That 'proof' would be worthless, anyway, since it too would merely consist of, or would be based on, yet more 'images', if Lenin were to be believed!]

 

It is worth pressing this point home: there is no evidence that the "naïve" beliefs of anyone -- not even the naïve beliefs of Dialectical Marxists -- are based on 'internal images', but there is much to suggest they aren't. Hence, there is no evidence that ordinary people, or even sophisticated socialists, believe any of the following (that is, before they had encountered the DM-classics, traditional epistemology and/or 'pop science'):

 

"Our sensation, our consciousness is only an image of the external world…." [Ibid., p.69. Bold emphasis alone added.]

 

"The gist of his theoretical mistake in this case is substitution of eclecticism for the dialectical interplay of politics and economics (which we find in Marxism). His theoretical attitude is: 'on the one hand, and on the other', 'the one and the other'. That is eclecticism. Dialectics requires an all-round consideration of relationships in their concrete development but not a patchwork of bits and pieces. I have shown this to be so on the example of politics and economics....

 

"A tumbler is assuredly both a glass cylinder and a drinking vessel. But there are more than these two properties, qualities or facets to it; there are an infinite number of them, an infinite number of 'mediacies' and inter-relationships with the rest of the world.... Formal logic, which is as far as schools go (and should go, with suitable abridgements for the lower forms), deals with formal definitions, draws on what is most common, or glaring, and stops there. When two or more different definitions are taken and combined at random (a glass cylinder and a drinking vessel), the result is an eclectic definition which is indicative of different facets of the object, and nothing more. Dialectical logic demands that we should go further. Firstly, if we are to have a true knowledge of an object we must look at and examine all its facets, its connections and 'mediacies'. That is something we cannot ever hope to achieve completely, but the rule of comprehensiveness is a safeguard against mistakes and rigidity. Secondly, dialectical logic requires that an object should be taken in development, in change, in 'self-movement' (as Hegel sometimes puts it). This is not immediately obvious in respect of such an object as a tumbler, but it, too, is in flux, and this holds especially true for its purpose, use and connection with the surrounding world. Thirdly, a full 'definition' of an object must include the whole of human experience, both as a criterion of truth and a practical indicator of its connection with human wants. Fourthly, dialectical logic holds that 'truth is always concrete, never abstract', as the late Plekhanov liked to say after Hegel...." [Lenin (1921), pp.90-93. Bold emphases alone added; quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Several paragraphs merged.]

 

In order to see this, consider the following example; suppose worker, NN, asserted the following:

 

L1: "That policeman hit me over the head with a truncheon!"

 

Now, only a rather desperate cop-defender would respond with this remark:

 

L2: "You are mistaken. What you experienced was in fact only an image of a policeman assaulting you."

 

We can be reasonably sure that NN doesn't need to wait for the asymptotic-train-of-knowledge to hit the buffers-of-absolute-certainty before she can claim to know what happened on the said picket line as the cops attacked it. Indeed, NN would be justifiably angry if a DM-fan tried to tell her that her knowledge of these uniformed assailants was only relative and partial, and that she had failed to consider all those pesky "mediacies" before arriving at such a 'rash' conclusion. Moreover, we can be quite certain now (without the presence of an accompanying 'image' -- and even before the epistemological train leaves the dialectical sidings on its endless meander to nowhere-in-particular) that NN knows she was hit on the head and who was responsible for it.

 

Indeed, that would be the line Socialist Worker and other revolutionary papers would (correctly) take if one of its correspondents witnessed Police violence -- in cases like the Police riot in Chicago in 1968, or in Red Lion Square London in 1974, or in relation to the death of Blair Peach in Southall 1979, the UK Miners' Strike, the picketing at Wapping in 1986, the march against the Nazis at Welling a few years later, the Police riots in Trafalgar Square in 1990, those in London in April 2009, Genoa in 2001 and 2003, those in New York and San Francisco in 2003, or even those in 2011 to clear the Occupy Movement off the streets, etc., etc. In fact, their readers would know precisely when they could stop trusting Socialist Worker and other Marxist papers: just as soon as they began describing such events in the way that Lenin characterised "knowledge", or if they started referring to the "images" in people's heads, offering the latter as 'solid evidence' substantiating claims made about Police violence -- as opposed to reporting the actual incidents themselves, referring them to video footage, photographs, witness statements and medical reports (etc.). Or, if those papers were foolish enough to insist that every "mediacy" had to be taken into account before anyone could decide what had actually happened on a given picket line or demonstration, and what to do about it.

 

Unsurprisingly then, in the Miners' Strike, for instance, the actual incidents were reported in Socialist Worker and other Marxist papers/articles (the same is true of subsequent analyses presented in their more theoretical journals and publications -- that also includes their websites). All wisely omit any reference to "internal images", or even "partial" and "relative knowledge", let alone any obvious "asymptotes" that might otherwise only be of interest to sundry Idealists.

 

Hence, in practice not one single revolutionary paper, book or article begins with "internal images" when covering the class war -- nor do they bang on about concepts eternally converging on reality. Not even the worst union bureaucrat in the history of the labour movement would adopt such language as a way of excusing the latest sell-out! That is, that everything that happens is just an "image"! Or that nothing should be done to help build a given strike before the infinite asymptote of knowledge had finally reached the safe haven of the 'x-axis'.

 

Update, May 1st 2024: Here, for example, is how Socialist Worker is currently reporting the murder of student protester, Jeffrey Miller, at Kent State University, Ohio, in May 1970 by The National Guard (in connection with Police violence on display in connection with the pro-Palestinian protests sweeping across the USA at present):

 

"Sometimes an image can capture a turning point in history. The photograph of Mary Ann Vecchio kneeling over the body of Jeffrey Miller [the picture is reproduced in the report, but it has been omitted from this quoted passage -- RL], who was shot dead by the Ohio National Guard at Kent State University on 4 May 1970, is one of those photos. On that day 54 years ago, national guards murdered four students who had been rallying against the United States. extension of its war in Vietnam into Cambodia. Not two weeks after, the police killed two students at Jackson State University, a historically black university. Revulsion that the government had brought killing sprees onto US soil spread across the country. It wasn't long before millions of students were on strike and protesting on the streets. It was a disaster for the ruling class and for president Richard Nixon, who eventually could no longer withstand the pressure from the anti-war movement. Finally he was forced to abandon his plans to expand the ruling class's war in Vietnam. The students now fighting for Palestine and battling the cops stand in the same spirit as the anti-war movement in the 1960s and 70s. And their resistance can also help bring the ruling class to its knees. A mass movement for Palestine that spills out of the campuses, onto the streets and into the workplaces could make it impossible for the US state to continue its support for Israeli slaughter in Gaza. And we have to try to do the same in Britain." [Quoted from here; accessed 01/05/2024. Links in the original. Paragraphs merged.]

 

The only image spoken about in fact concerns a widely circulated photograph of that poor student's lifeless body. Readers are invited to check if the article mentions any 'images' in people's heads. [Spoiler: it doesn't!]

 

Here, too, is a report posted at the World Socialist Web Site concerning attacks launched by New York Police on another group of pro-Palestinian protesters:

 

"At around 9 p.m. Tuesday night [i.e., 30/04/24 -- RL], hundreds of New York Police Department (NYPD) riot police descended on Columbia University to conduct mass arrests of students protesting the ongoing genocide in Gaza. Video shared on social media shows heavily armoured police arresting students and faculty attempting to block their access to the university. In order to prevent objective documentation of their brutality, police forced legal observers, press and medics to leave the campus area, and even public streets nearby, before they began their assault. As of this writing it is unclear how many protesters have been arrested and the extent of their injuries. The police brutality witnessed at Columbia Tuesday night was replicated across the country. At the University of South Florida in Tampa, riot police were recorded firing tear gas and rubber bullets against unarmed and peaceful protesters. The coordinated and violent assaults on non-violent student encampments have been ordered from the White House. On Tuesday, the Biden administration issued a series of statements doubling down on the lie that anti-Gaza genocide protests continuing to spread across US university campuses are anti-Semitic, signalling its support for stepped-up police attacks and arrests of peaceful protesters." [Quoted from here; accessed 01/05/2024. Spelling modified to agree with UK English. Paragraphs merged.]

 

Other than the video footage mentioned in this report (which film doesn't exist inside anyone's brain, anyway), can any of my readers spot a single mention of 'images' in anyone's head?

 

In fact, it is more than a little surprising that die-hard supporters of Lenin's theory never point out to the publishers and editors of Socialist Worker and other Marxist papers, journals, books and websites where they are going wrong -- i.e., when they foolishly report on actual events in the real world and ignore all those 'images' in diverse skulls. Why hasn't a single admirer of MEC written to these publications to insist that reports of, say, neo-Nazi violence be replaced with descriptions of 'images' in victims' heads? Whatever one thinks of the far left press, none of them have ever even hinted that their reports are defective because they foolishly write about actual events in the real world, recklessly and irresponsibly ignoring 'images' inside the skulls of observers and victims alike. Or, that they failed to mention any of those pesky "mediacies" and annoying "asymptotes".

 

Anyway, despite what he said, Lenin didn't actually begin with the "naïve" beliefs of mankind, he did the opposite: he undermined them from the start. Indeed, he began with theories concocted by notorious ruling-class hacks, even if he modified and adapted them to his own ends. This he did by reducing ordinary belief (partially or completely) to images, or he based such beliefs on them. The same can be said of any socialist (reporter or otherwise) who does likewise -- for example, by writing about the images of Police brutality inflicted on the images of miners in an image of 1984, which images of events occurred in their image of Orgreave --, in their paper (or an image of it).

 

[And it is little use being told that Lenin argued that such 'images' reflect 'objective' reality; the point at issue is whether or not he began with the naive beliefs of ordinary people. The question whether they actually reflect 'objective' reality will be considered below.]

 

In general, the actual starting point for DM-supporters is invariably consistent with an overt denigration of the vernacular. That is often accompanied by a condescending devaluation of the lives and experience of ordinary workers -- since it is claimed that many have been 'bought-off' by super-profits, or have been mesmerised by the 'banalities' of 'commonsense', hypnotised by 'formal thinking'/'commodity fetishism' --, which elitist paradigm DM-fans have in general copied from the patronising, dismissive and belittling attitude perennially displayed toward workers by the aforementioned ruling-class hacks.

 

[There is more on this in Essay Twelve (summary here).]

 

Clearly, this is the real "copy theory of knowledge":

 

(i) Reproduce the ideas and thought-forms of ruling-class ideologues; and,

 

(ii) Make sure your theories are an exact image of theirs!

 

Rees's Defence

[This Is Still Under Construction!]

 

Rees addresses none of the above problems in his book (or, indeed, anywhere else, as far as can be ascertained -- nor is there any sign he is even aware of them!), and neither has any other DM-supporter. That isn't to say that no one has tried to defend Lenin; far from it. I have already mentioned three who have -- Goldstick, Sayers, and, of course, Rees. [In Essay Thirteen Part One, I briefly examined some of the arguments advanced by another prominent defender of Lenin, Ruben. However, Ruben's book -- i.e., Ruben (1979) -- will be examined in greater detail in Essay Three Part Six. I would do so here, but this Essay is already far too long! Sayers defence will be addressed in Appendix Five. Another important defender of Lenin is Althusser, in Althusser (2001). His defence will also be scrutinised in Part Six.] Nevertheless, none of them address the (rather obvious) objections raised at this site, especially those aired in Essay Thirteen Part One.

 

Of course, the above criticisms were first published on-line more than ten years after Rees's book appeared, and many more after Goldstick, Sayers and Ruben's so it is hardly surprising they failed to address them! [Not that Rees, for example, would even deign to read this material or reply to it, even if he knew about it; after all, he blocked me on Twitter (now X) a few years ago for having the temerity, the 'audacity', to question, in the mildest of terms, 'the sacred dialectic'!]

 

But what shape does his defence of Lenin take, anyway? Here are the relevant passages from TAR (but, because italic and bold emphases both appear in the original, I have had to alter the bold highlighting present in the original in order to emphasise the words relevant to the points I want to make; italic emphases have been left as they appear in Rees's book):

 

"What does this conception of consciousness mean for Lenin's theory of knowledge? It required that Lenin make a considerable, though not complete, break with the ideas contained in Materialism and Empirio-criticism. First, let's look at what did not change. Lenin, of course, remained a materialist. He continued to insist that material reality existed independently of human thought and, indeed, that the very ability to think was a product of natural development: 'Concepts, and the art of operating with concepts are not inborn, but is the result of 2,000 years of the development of natural science and philosophy.' Thus, 'men's ends are engendered by the objective world and presuppose it, -- they find it as something given, present,' consequently, 'the dialectics of things produces the dialectics of ideas, and not vice versa.'

 

[The second two passages Rees briefly quotes are: Lenin (1961), pp.189,196. I can't find the first one anywhere in Lenin (1961), certainly not on the page Rees himself referenced (p.264). Minor typo corrected -- RL.]

 

"It is important not to lose sight of the fact that Lenin never abandoned this commitment to materialism. This is especially the case, because some otherwise valuable analyses of Lenin's Philosophical Notebooks, most recently Kevin Anderson's Lenin, Hegel and Western Marxism, tend to underestimate this element of continuity in Lenin's thought. Yet these broad statements of materialism were only the beginning of the problem, not its solution. They could not, for instance, furnish an account of the relationship between the dialectic of ideas and the dialectic of reality, which Lenin obviously no longer conceived in the linear and one-dimensional pattern outlined in Materialism and Empirio-criticism. The language of 'copies' and 'photographs' is entirely absent from the Philosophical Notebooks. Lenin still sometimes talks of consciousness reflecting reality in a general sense, but the term is rarely used without substantial qualification:

 

'The reflection of nature in man's thought must be understood not "lifelessly," not "abstractly," not devoid of movement, not without contradictions, but in the eternal process of movement, the arising of contradictions and their solution.' [Rees is here quoting Lenin (1961), p.195. Emphases in the original -- RL.]

 

"Indeed, Lenin insists that, 'Man cannot comprehend=reflect=mirror nature as a whole, in its completeness, its "immediate totality," he can only eternally come closer to this creating abstractions, concepts, laws, a scientific picture of the world, etc., etc.' [Rees is here quoting Lenin (1961), p.182 -- RL.] This is impossible partly because gaining knowledge is an infinite process, as Lenin had already noted in Materialism and Empiro-criticism. But now Lenin adds that it is also impossible because knowledge requires an active process of abstraction capable of discriminating between essence and appearance. This process is simply not possible using a crude copy theory of consciousness. Lenin himself makes the point:

 

'Logic is the science of cognition. It is the theory of knowledge. Knowledge is the reflection of nature by man. But this is not a simple, not an immediate, not a complete reflection, but the process of a series of abstractions, the formation and development of concepts, laws, etc., and these concepts, laws, etc.,… embrace conditionally, approximately, the universal, law governed character of eternally moving and developing nature.'  [This is also from Lenin (1961), p.182 -- RL.]

 

"Thus, Lenin develops a more active and independent role for consciousness than the framework of Materialism and Empirio-criticism could allow. He even went so far as to exclaim, 'Man's consciousness not only reflects the world, but creates it.' [Rees is here quoting Lenin (1961), p.212 -- RL.] That sentiment could never have found its way into Materialism and Empirio-criticism, if only because Bogdanov would have seized on it as contradicting Lenin's whole line of argument. Such ideas required a dialectical theory of cognition to root them in a marxist framework, and this was precisely what Materialism and Empirio-criticism lacked. But wasn't Lenin purchasing this more independent role for consciousness at the expense of scientific precision? How can we know that our consciousness really corresponds to the world if it is only an 'approximate,' 'conditional,' and abstract representation of reality? Lenin's answer has two aspects. First, abstraction can be a method of seeing reality more clearly, as we saw in relation to the question of essence and appearance, and, second, consciousness must issue in practical activity, which will furnish the proof of whether or not our conceptions of the world are accurate.

 

'Thought proceeding from the concrete to the abstract…does not get away from the truth but comes closer to it. The abstraction of matter, of a law of nature, the abstraction of value, etc., in short all scientific abstractions reflect nature more deeply, truly and completely. From living perception to abstract thought, and from this to practice, -- such is the dialectical path of the cognition of truth, of the cognition of objective reality.' [Rees is here quoting Lenin (1961), p.171 -- RL.]

 

"The second leg of this process, the movement to practice, is crucial because what is involved is a fusion of intellectual understanding and objective existence. Human action, in the sense that Marx understood the question in his analysis of human labour, is not simply an extension of thought nor merely an objective occurrence in the external world, like the wind blowing the branch of a tree. It is a conscious act. In conscious activity, human beings overcome the abstractness of thought by integrating it with concrete, immediate reality in all its complexity -- this is the moment when we see whether thought really does assume an objective form, whether it really can create the world, or whether it has mistaken the nature of reality and therefore is unable to enter the historical chain as an objective force which, in the case of the class struggle, seizes the masses. This is Lenin's meaning when he writes 'practice is higher than (theoretical) knowledge, for it has not only the dignity of universality, but also of immediate actuality.' [Rees is here quoting Lenin (1961), p.213. Emphasis in the original -- RL.] Or, in a slightly elaborated version of the same point:

 

'The activity of man, who has made an objective picture of the world for himself, changes external actuality, abolishes its determinedness (=alters some sides or other, qualities, of it), thus removes from it the features of Semblance, externality and nullity, and makes it as being in and for itself (=objectively true).' [Rees is here quoting Lenin (1961), pp.217-18. Bold emphasis added -- RL.]

 

"We can see here how for Lenin practice overcomes the distinction between subjective and objective and the gap between essence and appearance. The ground for this theoretical discovery had been laid by Lenin's theory of the party, always the most dialectical and the most important element in his marxism. The whole conception of a party that is part of, but for long periods separated from, the majority of the working class demands a dialectic that understands the unity of opposites, the essential nature of practice, and the concrete historical nature of development." [Rees (1998), pp.189-91. Spelling modified in line with UK English; quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Minor typos corrected; several paragraphs merged.]              

 

Rees is correct; Lenin's 'theory of knowledge' underwent significant changes between the writing of MEC and PN, even though there were important areas he didn't abandon (which Rees also briefly summarised). However, the phrase "theory of knowledge" has rightly been put in 'scare' quotes since it would be stretching the meaning of that phrase beyond breaking point to call what Lenin had to say on this topic in PN a theory. Free of irony or even sarcasm, what Lenin had to say in PN is far too brief, superficial, enigmatic and fragmentary for it to be so described (with a straight face). What he had to say is perhaps better described as 'scattered, enigmatic remarks'. It isn't easy to cobble-together a coherent theory of knowledge, adhered to by Lenin, even if we also focus on MEC, for goodness sake, never mind PN!

 

Nevertheless, Lenin nowhere repudiates his earlier comments about the sole source of our knowledge -- i.e., that it derives from experience/sensation and results in 'images'. In PN he certainly qualifies those earlier ideas, adding an active input of the intellect/'consciousness', in combination with practice (which, as we have seen, was a factor also underlined in MEC). In PN, there is an added emphasis on 'abstraction', which, as we have come to expect from every single DM-theorist, Lenin nowhere even gestures at explaining.

 

And that can be said with equal validity about Rees's book, TAR -- he nowhere even attempts to explain this 'process'.

 

We are, however, told the following (on p.189):

 

"The language of 'copies' and 'photographs' is entirely absent from the Philosophical Notebooks. Lenin still sometimes talks of consciousness reflecting reality in a general sense, but the term is rarely used without substantial qualification:

 

'The reflection of nature in man's thought must be understood not "lifelessly," not "abstractly," not devoid of movement, not without contradictions, but in the eternal process of movement, the arising of contradictions and their solution.' [Rees is here quoting Lenin (1961), p.195. Emphases in the original -- RL.]

 

But it might well be asked: How does 'reflection' work if it doesn't create 'images'? What does it produce? What does 'consciousness' operate with? This, apparently:

 

"Indeed, Lenin insists that, 'Man cannot comprehend=reflect=mirror nature as a whole, in its completeness, its "immediate totality," he can only eternally come closer to this creating abstractions, concepts, laws, a scientific picture of the world, etc., etc.' [Rees is here quoting Lenin (1961), p.182 -- RL.] This is impossible partly because gaining knowledge is an infinite process, as Lenin had already noted in Materialism and Empiro-criticism. But now Lenin adds that it is also impossible because knowledge requires an active process of abstraction capable of discriminating between essence and appearance. This process is simply not possible using a crude copy theory of consciousness. Lenin himself makes the point:

 

'Logic is the science of cognition. It is the theory of knowledge. Knowledge is the reflection of nature by man. But this is not a simple, not an immediate, not a complete reflection, but the process of a series of abstractions, the formation and development of concepts, laws, etc., and these concepts, laws, etc.,… embrace conditionally, approximately, the universal, law governed character of eternally moving and developing nature.'  [This is also from Lenin (1961), p.182.]

 

"Thus, Lenin develops a more active and independent role for consciousness than the framework of Materialism and Empirio-criticism could allow." [Rees, op cit, pp.189-90; bold emphases alone added.]

 

So, from the above it is clear that knowledge is still 'produced' (directly or indirectly) by:

 

(1) 'Reflection', even if this is just one aspect of, or factor in, an endless, even an "infinite process";

 

(2) 'Reflection' (somehow) produces, or leads to the creation of, "abstractions, concepts, laws, which are all part scientific picture of the world" (which is constantly being revised/improved); and,

 

(3) The updated, 'dialectical' theory developed in PN emphasises the active input both of 'practice' and 'consciousness' -- although Lenin and Rees fail to tell us if this is an individual or collective sort of 'consciousness', or even if 'consciousness' is itself an abstraction. (More on that presently.)

 

As we discovered in Part One of Essay Three, the nature of these "abstractions" is entirely mysterious, so exactly how the introduction of this term can help clarify anything is far from perspicuous.

 

After quoting several attempts by DM-theorists to explain the nature of an 'abstraction', I made the following points in Part One (slightly edited):

 

[P]erhaps there is some way of harmonising these passages that allows DM-supporters to come up with a convincing, or even a plausible, answer to the following questions:

 

(a) What is the precise nature of these DM-"abstractions"? And,

 

(b) Exactly what do they 'represent' or 'reflect' in nature and society, and how do they do it?

 

Satisfactory replies to both of the above from DM-fans would lend credence to the claim that their ideas haven't been "imposed" on nature and society, after all. However, given the additional fact that DM-supporters invariably ignore such 'pedantic quibbles' (or they are hand-waved aside), readers are advised not to hold their breath waiting for an effective, or even a plausible, response. Those same readers might like to ask DM-fans themselves for a clear answer to the above two questions. They will receive no such reply.

 

[If, per impossible, any of my readers do manage to receive a clear answer, please contact me with the details. In that eventuality I'll be keeping watch for a few flying pigs. There should be dozens of them!]

 

Be this as it may, another question now forces itself upon us:

 

(c) How is it possible for DM-theorists to avoid the Scylla of dogmatism while evading the Charybdis of Empiricism?

 

Well, in [Part One of this Essay] we will find out how they manage to avoid the latter by unfortunately careering headlong into the former -- i.e., by the way they all proceed "from principles which are validated by appeal to abstract reason, intuition, self-evidence or some other subjective or purely theoretical source" (to quote George Novack, again), despite their frequent protestations....

 

To state the obvious, without minds to invent them there would be no abstractions. On the surface, therefore, it looks like any theory committed to the 'objective' existence of 'abstractions' (or, "real abstractions") must be Idealist, whatever complaints are made to the contrary. As we will see, even when we dig 'below the surface', Idealist implications like these are difficult to resist. In which case, the above phrase, "looks like", itself turns out to be far too tentative, and by a rather wide margin, too.

 

If 'abstractions' aren't 'objective' -- that is, if they aren't "mind-independent", or if they fail to relate to (i.e., refer to) anything that exists in "mind-independent" reality --, it is difficult to see how they could possibly assist anyone construct an accurate or truthful theory of the world, or, at least, a theory that is supposed to be 'objective'. Nor is it easy to see how scientific knowledge could advance by means of 'abstractions' if they are somehow fictional. How could fictional concepts help account for a... -- for want of a better phrase -- ...non-fictional world?

 

Well, perhaps there is a way of interpreting the nature of abstractions, or what they supposedly 'reflect' in 'reality' -- that is, if they actually 'reflect' anything other than what is 'in the mind' of the one who invented them -- that succeeds in rescuing them from the world of make-believe. On the other hand, could it be that their only 'legitimate' role is to help maintain the morale of scientists and philosophers -- by making it easier to sell the idea that their latest theories are valid? That is, might it not turn out that 'abstractions' simply enable those who believe in them construct grandiose theories concerning 'fundamental features reality', valid for all of space and time, in the comfort of their own heads? One suspects so. And if those suspicions bear fruit, much of Traditional Thought should then perhaps be classified as a considerably less entertaining, but far more dogmatic, version of the collected works of the Brothers Grimm -- that is, as Fantasy Fiction on steroids.

 

On the other hand, if abstractions are 'objective' -- but only 'minds' are capable of constructing, or even of appreciating, them --, questions would naturally arise over what they could possibly reflect in nature. Exactly what is it in 'extra-mental reality' that corresponds with an 'abstract idea'? What do they capture 'in the world' if they only exist 'in the mind'?

 

Of course, for non-materialists and old-fashioned Realists, quibbles like these present few problems --, except perhaps in connection with awkward questions raised about the precise meaning of the word "objective".

 

Indeed, for Traditional Theorists the ultimate constituents of reality were in the end often taken to be either:

 

(i) Mind-like objects;

 

(ii) Non-material "concepts"; or,

 

(iii) "Ideas" floating about in some abstract 'mental', or even 'divine', arena.

 

In that case, the word "objective" -- that is, before its meaning flipped a couple of centuries ago (it used to mean what "subjective" now does, and vice versa; on this, see Daston (1994), and Daston and Galison (2007)) -- would almost be synonymous with another word frequently used these days, namely, "Ideal". In fact, at a fundamental level it isn't easy to distinguish old-fashioned Realists (i.e., Platonists and neo-Platonists) from Objective Idealists -- except, perhaps, in the way they both view logic/change --, and, truth be told, as far as the latter were concerned, the word "objective" clearly did no real work. But, the same can easily be said of "Ideal", and its close relative, "idealisation".

 

However, the same can't be said about dialecticians -- but only if we accept at face value their version of DM -- that is, that it represents Hegel's 'theory'/'method' put 'back on its feet', stripped of its outer 'mystical shell'. Nevertheless, and controversially, it can and will be said of them -- after the tangled undergrowth surrounding much of what they do say has been cleared, its roots in Traditional Thought exposed for all to see.

 

Oddly enough, we find a DM-classicist like Lenin arguing along such familiar lines, for all the world sounding like a born-again Realist with added Hegelian spin:

 

"Thought proceeding from the concrete to the abstract -- provided it is correct (NB)… -- does not get away from the truth but comes closer to it. The abstraction of matter, the law of nature, the abstraction of value, etc., in short all scientific (correct, serious, not absurd) abstractions reflect nature more deeply, truly and completely." [Lenin (1961), p.171. Emphases in the original.]

 

"Knowledge is the reflection of nature by man. But this is not simple, not an immediate, not a complete reflection, but the process of a series of abstractions, the formation and development of concepts, laws, etc., and these concepts, laws, etc., (thought, science = 'the logical Idea') embrace conditionally, approximately, the universal, law-governed character of eternally moving and developing nature." [Ibid., p.182. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

Unfortunately, Lenin forgot to say how any of this rather ambitious project is at all possible if abstractions are nothing but the creations of the human mind. If scientific knowledge more truly reflects the world the more its abstractions are correct, or valid, how is that possible if they don't actually exist 'objectively' in the material world, in some form or other for scientists, or, indeed, for Marxist philosophers, to reflect?

 

Once again: if abstractions don't exist in the 'outside world', what is there in nature for them to reflect, for them to represent to us, or for them to refer to in 'extra-mental reality'?

 

Recall that for Lenin, and those who agree with him, 'objectivity' concerns whatever exists exterior to, and independent of, the human mind, ratified by practice:

 

"The sole and unavoidable deduction to be made from this -- a deduction which all of us make in everyday practice and which materialism deliberately places at the foundation of its epistemology -- is that outside us, and independently of us, there exist objects, things, bodies and that our perceptions are images of the external world...." [Lenin (1972), p.111. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"To be a materialist is to acknowledge objective truth, which is revealed to us by our sense-organs. To acknowledge objective truth, i.e., truth not dependent upon man and mankind, is, in one way or another, to recognise absolute truth...." [Ibid., p.148.]

 

"Knowledge can be useful biologically, useful in human practice, useful for the preservation of life, for the preservation of the species, only when it reflects objective truth, truth which is independent of man." [Ibid., p.157.]

 

"[T]he sole 'property' of matter with whose recognition philosophical materialism is bound up is the property of being an objective reality, of existing outside our mind." [Ibid., p.311.]

 

"Thus…the concept of matter…epistemologically implies nothing but objective reality existing independently of the human mind and reflected by it." [Ibid., p.312.]

         

"[I]t is the sole categorical, this sole unconditional recognition of nature's existence outside the mind and perception of man that distinguishes dialectical materialism from relativist agnosticism and idealism." [Ibid., p.314.]

 

"The fundamental characteristic of materialism is that it starts from the objectivity of science, from the recognition of objective reality reflected by science." [Ibid., pp.354-55.]

 

Lenin never once repudiated the above claims.

 

That can only mean DM-abstractions can't be 'objective'. Plainly, that is because they don't exist "outside our minds".

 

[As we will see, practice can't rescue DM-abstractions from this bottomless pit of 'subjectivity', either.]

 

On the other hand, if we simply ignore 'annoying quibbles' like these -- and even if we were to suppose that abstractions actually exist in the 'outside world' so that abstract general words can and do refer to them, or which can and do 'reflect' them --, what form do any such 'abstractions' take? Of what are they composed? Worse still: where do they exist? And how can they possibly interact with human thought? As soon as they are capable of being experienced they become particular, not general. In that eventuality, the whole point of inventing them (i.e., to rise above the particular by ascending to the general -- as we will see below) would be lost. It seems that, because of their nature, they can't be 'objects of experience'. What then are they?

 

Are we somehow 'mentally linked' (or can we even be 'linked') with, or to, them? Is that the case? But, as we have just seen, there appears to be no conceivable way they could be physically connected to us, or could even physically interact with us, without automatically losing their status as abstract general 'concepts'.

 

Or, do we perceive them by what is in effect the equivalent of a 'non-physical' Third Eye? [As we will see in Part Two, this is indeed (roughly) how Rationalist Philosophers tended to approach this topic; readers are directed there for more details.]

 

Perhaps so; indeed, as August Thalheimer let slip (in relation to another of this theory's core precepts):

 

"Only a person trained in dialectics will perceive the permeation of opposites. Of course, this does not depend only upon training in dialectics, but also upon the class viewpoint, the social viewpoint which the individual adopts." [Thalheimer (1936), p.164.]

 

Maybe that is also true of DM-abstractions? Only the faithful, only those with the 'eyes to see', can 'see' them....

 

Perhaps this is being a little too hasty? Maybe dialecticians are capable of seeing or apprehending 'abstractions' by a special 'act of cognition'. If so, the Idealist implications of that source of knowledge would be plain for all to see (no pun intended). Indeed, it finds immediate echo in Plato:

 

"If mind and true opinion are two distinct classes, then I say that there certainly are these self-existent ideas unperceived by sense, and apprehended only by the mind; if, however, as some say, true opinion differs in no respect from mind, then everything that we perceive through the body is to be regarded as most real and certain. But we must affirm that to be distinct, for they have a distinct origin and are of a different nature; the one is implanted in us by instruction, the other by persuasion; the one is always accompanied by true reason, the other is without reason; the one cannot be overcome by persuasion, but the other can: and lastly, every man may be said to share in true opinion, but mind is the attribute of the gods and of very few men. Wherefore also we must acknowledge that there is one kind of being which is always the same, uncreated and indestructible, never receiving anything into itself from without, nor itself going out to any other, but invisible and imperceptible by any sense, and of which the contemplation is granted to intelligence only." [Plato (1997c), 51e-52a, pp.1254-55. I have used the on-line version here. Bold emphases added. The published edition translates the third set of highlighted words as follows: "It is indivisible -- it cannot be perceived by the senses at all -- and it is the role of the understanding to study it." Cornford renders it thus: "[It is] invisible and otherwise imperceptible; that, in fact, which thinking has for its object." [Cornford (1997), p.192.]

 

As far as Idealists are concerned, Plato's comments present few immediate difficulties -- although, Essay Three Part Two (Sections One and Two) will show this dogmatic approach to knowledge introduces serious problems of its own..

 

Nevertheless, this leaves dialecticians with more than a few annoying headaches, the origin and cause of which Essay Three (in all its Parts) aims to expose.

 

To that end, and in order to make genuine progress, we will need something a little more helpful than Lenin's enigmatic prose to light our way. Surprising as this might seem to those still living under a rock, DM-theorists have to this day remained studiously silent on these issues -- saving, of course, where they are content merely to repeat Lenin's words verbatim in the vain hope that repetition will generate clarity where enigmatic prose on its own manifestly can't....

 

Each (genuine) abstraction therefore seems to operate like some sort of 'conceptual key' capable of unlocking secrets that govern the 'inner workings' of the entire universe, an artefact of thought that supplies each mind prepared to indulge in this ancient sport with universally valid principles -- important components of which, oddly enough, don't actually exist anywhere in 'extra-mental reality'!

 

However, in order to exert a little more pressure on the opposing idea (that 'abstractions' actually do exist somehow, somewhere...), it might prove helpful to raise a handful of additional questions:

 

(d) If abstractions are general in form, and do in fact exist in the 'outside world', how does that 'generality' actually express itself?

 

(e) Is an abstraction somehow 'spread out', as it were -- like some sort of 'metaphysical liquid' or 'force field' -- in, or over, the 'concrete particulars' that supposedly instantiate it, uniting the diversity we see all around us, perhaps by a 'mysterious power'/'influence' as yet unbeknown to us?

 

(f) Or, are abstractions merely an aspect of the complex tales human beings tell one another? Are they simply subjective stories in pseudo-objective drag, but which are essential for the successful advancement of knowledge (even though they aren't really 'real' in themselves)?

 

(g) Are they not then simply useful fictions?

 

Unfortunately, the questionable origin of the traditional approach to knowledge (in the theories developed by openly Idealist Philosophers) has done little to improve its image among materialists, nor does it inspire much confidence. Small wonder then that consistent materialists have, in general, regarded abstract ideas as guilty until proven even more guilty.

 

Nevertheless, more work will need to be done before it becomes clear whether or not 'abstractions' aren't simply useful fictions, handy at least for maintaining the morale of scientists, or, indeed, for giving dialecticians something over which they can endlessly perseverate --, and, if we are brutally honest, precious little else.

 

Short of burying this entire topic under layers of impenetrable Hegelian jargon, dialecticians haven't advanced much beyond the 'subjective stage', if such it may be called. In fact, as we will see, the way they conceive of abstractions, and the 'process' by which they have been given life, undermines the very generality they had all along been introduced to explain.

 

As should now seem reasonably clear: if true, that accusation would completely undermine the DM-theory of knowledge.

 

This ironic 'dialectical inversion' -- whereby DM-abstractions end up killing the very theory that spawned them -- will be the subject of the rest of this Essay -- and Part Two.

 

Readers will search long and hard, and to no avail, through Rees's entire book (and the writings of other DM-theorists, like those mentioned earlier) for any answers to such questions, or even a vague recognition that they are aware of these 'problems', still less any sign they care to find out. Talk about living in an epistemological bubble, something we rightly accuse right-wingers of doing.

 

[Having said that, Rees does make some attempt in TAR to explain what the (supposed) abstract concept 'friendship' actually means. What he had to say will be analysed in detail in Essay Twelve Part Four.] 

 

It therefore looks like 'abstractions' aren't supposed to be images; what then are they? Again, as we found out in Part One, they typically make an appearance, in physical form, as the Proper Names of "abstract particulars" (no pun intended), thus destroying their generality. [That was the main theme of Part One.]

 

However, Lenin also had this to say:

 

"Man cannot comprehend=reflect=mirror nature as a whole, in its completeness, its 'immediate totality,' he can only eternally come closer to this creating abstractions, concepts, laws, a scientific picture of the world, etc., etc." [Lenin (1961), p.182. Bold emphasis alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

"The activity of man, who has made an objective picture of the world for himself, changes external actuality, abolishes its determinedness (=alters some sides or other, qualities, of it), thus removes from it the features of Semblance, externality and nullity, and makes it as being in and for itself (=objectively true)." [Ibid., pp.217-18. Emphasis partly in the original.]

 

But, what else is a picture but an image? Admittedly, Lenin calls this both an "objective" and a "scientific" picture, and he connects it with the "activity of man", which looks like another nod in the direction of practice. But, as we have also seen, DM-'abstractions' are all 'mental' entities, the product of private, 'mental processes', and are thereby no less obscure. Of course, Lenin might have meant to use the word "picture" here metaphorically, but if so, given all the 'image' talk we find in MEC, it might have been a good idea to make it clear he wasn't trying to be literal here.

 

Nevertheless, the metaphorical interpretation just aired seems unlike given other things we read. For example, Rees also points out the following:

 

"Indeed, Lenin insists that, 'Man cannot comprehend=reflect=mirror nature as a whole, in its completeness, its "immediate totality," he can only eternally come closer to this creating abstractions, concepts, laws, a scientific picture of the world, etc., etc.' [This is from Lenin (1961), p.182.] This is impossible partly because gaining knowledge is an infinite process, as Lenin had already noted in Materialism and Empiro-criticism." [Rees, loc cit. Bold emphasis alone added.]

 

But that admits knowledge is based on 'reflection' and 'mirroring', even if that is only partial: "Man cannot comprehend=reflect=mirror nature as a whole, in its completeness...he can only eternally come closer to this creating a scientific picture of the world...." That explicitly connects any such 'picture' with 'reflection' and 'mirroring'. And what does 'reflection' produce other than 'images'? If so, it looks like Lenin didn't intend his use of "picture" to be understood metaphorically.

 

Anyway, as we saw earlier (but in greater detail in Essay Ten Part One), this aspect of Lenin's theory (which he also derived from Engels) actually undermines knowledge, and, ironically, implies its opposite, scepticism.

 

Even though Lenin has now dropped his earlier (almost neurotic and repetitive) focus on 'images', the 'abstractions' he substituted for them -- if anything -- appear to be even more problematic. All of us know what an image is, but no one seems to be able to say what an 'abstraction' is -- other than use words that imply they are Abstract Particulars (or the Proper Names thereof), which are of an even more obscure nature. So, even if the above equation of 'mirroring' and 'reflecting' with the creation of 'images' were rejected (for some reason), in place of a screen of 'images' between each human being and the world, we now have a layer of 'abstractions'. Given the obscure nature of the latter, that represents a major step backwards!

 

Once again, it is little use Lenin or Rees appealing to practice here, since there now exists a veil of 'abstractions', not just between each individual involved and practice, but also between each individual and the results of practice -- and between any agents involved in that practice! Once again, this is just bourgeois individualism with a 'Marxist veneer' layered on top.

 

In which case it is impossible to agree with Rees when he says this:

 

"We can see here how for Lenin practice overcomes the distinction between subjective and objective and the gap between essence and appearance." [Rees, loc cit.]

 

Exactly how these mysterious 'abstractions' -- which seem to have elbowed aside all those pesky 'images', and greatly complicated by the introduction of an infinitary process that never reaches its goal -- is able to do what Rees says, he unsurprisingly passed over in total silence.

 

The bottom line therefore seems to be that Lenin's 'dialectical theory' provides no way out of the solipsistic hole into which MEC dropped it a few years earlier -- nor, indeed, does it rescue his ideas from the corrosive acid of scepticism.

 

Quite the reverse, it implies both.

 

Rees's rescue attempt is therefore a predictable but nonetheless total failure.

 

Appendix Four: Ernest Mandel On 'Essence', 'Appearance' And 'Abstraction'

 

[This Appendix Is still under construction.]

 

Ernest Mandel had the following to say about abstraction and the method Marx supposedly employed in Das Kapital:

 

"The purpose of Capital is itself a clear reminder of the method of knowledge applied by Marx to his main work: the method of the materialist dialectic. Marx left no doubt that this was indeed how he himself understood his labours. In a letter sent to Maurice Lachâtre, the editor of the first French edition of Capital Volume 1, he insisted on the fact that he was the first person to have applied this method to the study of economic problems. Again in his own postface to the second German edition of Capital Volume I, Marx specified this use of the dialectical method as the differentia specifica [specific difference -- RL] of Capital, which distinguished it from all other economic analyses. When the dialectical method is applied to the study of economic problems, economic phenomena are not viewed separately from each other, by bits and pieces, but in their inner connection as an integrated totality, structured around, and by, a basic predominant mode of production. This totality is analysed in all its aspects and manifestations, as determined by certain given laws of motion, which relate also to its origins and its inevitable disappearance. These laws of motion of the given mode of production are discovered to be nothing but the unfolding of the inner contradictions of that structure, which define its very nature. The given economic structure is seen to be characterized at one and the same time by the unity of these contradictions and by their struggle, both of which determine the constant changes which it undergoes. The (quantitative) changes which constantly occur in the given mode of production, through adaptation, integration of reforms and self-defence (evolution), are distinguished from those (qualitative) changes which, by sudden leaps, produce a different structure, a new mode of production (revolution).

 

"Marx clearly opposes his own dialectical method of investigation and knowledge to that of Hegel, although he never hesitates to recognize his debt of gratitude to the German philosopher who, spurred on by the French Revolution, catapulted dialectical thought back into the modern world. Hegel's dialectics were idealist: the basic motion was that of the Absolute Idea; material reality was only the outward appearance of ideal essence. For Marx, on the contrary, the dialectic is materialist, 'the ideal is nothing but the material world reflected in the mind of man, and translated into forms of thought'. The basic laws of motion of history are those of real men, themselves producing their own material existence in a given social framework. The development of thought corresponds in the final analysis to that basic movement, and reflects it, albeit through many mediations. Thus the scientific thought process through which Marx came to understand the operations of the capitalist mode of production was itself a product of that mode of production, of bourgeois society and, its contradictions. Only secondarily can it be seen as a product of the development of many human sciences and ideologies: classical German philosophy; English political economy; French historiography and political science; pre-Marxian socialism. Only the growth of bourgeois society and its contradictions, above all the struggle between capital and labour, enabled Marx to assimilate, combine and transform these sciences in the specific way and the specific direction he did. Nevertheless, while the materialist dialectic is Hegel's (idealist) dialectic 'turned right side up again', both have basic common traits. Dialectics as the logic of motion presupposes that all motion, all evolution, whether of nature, society or human thought, adopts certain general forms which are called 'dialectical'. Engels and Lenin both saw, in the very way in which Capital Volume 1 was constructed, a striking application of this general dialectical method; thus Lenin wrote that although Marx had never written his projected short treatise on dialectics, he had nevertheless left us Capital, which is the application of the materialist dialectic in the field of economic phenomena.

 

"Precisely because Marx's dialectic is a materialist one, however, it does not start from intuition, preconceptions or mystifying schemes, but from a full assimilation of scientific data. The method of investigation must differ from the method of exposition. Empirical facts have to be gathered first, the given state of knowledge has to be fully grasped. Only when this is achieved can a dialectical reorganization of the material be undertaken in order to understand the given totality. If this is successful, the result is a 'reproduction' in man's thought of this material totality: the capitalist mode of production. The main danger for any scientist involved in the study of social phenomena is that of taking anything for granted, of 'problem-blindness'. The distinction between appearance and essence, which  Marx inherited from Hegel and which is part and parcel of the dialectical method of investigation, is nothing but a constant attempt to pierce farther and farther through successive layers of phenomena, towards laws of motion which explain why these phenomena evolve in a certain direction and in certain ways. Constantly searching for questions -- calling into question! -- where others only see ready-made answers and vulgar 'evidence': this is certainly one of Marx's main merits as a revolutionary innovator in economic science. But for Marx, the materialist dialectician, the distinction between 'essence' and 'appearance' in no sense implies that 'appearance' is less 'real' than 'essence'. Movements of value determine in the last analysis movements of prices; but Marx the materialist would have laughed at any 'Marxist' who suggested that prices were 'unreal', because in the last analysis determined by value movements. The distinction between 'essence' and 'appearance' refers to different levels of determination, that is in the last analysis to the process of cognition, not to different degrees of reality. To explain the capitalist mode of production in its totality it is wholly insufficient to understand simply the 'basic essence', the 'law of value'. It is necessary to integrate 'essence' and 'appearance' through all their intermediate mediating links, to explain how and why a given' essence' appears in given concrete forms and not in others. For these 'appearances' themselves are neither accidental nor self-evident. They pose problems, they have to be explained in their turn, and this very explanation helps to pierce through new layers of mystery and brings us again nearer to a full understanding of the specific form of economic organization which we want to understand. To deny this need to reintegrate 'essence' and 'appearance' is as un-dialectical and as mystifying as to accept 'appearances' as they are, without looking for the basic forces and contradictions which they tend to hide from the superficial and empiricist observer.

 

"The way in which Capital starts with an analysis of the basic categories of commodity production, with the 'basic unit' (fundamental cell) of capitalist economic life, the commodity, has often been cited as a model application of this materialist dialectic. Marx himself makes it clear that he does not start from a basic concept value -- but from an elementary material phenomenon -- the commodity -- which is at the basis of capitalism, as the only economic organization based upon generalized commodity production. It is therefore correct but incomplete, strictly speaking, to say that Marx's method consists of 'rising from the abstract to the concrete '. In fact, he starts from elements of the material concrete to go to the theoretical abstract, which helps him then to reproduce the concrete totality in his theoretical analysis. In its full richness and deployment, the concrete is always a combination of innumerable theoretical 'abstractions'. But the material concrete, that is, real bourgeois society, exists before this whole scientific endeavour, determines it in the last instance, and remains a constant practical point of reference to test the validity of the theory. Only if the reproduction of this concrete totality in man's thought comes nearer to the real material totality is thought really scientific. At first sight, the movement which dominates Capital Volume 1 appears as a movement of economic 'categories', from the commodity and its inner contradictions to the accumulation of capital and its breakdown. The question has often been asked: is this movement just an abstract synopsis of the 'essence' of capitalism, or is it a greatly simplified reflection of real economic development, that is, the real history leading from the first appearance of commodity production up to full-scale capitalist production in the West, purified of all secondary and combined forms which would only obscure the basic nature of this movement? It is impossible to answer this question simply with a 'yes' or a 'no'. Commodities produced accidentally in pre-capitalist societies, at the very margin of the basic processes of production and consumption, obviously cannot trigger off the striking and terrifying logic of the 'law of value' which Marx majestically unfolds in Capital. Commodity production as a basic and dominant feature of economic life presupposes capitalism, that is a society in which labour-power and instruments of labour have themselves become commodities. In that sense it is true that the analysis of Volume 1 of Capital is logical (based upon dialectical logic) and not historical.

 

"But dialectics imply that every phenomenon has an origin and an end, that nothing is either eternal or finished once and for all. Hence the historical cell of capital is at the same time the key to the logical analysis of capital: phylogenesis and embryology cannot be completely separated. Within capital accumulation in contemporary everyday capitalist life, some aspects of primitive capital accumulation are reproduced: without that primitive capital accumulation, there would be no capitalist mode of production. So the logical analysis does reflect some basic trends of historical development after all. The simplest forms of appearance of the 'economic categories' (which are just forms of material existence, of material reality as perceived and simplified by the human mind) are often also their primitive, that is their original, form. However controversial this interpretation may be, it is difficult to deny that this unity of historical and logical analysis is the way in which Marx and Engels understood their own method. A whole literature has been produced, from Bernstein to Popper and on to contemporary academic economists, on the subject of the 'useless', 'metaphysical ' or even 'mystifying' nature of the dialectical method which Marx borrowed from Hegel. The positivist narrowness of outlook of these critics themselves generally bears eloquent testimony to the contrary, that is to the broad historical vision and the piercing lucidity which the dialectical method helped Marx to achieve. Thanks to that method, Marx's Capital appears as a giant compared to any subsequent or contemporary work of economic analysis. It was never intended as a handbook to help governments to solve such problems as balance-of-payments deficits, nor yet as a learned, if somewhat trite, explanation of all the exciting happenings in the market place when Mr Smith finds no buyer for the last of his I ,000 tons of iron. It was intended as an explanation of what would happen to labour, machinery, technology, the size of enterprises, the social structure of the population, the discontinuity of economic growth, and the relations between workers and work, as the capitalist mode of production unfolded all its terrifying potential. From that point of view, the achievement is truly impressive. It is precisely because of Marx's capacity to discover the long-term laws of motion of the capitalist mode of production in its essence, irrespective of thousands of 'impurities' and of secondary aspects, that his long-term predictions -- the laws of accumulation of capital, stepped-up technological progress, accelerated increase in the productivity and intensity of labour, growing concentration and centralization of capital, transformation of the great majority of economically active people into sellers of labour-power, declining rate of profit, increased rate of surplus value, periodically recurrent recessions, inevitable class struggle between Capital and Labour, increasing revolutionary attempts to overthrow capitalism -- have been so strikingly confirmed by history.

 

"This judgement has generally been challenged on two grounds. The easiest way out for critics of Marx is simply to deny that the laws of motion of the capitalist mode of production which he discovered have been verified at all. This is generally done by reducing them to a couple of misstated and oversimplified formulae (see below): 'progressive immiseration of the working class' and 'ever-worsening economic crisis'. A more sophisticated objection was advanced by Karl Popper, who denied the very possibility, or rather the scientific nature, of such 'laws', calling them 'unconditional historical prophecies' to be clearly distinguished from 'scientific predictions'. 'Ordinary predictions in science,' says Popper,' are conditional. They assert that certain changes (say, of the temperature of water in a kettle) will be accompanied by other changes (say the boiling of the water).' Popper denies the scientific nature of Capital by asserting that, unlike scientific theories, its hypotheses cannot be scientifically tested. This is obviously based upon a misunderstanding of the very nature of the materialist dialectic, which, as Lenin pointed out, requires constant verification through praxis to increase its cognition content. In fact, it would be very easy to 'prove' Marx's analysis to have been wrong, if experience had shown, for example, that the more capitalist industry develops, the smaller and smaller the average factory becomes, the less it depends upon new technology, the more its capital is supplied by the workers themselves, the more workers become owners of their factories, the less the part of wages taken by consumer goods becomes (and the greater becomes the part of wages used for buying the workers' own means of production). If, in addition, there had been decades without economic fluctuations and a full-scale disappearance of trade unions and employers' associations (all flowing from the disappearance of contradictions between Capital and Labour, in as much as workers increasingly become the controllers of their own means and conditions of production), then one could indeed say that Capital was so much rubbish and had dismally failed to predict what would happen in the real capitalist world a century after its publication. It is sufficient to compare the real history of the period since 1867 on the one hand with what Marx predicted it would be, and on the other with any such alternative 'laws of motion', to understand how remarkable indeed was Marx's theoretical achievement and how strongly it stands up against the experimental test of history." [Mandel (1976), pp.17-25. (This links to a PDF.) Links added; several paragraphs merged. Italic emphases in the original ]

 

He tackled the 'problem' concerning the connection between 'appearance' and 'essence' head on:

 

"But for Marx, the materialist dialectician, the distinction between 'essence' and 'appearance' in no sense implies that 'appearance' is less 'real' then (sic) 'essence'. Movements of value determine in the last analysis movements of prices; but Marx the materialist would have laughed at any 'Marxist' who suggested that prices were 'unreal', because in the last analysis determined by value movements. The distinction between 'essence' and 'appearance' refers to different levels of determination, that is in the last analysis to the process of cognition, not to different degrees of reality. To explain the capitalist mode of production in its totality it is wholly insufficient to understand simply the 'basic essence', the 'law of value'. It is necessary to integrate 'essence' and 'appearance' through all their intermediate mediating links, to explain how and why a given 'essence' appears in given concrete forms and not in others. For these 'appearances' themselves are neither accidental nor self-evident. They pose problems, they have to be explained in their turn, and this very explanation helps to pierce through new layers of mystery and brings us again nearer to a full understanding of the specific form of economic organization which we want to understand. To deny this need to reintegrate 'essence' and 'appearance' is as un-dialectical and as mystifying as to accept 'appearances' as they are, without looking for the basic forces and contradictions which they tend to hide from the superficial and empiricist observer." [Mandel (1976), p.20. (This links to a PDF.) Bold emphases alone added.]

 

It could be argued that this shows that Marxists don't believe that appearances are false.

 

First of all, it is worth noting that Mandel focussed exclusively here on social phenomena. He would hardly suggest, for example, that because sticks appear to be bent in water that that implies they are bent, or that this bending is somehow "real". So, do they really bend in water? Or would it be false to say sticks are actually bent in water? Indeed, it would. Here appearances taken at face value would be misleading.

 

Second, Mandel asserts that Marx would have laughed at any 'Marxist' who suggested "prices were 'unreal'" simply because prices are really determined by the movement of value. But, would it be true to say that price is an accurate reflection of value? No, it wouldn't. So, this appearance (that is, if it is one!) is deceptive and motivates a false belief among (bourgeois) economists. Are there any Marxists who would agree with them that this a true picture of the economy? Would Marx? Would Mandel? Again, no, neither would.

 

Third, Mandel then argues that:

 

"The distinction between 'essence' and 'appearance' refers to different levels of determination, that is in the last analysis to the process of cognition, not to different degrees of reality." [Ibid.]

 

Unfortunately, if correct, the above would suggest that Marxism doesn't actually tell us about "reality", since, according to Mandel, the distinction between "appearance" and "essence" is merely a heuristic device that no more relates to "reality" than any other "appearance". "Essence" would now seem to be no more "real" than, say, the shape of a table. When asked what the 'real shape' of a table is, what could anyone say? Tables look different from different angles, as does everything else. If someone were to insist that this is the 'real shape' of a table (when looking at it from above, at right angles, say), would they be stating a truth? Of course not.

 

Hence, Mandel's 'explanation' is no help at all. It fails to show that 'appearances' don't motivate false beliefs -- those held by anyone 'not in the know', for example. Nor does it demonstrate that the distinction drawn between 'appearance' and 'essence' doesn't invalidate the conclusion that Marxists believe 'appearances' are in some sense false.

 

To be continued...

 

Appendix Five: Sean Sayers And The Dialectics Of Confusion

 

Sayers (1985) is a sophisticated defence of Lenin and (what turns out to be) an idiosyncratic interpretation of  'dialectic epistemology'. Unlike Rees's attempt to defend Lenin (in TAR), Sayers does at least try to engage with Analytic Philosophy -- albeit superficially, and in the end, unsuccessfully. For that reason alone it merits detailed consideration. However, in this Appendix I only intend to advance a few general comments about this book (mainly because this Essay is already far too long!); I will say more, much more, in Essay Three Part Six (to be published sometime in 2027).

 

Still Under Construction...

 

Notes

 

01. As noted in the main body, it is all too easy to get lost in the weeds on this issue, but it is nevertheless important to distinguish between different types of words used in this area. Here is what I have posted to Essay Six about (certain) philosophers and logicians' opinions concerning the mode of signification of common nouns, beginning with the so-called "substantivals":

 

A substantival term is a common noun that in general (but not always) admits of number (i.e., it has a plural form) --, e.g., three books, two people, five comrades -- and where they do admit of number, they are often called 'count nouns'. Their distinguishing mark centres on the criteria of identity we use in each case. The following is what Professor Lowe had to say about this topic:

 

"...[N]ot all general terms are common names -- for instance, adjectival or characterizing general terms such as 'red' and 'circular' are not, nor are abstract nouns such as 'redness' and 'circularity' (if indeed the latter are deemed to be general terms, for an alternative view is that they are singular terms referring to abstract individuals). The distinguishing feature of common names -- sometimes also called substantival or sortal general terms -- is that they have associated with them, as a component of their meaning, a criterion of identity for the individuals to which they apply (see Lowe 1989, Ch. 2). A criterion of identity for individuals of a kind K is a principle which determines, for any individuals and y of kind K, whether or not and y are one and the same K. Thus, the criterion of identity for cities tells us that Paris and London are different cities, since they occupy different locations; and the criterion of identity for rivers tells us that the Isis and the Thames are the same river, since they flow from the same source to the same mouth. Different kinds of individuals, denoted by different sortal terms, very often have different criteria of identity governing them -- and in some cases there is philosophical debate as to precisely what these criteria are (for example, in the case of persons). Credit is once more due to Frege for recognizing the important role that criteria of identity have to play in the semantics of sortal terms." [Lowe, Internet Resource [2].] [This link no longer works!]

 

Count nouns are to be distinguished from other common nouns which don't admit of number, e.g., mass nouns (such as chalk, cabbage, meat, etc. -- it makes no sense to refer to "two meat", or "three chalk". Of course, these can be converted into count nouns, as in "two cabbages", "three chalks" or "four meats" (the latter two of which are in general short for "three pieces or sticks of chalk" or "two varieties, portions, slices, or cuts of meat"). However, some mass nouns are also substantivals, e.g., gold, lead, and plastic....

 

The above quoted passage has since disappeared from the Internet, but its author, Professor Lowe, has published something similar in one of his books:

 

"It is a plausible contention -- although one that I shall seek to qualify shortly – that for any given sort of individuals there is a criterion of identity for individuals of that sort. Linguistically, the point is reflected in a distinction emphasized by P. T. Geach between those general terms that are and those that are not 'substantival'. For Geach, the mark of a substantival general term is precisely that it has associated with its use -- as indeed a component of its very sense -- a criterion of identity for instances falling under it. By such a criterion, Geach means 'that in accordance with which we judge whether identity holds' in assessing the truth or falsehood of an identity statement concerning individuals. So, for instance, 'man' and 'gold' are by this account substantival general terms -- or, as I prefer to call them, in deference to John Locke, sortal terms -- because it seems that there are, at least in principle, ways of determining whether, if x and y are men or quantities of gold, they are the same man or the same gold. But a general term like 'red thing' is not for Geach substantival, precisely because it has no such criterion of identity associated with its use.

 

"A sufficient, but not necessary, condition for a general term's being a sortal is that there should exist some principle for counting or enumerating individual instances falling under it. Thus, there are ways of counting the number of men or tables or books in a given room, but no way of counting the number of red things that there are. And this is not because there is such a number, but one beyond our powers of determining -- as in the case of the number of atoms in the room – but rather because it apparently does not even make sense to speak of such a number until the sort or sorts of red thing that one is to count have been specified. Suppose, for example, that the room contained a red table: then that, it might be urged, is clearly one red thing. But what about its red top and its red legs, or the red knob on one of its red drawers? Are these to be counted as different 'red things' in the room in addition to the red table itself? And what about, say, the red paint covering one of the table's legs: is that also to count as a distinct 'red thing’ in its own right? It rapidly becomes apparent that there is no principled way of deciding these matters, until we are told what sorts of red thing we are supposed to be counting.

 

"Suppose, however, that we were instructed to count every sort of red thing in the room: would that in principle lead us to a determinate maximal number of red things in the room – perhaps, indeed, an infinite number, but still determinate? One problem arising here is that of providing criteria for the identity and diversity of sorts. Another is that of providing criteria for determining when two distinct sorts are disjoint, since one must avoid counting the same individual twice because, say, it is both a red φ and a red χ. A still more fundamental problem arises, however, once we acknowledge quantities or portions of red stuffs (such as portions of red ink) to qualify as red things in the room, as I believe we should. For there is clearly no principled way of determining how many such portions there are in a given place, in view of the indeterminate extent to which any such portion is divisible into further portions.

 

"For the foregoing reason, general terms such as 'man', 'table', and 'book' (but not 'thing') have the logical -- and not just the grammatical -- status of count nouns, and they form, as I say, a subset of sortal terms. But, to repeat, the countability of instances falling under it is not a necessary condition for a general term's being a sortal, since so-called mass nouns like 'gold' and 'water' apparently have criteria of identity associated with their use, despite the fact that it makes no sense to ask how many instances of gold or water exist in a certain place. Significantly, though, it does make sense to ask how much gold or water exists in a given place. The general tenor of my remarks is not without venerable historical precedent. If we were to ask what it is that sortal terms denote, a plausible answer would seem to be that they denote what Aristotle in the Categories called secondary substances: that is, species and genera -- or, in other words, sorts or kinds. Correspondingly, what Aristotle called primary substances we may refer to as the individuals or particulars instantiating such sorts or kinds. But an important point to appreciate here is that the notions of individual (or particular) and sort (or kind) are, very arguably, interdependent and mutually irreducible. Individuals are recognizable only as individuals of a sort, while sorts are intelligible only as sorts of individuals." [Lowe (2015), pp.12-14. Italic emphases in the original. Links added; several paragraphs merged.]

 

Also see Lowe (1999).

 

Exactly how the supposed 'process of abstraction' is meant to work with the above 'sorts of being' (expressed by substantivals, count and mass nouns, sortals and non-substantivals) is a mystery. I have yet to see a single DM-theorist address issues like this. But they are in good company on this too: I have yet to encounter a single theorist in the entire history of the misbegotten area of Traditional Confusion address it either. [If anyone knows differently, please email me with the details.]

 

The same comment applies to the other term mentioned, adjectives (of which there are apparently thirteen different types!). And that is before we even begin to ask similar questions about adverbs and verbs. How are they abstracted? Is it the same as, or different from, the way that common nouns are handled?

 

Total silence...

 

Cue crickets, cue tumbleweed, cue distant church bell...

 

 

Figure Ten: Humanity Still Awaits The Details And We've Only Been

Waiting For 2400 Years...

 

One recent (but failed) attempt to explain 'the process of abstraction' -- i.e., Laurence and Margolis (2012) -- doesn't even raise these questions let alone try to address them.

 

1. A short, admirably clear (but completely traditional) introduction to the entire topic of generality can be found in Staniland (1973) -- part of which will be quoted in Appendix Two. A more comprehensive survey is given in Aaron (1967), although that book largely concentrates on Post-Renaissance (Empiricist) theories -- and the author's own 'solution'. [See also, Bolton (2003) and Tugendhat (1982), as well as here, here, here and here.]

 

It is worth adding that DM-theorists have also adopted an idiosyncratic, entirely self-serving, interpretation of the word "metaphysics" (one they uncritically copied from Hegel). I have discussed this theoretical sleight-of-hand at greater length here; readers are directed there for more details.

 

1a. As we saw in Part One of this Essay, and as we will also see in Essay Four Part One, Ancient Greek Philosophers concocted a logico-grammatical theory that in the end altered the way general words operate in indicative sentences, transforming noun-, and verb-phrases (employed in predicate expressions) into the Proper Names of APs. The artificially-constructed 'abstractions' that emerged as a result were read into 'reality' so that what were then claimed to be its 'essential' features were actually a reflection of these artificially created 'abstractions', not the other way round. That is, these 'abstractions' were projected onto 'reality' by 'consciousness', not reflected in 'consciousness'. I have elsewhere called moves like this (i.e., inferences from words to the world), which occur throughout the entire History of Philosophy, Linguistic Idealism. As such, and in this way, the Ideal and the Artificial became the arbiter of the 'Real' for the next 2400 years.

 

[That will become a central theme of all Seven Parts of Essay Twelve.]

 

This approach to generality turns out to be one of the "ruling ideas" Marx and Engels spoke about:

 

"The ideas of the ruling class are in every epoch the ruling ideas, i.e. the class which is the ruling material force of society, is at the same time its ruling intellectual force. The class which has the means of material production at its disposal, has control at the same time over the means of mental production, so that thereby, generally speaking, the ideas of those who lack the means of mental production are subject to it. The ruling ideas are nothing more than the ideal expression of the dominant material relationships, the dominant material relationships grasped as ideas; hence of the relationships which make the one class the ruling one, therefore, the ideas of its dominance. The individuals composing the ruling class possess among other things consciousness, and therefore think. Insofar, therefore, as they rule as a class and determine the extent and compass of an epoch, it is self-evident that they do this in its whole range, hence among other things rule also as thinkers, as producers of ideas, and regulate the production and distribution of the ideas of their age: thus their ideas are the ruling ideas of the epoch." [Marx and Engels (1970), pp.64-65, quoted from here. Bold emphases added.]

 

Of course, Marx and Engels didn't identify (by name) this specific aspect of Traditional Thought (although they do speak about the ruling class, or the ideologues, controlling the production of ideas "in the whole range", so it is difficult to see how that would fail to encompass or implicate areas of Traditional Philosophy highlighted at this site), but, given its universal proliferation, its longevity and the intimate connection it has with the class war (covered below and in Essay Twelve), it is clear that it fits their description admirably well, especially when we read what they both had to say about 'the process of abstraction' (quoted at length later in this Essay). For example, this:

 

"The ordinary man does not think he is saying anything extraordinary when he states that there are apples and pears. But when the philosopher expresses their existence in the speculative way he says something extraordinary. He performs a miracle by producing the real natural objects, the apple, the pear, etc., out of the unreal creation of the mind 'the Fruit'. And in regard to every object the existence of which he expresses, he accomplishes an act of creation. It goes without saying that the speculative philosopher accomplishes this continuous creation only by presenting universally known qualities of the apple, the pear, etc., which exist in reality, as determining features invented by him, by giving the names of the real things to what abstract reason alone can create, to abstract formulas of reason, finally, by declaring his own activity, by which he passes from the idea of an apple to the idea of a pear, to be the self-activity of the Absolute Subject, 'the Fruit.' In the speculative way of speaking, this operation is called comprehending Substance as Subject, as an inner process, as an Absolute Person, and this comprehension constitutes the essential character of Hegel's method." [Marx and Engels (1975), pp.59-60. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Bold emphases alone added. Paragraphs merged.]

 

Hence, the 'rational universe' of Ancient Greek Thought (which morphed into a family of 'world-views' that underpinned the vast majority of subsequent metaphysical systems) was little more than a projection onto the world of systematically distorted language -- indeed, as Marx also argued:

 

"The philosophers have only to dissolve their language into the ordinary language, from which it is abstracted, in order to recognise it, as the distorted language of the actual world, and to realise that neither thoughts nor language in themselves form a realm of their own, that they are only manifestations of actual life." [Marx and Engels (1970), p.118. Bold emphasis alone added.]

 

He and Engels also noted how these forms-of-thought remain more-or-less the same across many centuries, or even longer -- and will continue to do so this side of the termination of class division:

 

"[O]ne fact is common to all past ages, viz., the exploitation of one part of society by the other. No wonder, then, that the social consciousness of past ages, despite all the multiplicity and variety it displays, moves within certain common forms, or general ideas, which cannot completely vanish except with the total disappearance of class antagonisms." [Marx and Engels (1968b), p.52. Bold emphasis alone added.]

 

A point Wittgenstein also made (albeit employing a different, non-political idiom):

 

"Language has the same traps ready for everyone; the immense network of easily trodden false paths. And thus we see one person after another walking down the same paths.... One keeps hearing the remark that philosophy really doesn't make any progress, that the same philosophical problems that occupied the Greeks keep occupying us. But those who say that don't understand the reason this must be so. The reason is that our language has remained constant and keeps seducing us into asking the same questions. So long as there is a verb 'be' that seems to function like 'eat' and 'drink', so long as there are the adjectives 'identical', 'true', 'false', 'possible', so long as there is talk about a flow of time and an expanse of space, etc., etc. humans will continue to bump up against the same mysterious difficulties, and stare at something that no explanation seems able to remove. And this, by the way, satisfies a longing for the transcendental [an alternative version of the manuscript has 'supernatural' here -- RL], for in believing that they see the 'limit of human understanding' they of course believe that they can see beyond it. I read '...philosophers are no nearer to the meaning of 'Reality' than Plato got...'. What a strange state of affairs. How strange in that case that Plato could get that far in the first place! Or that after him we were not able to get further. Was it because Plato was so clever?" [Wittgenstein (2013), pp.311-12e. Italic emphases in the original; quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Paragraphs merged.]

 

Hegel made a somewhat analogous point:

 

"Every philosophy is essentially an idealism or at least has idealism for its principle, and the question then is only how far this principle is carried out." [Hegel (1999), pp.154-55 §316. Bold emphasis added.]

 

But, DM-fans are not going to abandon this traditional approach to 'doing philosophy', no matter what is argued at this site (and for reasons set out in Essay Nine Part Two) -- as I pointed out in response to a question I was asked a few years ago, during an interview:

 

If I were an Idealist, I'd harbour illusions that my work could make some difference; that is, I'd be under the illusion that Dialectical Marxists could be argued out of their adherence to this creed. But, as a Historical Materialist, I know that only social change will bring to an end the conditions (and the consequent alienation) that motivates the vast majority of comrades into looking at the world in the traditional manner I outlined earlier. Since fundamental social change can only come about through the revolutionary activity of workers themselves, Dialectical Marxists of every stripe are going to need the proletariat to 'save them from themselves'. I stand no chance -- I might as well be speaking Klingon to the cat! [Quoted from here.]

 

Be that as it may, the (hypothetical) capacity fellow humans are supposed to possess of being able to 'abstract' certain 'Concepts' or 'Ideas' into existence, literally out of thin air, is also said to be innate -- as argued, for instance, in Laurence and Margolis (2012). We are all supposed to be natural experts, proficient abstractors from birth onward (or at least from when we begin to speak). Of course, hardcore Rationalists (like Descartes, Leibniz and Hegel) held that certain 'concepts' were also innate (or they were a consequence of the architectonic -- i.e., cognitive structure -- of the human 'mind'). In that case, the 'mind' was only capable of functioning in specific ways, with certain concepts and categories -- an approach to knowledge laid down by Aristotle and up-front in Kant, who sought to 'explain' how we are all able to apprehend 'universals' as and when they are instantiated in the objects we meet in experience (in some respect they constituted our apprehension of them). This theory was, in effect, a this-worldly version of Plato's -- which held that we are all born with knowledge of 'the Forms' since we supposedly encountered them in our 'pre-existent lives'. [Innatism is therefore just a 'secular form of Platonism'. On this, see Note 6a.] With Kant these 'concepts' appear to be 'pre-installed' since we can experience the world in no other way. As Lenin might have made the same point, this capacity is perhaps based on, or is an expression of, a 'law of cognition'. In more contemporary (Kantian) terms these 'concepts' 'organise experience'; in some cases, they actually 'constitute experience', or they 'constitute reality itself'. So, at some level, these 'abstract concepts' not only enable our experience of the world, they actually make it possible -- or, at least, they facilitate our comprehension of it. This theory was supposed to cut the ground from under the Empiricists since it highlighted the (hypothetical) fact that without these concepts/'abstractions', we wouldn't be able to apprehend anything at all via experience. [I have quoted Kant to this effect in the main body of this Essay -- a point also made explicit in Laurence and Margolis (2012).

 

Having said this, Kant distinguished between two different types of 'concept', empirical and a priori (which he also identified with the Categories -- e.g., 'Quantity', 'Quality', 'Relation', etc., etc.). It is the latter that are essential to the formation of knowledge and aren't derived by abstraction, but are somehow 'supplied' by the intellect. [On this, see Rohlf (2020), McLear (2015), Guyer (1992b) and Caygill (1995), pp.39-42, 102-06, 118-21.]

 

What Hegel meant by "abstract" and "concept" is more complicated than the above might seem to suggest. I will say much more about that in Essay Twelve Part Five. [In the meantime, cf., Inwood (1992), pp.29-31, 58-61; and Inwood (2002), pp.1-15, 366-80.]

 

As we also saw in the main body of this Essay, and as pointed out above, this approach is basically a re-configuration of Plato's theory, who expressed these ideas theologically:

 

"If mind and true opinion are two distinct classes, then I say that there certainly are these self-existent ideas unperceived by sense, and apprehended only by the mind; if, however, as some say, true opinion differs in no respect from mind, then everything that we perceive through the body is to be regarded as most real and certain. But we must affirm that to be distinct, for they have a distinct origin and are of a different nature; the one is implanted in us by instruction, the other by persuasion; the one is always accompanied by true reason, the other is without reason; the one cannot be overcome by persuasion, but the other can: and lastly, every man may be said to share in true opinion, but mind is the attribute of the gods and of very few men. Wherefore also we must acknowledge that there is one kind of being which is always the same, uncreated and indestructible, never receiving anything into itself from without, nor itself going out to any other, but invisible and imperceptible by any sense, and of which the contemplation is granted to intelligence only." [Plato (1997c), 51e-52a, pp.1254-55. I have used the on-line version here. Bold emphases added. The published edition translates the third set of highlighted words as follows: "It is indivisible -- it cannot be perceived by the senses at all -- and it is the role of the understanding to study it." Cornford renders it this way: "[It is] invisible and otherwise imperceptible; that, in fact, which thinking has for its object." (Cornford (1997), p.192.) See also Note 1b.]

 

There are also distinct reiterations of this theory in DM-epistemology, which isn't surprising given the fact that it is touted as an inverted, or 'right-way-up', form of Hegelianism -- although there are DM-fans who would repudiate that description. Nevertheless, this Idealist method has been openly welcomed and endorsed by generations of DM-theorists, as Lenin himself made abundantly clear:

 

"Thought proceeding from the concrete to the abstract -- provided it is correct (NB)… -- does not get away from the truth but comes closer to it. The abstraction of matter, the law of nature, the abstraction of value, etc., in short all scientific (correct, serious, not absurd) abstractions reflect nature more deeply, truly and completely." [Lenin (1961), p.171. Italic emphases in the original.]

 

"Logical concepts are subjective so long as they remain 'abstract,' in their abstract form, but at the same time they express the Thing-in-themselves. Nature is both concrete and abstract, both phenomenon and essence, both moment and relation. Human concepts are subjective in their abstractness, separateness, but objective as a whole, in the process, in the sum-total, in the tendency, in the source." [Ibid., p.208. Italic emphases in the original.]

 

[I have discussed the first of these two passages in more detail in Part One of this Essay.]

 

Lenin is both enthusiastic and effusive in the way he touts the ruling-class origin of ideas he also helped impose on our movement:

 

"The theory of socialism, however, grew out of the philosophic, historical, and economic theories elaborated by educated representatives of the propertied classes, by intellectuals. By their social status the founders of modern scientific socialism, Marx and Engels, themselves belonged to the bourgeois intelligentsia. In the very same way, in Russia, the theoretical doctrine of Social-Democracy arose altogether independently of the spontaneous growth of the working-class movement; it arose as a natural and inevitable outcome of the development of thought among the revolutionary socialist intelligentsia." [Lenin (1947), p.32. Bold emphases added.]

 

"The history of philosophy and the history of social science show with perfect clarity that there is nothing resembling 'sectarianism' in Marxism, in the sense of its being a hidebound, petrified doctrine, a doctrine which arose away from the high road of the development of world civilisation. On the contrary, the genius of Marx consists precisely in his having furnished answers to questions already raised by the foremost minds of mankind. His doctrine emerged as the direct and immediate continuation of the teachings of the greatest representatives of philosophy, political economy and socialism. The Marxist doctrine is omnipotent because it is true. It is comprehensive and harmonious, and provides men with an integral world outlook irreconcilable with any form of superstition, reaction, or defence of bourgeois oppression. It is the legitimate successor to the best that man produced in the nineteenth century, as represented by German philosophy, English political economy and French socialism." [Lenin, Three Sources and Component Parts of Marxism. Bold emphases alone added; paragraphs merged.]

 

Others have openly concurred with Lenin:

 

"According to Hegel, dialectics is the principle of all life…. [M]an has two qualities: first being alive, and secondly of also being mortal. But on closer examination it turns out that life itself bears in itself the germ of death, and that in general any phenomenon is contradictory, in the sense that it develops out of itself the elements which, sooner or later, will put an end to its existence and will transform it into its opposite. Everything flows, everything changes; and there is no force capable of holding back this constant flux, or arresting its eternal movement. There is no force capable of resisting the dialectics of phenomena…. At a particular moment a moving body is at a particular spot, but at the same time it is outside it as well because, if it were only in that spot, it would, at least for that moment, become motionless. Every motion is a dialectical process, a living contradiction, and as there is not a single phenomenon of nature in explaining which we do not have in the long run to appeal to motion, we have to agree with Hegel, who said that dialectics is the soul of any scientific cognition. And this applies not only to cognition of nature…. And so every phenomenon, by the action of those same forces which condition its existence, sooner or later, but inevitably, is transformed into its own opposite…. When you apply the dialectical method to the study of phenomena, you need to remember that forms change eternally in consequence of the 'higher development of their content….' In the words of Engels, Hegel's merit consists in the fact that he was the first to regard all phenomena from the point of view of their development, from the point of view of their origin and destruction…. [M]odern science confirms at every step the idea expressed with such genius by Hegel, that quantity passes into quality…. [I]t will be understood without difficulty by anyone who is in the least capable of dialectical thinking...[that] quantitative changes, accumulating gradually, lead in the end to changes of quality, and that these changes of quality represent leaps, interruptions in gradualness…. That's how all Nature acts…." [Plekhanov (1956), pp.74-77, 88, 163. Bold emphases alone added; paragraphs merged.]

 

"Previous chapters have shown that dialectics has a history which embraces many thousands of years and that it has passed through various stages of development. Disregarding the beginnings of dialectics in Indian and Chinese philosophy, the following main stages can be distinguished: (1) the dialectics of the old Greek philosophers of nature, Heraclitus; (2) the second and higher stage, the dialectics of Plato and Aristotle; (3) Hegelian dialectics; and (4) materialistic dialectics. Dialectics itself has undergone a dialectical development. Heraclitus, representing the first stage, develops the dialectics of one-after-the-other; Plato and Aristotle, representing the second stage, develop the dialectics of one-beside-the-other. The latter is in opposition to the dialectics of the first stage, being its negation. Hegel embraces both preceding stages of development and raises them to a higher stage. He develops the dialectics of the one-after-the-other and the one-beside-the-other, but in an idealistic form; in other words, he develops an historico-idealistic dialectics." [Thalheimer (1936), pp.157-58. Bold emphases added.]

 

"The integrity, the wholeness, the irrefutable logic and consistency (sic!) of Marxism-Leninism, which are acknowledged even by its opponents (sic!), have been achieved by the application of the unified philosophical dialectical-materialist world outlook and method. Marxism-Leninism cannot properly be understood without its philosophical basis. The philosophy of Marxism-Leninism is a result and the highest stage of the development of world philosophical thought. It has assimilated al that was best ad most progressive in the centuries of development of philosophy...." [Konstantinov (1974), p.15. Bold emphasis added; paragraphs merged.]

 

"The history of Western philosophy, however, begins not with idealism but with materialism. This asserts...that the material world, known to us and explored by science, is real; that the only real world is the material one; that thoughts, ideas and sensations are the product of matter organised in a certain way (a nervous system and a brain); that thought cannot derive its categories from itself, but only from the objective world which makes itself known to us through our senses. The earliest Greek philosophers were known as 'hylozoists' (from the Greek, meaning 'those who believe that matter is alive'). Here we have a long line of heroes who pioneered the development of thought.... What was startlingly new about this way of looking at the world was that it was not religious. In complete contrast to the Egyptians and Babylonians, from whom they had learnt a lot, the Greek thinkers did not resort to gods and goddesses to explain natural phenomena. For the first time, men and women sought to explain the workings of nature purely in terms of nature. This was one of the greatest turning-points in the entire history of human thought....

 

"Aristotle, the greatest of the Ancient philosophers, can be considered a materialist, although he was not so consistent as the early hylozoists. He made a series of important scientific discoveries which laid the basis for the great achievements of the Alexandrine period of Greek science.... The predominant philosophical trend of the Renaissance was materialism. In England, this took the form of empiricism, the school of thought that states that all knowledge is derived from the senses. The pioneers of this school were Francis Bacon (1561-1626), Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679) and John Locke (1632-1704). The materialist school passed from England to France where it acquired a revolutionary content. In the hands of Diderot, Rousseau, Holbach and Helvetius, philosophy became an instrument for criticising all existing society. These great thinkers prepared the way for the revolutionary overthrow of the feudal monarchy in 1789-93....

 

"Under the impact of the French revolution, the German idealist Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) subjected all previous philosophy to a thorough criticism. Kant made important discoveries not only in philosophy and logic but in science.... In the field of philosophy, Kant's masterpiece The Critique of Pure Reason was the first work to analyse the forms of logic which had remained virtually unchanged since they were first developed by Aristotle. Kant showed the contradictions implicit in many of the most fundamental propositions of philosophy.... The greatest breakthrough came in the first decades of the 19th century with George Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770-1831). Hegel was a German idealist, a man of towering intellect, who effectively summed up in his writings the whole history of philosophy. Hegel showed that the only way to overcome the 'Antinomies' of Kant was to accept that contradictions actually existed, not only in thought, but in the real world. As an objective idealist, Hegel had no time for the subjective idealist argument that the human mind cannot know the real world. The forms of thought must reflect the objective world as closely as possible. The process of knowledge consist of penetrating ever more deeply into this reality, proceeding from the abstract to the concrete, from the known to the unknown, from the particular to the universal. The dialectical method of thinking had played a great role in Antiquity, particularly in the naïve but brilliant aphorisms of Heraclitus (c.500 B.C.), but also in Aristotle and others. It was abandoned in the Middle Ages, when the Church turned Aristotle's formal logic into a lifeless and rigid dogma, and did not re-appear until Kant returned it to a place of honour. However, in Kant the dialectic did not receive an adequate development. It fell to Hegel to bring the science of dialectical thinking to its highest point of development.

 

"Hegel's greatness is shown by the fact that he alone was prepared to challenge the dominant philosophy of mechanism. The dialectical philosophy of Hegel deals with processes, not isolated events. It deals with things in their life, not their death, in their inter-relations, not isolated, one after the other. This is a startlingly modern and scientific way of looking at the world. Indeed, in many aspects Hegel was far in advance of his time. Yet, despite its many brilliant insights, Hegel's philosophy was ultimately unsatisfactory. Its principal defect was precisely Hegel's idealist standpoint, which prevented him from applying the dialectical method to the real world in a consistently scientific way. Instead of the material world we have the world of the Absolute Idea, where real things, processes and people are replaced by insubstantial shadows. In the words of Frederick Engels, the Hegelian dialectic was the most colossal miscarriage in the whole history of philosophy. Correct ideas are here seen standing on their head. In order to put dialectics on a sound foundation, it was necessary to turn Hegel upside down, to transform idealist dialectics into dialectical materialism. This was the great achievement of Karl Marx and Frederick Engels...." [Woods and Grant (1995), pp.40-42; pp.44-46 in the second edition. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Bold emphases and links added. Italics in the original; several paragraphs merged.] 

 

However, given that DM-theorists also believe that matter is an abstraction, and abstractions are creation of the mind, Woods and Grant telling us that dialectics began with the Greek materialists (inadvertently) confirms that dialectics itself is a purely 'mental construct'. Indeed, Ancient Greek materialism is no less idealist than post-Renaissance materialism -- both were dogmatically imposed on 'reality' -- and as Essay Twelve Part One has shown, this is a hallmark of Idealism. [That (rather lengthy) argument is summarised here and here.]

 

Indeed, as I pointed out earlier:

 

This also helps explain why Lenin could declare that he preferred intelligent Idealism to "crude materialism". Plainly, he hadn't fully shaken off the regressive influence of the sort of Christian Mysticism that had been forced down his throat as a child (his family was Russian Orthodox, into which faith Lenin had been baptised):

 

"Intelligent idealism is closer to intelligent materialism than stupid materialism. Dialectical idealism instead of intelligent; (sic) metaphysical, undeveloped, dead, crude, rigid instead of stupid." [Lenin (1961), p.274. (I explain why he said this, here.)]

 

From this, it is quite clear that Lenin meant "Dialectical idealism is closer to intelligent materialism than crude materialism...".

 

Many other dialecticians quote this passage, always approvingly -- for example, here, here, here, here and here (the last of these links to a PDF).

 

[There is an illuminating discussion of this trend in the Rationalist Tradition, alongside an exposé of its crippling effect on Philosophy in general, in Cowie (2002), pp.1-68. Cowie also shows that the underlying assumptions of Rationalism and Empiricism are remarkably similar. More-or-less the same can also be said about the connection those two main traditions in post-Renaissance thought enjoy with DM-epistemology. I will return to this theme in later Parts of Essay Three. See also, Cowie (2008) and Stich (1975). (Incidentally, I was shocked and saddened to hear that Fiona Cowie had passed away quite recently.)]

 

On this, see also Note 1aa, below.

 

1aa. Herbert Marcuse helped underline the Idealism implicit in the Hegelian Tradition. In fact, he openly championed this aristocratic approach to the acquisition of knowledge and seemed perfectly happy to see it adopted by Marxist Philosophers, thereby helping import it into the workers' movement:

 

"The doctrine of Essence seeks to liberate knowledge from the worship of 'observable facts' and from the scientific common sense that imposes this worship.... The real field of knowledge is not the given fact about things as they are, but the critical evaluation of them as a prelude to passing beyond their given form. Knowledge deals with appearances in order to get beyond them. 'Everything, it is said, has an essence, that is, things really are not what they immediately show themselves. There is therefore something more to be done than merely rove from one quality to another and merely to advance from one qualitative to quantitative, and vice versa: there is a permanence in things, and that permanent is in the first instance their Essence.' The knowledge that appearance and essence do not jibe is the beginning of truth. The mark of dialectical thinking is the ability to distinguish the essential from the apparent process of reality and to grasp their relation." [Marcuse (1973), pp.145-46. Marcuse is here quoting Hegel (1975), p.163, §112. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Minor typo corrected; bold emphases added.]

 

"Prior to this formalisation, the experience of the divided world finds its logic in the Platonic dialectic. Here, the terms 'Being,' 'Non-being,' 'Movement,' 'the One and the Many,' 'Identity,' and 'Contradiction' are methodically kept open, ambiguous, not fully defined. They have an open horizon, an entire universe of meaning which is gradually structured in the process of communication itself, but which is never closed. The propositions are submitted, developed, and tested in a dialogue, in which the partner is led to question the normally unquestioned universe of experience and speech, and to enter a new dimension of discourse -- otherwise he is free and the discourse is addressed to his freedom. He is supposed to go beyond that which is given to him -- as the speaker, in his proposition, goes beyond the initial setting of the terms. These terms have many meanings because the conditions to which they refer have many sides, implications, and effects which cannot be insulated and stabilised. Their logical development responds to the process of reality, or Sache selbst ['thing itself' -- RL]. The laws of thought are laws of reality, or rather become the laws of reality if thought understands the truth of immediate experience as the appearance of another truth, which is that of the true Forms of reality -- of the Ideas. Thus there is contradiction rather than correspondence between dialectical thought and the given reality; the true judgment judges this reality not in its own terms, but in terms which envisage its subversion. And in this subversion, reality comes into its own truth.

 

"In the classical logic, the judgment which constituted the original core of dialectical thought was formalised in the propositional form, 'S is p.' But this form conceals rather than reveals the basic dialectical proposition, which states the negative character of the empirical reality. Judged in the light of their essence and idea, men and things exist as other than they are; consequently thought contradicts that which is (given), opposes its truth to that of the given reality. The truth envisaged by thought is the Idea. As such it is, in terms of the given reality, 'mere' Idea, 'mere' essence -- potentiality.... This contradictory, two-dimensional style of thought is the inner form not only of dialectical logic but of all philosophy which comes to grips with reality. The propositions which define reality affirm as true something that is not (immediately) the case; thus they contradict that which is the case, and they deny its truth. The affirmative judgment contains a negation which disappears in the propositional form (S is p). For example, 'virtue is knowledge'; 'justice is that state in which everyone performs the function for which his nature is best suited'; 'the perfectly real is the perfectly knowable'; 'verum est id, quod est' ['the true is that which is' -- RL]; 'man is free'; 'the State is the reality of Reason.' If these propositions are to be true, then the copula 'is' states an 'ought,' a desideratum. It judges conditions in which virtue is not knowledge, in which men do not perform the function for which their nature best suits them, in which they are not free, etc. Or, the categorical S-p form states that (S) is not (S); (S) is defined as other-than-itself. Verification of the proposition involves a process in fact as well as in thought: (S) must become that which it is. The categorical statement thus turns into a categorical imperative; it does not state a fact but the necessity to bring about a fact. For example, it could be read as follows: man is not (in fact) free, endowed with inalienable rights, etc., but he ought to be, because he is free in the eyes of God, by nature, etc....

 

"Under the rule of formal logic, the notion of the conflict between essence and appearance is expendable if not meaningless; the material content is neutralised.... Existing as the living contradiction between essence and appearance, the objects of thought are of that 'inner negativity' which is the specific quality of their concept. The dialectical definition defines the movement of things from that which they are not to that which they are. The development of contradictory elements, which determines the structure of its object, also determines the structure of dialectical thought. The object of dialectical logic is neither the abstract, general form of objectivity, nor the abstract, general form of thought -- nor the data of immediate experience. Dialectical logic undoes the abstractions of formal logic and of transcendental philosophy, but it also denies the concreteness of immediate experience. To the extent to which this experience comes to rest with the things as they appear and happen to be, it is a limited and even false experience. It attains its truth if it has freed itself from the deceptive objectivity which conceals the factors behind the facts -- that is, if it understands its world as a historical universe, in which the established facts are the work of the historical practice of man. This practice (intellectual and material) is the reality in the data of experience; it is also the reality which dialectical logic comprehends." [Marcuse (1968), pp.110-17. Bold emphases alone added. Spelling modified to conform with UK English. I have used the on-line text here and have corrected any typographical errors I managed to spot. Several paragraphs merged.]

 

It is worth underlining the fact that, in the above, Marcuse openly connects the subject-predicate sentential form with the (supposed) 'contradiction' between 'essence' and 'appearance', which neatly confirms the analysis developed in Part One of this Essay. [Irony intended.] This is all worryingly similar to Christian Apologists who tell us not to trust our 'imperfect'/'sinful' reasoning powers, or even the facts -- and is, plainly, the 'dialectical equivalent' of the 'alternative facts' promoted by supporters of Donald Trump. Here are just two examples of the theological version of  this 'dialectical syndrome':

 

"People misuse reason when they frame their worldview apart from God's Word. This can involve either treating reason as its own ultimate standard (in other words, a replacement for God's Word) or tossing it aside as irrelevant to faith. Neither of these positions is biblical. We are never to attempt to reason in opposition to the Word of God. That is to say we are not to treat God's Word as a mere hypothesis that is subject to our fallible understanding of the universe. This, after all, was Eve's mistake. She attempted to use her mind and senses to judge God's Word (Genesis 3:6). This was sinful and irrational; she was trying to use a fallible standard to judge an infallible one. We are never to 'reason' in such an absurd, sinful way. Instead, we are supposed to reason from God's Word, taking it as our ultimate unquestionable starting point. Any alternative is arbitrary and self-refuting. Reason is not a substitute for God; rather, it is a gift from God." [Quoted from here. Accessed 18/06/2024. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Links in the original; paragraphs merged.]

 

"When we rely too much on our logic and reasoning, we leave ourselves vulnerable to the outcome of that reasoning instead of preparing ourselves for God's intervention. God is in control. I don't care how things appear to you right now. I don't care what authority your boss has over you right now. I don't care what your addiction, your mate, or your messy situation is telling you to do. None of those people or circumstances are in ultimate control. Yes, they may look as though they are. After all, during the exodus, Pharaoh had every appearance of control over the Israelites as his army chased them across the wilderness and backed them up against an enormous body of water (see Ex. 14:5-31). But what we see is never all there is to be seen. Sovereignty can reshape water and set souls free. Providence can pave a way where there seems to be no way at all. God is in control....  God's vantage point is so far above our own that when we seek to interject our logic or rationale into the equation, it's like trying to put together a puzzle with only a fraction of the pieces. Logically figuring out God's ways will never happen, simply because we don’t have all the information." [Quoted from here. Accessed 18/06/2024. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site; paragraphs merged.]

 

Here is meme I spotted on-line that makes this point rather succinctly:

 

 

Figure Eleven: Yet Another 'Endearing Trait' DM-Theorists Have Borrowed

Off Religious Bigots And Obscurantists

 

Mind control like this, that promotes and advocates only one trusted source, where acolytes are taught to distrust their powers of reason, and even their own eyes (i.e., the facts), are hallmarks of a cultic mentality (on that, see Lifton (1989, 2019)). Is it any wonder that many Marxist parties behave like cults? [On that, see here and here.]

 

Be this as it may, more-or-less the same basic point (like the one Marcuse was trying to make) was advanced by John Rees, but, fortunately, employing much plainer language:

 

"The important thing about a Marxist understanding of the distinction between the appearance of things and their essence is twofold: 1) by delving beneath the mass of surface phenomena, it is possible to see the essential relations governing historical change -- thus beneath the appearance of a free and fair market transaction it is possible to see the exploitative relations of class society, but, 2) this does not mean that surface appearances can simply be dismissed as ephemeral events of no consequence. In revealing the essential relations in society, it is also possible to explain more fully than before why they appear in a form different to their real nature. To explain, for instance, why it is that the exploitative class relations at the point of production appear as the exchange of 'a fair day's work for a fair day's pay' in the polished surface of the labour market.... There is a deeper reality, but it must be able to account for the contradiction between it and the way it appears." [Rees (1998), pp.187-88. Bold emphases alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Paragraphs merged.]

 

If we can't trust 'appearances', we need a party to tell us in what way our eyes and brains are deceiving us. This neatly prepares the way for a Dialectical Prophet, a 'Great Teacher', to save us from ourselves. [More about this in Essay Nine Part Two. We will have occasion to return to these two passages later in this Essay, here and here.]

 

The above remarks also align with the following remarks by Lenin:

 

"To begin with what is the simplest, most ordinary, common, etc., [sic] with any proposition...: [like] John is a man…. Here we already have dialectics (as Hegel's genius recognized): the individual is the universal…. Consequently, the opposites (the individual is opposed to the universal) are identical: the individual exists only in the connection that leads to the universal. The universal exists only in the individual and through the individual. Every individual is (in one way or another) a universal. Every universal is (a fragment, or an aspect, or the essence of) an individual. Every universal only approximately embraces all the individual objects. Every individual enters incompletely into the universal, etc., etc. Every individual is connected by thousands of transitions with other kinds of individuals (things, phenomena, processes), etc. Here already we have the elements, the germs of the concept of necessity, of objective connection in nature, etc. Here already we have the contingent and the necessary, the phenomenon and the essence; for when we say John is a man…we disregard a number of attributes as contingent; we separate the essence from the appearance, and counterpose the one to the other…. Thus in any proposition we can (and must) disclose as a 'nucleus' ('cell') the germs of all the elements of dialectics, and thereby show that dialectics is a property of all human knowledge in general." [Lenin (1961), pp.357-58, 359-60. Bold emphases alone added. Paragraphs merged.]

 

The Idealism implicit in both Lenin and Marcuse's remarks was highlighted (no doubt inadvertently) by George Novack:

 

"A consistent materialism cannot proceed from principles which are validated by appeal to abstract reason, intuition, self-evidence or some other subjective or purely theoretical source. Idealisms may do this. But the materialist philosophy has to be based upon evidence taken from objective material sources and verified by demonstration in practice...." [Novack (1965), p.17. Bold emphasis added.]

 

As we saw in Essay Two, Novack's comments apply to DM-theorists in general -- and that includes Novack himself.

 

1bb. It is worth underlining once again that the criticisms advanced in this Essay aren't aimed at the use of general/common nouns (or even 'abstract' nouns, although I don't prefer that description) -- nor at adverbs, adjectives and verbs -- in ordinary discourse, merely the 'abstractions' that have been invented by Traditional Philosophers and DM-fans.

 

However, if we accept Plato's more considered theory (i.e., that the Forms are exemplars), then it seems that an anthropological/sociological account of generality might prove to be workable. That is because, as Berkeley certainly appreciated (and as Wittgenstein argued in detail), generality may only be accounted for on the basis of rule-governed linguistic behaviour, rather than in terms of a mystical theory that appeals to a set of ghostly Forms, Concepts, Categories, Ideas, 'Universals' and 'abstractions', each one of a thoroughly obscure nature and ideologically dubious provenance.

 

Despite that, serious problems still remain for those who regard Plato's Forms as exemplars: if they end up (supposedly) working like the Standard Metre in Paris (an idea developed below, in Note 1b), then the 'Third Man Problem' will simply reassert itself. That is because even the Standard Metre shares properties or features with an ordinary measuring rod or device. However, if the Standard Metre is regarded as the embodiment of a rule (in which case, it becomes important how we apply the said rule -- and the rule itself can't legislate on that score; it takes a human/social agent to do this), and not so much as a physical exemplar, then such 'difficulties' will begin to vanish. It makes no sense to suppose that a rule shares anything (relevant) with whatever it is applied to; and the Standard Metre itself can't tell us how to apply it, either. [However, on this point, see Note 1b, below.]

 

In order to save my readers having to inform me: Yes, I am aware that the definition of a metre has recently been changed:

 

"In 1960 the metre was redefined as 1,650,763.73 wavelengths of orange-red light, in a vacuum, produced by burning the element krypton (Kr-86). More recently (1984), the Geneva Conference on Weights and Measures has defined the metre as the distance light travels, in a vacuum, in 1/299,792,458 seconds with time measured by a cesium-133 atomic clock which emits pulses of radiation at very rapid, regular intervals." [Quoted from here. Accessed 30/06/2020. Spelling altered to agree with UK English.]

 

1b. On the "Third Man Argument", see  Allen (1960), Code (1985), Cohen (1971), Geach (1956), Meinwald (1990, 1992), Owen (1953), Strang (1963), and Vlastos (1954, 1956). For the general background, see Crombie (1963), pp.247-472, and Copleston (2003a), pp.163-206.

 

It is important to add the following to what was said earlier: Plato himself doesn't always make the sort of mistake I attribute to others throughout this Essay -- except in places where he argues that the Forms also "participate" in their own Form (when, for example, he speaks of the Form of the Beautiful being beautiful, which implies that it, too, is an Abstract Particular), a move that has since been labelled 'Self Predication' (which topic I have dealt with here). In fact, Plato hypostatises the Forms in other ways (and not solely in order for them to provide a referential target for predicate expressions), but as exemplars -- as if they were (somehow) embodied somewhere (in Platonic Heaven -- or the 'Mind of God'?). That would have to be the case if we are supposed to be capable of interacting with then in our (hypothetical) pre-existent form.

 

Exemplars (this side of the 'ethereal veil') function rather like, say, the Standard Metre in Paris (or, at least, that used to be the case). [I owe this point to Peter Geach, who reveals that this idea originated with Wittgenstein; on that, see Geach (1956), pp.267, 269. There is also an echo of this approach to Plato in Donald Davidson's comment, above.] However, as pointed out earlier, even this interpretation of the Forms runs into the sand. On that, see Note 1bb, above  -- no exemplar can explain how it itself should be applied. [Further discussion of this point would take us too far afield into Wittgenstein's discussion of rule-following, a topic that will be examined in more detail in Essay Twelve Part One, here.]

 

1bc. This 'problem' has been widely discussed in 'the Plato literature'. However, since I regard it as a pseudo-problem I will say no more about it here. Readers who want to dip a toe in this fathomless ocean of confusion might like to start with Meinwald (1992).

 

1bd. On this, see Anderson (1979).

 

1c0. This isn't to suggest that there weren't other important currents in political thought (clearly not!), but in this sub-section I am concentrating on one of the main sources of 'Rationalist Theories of the State', as well as any background assumptions/'world-views' that supposedly underpinned them.

 

As we will see, it is essential that the universe is declared to be 'rational' if inequality, oppression and exploitation are capable of being 'justified' or granted a 'divine seal of approval' (and in a manner that preserves the status quo). This happens if 'Reality' is said to work for the benefit of those in power -- anything else would (of course!) be 'irrational'. That is just one of the reasons why atomism was anathematised for centuries, and although Einstein wasn't a theist (but it is arguable that he was some sort of Deistic Platonist, as are many Mathematicians and Physicists), similar ideas also found echo in his statement that "God doesn't play dice with the universe". A universe subject to randomness (at a fundamental level) would be 'irrational'. [On this, see Pyle (1997).]

 

[Why the above is so will be explored in more detail in Essay Twelve Parts Two and Three (summary here). The short version goes as follows: if everything (in the universe) is in its 'rightfully assigned' place, which it will be if there is a rational order to reality (and everything 'observed the rules/law'), then it turns out that inequality, oppression and exploitation actually exist because they are an integral, even an intended, factor in that order. Hence, any attempt to ameliorate the situation or radically alter it will therefore be condemned as 'irrational', 'against the natural order', 'contrary to god's will', etc., etc. Here we see a major source of conservative ideology. 'All change is change for the worse...' etc. (This isn't to argue that the universe is irrational, either!)]

 

1c. Some might wonder if this particular topic is all that important. That misconception will be laid to rest in Essay Twelve (summary link above), where philosophical moves like these will be related to broader ideological priorities that permeate the entire history of ruling-class thought, later to re-surface in DM -- alongside the substitutionism it served to 'rationalise' and 'legitimate'. [On that, see here, here and here.]

 

2. The ideological background to "Possessive Individualism" is explored in MacPherson (1964); an outline of the overall philosophical context can be found in Hacking (1975), with a more detailed background history in Prosch (1966), pp.83-306.

 

[Unfortunately, despite its other strengths, Hacking's book is largely a-historical --, i.e., in the sense that it fails to link changes to, and developments in, philosophical fashion to contemporaneous social and political forces (or even with the ideological motivating factors that invariably accompanied or underpinned both), or the rise of the bourgeois Mode of Production. Of course, that is no big surprise since Hacking doesn't claim to be a Marxist! More-or-less the same can be said about Prosch (1966), too.]

 

A clearer Marxist account -- restricted to philosophical theories connected with scientific change -- can be found in Freudenthal (1986), with a more sophisticated narrative in Hadden (1994). The latter is itself based on ideas advanced in Borkenau (1987), Grossmann (1987) and Sohn-Rethel (1978). See also, Kaye (1998). For a Wittgensteinian slant on all of this, see Robinson (2003), especially chapters 9, 10, 12 and 14. More details can be accessed at Guy Robinson's website, here. [Unfortunately, Guy's site is no longer available. However, many of his Essays can now be accessed at this site -- here (reproduced with the permission of his son). Sadly, I heard that Guy passed away in October 2011. It is also worth pointing out that Guy Robinson is one of the few Marxist Philosophers whose work is actually worth studying. In fact, I'd go further, his work should be required reading.]

 

2a. The bowdlerised and defective 'Term Logic' (developed by Medieval and Early Modern Logicians and Philosophers) interpreted each of the quantifiers (such as "every", "all", "nothing", "some", etc.) as a special sort of name. This (serious) error wasn't corrected until Frege's revolutionary logic was published a century-and-a-half ago.

 

[On this, see Kenny (2006), pp.11-13; cf., Geach (1972b), George and Van Evra (2006), and Beaney (1996). See also this, but note the caveats I have posted here.]

 

This Ancient Greek 'syntactical wrong turn' (to describe the latter in its best possible light) resurfaces in the way that DM-theorists also interpret concepts: linguistically, they are viewed as Proper Names that refer to, or "reflect", hidden (perhaps even 'mental') aspects of 'reality', and which somehow also lend to material objects their 'substance'. [This ontological and semantic slide was covered in detail in Part One.] Such 'concepts' are therefore capable of being true (or "relatively true") on their own, as isolated 'linguistic atoms'. While some dialecticians will try resist that implication, the way they themselves refer to the 'abstractions' they claim to have unearthed gives the lie to any such attempt. That can be seen by the way they end up turning these 'Concepts' (these 'abstractions') into the Proper Names of Abstract Particulars (also demonstrated in Part One).

 

Unfortunately, 'dialectical moves' like this are based on an age-old idea that the unit of meaning, or even of truth, is the individual word or 'concept', not an indicative sentence. As a result, naming, not saying, became the dominant paradigm for understanding (or expressing) meaning in language. [On this, see Hacking (1975). Also see the section of this Essay dealing with theories that portray knowledge as a relation between 'the Knower' and 'the Known', between an 'object' and a 'cognising mind' (i.e., Note 6a).] That is, of course, what 'allowed' Hegel to focus on the 'self-development' of concepts as the core of his system, ignoring how we actually use language. [On that, see also here. Admittedly Hegel tried to hide this doctrine behind a confused and confusing theory about 'the Whole' and its relation to 'the parts' (covered in Essay Eleven Parts One and Two), but the bottom line is the easily established fact that the basic unit of meaning for him was the individual 'concept' (and how it 'self-developed'). That helps explain why DM-theorists obsess about 'things', the 'thing-in-itself' and the 'thing-for-us' (covered in Note 6a), and how they are 'reflected' by 'images' in the CNS, etc. For them, everything meaningful is atomistic, despite their repeated and unconvincing nods in the direction of DM-Wholism. I have also dealt with this topic in greater detail in Essays Thirteen Part Three and Twelve Part Six.]

 

As Wittgenstein noted: Metaphysics is simply a shadow cast on 'reality' by grammar (which is a paraphrase of Wittgenstein (2009), p.123e, §§371-73) -- but in this particular case it is a shadow cast by distorted grammar, as, indeed, Marx himself also pointed out:

 

"We have shown that thoughts and ideas acquire an independent existence in consequence of the personal circumstances and relations of individuals acquiring independent existence. We have shown that exclusive, systematic occupation with these thoughts on the part of ideologists and philosophers, and hence the systematisation of these thoughts, is a consequence of division of labour, and that, in particular, German philosophy is a consequence of German petty-bourgeois conditions. The philosophers have only to dissolve their language into the ordinary language, from which it is abstracted, in order to recognise it, as the distorted language of the actual world, and to realise that neither thoughts nor language in themselves form a realm of their own, that they are only manifestations of actual life." [Marx and Engels (1970), p.118. Bold emphasis alone added.]

 

[There will be far more on this in Part Three of Essay Three, as well as Parts Two to Seven of  Essay Twelve (summary here), and Essay Thirteen Part Three. See also Hacker (1997), pp.179-214.]

 

2b. As we saw in Essay Three Part One, it is human beings who create the generality here, not words, concepts or ideas. Plainly, that is because words, concepts and ideas have no social structure, history, intelligence or language -- whereas we, as a species, possess all four.

 

2c. It might be thought Davidson is factually wrong when he said this:

 

"If universals existed independently, they would take their place alongside the things that instantiate them. Separate existence is just what would make universals like other particulars and thus no longer universal. But doesn't this argument show Aristotle to be confused? If universals can be talked about, they can be referred to. Yet whatever can be referred to is a particular. Confusion seems to have set in: universals are both particulars and at the same time necessarily distinct from particulars." [Davidson (2005), p.90. Bold emphasis added; paragraphs merged.]

 

In that case, someone could object that just because something can be referred to doesn't automatically mean it is a particular. There are collective nouns that name groups or classes, and hence can be used to refer to non-particulars such as these -- for example, "the team", "the committee", "the party", "the council", etc. None of these is a particular. In which case, referring to them doesn't make them particulars.

 

Or so it could be maintained...

 

I have dealt with that counter-argument in Note 3, below.

 

3. At least not without radical surgery.

 

The natural response here would be to argue that general names aren't like Proper Names, they have a different "mode of signification". That is undeniable; but while it is clear that Proper Names typically refer to, or stand for, individuals or particulars, some refer to works of art or music, others name mountains, oceans, rivers, countries, towns, forest fires, hurricanes, teams, diseases, numbers, wines, diseases, sets, non-existent deities, fictional characters, yet-to-be discovered particles, moves in chess (such as the Sicilian Defense, or the Queen's Gambit), as well as certain processes (such as the Haber Process or the Krebs Cycle). [Although, several of the latter could, at a stretch, also be titles or Definite Descriptions. It could be objected that several of these name sets or collections; for instance, the Krebs Cycle is the name of countless examples of the same process throughout nature. This means that a Proper Name, or even a Definite Description, doesn't always designate a particular. I have dealt with that response below. As a side note, Hegel appears to deny such subject terms refer to individuals (just particulars of a certain type); on that, see Aquila (1973). I will examine what the latter has to say in Essay Twelve Part Six, although I have already covered some of the background to this in Appendix D of Essay Three Part One.]

 

However, having said that, our use of such language is still rather complex (on that see Baker and Hacker (2005, pp.227-49)), and it is far from clear what general names actually succeed in naming. Even to raise such a question would be to give the game away, since, obviously, it trades on the suppressed assumption that general terms are just Proper Names writ small! Plainly, that would be to model the denotation of general names on the way Proper Names refer to whatever they denote. In turn, it would suggest general names (common nouns, etc.) should also be viewed as referring expressions, denoting an individual of some sort -- be this a 'Form', 'Universal', 'abstraction', class, group, natural kind, "range of values", set, Idea, 'Category' or 'Concept'. So, even though we use such phrases as, "the set of…", "the class of…", or "the natural kind…", whose referents are supposedly named by a relevant 'general noun' (such as "number", "table", "animal", "planet" or "molecule" -- as in, for example, "the class of planets" or "the set of numbers"), the use of the definite article clearly neutralises the generality that some imagine such terms could be used to express.

 

Hence, countless abstract particulars -- such as, "the Universal", "the set of…", or "the class of…", or "the natural kind…" -- would supposedly become the referents of these 'general names', a grammatical slide that only succeeds in cancelling their generality. That is because they would now operate just like Proper Names, even if their mode of signification appears to be different or more complicated.

 

Of course, giving such 'abstractions' a Proper Name begs the question --, i.e., that there is just one 'thing' there to be named, in the first place. In that case, "Table" would become the Proper Name of 'the set of all tables', just as "Cat" would designate 'the set of all cats'.

 

Despite the existence of an ancient grammatical/logical tradition that treats general nouns as general names (an approach which is itself based on the metaphysical theories questioned in Parts One and Two of Essay Three), as we have seen, we may only concur if we, too, seek to undermine the facility we have in language for using such terms to express generality (along the lines outlined in Part One).

 

[On this in general, see MacBride (2008). See also the detailed comments and Endnotes (i.e., Note 13 and Note14) I have added to Essay Four Part One, here.]

 

It could be objected that classes and sets, for example, aren't necessarily, or even typically, singular, but are composite or compound in nature, and as such often include or encompass an indefinite number of elements/members. In that case, when a predicate designates the extension of a class, it is neither naming it nor referring to it as a single 'entity'.

 

[The extension of a class is every object belonging to that class; so, the extension of the class human being is every human being.]

 

Of course, it isn't too clear whether predicates designate anything. If someone says "The boss is a crook", the use of "...is a crook" isn't to designate, it is to describe. [On that, see Slater (2000).] Moreover, the Proper Names given to human beings designate individuals who are also collections of limbs, organs, cells and molecules. The same can be said when we name, for instance, a molecule. It remains a particular even though it is itself compound, made of many atoms. Hence, that (in the main) doesn't prevent a compound individual from being a particular (unless, of course, we re-define "particular" to mean the same as "simple" --, i.e., as any 'thing' that has no parts --; I have covered this topic in Essay Eight Part One, specifically here). The same applies to the nouns we supposedly use to 'designate' sets, classes, collections or 'natural kinds' -- they become Proper Names (and hence singular terms) if we treat them as referring expressions in this way. [That takes care of the objection aired above, in Note 2c, and earlier.]

 

Once more, turning description into designation would be to repeat the errors analysed in Part One of this Essay; that is, it would be to model all meaningful discourse on the naming relation, except, in this case, using euphemisms like "designate" as some sort of fig-leaf to hide that fact.

 

Again, as the late Fraser Cowley pointed out:

 

"The open sentence 'x is a spider' determines a class only because 'spider' signifies a kind of thing. It is by being one of that kind...that a value of x is a member of the class. To identify something as a spider, one must know what a spider is, that is, what kind of thing 'spider' signifies. Kinds of things can come to be or cease to be. The chemical elements, kinds of substances, are believed to have evolved. The motorbike -- the kind of vehicle known as a motorbike -- was invented about 1880. The dodo is extinct. There is no obvious way of producing sentences equivalent to these in terms of classes. The class of dodos and the class of dead dodos are not identical: though all dodos are dead, a dead dodo is not a dodo.... Since a kind is to be found wherever there are particular things of the kind, it can have various geographical locations. The lion is found in East Africa. Lions are found in East Africa. It makes no difference whether we say 'the lion' or whether we say 'lions': what is meant is the kind of animal. To say that it can be seen in captivity far from its remaining natural habitats does not contradict the statement that it is found in East Africa. A kind is not a class: the class of lions is nowhere to be found...." [Cowley (1991), p.87. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Paragraphs merged. The rest of this section of Cowley's book is highly relevant.]

 

On this, see also, Ryle (1949). The Philosopher, Gilbert Ryle, labelled this widespread logical and philosophical error, the "Fido-Fido Fallacy". That description highlighted the (unsupported) supposition that to every word there must 'correspond something in reality' (abstract or concrete) that is designated or named by that word -- i.e., each term was in effect the Proper Name of a 'something', somewhere...

 

[Ryle's argument is summarised here. (This links to an article by Yorick Wilks , accessible here as a PDF. Wilks was at one time a student of Wittgenstein's.)]

 

4. Why that is so will be revealed presently.

 

5. It is arguable that, for all their apparent sophistication, modern 'scientific' theories of mind and language (cybernetically-, cognitively-, physicalistically-, neurologically-, physiologically-, or psychologically-orientated) haven't advanced much beyond this point. That contentious claim won't be expanded upon or substantiated here (it has been defended in depth in Essay Thirteen Part Three and in the two books mentioned below).

 

This entire approach to the Philosophy of Mind has been analysed in detail (and characterised in the above terms, too) in Bennett and Hacker (2008, 2022).

 

6. We saw the life drained out of general terms in Part One of this Essay, with all those lists.

 

6a0. For instance, witness the way DM-theorists speak about logic as a study of 'the laws of thought', "the science of cognition" or "the science of thought". Here are just a few examples, beginning with Engels:

 

"In every epoch, and therefore also in ours, theoretical thought is a historical product, which at different times assumes very different forms and, therewith, very different contents. The science of thought is therefore, like every other, a historical science, the science of the historical development of human thought. And this is of importance also for the practical application of thought in empirical fields. Because in the first place the theory of the laws of thought is by no means an 'eternal truth' established once and for all, as philistine reasoning imagines to be the case with the word 'logic'." [Engels (1954), p.43. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Bold emphases added.]

 

"As soon as each special science is bound to make clear its position in the great totality of things and of our knowledge of things, a special science dealing with this totality is superfluous. That which still survives, independently, of all earlier philosophy is the science of thought and its laws -- formal logic and dialectics. Everything else is subsumed in the positive science of nature and history." [Engels (1976), p.31. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"Logic is the science of cognition. It is the theory of knowledge…. The laws of logic are the reflections of the objective in the subjective consciousness of man.... [These] embrace conditionally, approximately, the universal, law-governed character of eternally moving and developing nature." [Lenin (1961), p.182. Bold emphasis alone added.]

 

"Hegel himself viewed dialectics precisely as logic, as the science of the forms of human cognition.... What does logic express? The law of the external world or the law of consciousness? The question is posed dualistically [and] therefore not correctly [for] the laws of logic express the laws (rules, methods) of consciousness in its active relationship to the external world.... Thought operates by its own laws, which we can call the laws of logic...." [Trotsky (1986), pp.75, 87, 106. Trotsky is apparently referring to Hegel's Introduction to The Science of Logic (i.e., Hegel (1999), pp.43-64). Paragraphs merged; bold emphases added.]

 

"Modern philosophy, beginning with Bacon of Verulam and closing with Hegel, carries on a constant struggle with the Aristotlean (sic) logic. The product of this struggle, the outcome of philosophy, does not deny the old rules of traditional logic, but adds a new and decidedly higher circle of logical perception to the former ones. For the sake of better understanding it may be well to give to this circle a special title, the special name of 'theory of understanding,' which is sometimes called 'dialectics.' In order to demonstrate the essential contents of this philosophical product by an investigation of the fundamental laws of traditional logic and to explain it thereby, I refer once more to the teacher of elementary logic, Dittes.

 

"Under the caption of 'Principles of Judgment' he teaches: 'Since judging, like all thinking, aims at the perception of truth, the rules have been sought after by which this purpose might be accomplished. As universally applicable rules, as principles or laws of thought, the following four have been named:

 

'(1) The law of uniformity (identity).

 

'(2) The law of contradiction.

 

'(3) The law of the excluded third.

 

'(4) The law of adequate cause.'...

 

"I have just declared that logic so far did not know that the perception produced by its principles does not offer us truth itself, but only a more or less accurate picture of it. I have furthermore contended that the positive outcome of philosophy has materially added to the clearness of the portrait of the human mind. Logic claims to be 'the doctrine of the forms and laws of thought.' Dialectics, the product of philosophy, aims to be the same, and its first paragraph declares: Not thought produces truth, but being, of which thought is only that part which is engaged in securing a picture of truth. The fact resulting from this statement may easily confuse the reader, viz., that the philosophy which has been bequeathed to us by logical dialectics, or dialectic logic, must explain not alone thought, but also the original of which thought is a reflex." [Dietzgen (1906), pp.385-88. Quotation marks altered to conform to the conventions adopted at this site; several paragraphs merged; link and bold emphases added. As I demonstrated in Essay Four Part One, the above comments are about as accurate as the average Tory Party election video. Dietzgen is here quoting a certain Dr Friedrich Dittes, who wasn't a logician, he was an Austro-German educator/psychologist.]

 

"We previously stressed the reactionary role of the philosophy of Plato and Aristotle. Now we shall speak of its great progressive role. This resides in the fact that the ruling classes of Athens at that time believed the aim of the exploitation of slave labor and their class rule to be the free development of human capacities, above all, the development of reason. This is closely connected with the fact that this slave production was not ultimately and predominantly commodity production, not production for the sake of surplus value like capitalist production. Its chief aim was production for individual use, production of use values. From this it followed that the ruling class was not absorbed in business or industry, but conceived its ideal to be the development of art and of science. Thus arose the extraordinary great interest in the investigation of human reason, in the discovery of the laws of thought. Through this activity the Greeks created a new epoch in the general development of history. As represented by Aristotle they built up the doctrine of the forms and laws of thought, known as formal logic. They also laid the foundation for what is called dialectics. Wherein dialectics and formal logic differ, we shall soon see. The science of the laws of thought, formal logic, reached its highest point with Aristotle. It was here developed so broadly and fully that it was not until the beginning of the 19th century that the German philosopher, Hegel, could make a significant and decisive advance over it.

 

"I will now briefly explain what formal logic is and how it differs from dialectics. Formal logic can be defined as the theory of the laws of thought without regard to the content of thought. The theory of thinking or logic describes how concepts are built and wherein the different concepts differ from each other in regard to form. It deals with the different kinds of propositions and, ultimately, with the different kinds and forms of inferences, of syllogisms. Logic seeks to teach how to think correctly." [Thalheimer (1936), pp.87-88. Bold emphases added. As Essay Four Part One has also shown, the characterisation of FL (and even AFL) that Thalheimer is about to unleash on his readers is entirely fictional.]

 

[FL = Formal Logic; AFL = Aristotelian FL.]

 

"[T]he science of the thought process. Logicians investigate the activities of the thought process which goes on in human heads and formulate the laws, forms and interrelations of those mental processes." [Novack (1971), p.17. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"Whatever thoughts we think, and whatever language they are expressed in, they must satisfy the basic requirements of the reflection of reality in thought. These requirements give rise to the laws of thought, to principles of logic. For thoughts are reflections of the real world, and in the process of reflection, as Marx said, the material world is translated into forms of thought. The process of reflection and translation has its own laws -- the laws of thought, the principles of logic.... Logical principles are laws of thought, not laws of reality; they are not laws of material processes, but the laws of the reflection of material processes." [Cornforth (1963), pp.50-52. Paragraphs merged; bold emphases added.]

 

"A view that is often encountered among dialectical materialists is that formal logic is applicable to static situations, but since, in reality, nothing is static, formal logic is superseded by dialectical logic, which permits logical contradictions. Within the framework of this view, thought is the appropriation (in the mind) of the objectively existing material world, while dialectical logic, that is, dialectics taken as logic, must be considered to be the laws of thought (or correct thinking). Thus, in the approximation where things are viewed as static, formal logic becomes the laws of thought, equally in approximation. When, however, things are viewed in their motion, change, and development, dialectical logic becomes properly the laws of thought." [Marquit (1990), quoted from here. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"Formal logic intended universal validity for the laws of thought. And indeed, without universality, thought would be a private, non-committal affair, incapable of understanding the smallest sector of existence. Thought is always more and other than individual thinking; if I start thinking of individual persons in a specific situation, I find them in a supra-individual context of which they partake, and I think in general concepts. All objects of thought are universals. But it is equally true that the supra-individual meaning, the universality of a concept, is never merely a formal one; it is constituted in the interrelationship between the (thinking and acting) subjects and their world. Logical abstraction is also sociological abstraction. There is a logical mimesis which formulates the laws of thought in protective accord with the laws of society, but it is only one mode of thought among others. [Marcuse (1968), p.115; bold emphases added.]

 

"Obviously the forms of thought are expressed (and realized) in language, in forms of language, but the main difference between this error and others which would be worse, but are also especially unpardonable for specialists in logic, is overlooked. It is impossible to put the identity sign between forms of thought and forms of expression of thought unless we put both feet on the ground of the old philosophical prejudice according to which language in general (in the broadest sense) is the one 'external form' in which thought is realized, 'manifested,' 'becomes explicit,' and hence thought is also investigated. In that case, indeed, forms and norms of 'language' would be also uniquely accessible to observation and investigation of the 'forms of thought,' its logical norms. However, this prejudice, as given and well-known, is fraught with sad consequences for the science of thought, in particular, a threat of the complete degeneration of logic as a science investigating general and necessary forms and laws of thought, into purely subjective 'rules,' not having and not being able to have any objective basis and justification except that they are established by an amicable agreement ('conventionally'); 'logic' in such an interpretation is unavoidably transformed into something resembling that convention which was previously violated by Panikovskii. Identifying the forms of thought with forms of language, by means of the [identity] sign whose logic was worked out by the Stoics and the Medieval scholastics, had, finally, its historical justification, which has disappeared into oblivion..... Naturally, the understanding of logic as the science of thought, as the science of activity which is realized not only in words, not only in speaking and written records of this speaking, but also (and above all!) in works, in acts of changing the external world, in experiments with fully real things, in the process of creation of objects of labor and in changing the relations between people, the matter begins to look essentially different from the views of those who side with the old, pure formal logic. They are primarily concerned not mainly with thought, but with the mode of connection of 'subject and predicate,' with the constitution of the verbal 'definitions' of things, with 'conjunctions of propositions,' which mutually cancel each other, and with similar situations of a linguistic rather than logical character." [Ilyenkov (1979), pp.123-25. Quoted from here. Accessed 25/05/2024. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site; bold emphases alone added. Paragraphs merged.]

 

"Dialectical philosophy does, therefore, involve a questioning of the idea that the law of non-contradiction and the other traditional laws of logic constitute necessary principles of reason and laws of thought." [Sayers (1982), pp.411-12. Bold emphasis added.]

 

This mischaracterisation of logic is disappointingly common (as a Google search will readily confirm), so DM-supporters aren't alone in this. On this specific topic, and why this is a serious mischaracterisation of logic, see my comments over at Wikipedia, which material has been re-posted here.

 

But mischaracterisations like the above don't stop there, and DM-advocates aren't alone in doing this, either. As we will see in Essay Thirteen Part Three, the vast bulk of what passes for Cognitive Theory, Philosophy of Mind and Neuroscience these days is locked in this neo-Cartesian Paradigm. [On that, see Bennett and Hacker (2008, 2022). See also below. For example, much of Laurence and Margolis (2012), analysed in Interlude One, is mired in this post-Renaissance 'Cognitive Quagmire'.]

 

6a. No wonder Plato had to appeal to the alleged pre-existence of the soul to account for these 'recognitional powers'. According to Plato, we all know (i.e., we are all not only able to identify, we can now (re-)cognise the Forms because we were all acquainted with them (again on a one-to-one basis) before we were born. The shock of birth apparently made us forget these pre-natal encounters, which means we are no longer consciously aware of them. Subsequently recovered, 'genuine' knowledge is therefore a form of recollection -- an idea developed in detail in his dialogue, Meno (i.e., Plato1997h) -- on that, see Essay Six), but (fortunately for us!) it takes a Philosopher to remind us of what we (in some sense) already know. This is Innatism on steroids. [How only philosophers are able to perform such neat tricks is somewhat unclear.] In that case, our (re)cognition of the Forms -- i.e., our ability to detect/identify them in the objects that supposedly instantiate them in this world -- is rekindled because the Forms are rather like long lost acquaintances (we had all met in our 'pre-existing life'), which we meet again this side of the 'heavenly veil'. That appears to be the case even though these 'Forms' are 'acquaintances' of a rather peculiar sort, about whom we had temporarily forgotten (or about whom we had temporarily lost all conscious awareness).

 

So, Philosophy supposedly reminds us of what we already know -- if we but knew it!

 

[On Platonic recollection, see the references in Note 25. There is more on this topic, here, but especially here. Exactly how we seem perfectly able to use general terms before we encounter these 'illuminating Philosophers' is unclear, but Plato's famous Allegory of the Cave is supposed to fill in some of the details. (If this Essay were about Plato's Epistemology or his Metaphysics, I would be tempted to go down that rabbit hole, but it isn't, so I won't.)]

 

It is here, in this doctrine, that we meet yet another pernicious corollary of Traditional Theories of Meaning: if meaning is a function of single words, concepts, 'abstractions', 'representations' or ideas, then any such theory must be framed in terms of one individual (or 'thing') relating another individual (or 'thing') -- as one mind relates to one concept, one idea, one 'image', one 'abstraction', one object, one 'representation', or one 'Form' --, just as they might do with any one of their (human) acquaintances. Knowledge and meaning are thereby turned into, or are based on, individual relations, relational powers or inter-personal (recognitional) skills and capacities (even if it takes a silver-tongued Philosopher to re-kindle the latter). Hence, the Knower is somehow supposed to be connected to the Known on a one-to-one basis. This is quintessential, bourgeois individualism already in Ancient Greece! And no, that isn't am egregious anachronism; it follows on from what Marx had to say (partially quoted earlier):

 

"[O]ne fact is common to all past ages, viz., the exploitation of one part of society by the other. No wonder, then, that the social consciousness of past ages, despite all the multiplicity and variety it displays, moves within certain common forms, or general ideas, which cannot completely vanish except with the total disappearance of class antagonisms. The Communist revolution is the most radical rupture with traditional property relations; no wonder that its development involved the most radical rupture with traditional ideas." [Marx and Engels (1968b), p.52. Bold emphasis alone added.]

 

This is a common thread that ruins through all of Traditional Thought, and is based on the mystical union of the Knower with the 'Mind of the Deity', later secularised and obscured under a ton of technical jargon (if written in the 'Analytic Tradition'), or under several tons of gobbledygook (if written in the 'Continental Philosophy' Tradition). [Readers should check out any randomly-selected, advanced work on Epistemology, the Theory of Mind, or the Theory of Meaning (not in the Wittgensteinian tradition) for ready confirmation of those allegations.]

 

Hence, the meaning of a word (which supposedly depicts/expresses a 'concept', an 'image', idea, 'universal', 'Form', 'representation', or 'abstraction', or which even refers to 'an object') is now 'related to its intended target' in a way that is analogous to the relationship that a knowing subject supposedly has with a single object/acquaintance. These days this overall idea is often typified by the Signifier/Signified paradigm in Semiotics.

 

In which case, as far as 'internal cognitive processes' are concerned, each 'Mind' is connected with its own ideas and concepts (which, as we have seen, are all abstract objects of a rather peculiar sort) as they individually manifest themselves to that individual. All this allegedly takes place in the privacy of their own 'consciousness' (especially since Descartes's theories hit the philosophical streets in the 17th Century). As far as 'external' connections were concerned, cognition is supposed to deal with them -- if they exist in the 'extra-mental world' -- by processing whatever these internal ideas/images/abstractions are said to 'reflect or represent in reality'. Here we find the origin of the theory that 'abstraction takes place in the mind' of each individual as they relate to, and then process, their own private ideas/impressions, one at a time -- such as 'the population', for instance. This explains why DM-theorists repeatedly speak about 'the Knower' knowing an 'object' -- often using such phrases as, "things", "this thing", "thing-in-itself", "things-in-themselves", "things-for-us", "this object", "this body" -- and why Engels fixated on Subject/Object Identity and the 'identity of Thought and Being'. This spurious relation has been fixated upon by DM-fans ever since they inherited it from the German Idealists -- and that is because it had been as core aspect of one of the main problematics of that current in early modern philosophy. Here is Engels (ruminating on this very 'problem'):

 

"The great basic question of all philosophy, especially of more recent philosophy, is that concerning the relation of thinking and being. From the very early times when men, still completely ignorant of the structure of their own bodies, under the stimulus of dream apparitions came to believe that their thinking and sensation were not activities of their bodies, but of a distinct soul which inhabits the body and leaves it at death -- from this time men have been driven to reflect about the relation between this soul and the outside world.... But the question of the relation of thinking and being had yet another side: in what relation do our thoughts about the world surrounding us stand to this world itself? Is our thinking capable of the cognition of the real world? Are we able in our ideas and notions of the real world to produce a correct reflection of reality? In philosophical language this question is called the question of identity of thinking and being, and the overwhelming majority of philosophers give an affirmative answer to this question.... The most telling refutation of this as of all other philosophical crotchets is practice -- namely, experiment and industry. If we are able to prove the correctness of our conception of a natural process by making it ourselves, bringing it into being out of its conditions and making it serve our own purposes into the bargain, then there is an end to the Kantian ungraspable 'thing-in-itself'. The chemical substances produced in the bodies of plants and animals remained just such 'things-in-themselves' until organic chemistry began to produce them one after another, whereupon the 'thing-in-itself' became a thing for us...." [Engels (1888), pp.593-95. Bold emphases added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Spelling modified to agree with UK English. Paragraphs merged.]

 

"But then come the Neo-Kantian agnostics and say: We may correctly perceive the qualities of a thing, but we cannot by any sensible or mental process grasp the thing-in-itself. This 'thing-in-itself' is beyond our ken. To this Hegel, long since, has replied: If you know all the qualities of a thing, you know the thing itself; nothing remains but the fact that the said thing exists without us; and, when your senses have taught you that fact, you have grasped the last remnant of the thing-in-itself, Kant's celebrated unknowable Ding an sich. To which it may be added that in Kant's time our knowledge of natural objects was indeed so fragmentary that he might well suspect, behind the little we knew about each of them, a mysterious 'thing-in-itself'. But one after another these ungraspable things have been grasped, analyzed, and, what is more, reproduced by the giant progress of science; and what we can produce we certainly cannot consider as unknowable. To the chemistry of the first half of this century, organic substances were such mysterious objects; now we learn to build them up one after another from their chemical elements without the aid of organic processes. Modern chemists declare that as soon as the chemical constitution of no-matter-what body is known, it can be built up from its elements. We are still far from knowing the constitution of the highest organic substances, the albuminous bodies; but there is no reason why we should not, if only after centuries, arrive at the knowledge and, armed with it, produce artificial albumen. But, if we arrive at that, we shall at the same time have produced organic life, for life, from its lowest to its highest forms, is but the normal mode of existence of albuminous bodies." [Engels (1892). pp.381-82. Bold emphases added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Minor typo corrected.]

 

Admittedly, Engels subjected several previous attempts to solve the 'problem of the relation of thinking to being' to searching criticism, but he still advanced his own 'solution' to it, never once questioning whether it was a genuine problem -- or if this even represented an appropriate or sensible way to try to understand human cognition or our knowledge of the world. As such he remained trapped within the confines of a ruling-class tradition that stretched back to the Ancient Greeks -- a paradigm that exclusively focussed on one-to-one connections between Knowers and the Known.

 

When knowledge is universally seen as a relation between two 'factors' -- 'the Knower' and 'the Known' --, the only way that various 'solutions' to this pseudoproblem could distinguish themselves from rivals in the field was either to:

 

(i) Change the 'cast list' involved; or,

 

(ii) Modify the underlying 'mechanism'/'processes' at work.

 

That is, in relation to the above, competitor theorists found they had to either:

 

(ia) Vary the interpretation of the two 'factors' either side of the said 'relation'; or,

 

(iia) Adjust the means by which they were somehow 'connected' or interacted.

 

So, with respect to Option (i), the 'solutions' on offer either held that:

 

(ib) The 'mind' connects with, 'processes', or relates to its own internal 'abstractions', 'ideas', 'representations', 'concepts', and 'images'; or,

 

(ic) The 'mind' directly connects with, or relates to, 'objects' in the 'external world' -- i.e., with 'things-in-themselves'.

 

With respect to Option (ii), this was to be achieved by:

 

(iib) Experience alone; or,

 

(iic) A purely 'cognitive'/'rational act' of some sort or description.

 

The only remaining issues were whether one or more of the above were:

 

(iii) Innate;

 

(iv) Taught/learned;

 

(v) 'Self-directed';

 

Or, whether they were governed/controlled by:

 

(vi) 'Intuition', 'acquaintance', 'description'; or,

 

(vii) 'Association'/'constant-conjunction'/'habit'.

 

Or, finally, by:

 

 (viii) An amalgamation of one or more of the above.

 

Whatever permutation finally turned out to be the one favoured by a given theorist, every solution on offer throughout the entire history of Traditional Thought has chosen among these elements and methods. There is nothing new in Traditional Thought. This is the script they all follow.

 

Sometimes the above alternatives were given bright and shiny new names; so, more recently, 'technical-sounding', 'scientific' labels (such as, "module", "software", "qualia", "trope", "programme", "neural net", "byte", "meme", "codon" or "merge") have been thrown into the mix. The only limiting factor being the extent of the creative imagination of the thinker involved -- how good he/she was at inventing new terminology to replace the old.

 

Hence, despite the fanfare -- or the change of jargon employed -- every single 'solution' to this pseudoproblem was connected with, focused on, or revolved around this failed relational paradigm -- i.e., that between 'the Knower' and 'the Known' -- invented over two thousand years ago by Plato.

 

That is still the case.

 

And this includes the theories of cognition/knowledge concocted by Dialectical Marxists.

 

Here is why:

 

"[O]ne fact is common to all past ages, viz., the exploitation of one part of society by the other. No wonder, then, that the social consciousness of past ages, despite all the multiplicity and variety it displays, moves within certain common forms, or general ideas, which cannot completely vanish except with the total disappearance of class antagonisms." [Marx and Engels (1968b), p.52. Bold emphasis alone added.]

 

"The ideas of the ruling class are in every epoch the ruling ideas, i.e. the class which is the ruling material force of society, is at the same time its ruling intellectual force. The class which has the means of material production at its disposal, has control at the same time over the means of mental production, so that thereby, generally speaking, the ideas of those who lack the means of mental production are subject to it. The ruling ideas are nothing more than the ideal expression of the dominant material relationships, the dominant material relationships grasped as ideas; hence of the relationships which make the one class the ruling one, therefore, the ideas of its dominance. The individuals composing the ruling class possess among other things consciousness, and therefore think. Insofar, therefore, as they rule as a class and determine the extent and compass of an epoch, it is self-evident that they do this in its whole range, hence among other things rule also as thinkers, as producers of ideas, and regulate the production and distribution of the ideas of their age: thus their ideas are the ruling ideas of the epoch." [Marx and Engels (1970), pp.64-65, quoted from here. Bold emphases added.]

 

Furthermore, if a theorist either accepts, appeals to, or utilises a 'reflection theory of knowledge' (which is the case with most Dialectical Marxists), they will inevitably focus on 'objects'/'things' that are 'reflected' in 'consciousness'/'the mind' (perhaps in the manner described by Cornforth, below). That remains the case even if this approach to epistemology and cognition is fortified by more complex ideas about how (correct) theories themselves 'correspond with reality' (or they do so in a decreasingly 'relative' way) --, for example, as we see in Ruben (1979), pp.165-99. [Ruben's attempt to rescue/repair Lenin's epistemology will be examined in detail in Essay Three Part Six.]

 

This means that 'reflection theories of knowledge' are intimately connected with the above tradition -- i.e., that knowledge is still regarded as a relation between the same two factors, 'the Knower' and 'the Known'. Again, this will be explored in more detail in Essay Three Part Six, where it will be shown that it ends up undermining propositional knowledge -- and hence science itself --, as well as throwing into doubt the social nature of knowledge and language. [Spoiler: that is because propositions aren't objects. On why they aren't, see below and here.]

 

Here, for example, is Lenin; in just the first one hundred-and-thirty-five pages of MEC he uses many of the words and phrases mentioned above (and this isn't an exhaustive list, either!):

 

"The materialists, we are told, recognise something unthinkable and unknowable -- 'things-in-themselves' -- matter 'outside of experience' and outside of our knowledge. They lapse into genuine mysticism by admitting the existence of something beyond, something transcending the bounds of 'experience' and knowledge. When they say that matter, by acting upon our sense-organs, produces sensations, the materialists take as their basis the 'unknown,' nothingness; for do they not themselves declare our sensations to be the only source of knowledge? The materialists lapse into 'Kantianism' (Plekhanov, by recognising the existence of 'things-in-themselves,' i.e., things outside of our consciousness); they 'double' the world and preach 'dualism,' for the materialists hold that beyond the appearance there is the thing-in-itself; beyond the immediate sense data there is something else, some fetish, an 'idol,' an absolute, a source of knowledge?" [Lenin (1972), p.10.]

 

"Our Machians have written so much about the 'thing-in itself' that were all their writings to be collected they would result in mountains of printed matter. The 'thing-in-itself' is a veritable bête noire [black beast, something to be avoided  -- RL] with Bogdanov and Valentinov, Bazarov and Chernov, Berman and Yushkevich. There is no abuse they have not hurled at it, there is no ridicule they have not showered on it. And against whom are they breaking lances because of this luckless 'thing-in-itself'? Here a division of the philosophers of Russian Machism according to political parties begins. All the would-be Marxists among the Machians are combating Plekhanov's 'thing-in-itself'; they accuse Plekhanov of having become entangled and straying into Kantianism, and of having forsaken Engels. (We shall discuss the first accusation in the fourth chapter; the second accusation we shall deal with now.) The Machian Mr. Victor Chernov, a Narodnik and a sworn enemy of Marxism, opens a direct campaign against Engels because of the 'thing-in-itself.'... [I]t is not true that Engels 'is producing a refutation of the thing-in-itself.' Engels said explicitly and clearly that he was refuting the Kantian ungraspable (or unknowable) thing-in-itself. Mr. Chernov confuses Engels' materialist conception of the existence of things independently of our consciousness. In the second place, if Kant's theorem reads that the thing-in-itself is unknowable, the 'converse' theorem would be: the unknowable is the thing in-itself. Mr. Chernov replaces the unknowable by the unknown, without realising that by such a substitution he has again confused and distorted the materialist view of Engels!... (pp.104-09)

 

"Engels clearly and explicitly states that he is contesting both Hume and Kant. Yet there is no mention whatever in Hume of 'unknowable things-in-themselves.' What then is there in common between these two philosophers? It is that they both in principle fence off 'the appearance' from that which appears, the perception from that which is perceived the thing-for-us from the 'thing-in-itself.' Furthermore, Hume does not want to hear of the 'thing-in-itself,' he regards the very thought of it as philosophically inadmissible, as 'metaphysics' (as the Humeans and Kantians call it); whereas Kant grants the existence of the 'thing-in-itself,' but declares it to be 'unknowable,' fundamentally different from the appearance, belonging to a fundamentally different realm, the realm of the 'beyond..., inaccessible to knowledge, but revealed to faith.... (pp.109-110)

 

"And if that is so, three important epistemological conclusions follow:

 

1. Things exist independently of our consciousness, independently of our perceptions, outside of us, for it is beyond doubt that alizarin existed in coal tar yesterday and it is equally beyond doubt that yesterday we knew nothing of the existence of this alizarin and received no sensations from it.

 

2. There is definitely no difference in principle between the phenomenon and the thing-in-itself, and there can be no such difference. The only difference is between what is known and what is not yet known. And philosophical inventions of specific boundaries between the one and the other, inventions to the effect that the thing-in-itself is 'beyond' phenomena (Kant), or that we can and must fence ourselves off by some philosophical partition from the problem of a world which in one part or another is still unknown but which exists outside us (Hume) -- all this is the sheerest nonsense,..., crotchet, invention.

 

3. In the theory of knowledge, as in every other branch of science, we must think dialectically, that is, we must not regard our knowledge as ready-made and unalterable, but must determine how knowledge emerges from ignorance, how incomplete, inexact knowledge becomes more complete and more exact. (pp.110-11)

 

"Once we accept the point of view that human knowledge develops from ignorance, we shall find millions of examples of it just as simple as the discovery of alizarin in coal tar, millions of observations not only in the history of science and technology but in the everyday life of each and every one of us that illustrate the transformation of 'things-in-themselves' into 'things-for-us,' the appearance of 'phenomena' when our sense-organs experience an impact from external objects, the disappearance of 'phenomena' when some obstacle prevents the action upon our sense-organs of an object which we know to exist. The sole and unavoidable deduction to be made from this -- a deduction which all of us make in everyday practice and which materialism deliberately places at the foundation of its epistemology -- is that outside us, and independently of us, there exist objects, things, bodies and that our perceptions are images of the external world.... (p.111) 

 

"What can be done with a Voroshilov whose every phrase makes confusion worse confounded! It is sheer ignorance, Mr. Victor Chernov, not to know that all materialists assert the knowability of things-in-themselves. It is ignorance, Mr. Victor Chernov, or infinite slovenliness, to skip the very first phrase of the thesis and not to realise that the 'objective truth'...of thinking means nothing else than the existence of objects (i.e., 'things-in-themselves') truly reflected by thinking. It is sheer illiteracy Mr. Victor Chernov, to assert that from Plekhanov's paraphrase (Plekhanov gave a paraphrase and not a translation) 'it appears as though' Marx defended the other-sidedness of thought. Because only the Humeans and the Kantians confine thought to 'this side of phenomena.' But for all materialists, including those of the seventeenth century whom Bishop Berkeley demolished..., 'phenomena' are 'things-for-us' or copies of the 'objects in themselves.' Of course, Plekhanov's free paraphrase is not obligatory upon those who desire to know Marx himself, but it is obligatory to try to understand what Marx meant and not to prance about like a Voroshilov....  Albert Lévy is a professor. And a proper professor must abuse the materialists as being metaphysicians. For the professorial idealists, Humeans and Kantians every kind of materialism is 'metaphysics,' because beyond the phenomenon (appearance, the thing-for-us) it discerns a reality outside us. A. Lévy is therefore essentially right when he says that in Marx's opinion there corresponds to man's 'phenomenal activity' 'an activity of things,' that is to say, human practice has not only a phenomenal (in the Humean and Kantian sense of the term), but an objectively real significance. The criterion of practice -- as we shall show in detail in its proper place... -- has entirely different meanings for Mach and Marx. 'Humanity partakes of the absolute' means that human knowledge reflects absolute truth; the practice of humanity, by verifying our ideas, corroborates what in those ideas corresponds to absolute truth.... The reader sees that Lévy does not for a moment doubt that Marx recognised the existence of things-in-themselves!... (pp.112-115)

 

"What two lines of philosophical tendency does Engels contrast here? One line is that the senses give us faithful images of things, that we know the things themselves, that the outer world acts on our sense-organs. This is materialism -- with which the agnostic is not in agreement. What then is the essence of the agnostic's line? It is that he does not go beyond sensations, that he stops on this side of phenomena, refusing to see anything 'certain' beyond the boundary of sensations. About these things themselves (i.e., about the things-in-themselves, the 'objects in themselves,' as the materialists whom Berkeley opposed called them), we can know nothing certain -- so the agnostic categorically insists. Hence, in the controversy of which Engels speaks the materialist affirms the existence and knowability of things-in-themselves. The agnostic does not even admit the thought of things-in-themselves and insists that we can know nothing certain about them.... (pp.116-17)

 

"To show how absurd are the assertions of our Machians that the materialists Marx and Engels denied the existence of things-in-themselves (i.e., things outside our sensations, perceptions, and so forth) and the possibility of their cognition, and that they admitted the existence of an absolute boundary between the appearance and the thing-in-itself, we shall give a few more quotations from Feuerbach. The whole trouble with our Machians is that they set about parroting the words of the reactionary professors on dialectical materialism without themselves knowing anything either of dialectics or of materialism.... This seems clear enough. The world in itself is a world that exists without us. This materialism of Feuerbach's, like the materialism of the seventeenth century contested by Bishop Berkeley, consisted in the recognition that 'objects in themselves' exist outside our mind. The an sich (of itself, or 'in itself') of Feuerbach is the direct opposite of the an sich of Kant. Let us recall the excerpt from Feuerbach already quoted, where he rebukes Kant because for the latter the 'thing-in-itself' is an 'abstraction without reality.' For Feuerbach the 'thing-in-itself' is an 'abstraction with reality,' that is, a world existing outside us, completely knowable and fundamentally not different from 'appearance.'... The objects of our ideas are distinct from our ideas, the thing-in-itself is distinct from the thing-for-us, for the latter is only a part, or only one aspect, of the former, just as man himself is only a fragment of the nature reflected in his ideas.... Sensation is the result of the action of a thing-in-itself, existing objectively outside us, upon our sense-organs -- such is Feuerbach's theory. Sensation is a subjective image of the objective world, of the world an und für sich [and also for itself -- RL]. ...All the mysterious, sage and subtle distinctions between the phenomenon and the thing-in-itself are sheer philosophical balderdash. In practice each one of us has observed times without number the simple and palpable transformation of the 'thing-in-itself' into phenomenon, into the 'thing-for-us.' It is precisely this transformation that is cognition. The 'doctrine' of Machism that since we know only sensations, we cannot know of the existence of anything beyond the bounds of sensation, is an old sophistry of idealist and agnostic philosophy served up with a new sauce.... (pp.129-32)

 

"1) The materialists of the seventeenth century, against whom Berkeley argues, hold that 'objects in themselves' are absolutely knowable, for our presentations, ideas, are only copies or reflections of those objects, which exist 'outside the mind'.... 2) Feuerbach, and J. Dietzgen after him, vigorously dispute any 'fundamental' difference between the thing-in-itself and the phenomenon, and Engels disposes of this view by his brief example of the transformation of the 'thing-in-itself' into the 'thing-for-us.' 3) Finally, to maintain that the materialists regard things-in-themselves as 'always only dimly discernible in the phenomenon' is sheer nonsense, as we have seen from Engels' refutation of the agnostic. The reason for Bogdanov's distortion of materialism lies in his failure to understand the relation of absolute truth to relative truth (of which we shall speak later). As regards the 'outside-of-experience' thing-in-itself and the 'elements of experience,' these are already the beginnings of the Machian muddle of which we have already said enough." (pp134-35)

 

[The last eight paragraphs are all from Lenin (1972), pp.104-35. Minor typo corrected; several paragraphs merged. Bold emphases alone added; quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

And, here he is in just the first half of PN (I have omitted the scores of Hegel passages that Lenin quoted -- often approvingly -- that spoke about the "thing-in-itself", or which employed other associated words and phrases, of the sort also mentioned earlier):

 

"This is very profound: the Thing-in-itself and its conversion into a Thing-for-others (cf. Engels ). The Thing-in-itself is altogether an empty, lifeless abstraction. In life, in movement, each thing and everything is usually both 'in itself' and 'for others' in relation to an Other, being transformed from one state to the other." [Lenin (1961),  p.109.]

 

"The Thing-in-itself is related to Being as the essential to the non-essential?...

 

"Transcendental idealism...places 'all determinateness of things (both with regard to form and to content) in consciousness...accordingly, from this point of view, it falls within me, the subject, that I see the leaves of a tree not as black but as green, the sun as round and not as square, and taste sugar as sweet and not as bitter; that I determine the first and second strokes of a clock as successive and not as simultaneous, and determine the first to be neither the cause nor the effect of the second, and so forth'.... Hegel further makes the reservation that he has here investigated only the question of the Thing-in-itself and [external reflection]." [Ibid., pp.149-50.]

 

"Hegel in favour of the cognisability of the Thing-in-itself." [Ibid., p.173.]

 

"Apparently, Hegel perceives scepticism here in the fact that Hume and Kant do not see the appearing Thing-in-itself in 'phenomena,' divorce phenomena from objective truth, doubt the objectivity of cognition, remove, [everything empirical] from the [Thing-in-itself]...." [Ibid., p.205.]

 

"Elements of dialectics. One could perhaps present these elements in greater detail as follows:

 

"1. the objectivity of consideration (not examples, not divergencies, but the Thing-in-itself).

 

"2. the entire totality of the manifold relations of this thing to others.

 

"3. the development of this thing, (phenomenon, respectively), its own movement, its own life.

 

"4. the internally contradictory tendencies (and sides) in this thing.

 

"5. the thing (phenomenon, etc.) as the sum and unity of opposites....

 

"8. the relations of each thing (phenomenon, etc.) are not only manifold, but general, universal. Each thing (phenomenon, process, etc.) is connected with every other...

 

"11. the endless process of the deepening of man's knowledge of the thing, of phenomena, processes, etc., from appearance to essence and from less profound to more profound essence." [Ibid., pp.220-21. Bold emphases alone added; quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. I have replaced any German words Lenin used with their English equivalents as suggested by the editors, and indicated by the use of square brackets.]

 

Finally (with respect to Lenin), we have already met these two passages:

 

"Logical concepts are subjective so long as they remain 'abstract,' in their abstract form, but at the same time they express the Thing-in-themselves. Nature is both concrete and abstract, both phenomenon and essence, both moment and relation. Human concepts are subjective in their abstractness, separateness, but objective as a whole, in the process, in the sum-total, in the tendency, in the source." [Ibid., p.208. Bold emphasis alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

"A tumbler is assuredly both a glass cylinder and a drinking vessel. But there are more than these two properties and qualities or facets to it; there are an infinite number of them, an infinite number of 'mediacies' and inter-relationships with the rest of the world…. [I]f we are to have true knowledge of an object we must look at and examine all its facets, its connections and 'mediacies'. That is something we cannot ever hope to achieve completely, but the rule of comprehensiveness is a safeguard against mistakes and rigidity…. [D]ialectical logic requires that an object should be taken in development, in change, in 'self-movement' (as Hegel sometimes puts it). This is not immediately obvious in respect of such an object as a tumbler, but it, too, is in flux, and this holds especially true for its purpose, use and connection with the surrounding world." [Lenin (1921), pp.92-93. Bold emphases added; paragraphs merged.]

 

Here, too, is Christopher Caudwell:

 

"A and B, and the relations between them, are all real. The Universe is one, and is as a whole absolutely self-determined, but no part of it is absolutely self-determined. All that is real exists, and all that is real is determined, that is, every part of the Universe is in mutually determining A-B relations with the rest of the Universe. Everything therefore is knowable, for the meaning of knowable is simply this, the possibility of expressing a determining relation between that unknown but knowable thing, and a thing already known. This possibility is given in our premises. This is our premise: that the Universe is a material unity, and that this is a becoming.

 

"This material unity of becoming cannot be established by thought alone. It is established by thought in unity with practice, by thought emerging from practice and going out into practice. Phenomena are exhibited by the thing-in-itself, and if we can by practice force the thing-in-itself to exhibit phenomena according to our desire, then we know this much about the thing-in-itself -- that in certain circumstances it will exhibit certain phenomena. This is positive knowledge about the thing-in-itself. When we can in practice achieve all possible transformations, we have all possible knowledge about the thing-in-itself. Thus we prove that the universe is a material unity by proving in practice the material basis of all phenomena. This material basis is the thing-in-itself, or the like content of any phenomena exhibited by the thing-in-itself. This proof of material unity is secured by change and is therefore a process of becoming, of differentiation, of the emergence of the new. But it is a proof of unity, of the sameness, likeness, or determinism in all phenomena....

 

"But if the newness of quality, the unlikeness, as it emerges, is time, the oldness, the likeness, is space. Qualities do not arrange themselves homogeneously in space, space is the homogeneity in their qualities. Space is quantity or known quality as it remains unchanged; it is therefore the thing-in-itself, the material unity of the Universe. The Universe is a spatial Universe. Space therefore is an aspect of matter, which is precisely what relativity physics has established by practice. Mass-energy, or the likeness in phenomena, generates space. This is established by practice. All laws of development, of evolution, of difference, of quality, of aesthetics, of consciousness, are temporal. All laws of conservation, of metrics, of comparability, of universal and unchanging relations, are spatial....

 

"We now see that there is a universal dialectic of reality, a mode of movement which is prior to time, space, life and all other events and qualities. This dialectic proceeds as follows. First we have a quality. But a quality is a relation between subject and object, between A, subject, and not-A, the rest of the Universe. But the rest of the Universe not-A, has as its object A, to A it is subject and to it A is the rest of the Universe. The most 'primitive' quality we take therefore has two terms and a relation, this relation is involved in 'becoming' and ensures that the process of reality is open and 'infinite' at both ends. Our most infinite regress into the past brings us therefore to a quality, to an event. We cannot imagine anything simpler, for such a simplex one-term thing would be absolutely self-determined and could not be known-by-us, since knowing is a mutually determining relation between us and the thing. Any known event is already a quality, is already a subject-object relation. It already involves within itself an antagonism which can generate the means by which it is known.

 

"We may take either term as primary and the other as dependent on it. Since we can take either term as primary, neither can be primary. They may be regarded as simultaneous. But they are not independent terms, for they are connected by a relation. The simplest quality therefore reveals itself as a subject-object relation. But the process of becoming involves that a new quality emerges (or event occurs) not by the increment of something already there, but abruptly, exhibiting something altogether unlike. But it also involves that this new state contains the first old quality in addition to the unlike new. This new state or quality is also analysable as a two-term relation, and must in turn be succeeded by a new quality....

 

"This movement is not imposed on becoming by thought. It is the only way becoming can really become, conformably to our reason and experience; and it is in our reason because our experience is part of this becoming. This movement contains within it time and space, memory and perception, quality and quantity, all of which entities are abstractions from it. Time is the difference between synthesis and the preceding relation, space is the similarity between them. The dialectic movement of the Universe does not occur in space and time, it gives rise to them. The external world does not impose dialectic on thought, nor does thought impose it on the external world. The relation between subject and object, ego and Universe is itself dialectic. Man, when he attempts to think metaphysically, merely contradicts himself, and meanwhile continues to live and experience reality, dialectically." [Caudwell (1938b), quoted from here. Bold emphases added. Several paragraphs merged; a handful of minor typos corrected. The above continues on for several more thousand words!]

 

And, here is Maurice Cornforth (in a section of his book entitled "Things In Themselves"):

 

"Many philosophers have maintained that our knowledge is limited to the appearances of things in our own minds, and that 'things in themselves', things as they really are 'in themselves' and independently of how they appear to us, must be unknowable. According to such philosophers there is an impassable gulf between the data of sense given in our consciousness on the one hand and the things existing independently of our consciousness, things in themselves, on the other hand. And many not only deny that we can know things in themselves but also that such things exist at all. And yet already in judgments directly based on perception we are gaining knowledge of things in themselves -- not in the first place complete or profound knowledge but knowledge at least of various separate aspects and external relations of things. We gain this knowledge precisely by means of the data of sense. And when by further investigations and reasoning we reach conclusions about the relations of things, their properties, the processes into which they enter and their laws of motion, then we are gaining deeper knowledge of the very same things, existing independently of our consciousness of them, which before we knew only superficially.

 

"There is, then, no gulf between things in themselves and their appearances or 'phenomena'. We know things precisely by means of their appearances to us, and the more we study the appearances the more we can find out about the things. Nor is there any gulf between the appearances of things and their reality, since the appearance is a manifestation of the reality, and we do not know the reality separately from the appearance but only through it. 'If you know all the qualities of a thing, you know the thing itself', wrote Engels in the Introduction to Socialism, Utopian and Scientific. [Cornforth is here quoting Engels (1892), pp.381-82, reproduced above -- RL.] We know about the real properties and relations of things by practice and study. By finding out what we can do with things, and by studying the various appearances of their various aspects under many conditions, we gain more and more knowledge of the things themselves. Hence all our knowledge is knowledge of real things which certainly exist independently of their appearances to us. 'The materialist affirms the existence and knowability of things in themselves', wrote Lenin, in Materialism and Empirio-Criticism, chapter 2. [Cornforth is here quoting Lenin (1972), p.117, reproduced above -- RL.] First we know things superficially through perception, and then more deeply and comprehensively by thought operating with the data of perception. There is, and can be, no difference between the things known to us and things in themselves. The only difference is between what is known and what is not yet known, and between what is known only superficially in certain of its aspects and what is known more thoroughly." [Cornforth (1963), pp.176-77. Bold emphases alone added. Paragraphs merged, quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

One might well wonder how it is possible for a Marxist like Cornforth (or even Engels and Lenin, whom he quotes) to believe that, "There is, then, no gulf between things in themselves and their appearances or 'phenomena'." Does this mean that if sticks look like they bend in water, and objects seem to shrink when they recede from us, and the Sun appears to rise each morning, and price looks like it is an accurate reflection of value, they must all true? All of these would seem to be the case if there is no 'gulf' between appearance and 'things-in-themselves'? [Irony intended.]

 

If so, why on earth did Marx say the following?

 

"But all science would be superfluous if the outward appearance and the essence of things directly coincided." [Marx (1981), p.956; Marx (1998), p.804. Bold emphasis added.]

 

[Not that I agree with Marx on this, but DM-fans often approvingly quote this passage. So, is Lenin right, or is Marx? Is there a "gulf" or not?]

 

And why would countless other Marxists tell us there is a 'contradiction' between the way 'things appear' and their 'essence'? Or that 'appearances' are, or can be, misleading?

 

It wouldn't be difficult to illustrate a similar, positively neurotic obsession with "things"/"objects" (etc.) -- which each Knower 'knowing' by entering onto a relation with 'it'/'them' via 'reflection' or 'sensation' (a "thing-in-itself", an "image" of it, or a 'concept' under which it supposedly falls, etc.) -- in the work of theorists drawn from all areas of Dialectical Marxism. Or, indeed, from right across HCD, Academic Marxist literature. Here for example is Andrew Sayer:

 

"In most discussion of this [i.e., knowledge and the relation between 'subject' and 'object' -- RL], the term 'subject' (or sometimes 'knowing-subject') refers to the observer or investigator or simply 'thinker', while the 'object' is defined as the thing being studied." [Sayer (1992), p.22. Bold emphasis added. The page number is completely different in the Second Corrected Edition, i.e., Sayer (2010), pp.14-15.]

 

Although Sayer accepts this characterisation, he advanced two qualifications: (i) He doesn't restrict the 'knowing-subject' simply to scientists, and (ii) He also includes an older meaning of 'subject', which implies the involvement of a creative agent (thereby rejecting the idea that knowledge is purely passive or contemplative). The bottom line, though, is that he too has bought into this ancient mischaracterisation of knowledge (which sees it as a subject-object relation between 'the knower' and 'the known'), only now with added 'dialectical spin'. He earlier rejected a restriction of knowledge to the "knowing-that" form (which he connects with the 'contemplative' paradigm), adding that the "knowing-how" form should also be taken into account (p.14); a point I have also made. [On that, see Essay Thirteen Part Three.] Nevertheless, Sayer has both retained and bought into the old picture of knowledge as a relation (in the above sense), and, indeed, has directly connected it with what has elsewhere in this Essay been called 'bourgeois individualism', with his reference to the "knowing subject". Only this time it is an active individual not a passive one. Big difference! Active bourgeois individualism! Hence, Sayer remains trapped within an individualism approach to knowledge. [I have said much more about his book in Part One -- e.g., here and here.]

 

In this respect, Sayer isn't a lone figure in Marxist academia, either; there are countless others. For example, the 'traditional approach to knowledge' blights an otherwise careful, detailed and nuanced study -- Ruben (1979) -- where there are far too many references to the relation between 'minds' and the 'objects' of knowledge, between 'things' and 'consciousness', to list here. [I will say much more about Ruben's (untypically high quality) book in Essay Three Part Six, where the relevant work of several other Academic Marxist will also be scrutinised.] Here, too, is Sean Sayers (nailing his colours to this 'Platonic mast'):

 

"The main aim of this book is to develop and defend a realist theory of knowledge. By 'realism' I mean the theory that there is an objective, material world, which exists independently of consciousness and which is knowable by consciousness. This idea will, I know, appear so evident and obvious to many people -- and particularly to those unfamiliar with philosophy -- that it will seem strange to dignify it with an imposing philosophical title like 'realism', and stranger still to spend time and effort defending it. For this is the view of common sense, which most people adopt in a quite natural and unquestioning way in the course of their everyday lives. Nevertheless, realism has been one of the most controversial and disputed theories in the history of philosophy. These disputes turn around the relation of subject and object; they concern the nature of appearance and reality, and the character of reason and truth; they raise some of the most basic and fundamental questions of philosophy. It soon becomes clear that in order to defend realism -- which at first seems so obvious -- it is necessary to entertain views and to develop philosophical theories which are far from obvious or commonsensical. It is not difficult to see the sorts of philosophical problem that realism involves. It seems to want to say two opposed and incompatible things about the relation of subject and object. For realism maintains that the object is independent of the subject, and yet it also insists that there is no absolute gulf between them, and that the object can be grasped and known by the subject. It seems to want to say that subject and object, appearance and reality, are both distinct and yet also united. Paradoxical as it at first seems, I shall argue that this is indeed what realism must say, and that it is a true and illuminating thing to say." [Sayers (1985), pp.3-4. Bold emphases alone added; paragraphs merged.]

 

Once again, if every such passage were to be quoted, this Essay would be many thousands of words longer than it already is.

 

Finally, here are three randomly-selected passages off the Internet (there are scores more like it!) followed by one from the Marxist Internet Archive, that attempt to explain Hegel's use of the word "semblance" (which we will meet again later), in similar terms:

 

"Hegel discovered the method of dialectics in which mediation between the subject or thinking mind and the objective world takes place. Hegel describes this whole process in great detail; in the beginning there lies an immediacy, or the moment when the process of mediation has yet to begin between the subject and the thing-in-itself.... Hegel explains in detail this whole process of appropriating the object. At the end of this process the 'thing-in-itself', mediating with the subjective mind becomes the 'thing for itself'." [Quoted from here; accessed 25/05/2024. Bold emphases added; paragraphs merged. This was taken from the so-called 'Marxist University', which is in fact an IMT front. The IMT is currently in the process of rebranding itself as The Revolutionary Communist Party. This new 'party' has zero to do with the old RCP, which broke away from the UK-SWP back in the 1970s and later morphed into the group behind the far right, Koch brothers-funded, libertarian Spiked! magazine.]

 

"So, as a particularly simple example, if the idea we were examining through dialectics was temperature, then one of the contradictions that helps us better understand temperature would be the contradiction between hot and cold (sic!). If the idea was war, then we might examine it as a series of advances and retreats to better grasp what happened. Things are not things-in-themselves, they exist as a part of something else, too. The reason we understand things as contradictions comes from Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel.... Remember that a contradiction is a 'unity of opposites', or mutually antagonistic forces that drive development, yet also together comprise a larger whole." [Quoted from here; accessed 18/06/2021. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"The Doctrine of Essence is the most important part of Hegel’s philosophy, because it is here that he explains the dialectic in detail. Human thought does not stop at what is immediately given in sense perception, but seeks to go beyond it and grasp the thing-in-itself. The contradiction which lies at the heart of all things is expressed as the idea of the unity of opposites. Dialectically, what seem to be mutually exclusive phenomena are actually inseparable." [Quoted from here, accessed 12/01/2022. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"Illusory Being [or semblance] is a category of Hegel's philosophy denoting the sceptical moment when an object is first perceived. The Dialectic of Reflection is the dialectic of the essential and unessential. Illusory Being is the negative moment in this dialectic -- the unessential. Against the position of scepticism, Hegel says that it must be recognised that the unessential is Being's unessential, that is, the thing is expressed in the unessential as well as in the essential, only the unessential is not yet recognised for what it is." [Quoted from here; accessed 14/02/2017. Italic emphasis and link in the original; bold added.]

 

Hence, regarding knowledge as a relation between 'the Knower and 'the Known', the latter half of which often takes the form of an 'idea', an 'image', an 'abstraction', a 'concept', an object' a 'representation', or even a 'thing'/'thing-in-itself' (which are all the result of 'reflection', 'sensation' or 'perception') is mainstream among Dialectical Marxists. Unfortunately, as we have seen, this approach undermines propositional knowledge (which clearly has a knock-on effect, compromising science itself) -- with outright scepticism soon following in its wake.

 

[On the significance of several of these observations, see Essay Six, here. I have said much more about 'Subject/Object Identity' in Note 18a, below; see also Note 25. The above comments in no way minimise the importance of perception or sensation, they merely question the role they play in Traditional Epistemology and the theory that knowledge is a relation of some sort or description.]

 

The problem with this ancient approach to knowledge, which the above dialecticians have clearly failed to appreciate -- let alone notice --, is that it is characterised in terms of the relation between an individual and an 'object'/'thing', totally undercutting the social nature of knowledge and language, which is a (scientific) theory Marxists elsewhere at least claim to accept. Once again, this should surprise no one since this entire family of traditional philosophical doctrines is based on, and was motivated by, atomistic theories of language -- covered in Essay Three Part One, Essay Twelve (across all its Parts), and Thirteen Part Three -- that were themselves based on abstractionist theories of cognition and meaning. Nor should it surprise anyone given the additional fact that, in its post-Renaissance form, this approach received a major boost from ideological currents set in motion by the rise of Capitalism, with its attendant bourgeois individualism, covered earlier.

 

Even when the importance of propositional knowledge is admitted by a few DM-theorists (such as David-Hillel Ruben and Alex Callinicos), propositions are themselves reified as objects. What happens then is that the 'knowing-subject' is put in a relation with a 'sentence-as-object', a 'fact' it is supposed to 'reflect', or even a psychological/neurological 'embodiment' of that sentence in the CNS/'mind' (i.e., a yet-to-be-indentified 'mental process' or 'structure').

 

Again, as Meredith William pointed out in connection with Vygotsky's theory (but this comment applies with equal measure to every DM-theorist covered in this Essay -- and, indeed, at this site -- who has written on this topic):

 

"Vygotsky attempts to combine a social theory of cognition development with an individualistic account of word-meaning.... [But] the social theory of development can only succeed if it is combined with a social theory of meaning." [Williams (1999b), p.275. Bold emphasis added.]

 

But, dialecticians have only succeeded in shooting themselves in the foot when they bought into the Platonic/Christian/Cartesian Paradigm, which characterises the 'mind' as a surrogate human being that resides inside each skull (an homunculus, also covered earlier), and when they accepted atomistic theories of language motivated by, and based on, abstractionism. In which case, there is no chance they will ever be able to do what Williams suggests while they remain trapped inside this ancient, aristocratic paradigm.

 

However, these Forms, these Platonic 'acquaintances', are not only total strangers, they are also completely featureless phantoms. [Once more, the significance of that remark will emerge when the rest of Essay Three has finally been published.] Furthermore, since such 'ideas' (such 'objects of knowledge') plainly don't carry a 'Metaphysical Identity Card' around with them (so to speak), how a single Knower is capable of cognising, let alone (re)cognising, these formless apparitions is a complete mystery, to say the least. Would any of my readers recognise someone they had never seen before? Still worse would they recognise something for which they don't yet possess the words, which must be the case with these formless spectres? Anyone who thinks they would recognise any of them might like to try to recognise one of the Meskonators mentioned in Essay Six.

 

[As hinted above, this 'problem' re-surfaces in more recent Nativist theories of language that are based, for example, on the work of Noam Chomsky -- with his attempt to re-habilitate the Platonic/Cartesian Paradigm. On that, see Cowie (1997, 2002, 2008) and Sampson (2005). See also a summary of the points Sampson makes, here. (Having said that, I hesitate to refer anyone to Sampson's work since he is a right-wing Tory who holds some highly offensive beliefs about race, among several other topics. Fortunately, that doesn't appear to have affected his work in this area of linguistics.) Furthermore, the article by Yorick Wilks (mentioned in Note 3, above) takes Jerry Fodor to task for committing somewhat similar errors.]

 

6b. In fact, the insurmountable 'problems' the 'Doctrine of the Trinity' introduced into Christian Theology arose directly out of earlier attempts by Plato and Aristotle to account for generality; more specifically because of the 'Forms', 'Universals' and 'Substances' they invented. Of course, this fact hasn't been lost on anti-Trinitarian Christians for many centuries.

 

7. This isn't to suggest that there aren't, or haven't been, countless 'solutions' to these 'classical brainteasers', only that they have resisted every single one of them for nigh on 2400 years. Part of the reason for that is summarised in Note 6a, above.

 

Plainly, an entirely new approach is now long overdue.

 

Fortunately, one such was suggested a few generations ago, the central plank of which was that 'philosophical problems' like this may be resolved by dissolving them, by identifying the logical, syntactic and semantic errors that originally breathed life into them -- and even now still keep them on life support. Unsurprisingly, this new approach emphasised a return to ordinary discourse, also recommended by Marx himself. This novel approach possesses the following advantage (at least as far as Marxists are concerned!): it re-situates language, science and the search for knowledge in the public domain, and hence on home turf for the left, basing it on the material language and experience of the working class.

 

[This topic will be examined in more detail in Essay Twelve Parts Two and Seven (summary here).]

 

7b. Here is what we read about Mao's early life and education:

 

"Mao had to learn by rote the Confucian classics, then an essential part of education in China, at which he was exceptionally talented. He was known by his pupils as a diligent and smart student, gathering a good foothold in Chinese history and learning to write legible calligraphy. Mao absolutely adored reading, flipping through pages well into the night when the entire village was asleep." [Quoted from here; accessed 14/08/2024. Bold emphasis added.]

 

In addition, Mao had also been a student of Daoism (i.e., The Yijing, or I Ching), which, given its similarity to DM, should hardly surprise us:

 

"Mao had studied little Western philosophy before 1909 when he was sixteen. What he had learned by then were the Four Books, namely The Great Learning (Daxue), The Doctrine of the Mean (Zhongyong), The Analects of Confucius (Lunyu), and Mencius (Mengzi), and the Five Classics, The Book of Songs (Shijing), The Book of History (Shujing), The Book of Changes (Yijing), The Book of Rites (Liji), and The Spring and Autumn Annals (Chunqiu). He had loved Confucius. Mao had never suspended his study of classical Chinese philosophy, especially pre-Qin Confucianism, Daoism, the Li Learning (lixue) of Song and Ming dynasties, even though he was heavily influenced by Western thought during the New Culture period around [the] 1920s. According to Li Yongtai, Mao was particularly interested in Chinese dialectics, sophisticated in the dialectic of Confucius, Mencius, Laozi, Zhuangzi, Xunzi, Mozi, Qu Yuan, Sima Qian, Zhu Xi, Zhang Zai, and Wang Fuzhi, and finally developed his early dialectical style of thought and employed it in his own thinking and writings." [Tian (2005), p.150. Italics in the original; bold emphases and links added.]

 

Here are just some of the relevant, core tenets of Confucianism:

 

"The dynamic and holistic perspective of the Confucian worldview may offer significant contributions in this regard, enlarging our sense of the ethical terrain and moral concerns, and providing a rich source for rethinking our own relationship with nature. Confucianism's organic holisms can give us a special appreciation for the interconnectedness of all life forms and renew our sense of the sacredness of this intricate web of life. Moreover, the Confucian understanding of the dynamic vitalism underlying cosmic processes offers us a basis for reverencing nature. From a Confucian perspective, nature cannot be thought of as simply composed of inert, dead matter. Rather, all life forms share the element of qi or material force. This shared psycho-physical entity becomes the basis for establishing a reciprocity between the human and nonhuman worlds....

 

"The Chinese have a term to describe the vibrancy and aliveness of the universe. This is qi or ch’i, which is translated in a variety of ways in the classical Confucian tradition as spirit, air, or breath, and later in the Neo-Confucian tradition as material force, matter energy, vital force. It describes the realization that the universe is alive with vitality and resonates with life. What is especially remarkable about this ancient and enduring realization of the Chinese people is that qi is a unified field embracing both matter and energy. It is thus a matrix containing both material and spiritual life from the smallest particle to the largest visible reality. Qi moves through the universe from the constituent particles of matter to mountains and rocks, plants and trees, animals, and birds, fish and insects. All the elements -- air, earth, fire, and water -- are composed of qi. We humans, too, are alive with qi. It makes up our body and spirit as one integrated whole, and it activates our mind-and-heart, which is a single unified reality in Chinese thought....

 

"Li is the inner ordering principle of reality that is embedded in the heart of qi. The Chinese character for li suggests working on the geological veins found in the mineral jade, which must first be discovered, and then carved adeptly. Li is comparable to the principle of logos, whereby all of reality is imprinted with structure and intelligibility. It is both pattern and potential pattern, and thus gives reality its intricacy of design as well as its thrust toward directionality and purpose. It is a revealing and concealing sensibility for human consciousness." [Quoted from here; accessed 14/08/2024. Bold emphases alone added.]

 

One of the core Daoist ideas is the following (does this sound familiar to anyone?):

 

"The Yin Yang principle is 'the' preeminent ancient Chinese secret offering explanation to everything that exists, changes or moves. Its origin comes from observing the very essence of the Universe -- from darkness there is light. Yin Yang embodies duality or an opposite nature with Yin tending toward passive, dark, feminine, downward seeking and Yang tending toward active, light, masculine, upward seeking. Because we can see dark and we can see light they appear separate yet they are connected. Everything in life has this same connective quality. However, notice your tendency to identify Yin and Yang as separate and to judge which one you relate to or prefer over the other. This same human tendency prevents us from accessing the power of the principle. So to access the power of Yin Yang we must embrace both Yin and Yang and observe without judgment. There is also a cyclical nature to Yin Yang. Everything changes into its opposite in an ongoing cycle of reversal. Health changes to sickness and sickness changes into health. The more you embrace Yin Yang and see your life as one continuous flow; your experiences in life will naturally reverse or begin to flow more easily." [China Daily, 25/02/2011. Bold emphases added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site; paragraphs merged.]

 

So, other than a choice some of some of the (relevant) words Daoism and Confucianism employ, both of the above aren't a million miles different from DM.

 

What was that again about "The ideas of the ruling-class"?

 

I keep forgetting...

 

[For the religious upbringing and indoctrination of the other DM-Classicists (that helped pre-dispose them toward accepting ideas they found in Hegel), see Essay Nine Part Two. A detailed survey of the close links that exist between Daoism and Maoist 'Dialectics' can be accessed here.]

 

8. These rather gnomic remarks have been expanded upon in Essay Thirteen Part Three.

 

8a0. The connection between a 'rational soul' and a well ordered city was made explicit in Plato's Republic. I have reproduced the relevant passage in Appendix Two. [On this, see Williams (1973) and Ferrari (2005). See also Kenny (1969), and here.]

 

8a. Again, this theme will be developed and defended in Essay Three Part Five -- along lines suggested by Bertrand Russell [in Russell (1917b)], expanded on here and here; the first of these is Swartz (2009), the second, Swartz (1985).

 

How Traditional Theories in general grew out of the systematic distortion of language is explored in Essay Twelve Part One; the 'anthropomorphisation of the brain' is examined at length in Essay Thirteen Part Three -- specifically, here and here. I have also dealt with 'natural necessity' in Essay Thirteen Part Three, here.

 

[More details can be found in Price and Corry (2007). The line I will be promoting (but given a far less theoretical spin) can be found in Hacker (2007), pp.57-89.]

 

9. We will meet this particular option again in connection with the RRT in Essay Twelve Part Four (summary here).

 

[RRT = Reverse Reflection Theory (which is perhaps better described as the Projection Theory of 'Knowledge'). That theory will be fully explained in Essay Twelve Part Four. Basically, the idea is that, given DM, language and 'mind' do not in fact 'reflect reality' (as its proponents maintain). The reverse is the case. 'Reality' is structured so that it conforms with how DM-theorists think we cognise it. So, discourse doesn't reflect the world, the world is made to conform with how 'dialectical jargon' tries to picture it. Language and meaning are thereby projected onto the world. Indeed, the ersatz 'reality' that results from this 'reverse-reflection' (this projection) is little more than a shadow cast on the world by a systematic distortion of language, to paraphrase Wittgenstein (and Marx), again. The RRT is therefore intimately connected (via Hegel and other mystics) with ancient theories about the origin of the world via speech, a universe created by the Logos (as illustrated in The Book of Genesis) -- a topic covered earlier in this Essay and in Part One. The world is therefore regarded as ultimately discursive; it is both the product of language and constituted by language. For those who prefer this way of 'doing philosophy' (i.e., dogmatically, treating it as a sort of Super-Science) it seems 'perfectly natural and legitimate' to impose linguistic categories on the world, in a 'like-reflects-like' sort of way. They are just two sides of the same coin: the world is ultimately linguistic so philosophical theories may be imposed on to it, dogmatically. Unsurprisingly, dialecticians bought into this approach when they began to take philosophical and logical advice from a Christian Mystic (upside down or the 'right way up'). See also Note 19, below.]

 

10. This helps explain an earlier aside: Traditional Philosophy is based on, (a) Distorted language, (b) Ruling-class thought-forms, and (c) The fetishisation of discourse. [There is more on this in Essay Twelve, summary here.]

 

10a. Here is Hegel (who is a model of clarity, as I am sure readers will agree):

 

"Essence becomes matter in that its reflection is determined as relating itself to essence as to the formless indeterminate. Matter is therefore the differenceless identity which is essence, with the determination of being the other of form. It is consequently the real basis or substrate of form, because it constitutes the reflection-into-self of the form-determinations, or the self-subsistent element to which the latter are related as to their positive subsistence. If abstraction is made from every determination, from all form of anything, what is left over is indeterminate matter. Matter is a sheer abstraction. (Matter cannot be seen, felt, and so on -- what is seen, felt, is a determinate matter, that is, a unity of matter and form). This abstraction from which matter proceeds is, however, not merely an external removal and sublating of form, rather does form, as we have seen, spontaneously reduce itself to this simple identity." [Hegel (1999), pp.450-51, §§ 978-979. Bold emphasis alone added. Typos in the on-line version corrected. Paragraphs merged. Of course, Hegel's theory of matter is far more complex that this passage might suggest; on what sense can be made of it, see Kabeshkin (2022). (This links to a PDF.)]

 

Once again, we see 'abstractions' are required for matter itself actually to exist. Language and concepts precede the existence of matter. [This is just the RRT again, as pointed out in Note Nine above.]

 

11. More details will be given in Essays Twelve and Fourteen (summaries here and here).

 

12. This 'problem' revolves around questions raised about the past behaviour of objects and processes, reference to which is necessary in order to determine whether or not they will behave the 'same way' in the present and future as they have done in the past. But, what constitutes 'the same' or even 'different behaviour' might be difficult to specify in non-question-begging terms -- or in a way that isn't itself compromised by the next few points I'm about to make.

 

That is because such questions themselves depend on:

 

(i) The reliability of memory;

 

(ii) The ability to access, read and understand evidence in physical form; and,

 

(iii) The words we use having the same meaning from moment-to-moment.

 

But the 'reliability of memory' and any such evidence is itself based on induction. Or, rather, both are founded on a belief that objects and processes will behave the same way in the present and future as they have done in the past. Abandon that belief, or throw it into doubt, and no content can be given to the terms "the same way" and "different". Hence, if such beliefs are questioned or thrown into doubt, that impacts on the dependability of any reference to "processes and events and their past behaviour". So, if the method used to determine the current and future behaviour of objects and processes is the same as the one used to determine what happened in the past (which, on this account, must also based on the regular behaviour any factors involved -- or, at least, on any such assumptions), and sceptical questions are raised about the methods used to determine the current and future behaviour of objects and processes, they must surely also apply to those used to determine, or recall, what happened in the past. In that case, the entire 'problem' collapses for want of anything to judge it by. That is, the acid of scepticism, as usual, turns out to be far too strong, for it dissolves the means by which any such questions might legitimately be asked.

 

For example, if we rely on what we currently think we used to mean by our past employment of (the same!) words, and we do so by a method that itself questions regularity (which, as we have seen, has to be the case here -- after all, if he were consistent, even Hume had to assume his words might mean something different from moment-to-moment), then we couldn't rely on the meaning of phrases like "same way" or "different" remaining the same today as they did yesterday. In that case, Hume's scepticism (at least in this respect) must end up torpedoing itself. That is because it cant be expressed in language that fails to undermine its own meaning.

 

 [Once again, I am forced to express this 'problem' traditionally, but readers mustn't assume I think any of it makes the slightest sense.]

 

In case one or two readers wonder how it is possible to understand words that can't be made sense of, may I point them in the direction of my explanation of what I mean by the words "sense" used in such a context? So, a sentence can fail to make sense (in the meaning of "sense" explained at the last link), but it could use words that have a contextual meaning. For instance, few atheists will think that a sentence like the following makes any "sense": "The Spirit of God was hovering on the face of the waters" -- Genesis 1:2. Nevertheless, I imagine many atheists will be able to say what (most) Christians think they mean something by the word "God". More-or-less the same applies here, in connection with the 'Problem of Induction', and, indeed, with other metaphysical propositions that express the pseudoproblems that litter Traditional Philosophy (and DM).

 

12a. The material that used to be here has now been moved to the main body of the Essay.

 

I will say much more about this topic in Essay Three Part Five, where I will link the above considerations with Traditional Theories of Mind, Will, Freedom, Necessity and Determinism. This will also connect them with the re-enchantment of nature at the hands of Dialectical Marxists (i.e., in Essay Fourteen Parts One and Two (summary here)). See also, Note 14a1, below.

 

13. Anyone who objects to my use of flowery language should rather take issue with those who concocted the theories targeted at this site, not those who seek to lampoon them.

 

14. This is a call-back to Rousseau:

 

"Man is born free; and everywhere he is in chains. One thinks himself master of others, and still remains a greater slave than they. How did this come about? I do not know. What can make it legitimate? That question I think I can answer." [Rousseau (1913), p.3; Book One, Chapter One.]

 

14a0. The phrase "undermining the unity of the proposition" alludes to the fact that Traditional Logic and Grammar turned propositions into lists of names. Since lists say nothing (unless they are articulated with words that aren't names), this destroys the capacity language has for expressing anything at all, never mind generality. That was one of the main results of Part One. Readers are directed there for more details.

 

14a1. As Glenn Magee points out:

 

"What Hegel's system promises is a transformed experience of the world, in which we see familiar things in a new light. Science, poetry, art, religion, the state, are all seen to be expressions or embodiments of the Absolute. Ordinary things suddenly take on new meaning. That which had been thought to be a human contrivance, carried out only for finite human ends, devoid of any higher meaning, mystery or religious significance...is now suddenly imbued with spiritual significance.... Thus, Hegel attempts to heal the rift in the modern consciousness between thought and sensation, or thought and experience, by giving us a new form of experience. The very modern scientific and philosophical ideas that formerly seemed to cut us off from experience and from our intuitions of the divine are now seen to be moments of a system of experience that constitutes the divine itself. Hegel's system is an attempt to 're-enchant' the world, to re-invest nature with the experience of the numinous lost with the death of the mythical consciousness." [Magee (2008), p.97. Bold emphases and link added; quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

While Hegel thought he saw the 'Absolute' (or traces of 'It') everywhere he looked, DM-theorists see the "Totality" and universal inter-connection. In that light, everything, similarly, "takes on a new meaning". The Whole gives new meaning to the parts and the parts reciprocate and lend meaning to the whole. Don't take my word for it; here are the quasi-religious ruminations of a few DM-fans:

 

"[W]hen we bring these terms [belonging to the totality] into relation with each other their meaning is transformed…. In a dialectical system, the entire nature of the part is determined by its relationships with the other parts and so with the whole. The part makes the whole, and the whole makes the parts. In this analysis, it is not just the case that the whole is more than the sum of the parts but also that the parts become more than they are individually by being part of a whole…. [F]or dialectical materialists the whole is more than the simple sum of its parts." [Rees (1998), pp.5, 77. Paragraphs merged; bold emphases added.]

 

"The last dogmatic assumption of [mechanical materialism] to be mentioned is that each of the things or particles, whose interactions are said to make up the totality of events in the universe, has its own fixed nature quite independent of everything else.... Proceeding from this assumption it follows that all relations between things are merely external relations. That is to say, things enter into various relationships one with another, but these relationships are accidental and make no difference to the nature of the things related. And regarding each thing as a separate unit entering into external relations with other things, it further follows that [mechanical materialism] regards the whole as no more that the sum of its separate parts.... Not one of these assumptions is correct. Nothing exists or can exist in splendid isolation, separate from its conditions of existence, independent of its relationships with other things.... The very nature of a thing is modified and transformed by its relationships with other things. When things enter into such relationships that they become parts of a whole, the whole cannot be regarded as nothing more than the sum of the parts.... [The] mutual relations which the parts enter into in constituting the whole modify their own properties, so that while it might be said that the whole is determined by the parts it may equally be said that the parts are determined by the whole." [Cornforth (1976), pp.46-47. Bold emphasis added; paragraphs merged.]

 

"When we consider a phenomenon from the point of view of its content it appears as a whole, as a totality of all the elements and aspects that make it up and of all their interactions. It is through this totality that content relates to form.... [The content of a part], however, is conditioned not only by their specific nature, but also by the general nature of the whole. For this reason they play their specific roles not by themselves but as parts of the whole. On the other hand, the general nature of the whole...depends on the specific nature of the parts that make it up.... The interconnection of the whole and part, expressed in the dependence of the quality of the whole on the specific nature of its component parts, on  the one hand, and the qualities of the parts on the specific nature of the whole, on the other, results from the interconnection between parts within the whole, this interconnection constituting the structure of the whole.... [T]he properties of the elements depends on the structure of the whole they make up, whereas the structure of the whole depends on its constituent elements, their nature and quantity. In other words, the elements of an object and the structure of this object (the manner of connection of the elements) are necessarily interdependent and constitute a dialectical unity." [Sheptulin (1978), pp.227-31. Bold emphasis added; paragraphs merged.]

 

"In contrast, in the dialectical world view, things are assumed from the beginning to be internally heterogeneous at every level. And this heterogeneity does not mean that the object or system is composed of fixed natural units. Rather the 'correct' division of the whole into part varies, depending upon the particular aspect of the whole that is in question.... It is a matter of simple logic that parts can be parts only when there is a whole for them to be parts of. Part implies whole, and whole implies part. Yet reductionist practice ignores this relationship, isolating parts as pre-existing units of which wholes are then composed. In the dialectical world the logical dialectical relation between part and whole is taken seriously. Part makes whole, and whole makes part....The first principle of a dialectical view, then, is that a whole is a relation of heterogeneous parts that have no prior independent existence as parts. The second principle, which flows from the first, is that, in general, the properties of parts have no prior alienated existence but are acquired by being parts of a particular whole. In the alienated world the intrinsic properties of alienated parts confer properties on the whole, which may in addition take on new properties which are not characteristic of the parts: the whole may be more than the sum of the parts. But the ancient debate on emergence, whether indeed wholes may have properties not intrinsic to the parts, is beside the point. The fact is that the parts have properties that are characteristic of them only as they are parts of wholes; the properties come into existence in the interactions that makes the whole. A person cannot fly by flapping her arms simultaneously. But people do fly, as a consequence of the social organisation that has created airplanes, pilots and fuel. It is not that society flies, however, but individuals in society, who have acquired a property they do not have outside society. The limitations of individual physical beings are negated by social interactions. The whole, thus, is not simply the object of interaction of the parts but is the subject of action of the parts." [Levins and Lewontin (1985), pp.272-73. Bold emphases added; paragraphs merged.]

 

"According to formal logic, the whole is equal to the sum of its parts. On closer examination, however, this is seen not to be true.... It is necessary to acquire a concrete understanding of the object as an integral system, not as isolated fragments; with all its necessary interconnections, not torn out of context, like a butterfly pinned to a collector's board; in its life and movement, not as something lifeless and static. Such an approach is in open conflict with the so-called 'laws' of formal logic, the most absolute expression of dogmatic thought ever conceived, representing a kind of mental rigor mortis. But nature lives and breathes, and stubbornly resists the embraces of formalistic thinking. 'A' is not equal to 'A.' Subatomic particles are and are not. Linear processes end in chaos. The whole is greater than the sum of its parts. Quantity changes into quality. Evolution itself is not a gradual process, but interrupted by sudden leaps and catastrophes. What can we do about it? Facts are stubborn things." [Woods and Grant (1995), pp.57, 82-83. Bold emphasis added; paragraphs merged.]

 

[I have subjected the above ideas to detailed and sustained criticism in Essay Eleven Part Two. I have also explained more about the quasi-religious stench given off by words like these in Essay Nine Part Two -- and the reasons for it.]

 

'Reality' ends up re-enchanted because anthropomorphic concepts have not only been imposed on, or read into, it, they have also been forced into every pore so that nothing can escape their influence. This is why systems, processes, 'things' and objects wind up 'contradicting' one another -- as if they were engaged in some sort of 'cosmic conversation' or argument among themselves. The world has been re-animated by the operation and interaction of these omnipresent 'contradictions', which sees everything locked in 'struggle' with everything else. In this way, even the class war was projected onto the universe!

 

"Contradiction is the root of all movement and life, and it is only in so far as it contains a contradiction that anything moves and has impulse and activity." [Hegel (1999), p.439, §956. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"So long as we consider things at rest and lifeless, each one by itself…we do not run up against any contradictions in them…. But the position is quite different as soon as we consider things in their motion, their change, their life, their reciprocal influence. Then we immediately become involved in contradictions. Motion itself is a contradiction…. [T]here is a contradiction objectively present in things and processes themselves, a contradiction is moreover an actual force...." [Engels (1976), pp.152-53. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"Dialectics…prevails throughout nature…. [T]he motion through opposites which asserts itself everywhere in nature, and which by the continual conflict of the opposites…determines the life of nature." [Engels (1954), p.211. Bold emphases added.]

 

"The identity of opposites…is the recognition…of the contradictory, mutually exclusive, opposite tendencies in all phenomena and processes of nature…. The condition for the knowledge of all processes of the world in their 'self-movement,' in their spontaneous development, in their real life, is the knowledge of them as a unity of opposites. Development is the 'struggle' of opposites. The two basic (or two possible? or two historically observable?) conceptions of development (evolution) are: development as decrease and increase, as repetition, and development as a unity of opposites (the division of a unity into mutually exclusive opposites and their reciprocal relation). In the first conception of motion, self-movement, its driving force, its source, its motive, remains in the shade (or this source is made external -- God, subject, etc.). In the second conception the chief attention is directed precisely to knowledge of the source of 'self'-movement. The first conception is lifeless, pale and dry. The second is living. The second alone furnishes the key to the 'self-movement' of everything existing; it alone furnishes the key to the 'leaps,' to the 'break in continuity,' to the 'transformation into the opposite,' to the destruction of the old and the emergence of the new. The unity (coincidence, identity, equal action) of opposites is conditional, temporary, transitory, relative. The struggle of mutually exclusive opposites is absolute, just as development and motion are absolute." [Lenin (1961), pp.357-58. Bold emphases alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. Paragraphs merged.]

 

"The law of contradiction in things, that is, the law of the unity of opposites, is the basic law of materialist dialectics.... As opposed to the metaphysical world outlook, the world outlook of materialist dialectics holds that in order to understand the development of a thing we should study it internally and in its relations with other things; in other words, the development of things should be seen as their internal and necessary self-movement, while each thing in its movement is interrelated with and interacts on the things around it. The fundamental cause of the development of a thing is not external but internal; it lies in the contradictoriness within the thing. There is internal contradiction in every single thing, hence its motion and development.... The universality or absoluteness of contradiction has a twofold meaning. One is that contradiction exists in the process of development of all things, and the other is that in the process of development of each thing a movement of opposites exists from beginning to end....There is nothing that does not contain contradictions; without contradiction nothing would exist.... Thus it is already clear that contradiction exists universally and is in all processes, whether in the simple or in the complex forms of motion, whether in objective phenomena or ideological phenomena.... Contradiction is universal and absolute, it is present in the process of the development of all things and permeates every process from beginning to end...." [Mao (1937), pp.311-18. Bold emphases added; paragraphs merged.]

 

Human rationality was also projected onto 'reality':

 

"From this dialectical essence of reality Hegel drew the conclusion that constitutes an indispensable part of his famous aphorism: All that is rational is real. But for Hegel all that is real is not without exception and qualification worthy of existence. 'Existence is in part mere appearance, and only in part reality.' (Introduction to the Shorter Logic, §6.)  [I.e., Hegel (1975), p.9, §6 -- RL.] Existence elementally and necessarily divides itself, and the investigating mind finds it to be so divided, into opposing aspects of appearance and essence. This disjunction between appearance and essence is no more mysterious than the disjunction between the inside and outside of an object." [Novack (1971), p.86. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. I have reproduced the edition of Hegel's work used by the editor of Novack's on-line text, Andy Blunden, not the version that appears here. Links and bold emphasis added.]

 

As I pointed out earlier (slightly edited):

 

In sharp contrast, while Hegel's 'logic' seemed to offer real hope in this direction, he soon discovered that his Ideas controlled him, not he them. By fetishising the thoughts he imagined were ('logically') fighting it out inside his head he turned them into what were in effect self-directed agents, himself into their compliant stooge. By these means he magicked the animated contents of his head into 'laws' that ran the entire show. Hence, for him, what had once been the product of the social relations between human beings (language, inference, negation, contradiction) not only ended up manipulating his thoughts, they now powered the universe!

 

As noted earlier, critics might be forgiven for labelling this, 'Ontology for Megalomaniacs'. It is indeed the philosophical equivalent of a seriously deranged individual claiming to be Napoleon -- or, perhaps even worse, 'God Himself'.

 

According to Hegel, his crazy Ideas appear to have taken over the Asylum! Instead of the 'psychologically-challenged' contradicting themselves, Hegel's universe did that for them!...

 

In relation to this, Feuerbach plainly got things (slightly) wrong: Hegel's 'God' in fact results from the projection of linguistic rules and human characteristics inwards and outwards -- into himself, and then onto the universe.

 

This should therefore be renamed, Feuerbach 2.0, involving: Speculation on Steroids, Metaphysics on Mescaline, Anthropomorphism on Amphetamines, Epistemology on Ecstasy, Ontology on OxyContin and Logic on LSD!

 

[These are the 'substitute opiates' Marx might very well have spoken about if he were alive today -- and this  is why he would have been right.]

 

But, it is precisely here, over such issues, that the fetishisation of language -- detailed in Part One -- elbowed its way into Dialectical Philosophy, and hence into Dialectical Marxism.

 

Subsequently for DM-fans, their ideas supposedly 'reflected' the world, but that turns out to be the case only if Hegel's 'logic' is allowed to control their thoughts and lead them by the nose, too.

 

No wonder then that Max Eastman expressed himself as follows:

 

"Hegelism is like a mental disease; you can't know what it is until you get it, and then you can't know because you have got it." [Eastman (1926), p.22. Bold emphasis added.]

 

[Anyone who objects to my quoting Max Eastman should check this out, and then perhaps think again.]

 

Which, of course, helps explain the quasi-religious fervour with which 'The Sacred Dialectic' is protected and defended by all those whose brains it has colonised.

 

[On that, see here and here.]

 

14a2. Which might help explain why Trotsky came out with the following remark:

 

"Dialectic training of the mind, as necessary to a revolutionary fighter as finger exercises to a pianist, demands approaching all problems as processes and not as motionless categories. Whereas vulgar evolutionists, who limit themselves generally to recognizing evolution in only certain spheres, content themselves in all other questions with the banalities of 'common sense.'" [Trotsky (1971), p.70. Bold emphases added; quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

As is the case with opiate addiction, regular hits become necessary. Not only that, but this 'intellectual drug' seems to rob DM-junkies of their free will (or at least their rationality in this regard), a point underlined by Max Eastman (quoted earlier):

 

"Hegelism is like a mental disease; you can't know what it is until you get it, and then you can't know because you have got it." [Eastman (1926), p.22.]

 

Some might take offence at the analogy I have just drawn between the acceptance of DM and opiate addiction. I have explained its relevance in Essay Nine Part Two, here. The short version is as follows: this analogy is connected with two of Marx's remarks (in conjunction with the points made above, in Note 14a1):

 

"Feuerbach's great achievement is.... The proof that philosophy is nothing else but religion rendered into thought and expounded by thought, i.e., another form and manner of existence of the estrangement of the essence of man; hence equally to be condemned...." [Marx (1975e), p.381. I have used the on-line version, here. Bold emphasis and link added.]

 

"The foundation of irreligious criticism is: Man makes religion, religion does not make man. Religion is, indeed, the self-consciousness and self-esteem of man who has either not yet won through to himself, or has already lost himself again. But man is no abstract being squatting outside the world. Man is the world of man -- state, society. This state and this society produce religion, which is an inverted consciousness of the world, because they are an inverted world. Religion is the general theory of this world, its encyclopaedic compendium, its logic in popular form, its spiritual point d'honneur, its enthusiasm, its moral sanction, its solemn complement, and its universal basis of consolation and justification. It is the fantastic realization of the human essence since the human essence has not acquired any true reality. The struggle against religion is, therefore, indirectly the struggle against that world whose spiritual aroma is religion. Religious suffering is, at one and the same time, the expression of real suffering and a protest against real suffering. Religion is the sigh of the oppressed creature, the heart of a heartless world, and the soul of soulless conditions. It is the opium of the people. The abolition of religion as the illusory happiness of the people is the demand for their real happiness. To call on them to give up their illusions about their condition is to call on them to give up a condition that requires illusions. The criticism of religion is, therefore, in embryo, the criticism of that vale of tears of which religion is the halo." [Marx (1975d), p.244. Bold emphases alone added; paragraphs merged.]

 

So, in relation to the above analogy, anyone who has tried to engage DM-fans in debate concerning 'dialectics' will know exactly what Eastman meant and what I am driving at. DM-fans certainly won't get it, and for the above reasons -- "You can't know what it is until you get it, and then you can't know because you have got it."

 

Again, in Essay Nine Part Two, it will be revealed why (otherwise) level-headed revolutionaries (like Engels, Lenin and Trotsky) surrendered (or "alienated") their rationality (in this respect) to ideas that depend on, or implicitly imply, the 'rationality' of the physical universe and existence of just such a 'Cosmic Will' (which is, in effect, a secular version of the 'Holy Spirit'/'the Logos' -- on that, see Note 20, below). What next? 'Intelligent photons' and 'inquisitive x-rays'?

 

14a. This also helps account for the rather peculiar fact that the more 'dialectical' the party the more autocratic it appears to be, the more prone it seems to fragmentation, and for its 'leaders' to 're-educate', imprison or execute annoying critics and infidel 'Revisionists!' when in power. In such circumstances (as is also the case when the religious gain control of the state), the 'dialectical mailed fist' soon replaces the 'invisible hand' of reasonableness and internal fights readily break out. This is especially the case with Stalinists and Maoists (if or when they actually manage to seize power). While parties belonging to those two political traditions don't split or fragment nearly as much as Trotskyist parties do -- who have incidentally turned sectarianism and fragmentation into an art form --, they are nevertheless quite prepared to turn the level of vitriol up to eleven as they imprison, section, 're-educate', silence or 'liquidate' the ideologically recalcitrant. In which case, there is no need for such parties to fragment or expel; after all, 'No man, no problem...'.

 

[Yes, I am aware Stalin probably didn't say that! As one pro-Communist site puts it, those words were invented by: "Anti-Stalinist novelist Anatoly Rybakov [who] included this phrase...in his book 'Children of the Arbat' (1987)." (Link added.) Nevertheless, that is certainly what happened a few generations ago in states we can all name, and is still happening in others we can also name. These accusations have been fully substantiated in Essay Nine Part Two, which exposes the damage DM has inflicted on all forms of Dialectical Marxism, and what all form of the latter have inflicted on Marxism itself.]

 

14b. In the main body of this Essay, I have shown that, given the traditional view of abstraction, it is impossible to construct a workable, let alone a believable, theory of the social nature of language and knowledge. It has also been shown that this view of abstraction (when coupled with Lenin's 'theory of knowledge', developed in MEC), traps each lone abstractor in their own private, solipsistic universe. As such -- and as far as their 'knowledge' is concerned -- they are isolated individuals, since, for all they know -- or can prove otherwise -- given the meagre resources with which DM-epistemology has saddled them, they are alone, trapped in their own 'image' of 'the universe' and 'all it contains'.

 

[I have developed the above claims at length in Essay Thirteen Part One; readers are directed there for more details. See also Note 15, below.]

 

15. In fact, from inside this 'bourgeois conceptual universe' -- which is an intellectual space populated by little other particularised ideas, atomised concepts and socially-isolated thinkers (i.e., as far as their own theorists picture both themselves and their 'world') -- any attempt to prove there are any other minds becomes impossible.

 

Some might object to the above that a lone abstractor could extrapolate from her own experience to the conclusion that there are others just like her who also have minds. However, any theory based on one observation or on only one example is no better than a guess. Worse still, since the language used to formulate any such projection/guess can't be used this way, since, as we have seen, every word has been tuned into a Proper Name. In that case, it would be impossible for a lone abstractor to be able to specify exactly what the target of any such projection/guess actually is. That is because, of course, belief in other minds requires the use of yet more general terms, which this theory lacks -- or, rather, which it has just emptied of their generality. And this is quite apart from the fact that Lenin's theory of perception would trap him, her, and 'everyone else', in a solipsistic dungeon from which there is no escape. [Again, on that, see Essays Ten Part One and Thirteen Part One.]

 

[The details surrounding Wittgenstein's dissolution of these and other 'problems' won't be entered into here. I will say more about that in Essay Thirteen Part Three. However, readers new to his method should perhaps begin with Kenny (1973a), Glock (1996), Hacker (1996, 1997), and Sluga and Stern (1996); see also here. Concerning Wittgenstein's 'early work' there is no better introduction than White (2006).]

 

16. This topic was discussed much more fully in Essay Six.

 

16a. Be this as it may, any attempt to appeal to the 'relative stability of language' would be no help, either. That is because, given DM-epistemology, no two dialecticians could possibly have the same idea about 'relative stability' -- and worse, no DM-fan could have the same idea about 'relative stability' they themselves entertained only a few moments earlier. The HF takes care of that possibility.

 

And, it is even less use replying that they would have 'relatively' or 'approximately the same idea' about 'relatively' or 'approximately the same idea'. That is because the phrase, "relatively or approximately the same" is itself subject to these very 'limitations', since it now has no determinate meaning. [Irony intended.] The reason for saying so is that if we have no idea what counts as 'exactly the same this' or 'exactly the same that', we are surely in no position to declare that something only approximates to either option. We may only approximate to something when we have some idea what it is we are trying to approximate (i.e., 'absolute identity'). But we have no idea in this case because DM-theorists tell us there is no such thing as absolute identity.

 

Plainly, if there is no such thing as absolute identity there can be no approximation to it.

 

Nor would we even know if our idea of identity was, or wasn't, absolutely identical with absolute identity unless we already had a grasp of the term "absolute identity". "Approximate identity" would be no use here.

 

[Any who disagree might like to tell us what an approximate Meskonator is.]

 

And, the same would be true of any other words thrown in for good measure in a vain attempt to sort this out -- and that includes the word "words".

 

In a 'dialectical universe', where the HF reigns supreme, all that is solid melts into air.

 

[Again, I hasten to add that the above remarks don't represent my view! I am simply exposing the ridiculous implications of DM-Epistemology, DL and the theories of anyone who believes in the HF.]

 

[DL = Dialectical Logic; HF = Heraclitean Flux.]

 

17. At this point it would be no use appealing to the 'relative' or 'partial' nature of knowledge, since, as we saw in Essay Ten Part One, if, per impossible, DM were true, 'reality' would be indistinguishable from Kant's Noumenon -- even if we could say that much about either!

 

18. This idea is up front in Kant, although less sophisticated versions can be found in the work of several earlier thinkers. However, since Hegel (by-and-large) adopted, and then adapted, Kant's approach to suit his own ends, the comments in the main body of this Essay only need to be true of post-Kantian Idealism for it to apply to DM (upside down or 'the right way up').

 

Of course, these days evolution is considered by many to have shaped the 'mind' in this and many other respects. I have devoted several sections of Essay Thirteen Part Three to showing how misguided that idea is, too. Readers are directed there for more details.

 

18a. In relation to which we read the following about this 'mystical union':

 

"Nature, the real, what is perceived, is the 'Idea in apparent shape, which mind, in its synthetic power, posits as the object opposed to itself,' as described by Hegel (p.127). What is perceived is thus 'the determination by mind of its own substance, its ideality and power of determination, through a process which no doubt begins with a separation of itself into two factors which apparently negate each other, but which, by the very activity of such negation and separation, passes beyond the contradiction it implies to a unity which heals the fracture.' The dialectical synthesis of the differentiation in the absolute in the ideal constitutes the subjectivity of mind, the subjective. In subjective mind, the real is not 'explicitly unfolded,' as it is in perception, and complete self-consciousness. The real becomes the other to subjective mind in its state of explication, but an other that is defined by finitude rather than the infinity of the absolute. Mind must project itself into its other in order to recover the infinity of the absolute in the subjective. Mind cannot recover its subjectivity in the real through logic or discursive reason, through that which established its finitude in the real. This can only be accomplished in the intellectual in philosophy.

 

"In perception, mind always has a sense that what is being given of the real in perception is not being in its completion; the limitations of reason are self-apparent in self-consciousness as well. The nature of the human mind is to seek completion in being, whether it be reconciliation of the primordial dehiscence, or recognition of the presence of the absolute in the ideal. Ordinary consciousness is the 'entirely finite, temporal, contradictory, and for that reason transitory, unsatisfied, and un-reconciled spirit' (p.128). In such a consciousness, the satisfactions of reason can only have a 'purely relative and isolated validity,' a condition which thought must necessarily seek to surpass. Appearance as given by perception is seen as a finite function of reason, and in the perception of the real, the intersection of mind and what is external to it, 'mind grasps its finiteness as the negation of its own essential substance, and is aware of its infinity.' In this activity mind is subjective because it is self-determinate and the object of its own will. In this activity mind enacts the principle of differentiation which is the essence of the absolute; reasoning mind doubles itself in relation to the absolute, where the knower and the known are undifferentiated. In this way the infinite is injected into the finite, the ideal into the real, as the real is participant in reason. In absolute mind, the intellectual of Plotinus, principle and activity are the same, ideal and real. In the ideal, the real is participant in the absolute." [Hendrix (2019); quoted from here (this links to a PDF). Bold emphases and links added. The page references are to Hegel (1920), Volume One, in the edition I have used.]

 

The details underlying Hegel's, shall we say, 'Rosicrucian leanings' can be found in Magee (2008), pp.35-36, 51-53, 248-57. See also Benz (1983) and O'Regan (1995). On Rosicrucianism in general, see Yates (2004). [The Introduction to Magee (2008) can now be accessed here.]

 

This terminally obscure 'philosophical problem' (i.e., 'Subject/Object Identity') has dominated much of what currently passes for theory among HCDs/'Academic Marxists', and has formed an important strand in Continental Philosophy for well over two hundred years. However, its origin in 'Mystical Systems of Thought' (in fact, it constitutes the main 'problematic' of Mystical Philosophy in general) hardly raises an eyebrow in either tradition, but definitely not in ideologically-compromised HCD-circles. In fact, I have lost count of the number of books and articles written (in both traditions) concerning the (mystical) union between the Knower and the Known, between 'Subject' and 'Object', the 'Subjective' and the 'Objective', or, indeed, concerning "the thing-in-itself" and "things-for-us". These theorists are all trapped by a picture/metaphor that depicts knowledge as a relation between two objects, the Knower and the Known, once more. [On this, see Note 6a above, where Engels and Lenin's thoughts on this have been quoted (as have others), and where more has been said about this topic in general.]

 

Of course, HCDs will most definitely reject this way of seeing things (i.e., as a mystical union), but mystical union is nevertheless what they (unwittingly) seek. [But, a rose by any other name...]  Indeed, in some cases they are quite open about this union (wisely using less ideologically-compromised terminology to describe it).

 

[There is more on this, here, and another excellent example can be found here. (Unfortunately that link is now as dead as the ideas it once promoted. Added on Edit: That article has now re-surfaced here.)]

 

[HCD = High Church Dialectician; that term is explained here.]

 

Here is what the Glossary at the Marxist Internet Archive had to say about this topic:

 

"'Subject' refers to the person or entity carrying out and responsible for an action, rather than the object which is being acted upon. The term is often used as a synonym for 'human being', or the consciousness of a human being. In the context of history, 'subject' means the agent of history, the people who are the conscious architects of events, rather than their unconscious tools. The 'subject-object' problem, or the separation of subject and object is often taken as a fundamental problem of Western thinking, ever since Descartes invented the 'Cartesian divide' as an epistemological problem. [In fact this 'divide' is much older (albeit expressed differently), as we have seen -- RL.] For dialectics, subject and object can only be understood as opposite aspects of the subject-object relation and thus inseparably part of the same relation. It was Kant who defined the 'Subject' in ethical terms, as the moral agent, having freedom and subject to moral laws. Hegel further developed the concept to overcome the division between the individual 'Subject' or person and the corporate or collective 'Subject,' by means of an understanding of 'Subject' as a self-conscious system of activity, in which the Individual, Universal and Particular aspects are coordinated. Historically, the individual subject only gradually distinguishes herself from the social subject of which she is a part. See 'Subjectivity.'... The earliest recorded use of the word was in 1315 as an adjective meaning 'bound to a superior by some obligation' and in 1340 the word was used as a noun to mean a person under the dominion of a Monarch, as in 'a subject of King Henry.'

 

"In 1374, Chaucer used the word in the sense of 'subject matter' about which different things could be said, and in 1380 the word was used to refer to the substance to which attributes (in the Aristotelian sense) adhered. In this sense, the word has been generalised from being 'subject' to an obligation to being 'subject' to any kind of attachment or property. In 1551, 'subject' was used in the sense of something to which properties could be attributed, and in 1603, Shakespeare used the word in the sense of a thing having a real independent existence, and therefore properties inhered in it, and to which attributes could be contingently attached. By 1638 it had taken on the modern meaning of the word 'subject' in grammar, as opposed to 'predicate' which expresses properties of the subject. The subject is then the 'do-er' of the verb, and we can see the beginnings of a move from the passive carrier of attributes and obligations to the do-er of actions. With René Descartes in 1638, as the Latin subjectum, the word then came to mean a fully conscious thinking 'subject,' in particular the mind or ego, as the subject in which all ideas inhere, and to which all representation and operations are to be attributed. In other words, the thinking and cognising agent. With Descartes, the word did not have an ethical connotation however, but is understood epistemologically. With Kant, the meaning of the word stabilised in its modern philosophical meaning as the moral agent:

 

'A person is a subject who is capable of having his actions imputed to him. Moral personality is, therefore, nothing but the freedom of a rational being under moral laws; and it is to be distinguished from psychological freedom as the mere faculty by which we become conscious of ourselves in different states of the identity of our existence. Hence it follows that a person is properly subject to no other laws than those he lays down for himself, either alone or in conjunction with others.' [Introduction to the Metaphysics of Morals, 1785] [Emphases in the original -- RL.]

 

"With Hegel, the word takes on the broader meaning, not restricted to the individual ego or person, but rather the self-conscious, self-legislating social actor which is both corporate and individual, including for example, states, families and individuals -- provided they are legally free agents (in his day, excluding women and children, for example)." [Quoted from here; accessed 05/02/2017. Several paragraphs merged. Except where indicated, bold emphases alone added; quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. One link added; minor typos corrected.]

 

"Subject and Object are crucial concepts in Epistemology, the study of knowledge. 'Subject' refers to the active, cognising individual or social group, with consciousness and/or will, while 'object' refers to that on which the subject's cognitive or other activity observes. In the dialectical theory of knowledge, the important thing is to understand the subject and object as a unity and to see both the activity of the subject (which had been developed by idealism -- see Theses on Feuerbach No.1) and the independent existence of the world of which the subject is a part (which had been emphasised by materialism)." [Quoted from here; accessed 05/02/2017. Bold emphases and one link added; paragraphs merged.]

 

The background to this murky tale can be found in Beiser (1987, 2002, 2005, 2008); cf., also: Copleston (2003d, 2003f, 2003g), O'Hear (1999) and Pinkard (2002). On this, see also David Stove's article: 'Idealism: A Victorian Horror-Story, Parts I and II', in Stove (1991), pp.83-177. [However, in connection with Stove's overall work, readers should take note of the warning I have posted here.] In relation to the words "objective" and "subjective", see here and here. See also the path-breaking study, Daston and Galison (2007).

 

One unfortunate HCD critic of this site has fallen under its spell, too -- as has another, even more recently. See also here; many of the archived articles at that site were (originally) written by Raya Dunayevskaya, where it is abundantly clear that this Hermetic Creed now completely dominates what passes for 'theory'. The same can be said with equal force about Andy Blunden's homepage. [See also here. Several more examples of this HCD/LCD-affliction will be given in Essays Twelve and Fourteen (summaries here and here).]

 

The above article (from the Marxist Internet Archive) says that for Hegel the word "subject":

 

"...takes on the broader meaning, not restricted to the individual ego or person, but rather the self-conscious, self-legislating social actor which is both corporate and individual, including for example, states, families and individuals...." [Quoted from here; accessed 05/02/2017.]

 

Certainly, that might have been Hegel's intention, but he no more proved it to be the case than he proved anything else in the tangled mess he inflicted on his unfortunate readers. But, even if we were to assume Hegel was 100% correct about this, Lenin's theory of knowledge (in MEC, which based everything on 'images') undermines it completely. In that case, the 'knowing subject' of DM becomes the bourgeois individual again, and is left trapped in the solipsistic prison cell mentioned earlier, the 'object' of knowledge having now evaporated into thin air. [On this, see Essay Thirteen Part One. See also an analogous difficulty for Hegel analysed earlier (applied to his use of words like "Being"). How the points made there are relevant to the above remarks will be made fully explicit in Essay Twelve Part Six. On a failed attempt to argue that Lenin's later theory of knowledge (in PN) benefitted from, or was even improved by, his engagement with Hegel, see Appendix Three.]

 

[MEC = Materialism And Empirio-Criticism, i.e., Lenin (1972); PN = Philosophical Notebooks, i.e., Lenin (1961).]

 

[On this topic, see also Note 25 and Note 19.]

 

19. If the 'mind' knows only its own 'images', 'concepts', 'ideas', 'representations', and 'impressions' (etc.), then the 'outer world' can't fail to be the result of a back-reflection -- i.e., a projection -- of these 'contents' onto 'reality', howsoever they are re-packaged, spun or spruced up with complex 'theories of cognition' and 'objectivity'. When a theorist begins with the 'contents of the mind', there is no escape from this philosophical strait-jacket. Indeed, the 'world' that supposedly results from this projection isn't just a mere idea, it is the subject's own idea, and that applies to erstwhile materialists who fall for this aristocratic way of framing this 'problem'. In the end there is no, nor can there be, a real difference (just a 'rhetorical distinction') between the 'objective' and the 'subjective', given this way of conceiving of 'knowledge'.

 

Naturally, Empiricists might want to deny such implications, but if they are right, every single one of them will simply be arguing with him/herself, not me!

 

Others might object that this confuses Empiricism with Solipsism, but that isn't so. In fact, it goes much further; it identifies them. That isn't just to pick on Empiricists; one implication of the criticisms levelled at this site is that all metaphysical theories of knowledge collapse into some form of Solipsism -- that is, given what little sense can be made of them, in the first place.

 

That controversial claim will be defended in Parts Four and Six of this Essay (when they are published). See also, Note 20, below.

 

20. Of course, this means that this 'inverted', eviscerated, sophomoric version of Hegel's system (i.e., DM) is no less Ideal (upside down and 'the right way up').

 

Hegel was quite clear: Logic and the Divine Logos are one, Nature is Idea and Logos in self-development:

 

"Actuality is the unity, become immediate, of essence with existence, or of inward with outward. The utterance of the actual is the actual itself: so that in this utterance it remains just as essential, and only is essential, in so far as it is immediate external existence. We have ere this met Being and Existence as forms of the immediate. Being is, in general, unreflected immediacy and transition into another. Existence is immediate unity of being and reflection; hence appearance: it comes from the ground, and falls to the ground. In actuality this unity is explicitly put, and the two sides of the relation identified. Hence the actual is exempted from transition, and its externality is its energizing. In that energizing it is reflected into itself: its existence is only the manifestation of itself, not of another.

 

"Actuality and thought (or Idea) are often absurdly opposed. How commonly we hear people saying that, though no objection can be urged against the truth and correctness of a certain thought, there is nothing of the kind to be seen in actuality, or it cannot be actually carried out! People who use such language only prove that they have not properly apprehended the nature either of thought or of actuality. Thought in such a case is, on the one hand, the synonym for a subjective conception, plan, intention, or the like, just as actuality, on the other, is made synonymous with external and sensible existence. This is all very well in common life, where great laxity is allowed in the categories and the names given to them; and it may of course happen that, e.g., the plan, or so-called idea, say, of a certain method of taxation, is good and advisable in the abstract, but that nothing of the sort is found in so-called actuality, or could possibly be carried out under the given conditions. But when the abstract understanding gets hold of these categories and exaggerates the distinction they imply into a hard and fast line of contrast, when it tells us that in this actual world we must knock ideas out of our heads, it is necessary energetically to protest against these doctrines, alike in the name of science and of sound reason. For on the one hand Ideas are not confined to our heads merely, nor is the Idea, on the whole, so feeble as to leave the question of its actualisation or non-actualisation dependent on our will. The Idea is rather the absolutely active as well as actual. And on the other hand actuality is not so bad and irrational, as purblind or wrong-headed and muddle-brained would-be reformers imagine. So far is actuality, as distinguished from mere appearance, and primarily presenting a unity of inward and outward, from being in contrariety with reason, that it is rather thoroughly reasonable, and everything which is not reasonable must on that very ground cease to be held actual." [Hegel (1975), pp.200-01, §142; I have used the on-line version here, leaving the MIA links in. Minor typos corrected. (I have informed the editors over at the MIA.) Several paragraphs merged; bold emphases added.]

 

"The divine Idea is just this: to disclose itself, to posit this Other outside itself and to take it back again into itself, in order to be subjectivity and Spirit.... God therefore in determining Himself, remains equal to Himself; each of these moments is itself the whole Idea and must be posited as the divine totality. The different moments can be grasped under three different forms: the universal, the particular and the individual. First, the different moments remain preserved in the eternal unity of the Idea; this is the Logos, the eternal son of God as Philo conceived it.... The third form which concerns us here, the Idea in the mode of particularity, is Nature.... A rational consideration of Nature must consider how Nature is in its own self this process of becoming Spirit, of sublating its otherness -- and how the Idea is present in each grade or level of Nature itself...." [Hegel (2004), p.14, §247. Paragraphs merged. As far as can be ascertained, the material published at the MIA with this title is a different version of the same edition. Indeed, this is what the MIA has to say about it: "From 'Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences in Outline and Critical Writings', Edited by Ernst Behler, translated by Steven A Taubeneck from the Heidelberg text of 1817, published by Continuum, 1990. The more widely known translation by A V Miller (1970) -- (i.e., Hegel (2004) -- RL) -- is a translation of the late versions of Hegel's Encyclopedia with additions by Leopold von Hemming and K L Michelet." Bold emphasis added.]

 

[MIA = Marxist Internet Archive (link above).]

 

Moreover, Hegel explicitly connects this understanding of the relation between Logic and the world with theories originally spun by Ancient Greek (ruling-class) ideologues:

 

"This objective thinking then, is the content of pure science. Consequently, far from it being formal, far from it standing in need of a matter to constitute an actual and true cognition, it is its content alone which has absolute truth, or, if one still wanted to employ the word matter, it is the veritable matter -- but a matter which is not external to the form, since this matter is rather pure thought and hence the absolute form itself. Accordingly, logic is to be understood as the system of pure reason, as the realm of pure thought. This realm is truth as it is without veil and in its own absolute nature. It can therefore be said that this content is the exposition of God as he is in his eternal essence before the creation of nature and a finite mind. Anaxagoras is praised as the man who first declared that Nous, thought, is the principle of the world, that the essence of the world is to be defined as thought. In so doing he laid the foundation for an intellectual view of the universe, the pure form of which must be logic. What we are dealing with in logic is not a thinking about something which exists independently as a base for our thinking and apart from it, nor forms which are supposed to provide mere signs or distinguishing marks of truth; on the contrary, the necessary forms and self-consciousness of thought are the content and the ultimate truth itself." [Hegel (1999), pp.50-51, §53-54. Bold emphases alone added. Links added; paragraphs merged. See also Hegel's extended comments on Anaxagoras in Hegel (1995a), pp.319-49.]

 

So, just another "ruling idea".

 

Odd how they keep cropping up...

 

20a. On this, see Note 20, above. The entire topic will be covered in more detail in Essay Twelve Parts Two to Four, as well as Essay Fourteen Part One (summaries here and here).

 

21. The reader shouldn't conclude from these comments that Nominalism is the present author's preferred option, nor even that it is 'correct'. In fact, as the Introductory Essay pointed out, I reject all philosophical theories as incoherent non-sense, and that includes Nominalism. Why that is so was explained in detail in Essay Twelve Part One (summarised here).

 

22. And we now know why Lenin meant what he said when he wrote the following: "Dialectical idealism is closer to intelligent materialism than crude materialism...". The importation into Marxism of these ancient, well-entrenched "ruling ideas" significantly compromised his (otherwise) materialist good sense:

 

"The history of philosophy and the history of social science show with perfect clarity that there is nothing resembling 'sectarianism' in Marxism, in the sense of its being a hidebound, petrified doctrine, a doctrine which arose away from the high road of the development of world civilisation. On the contrary, the genius of Marx consists precisely in his having furnished answers to questions already raised by the foremost minds of mankind. His doctrine emerged as the direct and immediate continuation of the teachings of the greatest representatives of philosophy, political economy and socialism. The Marxist doctrine is omnipotent because it is true. It is comprehensive and harmonious, and provides men with an integral world outlook irreconcilable with any form of superstition, reaction, or defence of bourgeois oppression. It is the legitimate successor to the best that man produced in the nineteenth century, as represented by German philosophy, English political economy and French socialism." [Lenin, Three Sources and Component Parts of Marxism. Bold emphases alone added; paragraphs merged.]

 

How and why that happened with Lenin (indeed, as happens with all Dialectical Marxists) -- and what ideological imperatives they underpin, express, or promote -- are the subject of Essays Nine Parts One and Two, Twelve Parts Two and Three (summary here), and Fourteen Part Two.

 

23. The material that used to be here has now been moved to the main body of this Essay.

 

To be fair to John Rees, and as noted in Appendix Three, he does at least try to defend a 'DM-view of concepts' (i.e., those that aren't somehow 'fully material'); for example, in his brief 'analysis' of "friendship" (pp.109-10, of TAR). What he has to say will be examined in detail in Essay Twelve Part Four (when it is published in 2025).

 

24. The views of several of these will be examined in Essay Thirteen Part Two.

 

This was a call-back to Mark Antony's speech (at least as attributed to him by William Shakespeare):

 

"Friends, Romans, countrymen, lend me your ears; I come to bury Caesar, not to praise him." [Julius Caesar, Act 3, Scene 2.]

 

The material that used to be here has now been moved to the main body of this Essay. In addition, my criticism of Bertell Ollman's 'Theory of Abstraction', which also used to be here, has been re-located to Appendix One.

 

25. The following material takes up where Note 18a left off.

 

This seems to be the import of a passage from TAR, quoted earlier:

 

"[I]t is impossible simply to stare at the world as it immediately presents itself to our eyes and hope to understand it. To make sense of the world, we must bring to it a framework composed of elements of our past experience; what we have learned of others' experience, both in the present and in the past; and of our later reflections on and theories about this experience." [Rees (1998), p.63.]

 

As will be argued later, this is a rather odd way of making the point that knowledge isn't solely, or maybe even directly, derived from 'experience'.

 

While several of the comments in the main body of this Essay might suggest this latest objection centres on the recognitional powers or skills exhibited, for example, by trainee canine classifiers, it doesn't. As pointed out in Essay Six (and Note 6a, above), this particular metaphor trades on a confusion between two different uses of the verb "to know" introduced into Traditional Epistemology by Plato, which he then proceeded to merge into a single concept, 'knowledge' -- or, rather, he tried to explain 'knowledge-as-such' in terms of a relation between a 'pre-existing soul' and a Form, mediated (it seems) by sight or by acquaintance. Plato downgraded propositional knowledge (what we might now call empirical knowledge -- [EK]) and classified it as mere opinion or belief, not as 'knowledge itself'. EK was unstable, changeable, unreliable. He accepted Heraclitus's view of universal change in the physical universe and this affected his view of EK. The result was to identify knowledge with what has come to be known as "knowledge by acquaintance" [AK], but this was now acquaintance of a special sort, 'acquaintance with the Forms' (although there are Plato scholars who question this interpretation, and argue, with textual support, that Plato does acknowledge the validity some forms of EK -- for instance, Gail Fine, references below). Nevertheless, the long-term effect -- when the Forms themselves were later dropped by subsequent theorists -- was to merge AK and EK, so that AK became the prevailing paradigm. This paradigm, in one form or another, has come to dominate the last 2400 years of Traditional Epistemology. [Even if it wasn't always given that title!]

 

Hence, for much of subsequent Epistemology (and that includes theories developed by Dialectical Marxists), knowledge was interpreted in terms of a relation between an individual and an 'object', or an 'image'/'idea'/'concept'/'representation' -- on a one-to-one basis. I will say more about this in Part Six of Essay Three.

 

[On this, see Copleston (2003a), pp.142-206; Chappell (2019); Crombie (1963), pp.135-47; Fine (1978, 1990,); Frede (1992), Guthrie (1986), pp.249-77; Irwin (1999); Meinwald (1990, 1992), Miles (2003), pp.275-360; Rickless (2020); Scott (1995); and Silverman (2014). More will be said about this in Appendix Two of this Essay.

 

[See also Appendix B of Essay Eight Part Two, where I briefly deal with another important aspect of Plato's Epistemology, expressed in and by his 'Allegory of the Cave'.]

 

Knowledge of a friend or an acquaintance isn't the same as propositional knowledge. There is a clear difference between "NN knows that p" and "NM knows A" -- where "p" is a (conformable) propositional variable, and "A", "NN" and "NM" stand for Proper Names. "A" might also go proxy for a definite description, such as, "The F that is G", or "The F of the G" -- where "F" and "G" are noun phrases -- yielding, for example "The President of the United States".

 

However, Modern English doesn't have a pair of words that brings this distinction out very well, while French does: connaitre and savoir. "Acquaintance" is far too weak and misleading (even if that word is used in AK!). If NN knows NM, then they aren't just acquainted, even if this would still be an example of AK! So, knowledge by acquaintance -- AK -- isn't just acquaintance, it is a specific form of knowledge that goes beyond mere acquaintance, even if it is characterised by it. Hence, it is necessary for NN to be acquainted with NM for this to count as an example of AK, but it isn't sufficient. I will say more about what might turn mere acquaintance into AK in Essay Three Part Six. [I have omitted that material from this Essay since it isn't integral to points I want to make here.]

 

[I owe this general point to Peter Geach.]

 

[A "conformable" proposition would be one that makes sense in a relevant context. So with respect to: "NN knows that Paris is the capital of France", "Paris is the capital of France" makes sense (independently of its use in "NN knows that Paris is the capital of France"), so it is conformable. But, "NN knows that Julius Caesar lives between Marx and Saturn", where "Julius Caesar lives between Marx and Saturn" (sic) doesn't make sense independently of anything, so it isn't conformable. How we decide what is and what isn't conformable is far too involved a topic to enter into here; but, in most cases, a non-conformable expression will stand out like a sore thumb (as was the case with "NN knows that Julius Caesar lives between Marx and Saturn").]

 

Knowledge (connaitre) of one's friends, for instance, does involve recognitional capacities since it trades on an ability we are all supposed to possess: being able to identity (over time) specific individuals with whom we are acquainted as friends. Propositional knowledge (savoir) isn't a relation between the Knower and the Known, unless we regard a proposition -- or what it supposedly refers to (i.e., a fact or a state of affairs) -- as an object of some sort. In this specific case, that would perhaps be a set of ink marks on the page (or pixels on a screen). If that were so, it would express an alleged relation between the supposed Knower and that set of ink marks/pixels, which one presumes isn't what was meant by knowing something to be the case. When we know, for instance, that the Nile is longer than the Thames, we aren't adverting to a relationship we might have with a set of inscriptions -- or even certain sound waves propagated through the air --, nor yet with the rivers themselves.

 

This shows that we already distinguish between the relational (transitive) and the non-relational (intransitive) form of the verb "to know" -- "NN knows that p", being of the latter variety, and "NN knows MM", the former.

 

[These observations alone render obsolete large swathes of Ancient, Medieval and Contemporary Epistemology (much of which still plagues French 'Philosophy' -- a rather ironic twist of fate when we remember that French does have two verbs (connaitre and savoir) that distinguish between these two forms of knowledge! This isn't to suggest that the above are the only two forms of the verb "to know". Clearly there are many more (at least in English), several of which will be examined more closely in Essay Three Part Six.]

 

On the other hand, if these terms are conflated, generality will quietly exit through the back door, as we saw in Part One. The same comment applies if it were concluded that knowing that the Nile is longer than the Thames puts us in some sort of relation with one or other of these rivers.

 

In the second case, it confuses objects with states of affairs and what we might claim to know about them.

 

Moreover, if the successful use of general terms were based on recognitional capacities we should then have to postulate a second order ability to recognise when a particular was an example of the right type, as well as recognise which word correctly applied to either or both of them -- and so on, ad infinitem. But, that just re-introduces Aristotle's objection through the back door, since, at a stroke, it doubles the number of 'difficulties' with which we began. Furthermore, and once again, it would involve the use of the very thing that was supposed to be explained -- i.e., generality. In which case, reference would now have to be made to further mysterious, inner "mental acts" to buttress the public use of words, and so on. [On this, see Note 26.]

 

In relation to this topic in general, see Hacker (1987) and Geach (1957). Problems associated with naive accounts of language acquisition are examined in Cowie (1997, 2002) -- who has, to her credit (on pp.x-xi of her (2002)), highlighted the connection between Nativist Theories of language and reactionary, right-wing political and social nostrums that have become 'popular' of late in conservative and neo-fascist circles. [Although Chomsky most definitely can't be associated with such regressive moves, his theory of language certainly lends weight to them, and has been criticised on these and other lines in Essay Thirteen Part Three.]

 

26. That this is the correct approach can be seen from the fact that Traditional Philosophers themselves have to employ general words to account for general ideas, whatever else they later try to transform them into.

 

However, the 'abstractions' they attempt to define, or construct, are (supposedly) to be found in one or other of the following locations:

 

(i) A yet-to-be-identified region or 'module' of the 'mind'/brain in an as-yet-unspecified form (are they 'stored in the brain/CNS' neurologically, electrically, chemically, structurally, psychologically, or in some other way?) -- many of these alternatives  have already been considered and rejected in Essay Thirteen Part Three, Sections Five and Six;

 

(ii) An otherworldly ('heavenly'), 'Platonic Repository'/'Storage-Facility' (these days, this is the so-called 'Third Realm') -- this is what Bruce Aune calls a 'P-theory' [Aune (2002), pp.131-32]; or,

 

(iii) The actual objects from which they have supposedly been 'abstracted' -- where, presumably, they exist 'spread out' somehow, distributed or shared equally among their exemplars (actual and possible, existent and non-existent) in a thoroughly mysterious manner -- what Aune calls an 'A-theory'; when these are 'tropes', Aune calls this a 'T-theory' [Aune (2002), pp.131-32]. (On this 'possibility', readers are referred back to an earlier section of this Essay. I will return to consider this alternative in more detail in Essay Thirteen Part Two).

 

In the Rationalist Tradition, these 'abstractions'/'Ideas' are supposedly 'apprehended' by 'special acts of intellection' (also of a mysterious nature and provenance, an 'ability' possessed by a tiny minority of self-appointed 'theorists'), or by something perhaps more enigmatic still, 'intuition' -- or even by 'the light of reason' (which, once again, only a select few even among fast-talking philosophers seem able to access or activate).

 

Whichever of the above alternatives turns out to be the case (if any are!), 'abstract particulars' may only be accessed privately, and even then only by the individual abstractor who dreamt them up. Unlike objects and events in the natural and social world --, which are openly and publicly accessible to anyone involved in conversation, research, collective labour, or just sight-seeing --, abstract particulars are quintessentially private and unique to each 'mind'. In that case, not only is their nature and existence in principle un-checkable, they can't be compared with the 'abstractions' cognised by anyone else. No wonder then that even those who accept the validity and viability of abstractionism have so far failed to explain with any clarity, let alone plausibility, which of the above three alternatives is correct, nor have they produced a scrap of physical evidence in support of any preferred choice.

 

In this respect, traditional theorists aren't even close, as Peter Hacker notes:

 

"For two and a half millennia some of the best minds in European culture have wrestled with the problems of philosophy. If one were to ask what knowledge has been achieved throughout these twenty-five centuries, what theories have been established (on the model of well-confirmed theories in the natural sciences), what laws have been discovered (on the model of the laws of physics and chemistry), or where one can find the corpus of philosophical propositions known to be true, silence must surely ensue. For there is no body of philosophical knowledge. There are no well-established philosophical theories or laws. And there are no philosophical handbooks on the model of handbooks of dynamics or of biochemistry. To be sure, it is tempting for contemporary philosophers, convinced they are hot on the trail of the truths and theories which so long evaded the grasp of their forefathers, to claim that philosophy has only just struggled out of its early stage into maturity.... We can at long last expect a flood of new, startling and satisfying results -- tomorrow. One can blow the Last Trumpet once, not once a century. In the seventeenth century Descartes thought he had discovered the definitive method for attaining philosophical truths; in the eighteenth century Kant believed that he had set metaphysics upon the true path of a science; in the nineteenth century Hegel convinced himself that he had brought the history of thought to its culmination; and Russell, early in the twentieth century, claimed that he had at last found the correct scientific method in philosophy, which would assure the subject the kind of steady progress that is attained by the natural sciences. One may well harbour doubts about further millenarian promises." [Hacker (2001), pp.322-23. Paragraphs merged.]

 

Well, we have only been waiting for 2400 years, so it might be a little impatient of critics to expect a clear answer any day/year/century soon.

 

Independent of that, the situation is even worse for Marxists. That is because postulating the existence of 'abstractions' (or 'abstract ideas' and/or 'concepts') only succeeds in undermining the social nature of language and knowledge by suggesting that key linguistic skills, performances and activities are fundamentally private, socially-atomised and representational in nature.

 

It is worth recalling, too, that what had been advertised all along as an ontological and epistemological exercise (aimed at tracking down these elusive 'Universals', these 'abstractions'), now turns out to be little more than a quibble about the meaning of general nouns (and other targeted parts of speech), only surprisingly ineptly executed -- indeed, as Part One of this Essay amply demonstrated.

 

26a. In addition to what has already been covered (i.e., based on Hegel's work), additional 'dialectical background' can be accessed here -- and good luck trying to make sense of it!

 

[The material that used to be here has now been moved to the main body of this Essay.]

 

27. I have employed the rather stilted sentential prefixing clause (or, as it is generally known: 'sentence-forming operator'), "It is not the case that…", in order to avoid well-known scope ambiguities (this links to a PDF), which often result from an incautious use of the negative particle in certain propositional contexts.

 

28. R6 has also been left somewhat 'stylistically-challenged' to minimise the differences between the stated examples. The same applies to several other illustrative sentences employed in this part of the Essay.

 

R6: It is not the case that this stick is bent in water.

 

29. I have said much more about "contradiction" -- and the many failed attempts to explain what Hegel imagined he was trying to say with, and in relation to, that word -- in Essays Four, Five, Eight Parts One, Two, Three and Eleven Part One.

 

29a00. This comes from Part One:

 

What counts as a "legitimate substitution instance" depends on whether we are speaking about, (a) The interpretation of sentence schemas in a formal language or a formal system, or whether we are, (b) Trying to make sense of the sentential patterns we use in everyday speech. As far as (a) is concerned, the formal pattern will probably be expressed in the following way: "F(ξ,ζ)" -- where "F( , )" stands for a two-place, first level (formal) linguistic function or predicate variable. [Again, these technical terms are explained in Note 15a, link below.]

 

An interpretation in this sense amounts to the replacement of the above schematic letters/sentences -- i.e., predicate expressions, linguistic functions (follow the link for an explanation of that term), or gap markers, for example -- with terms defined by the formal rules of the system itself (or implied by the natural language concerned) in order to form an ordinary indicative sentence. So, for example, a formal system might allow for the substitution of singular terms for the two Greek letters above, which when translated into English might yield the following sentences, or "substitution instances":

 

Y1: "Mount Everest is higher than Mount McKinley."

 

[Yes, I am aware Mount McKinley is now called Denali!]

 

Here substituting "Mount Everest" for "ξ", "Mount McKinley" for "ζ", and "ξ is higher than ζ" for "F(ξ,ζ)".

 

[Again, an explanation for the peculiar order of the letters in F(ξ,ζ) is given in Note 15a, specifically, here.]

 

Or:

 

Y2: "Romeo loves Juliette."

 

Substituting "Romeo" for "ξ", "Juliette" for "ζ", and "ξ loves ζ" for "F(ξ,ζ)".

 

Y3: "The River Thames loves Paddington Bear."

 

Substituting "The River Thames" for "ξ", "Paddington Bear" for "ζ", and "ξ loves ζ" for "F(ξ,ζ)".

 

As will no doubt be appreciated, some substitution instances fail to yield sentences that make sense to English speakers. In which case, as far as Option (b) from earlier is concerned, acceptable substitution instances will depend on what is counted as a legitimate ordinary language interpretation of the schematic letters involved. Such restrictions might be waved to some extent, or even completely ignored, in a formal language. However, since English isn't a formal language (to state the obvious!), there are no formal rules to guide us with respect to the vernacular, although there are rules of thumb that can and do provide a rough guide. For example, in relation to "ξ loves ζ", acceptable substitutions would normally be limited to sentences formed by the use of the names of, or the names for, a human being. [On the distinction between a "name of" and a "name for", see here.] Largely because of that, the vast majority of English speakers (if not all of them) would recognise Y3 above as non-sensical and Y1 and Y2 as legitimate indicative sentences (even if the latter relates to two fictional characters).

 

For more details and an explanation of the use of Greek letters like these, readers are directed to Note 15a of Part One, where an explanation is also given why this method of analysis has much to recommend it, despite appearances to the contrary.

 

29a0. The alleged contradiction might emerge along something like the following lines (although it isn't being suggested that this is how the argument has ever actually been developed, or has been openly expressed, only how it might be):

 

C1: NN believes that p.

 

C2: Science has shown that not p.

 

C3: Therefore, not p.

 

C4: NN accepts the truth of C3.

 

C5: Therefore, NN believes both p and not p.

 

[Where "p" is a propositional variable, and "NN" is a Proper Name surrogate.]

 

Of course, it is now up to NN to adjust her beliefs, or otherwise (when the above variables have been interpreted).

 

However, C3 doesn't follow from C2, unless the following assumption is added:

 

C2a: Whatever science has shown to be the case is true.

 

Or something like that.

 

[Recall that "not p" (when disquoted -- i.e., when those quotation marks have been removed, and p has been interpreted) is just as capable of being true as any non-negated proposition is (when it too has been interpreted). For example: "The Thames is neither longer than, nor the same length as, the Nile" is just as true as, "The Nile is longer than the Thames", whatever rhetorical or stylistic differences there might be between them. (In order to save on needless repetition the caveat that an interpretation is required in all such cases will be omitted, but the reader should assume one is always required -- unless stated otherwise). How observation and experiment (but not beliefs) are capable of contradicting a given scientific theory will be examined in much more detail in Essay Thirteen Part Two.]

 

It is worth pointing out that the relation between a sentence that expresses a belief and one that expresses the latter's negation isn't at all straight-forward. Here are just a few instances that illustrate this:

 

B12: MM believes that p.

 

B13: MM does not believe that p.

 

B14: It is not the case that MM believes that p.

 

B15: MM believes that not p.

 

B16: MM disbelieves (that) p.

 

B17: MM has no belief either way that p or that not p.

 

[In many of the above, "that" will often be omitted in ordinary speech. Its presence there would make many of the above rather stilted. Several of the above would also be enunciated rather differently; for instance B17 would probably come out as "MM has expressed no belief either way about p or not p." And, when interpreted, B17, or its equivalent, would probably be articulated even more differently -- for example, as "Arthur Farfenickle hasn't expressed a belief either way about whether or not it is raining."]

 

While it looks like B12 and B13 contradict one another, that isn't at all clear since B13 itself might mean any one of B14-B17. In fact, only B14 is the unambiguous contradictory of  B12 (that is because it is the only one that always has an opposite truth-value to B12). B12 and B15, as they stand, are merely inconsistent since both could be false. That in turn would be so if or when B17 itself were the case -- i.e., if MM is indifferent toward the truth or the falsehood of B12 and B15 (i.e., if MM has no belief either way; in other words, MM would be one of the "don't knows" that make an appearance in opinion polls all the time). In that eventuality, B12 and B15 would both be false.

 

I will say no more about the logical connections between the above five sentences since that would take us too far afield -- and the logic of such sentences becomes impossibly complex alarmingly quickly! Anyone interested in diving into this extremely knotty topic might like to begin with Hintikka (2005), and then perhaps move on to the much more recent, Rendsvig, et al (2023).

 

29a. Admittedly, it could be argued that Hegel also appeared to believe this (i.e., that appearances were 'part of reality' -- although he would have refrained from calling them "real" -- on that, see Note 29b, below). In which case, it isn't too clear what the (alleged) contradiction here is supposed to be.

 

Alas, what little help we get from DM-fans when trying to make sense of this turns out to be about as useful and effective as a chocolate fire door.

 

Anyway, what Hegel had to say about 'appearances' is not only useless, it is as clear as mud (to vary the image). I have said more about that, here. [See also, the next Note.]

 

29b. As pointed out earlier, Novack argued as follows:

 

"Let us consider a few illustrations of this process, this contradiction between essence and appearance, resulting from the different forms assumed by matter in its motion. In the production of the plant, seed, bud, flower and fruit are all equally necessary phases or forms of its existence. Taken separately, each by itself, they are all equally real, equally necessary, equally rational phases of the plant's development. Yet each in turn becomes supplanted by the other and thereby becomes no less unnecessary and non-real. Each phase of the plant's manifestation appears as a reality and then is transformed in the course of development into an unreality or an appearance. This movement, triadic in this particular case, from unreality into reality and then back again to unreality, constitutes the essence, the inner movement behind all appearance. Appearance cannot be understood without an understanding of this process. It is this that determines whether any appearance in nature, society or in the mind is rational or non-rational." [Novack (1971), pp.86-87. Bold emphasis added; paragraphs merged.]

 

Why Novack thought it wise, or even sensible, to describe plants as "non-real" is far from clear, to say the least! If the flowers he was speaking about were plastic, were a decorative feature in the icing on a cake, were represented in a painting or were part of a sculpture, he might have had a point. Perhaps he meant the existence of such plants is only transient? Or that they can/will at some point perish? But, how that disqualifies them from being genuine plants (i.e., 'real') is still far from clear. Are 'real' plants supposed to be eternal beings?

 

However, Novack openly agrees with Hegel by regarding as 'not real', or not 'fully real', whatever it is that perishes, or can perish (a dogma typical of the Rationalist Tradition, as we saw earlier):

 

"We have already seen what great measure of truth there is in the proposition that the real is rational. We have ascertained that all things come into existence and endure in a lawful and necessary way. But this is not the whole and final truth about things. It is one-sided, relative, and a passing truth. The real truth about things is that they not only exist, persist, but they also develop and pass away. This passing away of things, eventuating in death, is expressed in logical terminology by the term 'negation.' The whole truth about things can be expressed only if we take into account this opposite and negative aspect. In other words, unless we introduce the negation of our first affirmation, we shall obtain only a superficial and abstract inspection of reality.

 

"All things are limited and changing. They not only force their way and are forced into existence and maintain themselves there. They also develop, disintegrate and are pushed out of existence and eventually disappear. In logical terms, they not only affirm themselves. They likewise negate themselves and are negated by other things. By coming into existence, they say: 'Yes! Here I am!' to reality and to thought engaged in understanding reality. By developing and eventually going out of existence, they say on the contrary: 'No, I no longer am; I cannot stay real.' If everything that comes into existence must pass out of existence, as all of reality pounds constantly into our brains, then every affirmation must inexorably express its negation in logical thought. Such a movement of things and of thought is called a dialectical movement.

 

'All things...meet their doom; and in saying so, we have a perception that Dialectic is the universal and irresistible power, before which nothing can stay, however secure and stable it may deem itself,' writes Hegel. (Shorter Logic, p.128.) [I.e., Hegel (1975), p.118, §81 -- RL.]

 

"There is a fable in The Arabian Nights about an Oriental monarch who, early in life, asked his wise men for the sum and substance of all learning, for the truth that would apply to everything at all times and under all conditions, a truth which would be as absolutely sovereign as he thought himself to be. Finally, over the king's deathbed, his wise men supplied the following answer: 'Oh, mighty king, this one truth will always apply to all things: "And this too shall pass away".' If justice prevailed, the king should have bequeathed a rich reward to his wise men, for they had disclosed to him the secret of the dialectic. This is the power, the omnipotence of the negative side of existence, which is forever emerging from, annihilating and transcending the affirmative aspect of things. This 'powerful unrest,' as Leibnitz (sic) called it, this quickening force and destructive action of life -- the negative -- is everywhere at work: in the movement of things, in the growth of living beings, in the transformations of substances, in the evolution of society, and in the human mind which reflects all these objective processes.

 

"From this dialectical essence of reality Hegel drew the conclusion that constitutes an indispensable part of his famous aphorism: All that is rational is real. But for Hegel all that is real is not without exception and qualification worthy of existence. 'Existence is in part mere appearance, and only in part reality.' (Introduction to the Shorter Logic, §6.)  [I.e., Hegel (1975), p.9, §6 -- RL.] Existence elementally and necessarily divides itself, and the investigating mind finds it to be so divided, into opposing aspects of appearance and essence. This disjunction between appearance and essence is no more mysterious than the disjunction between the inside and outside of an object." [Novack (1971), pp.84-86. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site. I have reproduced the edition of Hegel's work used by the editor of Novack's on-line text, Andy Blunden, not the version that appears here. Links added; several paragraphs merged.]

 

As should seem obvious (at least to atheists), this sort of language will only make sense to Theists. It is integral to the Platonic and Christian contempt for the material world (which I have elsewhere linked to the ruling elite, their fear and hatred of the 'great unwashed', the 'mob', those 'easily incited' by an itinerant 'rabble-rouser' -- the mythical 'external agitator' --, who collectively threaten their wealth and power, and which right-wingers readily and regularly connect with 'dark forces', 'the Devil', and, these days, you guessed it, 'the Jews').

 

But, when 'God' is taken out of the picture this 'dialectical fairy tale' falls apart faster than one of Donald Trump's policy proposals. That is partly because the distinction between what is and what isn't 'real' is entirely bogus when applied in the above, careless manner. [Again on this, see Austin (1964), pp.62-83.] As if the difference between a 'real' and a counterfeit dollar bill lies in the fact that the latter will perish while the former might not! Or, indeed, that there exists somewhere a 'real dollar bill' that will never perish and which forever stands in silent judgement on its inferior, this-worldly, material 'copy'. Anyone who thinks that a real Van Gogh (painting), for instance, will never fade or never require preservation or restoration, no matter what is done to it, whereas a fake van Gogh (i.e., one that can be described as "not a real van Gogh") will crumble to dust if left to its own devices, would be well advised never seek employment in the Art Industry. As if those charged with determining whether a certain painting is or isn't a real Vermeer, for example, will do so by hanging around for a couple of million years to see if it perishes!

 

 

Figure Twelve: 'The Potato Eaters' By Vincent Van Gogh -- Not The 'Real' Painting, Of Course,

Just A 'Perishable' Copy

 

 

Figure Thirteen: A "Real Vermeer"? According To Hegel

And His Latter Day Clones, Maybe Not...

 

I trust readers won't mind checking on the above Vermeer for, say, the next two hundred thousand years to see whether or not it perishes -- just so the above question can be answered one way or the other.

 

Update May 2024: The BBC has just reported that a newly discovered painting has now been authenticated as a genuine Caravaggio:

 

 

Figure Fourteen: Art Experts Say This Is A "Real Caravaggio", But Maverick Hegelians Insist On Waiting

A Few Million Years To See Whether Or Not It Disintegrates Before They Concur

 

Be this as it may, except for the use of overtly religious language, the above passage of Novack's isn't significantly different from the way that some of the Hindu faithful, for example, depict the 'god', Shiva:

 

"Shiva (Sanskrit: Auspicious One), or Siva, is one of the main Deities of Hinduism, worshipped as the paramount lord by the Saivite sects of India. Shiva is one of the most complex gods of India, embodying seemingly contradictory qualities. He is the destroyer and the restorer, the great ascetic and the symbol of sensuality, the benevolent herdsman of souls and the wrathful avenger." [Quoted from here. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"Shiva is 'shakti' or power, Shiva is the destroyer, the most powerful god of the Hindu pantheon and one of the godheads in the Hindu Trinity. Known by many names -- Mahadeva, Mahayogi, Pashupati, Nataraja, Bhairava, Vishwanath, Bhava, Bhole Nath -- Lord Shiva is perhaps the most complex of Hindu deities. Hindus recognize this by putting his shrine in the temple separate from those of other deities.... Shiva, in temples is usually found as a phallic symbol of the 'linga', which represents the energies necessary for life on both the microcosmic and the macrocosmic levels, that is, the world in which we live and the world which constitutes the whole of the universe. In a Shaivite temple, the 'linga' is placed in the centre underneath the spire, where it symbolizes the naval of the earth.... Shiva is believed to be at the core of the centrifugal force of the universe, because of his responsibility for death and destruction. Unlike the godhead Brahma, the Creator, or Vishnu, the Preserver, Shiva is the dissolving force in life. But Shiva dissolves in order to create, since death is the medium for rebirth into a new life. So the opposites of life and death and creation and destruction both reside in his character.... Since Shiva is regarded as a mighty destructive power, to numb his negative potentials he is fed with opium and is also termed as 'Bhole Shankar', one who is oblivious of the world. Therefore, on Maha Shivratri, the night of Shiva worship, devotees, especially the menfolk, prepare an intoxicating drink called 'Thandai' (made from cannabis, almonds, and milk) sing songs in praise of the Lord and dance to the rhythm of the drums." [Quoted from here. Spelling modified to conform with UK English. Bold emphases added. Links in the original; paragraphs merged.]

 

Might this not be called: "The Dance of the 'Hindu Dialectic'"?

 

Could it be that only those who 'understand' Hindu Dialectics will be able to answer that one?

 

[On this specific topic, see Solomon (1976).]

 

Shiva, is also supposed to be the "most powerful god"; compare that claim with the following:

 

"This is the power, the omnipotence of the negative side of existence, which is forever emerging from, annihilating and transcending the affirmative aspect of things." [Novack, op cit. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"According to Hegel, dialectics is the principle of all life…. [M]an has two qualities: first being alive, and secondly of also being mortal. But on closer examination it turns out that life itself bears in itself the germ of death, and that in general any phenomenon is contradictory, in the sense that it develops out of itself the elements which, sooner or later, will put an end to its existence and will transform it into its opposite. Everything flows, everything changes; and there is no force capable of holding back this constant flux, or arresting its eternal movement. There is no force capable of resisting the dialectics of phenomena…." [Plekhanov (1956), p.74. Bold emphases added.]

 

Or, indeed, compare it with Raya Dunayevskaya's entire book: "The Power of Negativity". [I.e., Dunayevskaya (2002).]

 

Similar thoughts can be found in other religions (e.g., Buddhism, Manichaeism, Zoroastrianism and Daoism).

 

Er..., once again..., what was it that someone once said about "The ideas of the ruling class..."?

 

Even so, the following question is still in want of a clear answer: Is it the "whole and final truth about things" that they pass away, or is that itself a "one-sided, relative, and...passing truth"?

 

If the latter is the case, we can ignore it (since it might not be true tomorrow). On the other hand, if it isn't the case, then some things are permanent (namely that specific truth, at least), and the above idea (i.e., 'the "whole and final truth about things" [is] that they pass away'), is false, which means we can ignore it.

 

Either way, we can ignore it.

 

Be this as it may once more, as we will see in Essays Seven Part One and Fourteen Part One (summary here), Novack's words express a mystical, perhaps even poetic, view of nature, one that openly confuses linguistic and logical categories with reality itself (i.e., it conflates talk about talk with talk about things, a tendency we have witnessed several times exhibited by DM-fans). It also represents a faint echo of the doctrine (which Hegel certainly accepted) that only 'God' is fully 'Real', since 'He' alone 'exists of necessity'. Everything else is contingent and depends on 'Him' for its own insecure, tenuous and transient grip on existence.

 

In connection with that, Novack omitted the following remarks from the above passage, and it isn't hard to see why:

 

"...we must presuppose intelligence enough to know, not only that God is actual, that He is the supreme actuality, that He alone is truly actual; but also, as regards the logical bearings of the question, that existence is in part mere appearance, and only in part actuality." [Hegel (1975), p.9, §6; bold emphasis added.]

 

The only question that should now be asked is: Why on earth has anyone on the revolutionary left adopted or appropriated even so much as one 'logical' or 'philosophical' idea from that Christian Mystic, Hegel? The above quasi-Christian piffle Novack saw fit to publish (never mind the rest of his seriously unhinged book) is surely all the proof anyone needs that Hegelianism seriously rots the brains of those who claim to be  radical.

 

But, to interrupt all this Hermetic Hilarity, it is worth reminding ourselves that Protons, for example, seem to have received an exemption certificate from all that perishing and passing away palaver, since they don't change -- or, if they do, they don't do so as a result of their 'internal contradictions'. As far as we know, they last forever, unless they are acted upon. Left alone they appear to be eternal beings. Photons are no less dialectically-uncooperative, since they are as changeless as Electrons. [There is much more on this, here.]

 

One Professor of theoretical physicist had this to say about such 'particles':

 

"The only known stable particles in nature are the electron (and anti-electron), the lightest of the three types of neutrinos (and its anti-particle), and the photon and (presumed) graviton (which are their own anti-particles). The presumed graviton, too, is stable. The other neutrinos, the proton, and many atomic nuclei (and their anti-particles.... I'm going to stop mentioning the anti-stuff, it goes without saying) are probably not stable but are very, very, very long-lived. Protons, for instance, are so long-lived that at most a minuscule fraction of them have decayed since the Big Bang, so for all practical purposes they are probably stable. The other rather long-lived particle is the neutron, which when on its own, outside an atomic nucleus, lives just 15 minutes or so. But neutrons inside many atomic nuclei can live far longer than the age of the universe; such nuclei provide them with a stable home. Finally, I should add that if dark matter is made from particles, then those particles, too, must be stable or very, very long-lived.

 

"Why are these particles stable? It turns out that our world imposes some rules on particle behaviour, ones not visible to us in the physics of waves and vibrations that we encounter in daily life, that prevent some particles from decaying, either rapidly or at all. The fundamental rules are 'conservation laws', statements that certain quantities in the universe never change in any physical process. (These quantities include energy, momentum, electric charge, and a few others.) There are also some approximate conservation laws, stating that certain quantities only change very rarely. Conservation laws do not appear from nowhere, imposed out of thin air by theorists; they are related to other properties of the world. For example, if the laws of nature do not change over time, then it follows (thanks to a theorem of the mathematician Emmy Noether) that energy is conserved. Meanwhile, the stability of the matter out of which we are made provides strong tests of these conservation laws, as we'll see.

 

"Combining these laws with the properties of particles leads to a set of simple rules that determine when particles simply cannot decay, or when they can at most decay very rarely. And these rules are (almost) entirely sufficient to explain the stability of the particles out of which we are made, and those that we interact with most often." [Matthew Strassler, quoted from here; accessed 19/02/2014. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at the site. Spelling adjusted to agree with UK English; several links added. Italic emphases in the original. The professor then proceeds to spell out those rules, which I have omitted.]

 

Here is an even more recent report, published in Nature Reviews Physics, dated January 8, 2021:

 

"Does the proton decay? The proton could decay into a positron and a pion and if so the predictions of some beyond standard model grand unified theories would be confirmed. Since the 1980s underground experiments have been looking for signs of such decay. No proton decay has yet been spotted, but one of the experiments, the Kamioka Nucleon Decay Experiment...detected neutrinos from the supernova SN1987a instead. Its successor, the Super-Kamiokande, set the best current lower-limit for proton lifetime: 1.6 x 1034 years. Some grand unified theories predict proton lifetimes up to around 1036 years so there is still room for surprises. Upcoming neutrino experiments also have proton decay measurements planned and are expected to push the limits on the proton lifetime. These measurements will take place at Deep Underground Neutrino Experiment (DUNE) currently under construction [at the] Jiangmen Underground Neutrino Observatory (JUNO) which is almost completed and Hyper-Kamiokande whose construction received the green light last year." [Quoted from here; accessed 09/08/2021. One link and bold emphasis added.]

 

[As of June 2024, the above is still the case: Proton decay has yet to be observed.]

 

So, it seems like several particles, and not just the Proton, have been issued with a 'Perishability Exemption Certificate' by mischievous 'Being'. Too bad Hegel perished long before scientists learned about such non-dialectical sub-atomic particles.

 

Be this as it may (a third time!), anyone familiar with the DM-literature will also know that the sort of flowery, quasi-religious language Novack inflicted on his readers goes down rather well with most believers (and that is even more so with characters drawn from the HCD-fraternity, where the use of such baroque terminology is de rigeur). This is still the case even though a distinctly offensive, Christian stench (with a minor chord whiff of Hinduism, or even Buddhism, wafting away in the background) permeates the entire genre, especially when 'Novackian' passages like the one above are viewed in all their mystical glory. As also seems to be the case with openly religious thinkers, such ornate language clearly provides its hapless victims some form of consolation.

 

And, of course, obscure language like this helps hide what is actually going on from 'bothersome scrutiny' by the 'uneducated', the 'un-philosophical', the 'undialectical', working class -- a handy device State Capitalist regimes fond, and still find, highly useful. Obscure, DM-jargon also serves other purposes, explored in Essay Nine Parts One and Two. -- especially here.]

 

[HCD = High Church Dialectics/Dialectician, depending on context; that term is explained here.]

 

[Again, on this in general see also David Stove's: 'Idealism: A Victorian Horror-Story, Parts I and II', in Stove (1991), pp.83-177. (However, in relation to Stove's work, readers should take note of the caveats I have posted here.)]

 

The bottom line is, of course, that DM-jargon (like Novack's) only makes sense if we are prepared to anthropomorphise 'reality' and thereby re-enchant nature. Novack's "Here I am" and "No I am not" inadvertently gives the game away, one feels. As far as I am aware, there's isn't a philosophical equivalent of the term, "Freudian Slip", but in this particular case, there should be. We can perhaps label it a 'Novackian Slip'.

 

Last but not least: we have yet to be told what the 'contradiction' here is actually supposed to be!

 

30. There is something distinctly odd about the idea that 'appearances' are even capable of 'contradicting' 'reality', the facts, or, indeed, anything at all. That is because, plainly, 'appearances' can't contradict anything unless both ('appearance' and 'reality') are expressed in indicative sentences -- or, perhaps, both motivate beliefs to that end (which are also expressed propositionally). Clearly, this isn't an insignificant detail to be brushed aside as 'bourgeois prejudice' (or blamed on 'excessive tenderness for the world', as Essay Eight Parts One, Two and Three have demonstrated). The reason is that this insistence re-focuses attention on the conflict that might or might not exist between contradictory beliefs, something we can get a handle on. But, in that regard and with respect to bent sticks, for instance, who actually believes sticks are bent in water? Perhaps even more to the point: which person of sound mind believes that sticks are both bent and not bent in water?

 

If that is the sort of confusion that scientific progress encourages us to abandon, it would be no great loss.

 

Despite that, none of this seems to have anything to do with the supposed 'contradiction' between appearance and reality, since those contradictions actually occur between beliefs expressed in language. Still less would it have anything to do with 'commonsense'.

 

It could be argued that sticks actually look both bent and not bent when partially immersed in water: the lower half in the liquid looks bent while the upper half doesn't. But not even that is a contradiction since what we now have here are two different propositions:

 

V1: The bottom half of this stick looks bent in water. [Where a pointing gesture makes it clear which stick and what part is meant.]

 

V2: The top half of this stick doesn't look bent in water. [Where a pointing gesture makes it clear that the same stick is meant, alongside which part.]

 

We would only have a contradiction here if either of these were the case:

 

V3: The bottom half of this stick looks and does not look bent in water, at the same time. [Where a pointing gesture makes it clear which stick and which part are meant.]

 

V4: The top half of this stick does and doesn't look bent in water, at the same time. [Where, again, a pointing gesture makes it clear that the same stick is intended and which part is meant.]

 

But they aren't, so we don't.

 

30a. Clearly, R10 can be interpreted in several different ways, each of which will affect its truth-value, and hence the logical connections it enjoys with the other two propositions (re-posted at the end of this Note):

 

R10: It isn't the case that the Sun rises each morning.

 

R10 would be false if this use of "rise" implied the Earth was stationary while the Sun orbits it (e.g., as this represented in the defunct Ptolemaic System). In that case, R10 could be used to reject the Copernican System that replaced it, which implies it is the Earth that rotates on its axis while it orbits the Sun. [I have in fact considered this specific possibility, alongside one or two others, in the main body of this Essay; for example, here.]

 

On the other hand, R10 be true if any of the following were the case (again, depending on how "rises" was understood):

 

(i) The Earth intermittently stopped rotating (for whatever reason), or even did so permanently;

 

(ii) The Earth and/or the Sun were destroyed (again, for whatever reason). In that case, it might prove difficult to explain how R10 would be a proposition, if it were implicit that R10 relates to the rise of the Sun above the Earth's horizon, and there were observers to witness it. In that case, if there were no Earth, no Sun and no observers, R10 would lose its truth-conditions; that is, it would lose its sense, making it truth-valueless; or,

 

(iii) An interpretation that is explored later in this Essay is taken into consideration, which concerns a change in the inertial frame, connected with the Equivalence Principle in Relativistic Physics.

 

["Sense", as it is used in (ii) above, is explained here.]

 

Alternatively, R10a would be true if "rises" were taken to mean that, while the Earth rotates on its axis once every 24 hours as it orbits the Sun, the angle between the geometric centre of the Sun and the Eastern horizon increases as the day wears on, going from in the morning to 180º at dusk (if we assume this happens on a cloudless day).

 

R10a: The Sun rises each morning.

 

There are other weird and wonderful scenarios (based on science fiction/fantasy) that might seem to make R10 (or even R10a) true, but they too would undermine its propositional status (for reasons explored in Essay Thirteen Part Three, here).

 

In the main body of this Essay I have discounted such considerations in so far as they impact on the truth-functional connections that exist, might exist, or even fail to exist, between the following three propositions:

 

R8: The Sun appears to rise each morning.

 

R9: It isn't the case that the Sun appears to rise each morning.

 

R10: It isn't the case that the Sun rises each morning.

 

If anyone wants to make a case for their 'defence' (i.e., that the aforementioned weird and wonderful scenarios should be taken into account when assessing the above connection, they should email me with their best shot).

 

31. Those who think this unlikely should follow the link in Note 32, below --  and then check out Note 30a, above.

 

32. The content of Note 32 has now been moved to the main body of this Essay, here.

 

33. The content of Note 33 has now been moved here.

 

33a. Here is that remark (my quoting it doesn't imply I agree with everything it says!):

 

"Third, we must distinguish between concepts, and statements or propositions. It is an important feature of any language that it is always possible to express the negation of any statement made within it. Thus, from the fact that a group of people, through sharing a language, share the concepts embodied in that language, it does not follow that they must also share the same set of beliefs. To have common concepts is not thereby to have common beliefs, since, for any statement made within a particular set of concepts, it is always possible to deny the truth of that statement. It is therefore misleading to talk of a set of beliefs as constituting a 'conceptual framework', since it may seem to follow, either that it is impossible to reject those beliefs without also rejecting the 'conceptual framework', or that people whose beliefs differ must therefore be operating within different 'conceptual frameworks'. There is thus an important sense in which concepts do not determine beliefs." [Keat and Urry (1982), pp.217-18. Bold emphases added.]

 

34. Anyway, and once more, the following two sentences are far too ambiguous even to be considered contradictory. Furthermore, in relation to R17 and R18, it is worth asking the following: "'Appears' to whom? And in what way? Indeed, what is the criterion of 'fairness' being applied here?"

 

R17: Capitalism appears to be fair.

 

R18: It isn't the case that Capitalism appears to be fair.

 

35. For the sake of argument (which was also the case here), I am assuming this reductio is valid (which it isn't!), and that R26 is a contradiction. But, even if, per impossible, this argument were valid, it would still be of no help to DM-fans. If contradictory pairs of propositions can both be true at once (or what they supposedly depict can coexist), R27 would be false, and R28 would no longer follow from R21-R27. Given DM, therefore, the argument would then be 'valid' just in case it wasn't!

 

[For reasons already given (but repeated in Note 37), I have ignored what seems to be a valid implication of some of the sentences comprising this argument -- which is that people (i.e., workers) can, and maybe often do, hold contradictory beliefs about Capitalism.]

 

For ease of reference, R21-R28 were as follows:

 

R21: Capitalism appears to be fair.

 

R22: That leads people (including workers) to think it is fair.

 

R23: Hence, Capitalism is fair. [Or, so they conclude.]

 

R24: But, revolutionary theory and practice convince others that Capitalism isn't fair.

 

R25: Therefore, Capitalism isn't fair. [Or, so they conclude.]

 

R26: Consequently, Capitalism is both fair and not fair.

 

R27: However, the contradiction in R26 implies that R23 can't be true (based on the truth of R25).

 

R28: Therefore, Capitalism isn't fair.

 

36. Naturally, the way this particular point has been developed in the main body of the Essay prejudices, or even biases, any conclusions that might be drawn from it. Anyway, it isn't faithful to the aim of the re-constructed argument (expressed in R21-R28, reproduced in Note 35, above). But, DM-texts are themselves the source of the 'problem'. As noted earlier, since it isn't possible to form a contradiction by conjoining a proposition that just expresses an appearance with one that expresses an actual fact of the matter (which isn't also an appearance), any attempt to do so will, not unsurprisingly, flounder. Moreover, and for the same reason, the options available to DM-theorists to extricate themselves from this dialectical mess offer little help (as I have shown elsewhere in this Essay). So, until DM-theorists clarify what they mean by much of what they say (at least on this topic), little more can be done to make sense of anything they have so far said.

 

37. The reasons for the presence -- or even for the formation -- of contradictory beliefs (in the 'minds' of the unwitting, the careless, or the inattentive) won't be entered into here since that would take us too far afield into areas covered by HM. However, several possible examples were covered in a little more detail, here.

 

38. It could be objected that this latest assertion contends that appearances are 'subjective' when it was argued earlier that they were 'objective'.

 

Again: which is it to be?

 

Of course, it is the philosophical use of words like "objective" and "subjective" to which exception is being taken. So, this part of the Essay is simply responding to the employment (by dialecticians) of hopelessly vague, possibly even hopelessly obscure, terms such as these. DM-supporters certainly seem to believe that appearances are subjective (or, at best, they might be thought inter-subjective), and it is that assumption which is being used in order to exert pressure on the rest of their theory. But, none of this implies I accept "subjective" and "objective" have a clear meaning when employed 'philosophically', or, indeed, 'dialectically'.

 

On the other hand -- to continue with this hopeless idiom for a little longer --, appearances are also 'objective' in that they are (presumably) part of the 'real world' (i.e., they don't belong to any other!). Even if propositions about appearances turn out to be totally mistaken, fictional or entirely made up, they would still exist as a brain state or process (i.e., on this view, not mine!), or they will have 'emerged' from some such state or process in the CNS (again, on this view, not mine!). Moreover, they will 'exist in each individual mind independently of every other mind', or so it would seem. But, if your thoughts are 'external' to my 'mind', and are 'external' to every other 'mind' on the planet, then, according to Lenin, they must be 'objective' -- that is, for everyone else, but maybe not for you!

 

"We ask, is a man given objective reality when he sees something red or feels something hard, etc., or not? This hoary philosophical query is confused by Mach. If you hold that it is not given, you, together with Mach, inevitably sink to subjectivism and agnosticism and deservedly fall into the embrace of the immanentists, i.e., the philosophical Menshikovs. If you hold that it is given, a philosophical concept is needed for this objective reality, and this concept has been worked out long, long ago. This concept is matter. Matter is a philosophical category denoting the objective reality which is given to man by his sensations, and which is copied, photographed and reflected by our sensations, while existing independently of them. Therefore, to say that such a concept can become 'antiquated' is childish talk, a senseless repetition of the arguments of fashionable reactionary philosophy. Could the struggle between materialism and idealism, the struggle between the tendencies or lines of Plato and Democritus in philosophy, the struggle between religion and science, the denial of objective truth and its assertion, the struggle between the adherents of supersensible knowledge and its adversaries have become antiquated during the two thousand years of the development of philosophy?...

 

"As the reader sees, all these arguments of the founders of empirio-criticism entirely and exclusively revolve around the old epistemological question of the relation of thinking to being, of sensation to the physical. It required the extreme naïveté of the Russian Machians to discern anything here that is even remotely related to 'recent science,' or 'recent positivism.' All the philosophers mentioned by us, some frankly, others guardedly, replace the fundamental philosophical line of materialism (from being to thinking, from matter to sensation) by the reverse line of idealism. Their denial of matter is the old answer to epistemological problems, which consists in denying the existence of an external, objective source of our sensations, of an objective reality corresponding to our sensations. On the other hand, the recognition of the philosophical line denied by the idealists and agnostics is expressed in the definitions: matter is that which, acting upon our sense-organs, produces sensation; matter is the objective reality given to us in sensation, and so forth....

 

"'Matter is disappearing' means that the limit within which we have hitherto known matter is vanishing and that our knowledge is penetrating deeper; properties of matter are likewise disappearing which formerly seemed absolute, immutable, and primary (impenetrability, inertia, mass, etc.) and which are now revealed to be relative and characteristic only of certain states of matter. For the sole 'property' of matter with whose recognition philosophical materialism is bound up is the property of being an objective reality, of existing outside our mind." [Lenin (1972), pp.144-45, 165, 311. Bold emphases alone added, quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

"To be a materialist is to acknowledge objective truth, which is revealed to us by our sense-organs. To acknowledge objective truth, i.e., truth not dependent upon man and mankind, is, in one way or another, to recognise absolute truth." [Ibid., p.148. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"Knowledge can be useful biologically, useful in human practice, useful for the preservation of life, for the preservation of the species, only when it reflects objective truth, truth which is independent of man." [Ibid., p.157. Bold emphasis added.]

 

So, if we were to accept what Lenin has to say about 'objectivity', then, in relation to the minds of everyone on the planet -- other than you, dear reader --, your thoughts are 'objective' for them, but, alas, not for you, since your thoughts are external to, and exist independently of, billions of other minds.

 

[I have said more about this seldom recognised, paradoxical implication of Lenin's theory, in Essay Thirteen Part One --, for example, here and here. Moreover, since Lenin's thoughts aren't independent of his mind, none of them can be 'objective' for him! And the same goes for every single DM-fan; none of their thoughts can be 'objective' for them, either. On this basis, Lenin's rather careless wording doesn't rule the following out: while NN's thoughts aren't 'objective' for NN -- because they aren't 'external' to her 'mind' --, they are for NM since they are 'external' to his 'mind'!]

 

39. Again, the circumstances which motivate members of different classes to draw true or false conclusions about the nature of Capitalist society won't be entered into at this site.

 

39a. But, even for Descartes, his 'self-certifying ideas' only seemed to him to be reliable. After all, he admitted he needed 'God' to ratify his "clear and distinct" ideas if they were to be declared 'indubitable'. He would hardly have said that if his ideas were 'self-certifying'.

 

"For since God has endowed each of us with some light of reason by which to distinguish truth from error, I could not have believed that I ought for a single moment to rest satisfied with the opinions of another, unless I had resolved to exercise my own judgment in examining these whenever I should be duly qualified for the task...." [Descartes (1997b), Part 3, p.88. Quoted from here; bold emphasis added.]

 

"For, in the first place even the principle which I have already taken as a rule, viz., that all the things which we clearly and distinctly conceive are true, is certain only because God is or exists and because he is a Perfect Being, and because all that we possess is derived from him: whence it follows that our ideas or notions, which to the extent of their clearness and distinctness are real, and proceed from God, must to that extent be true. Accordingly, whereas we not infrequently have ideas or notions in which some falsity is contained, this can only be the case with such as are to some extent confused and obscure, and in this proceed from nothing (participate of negation), that is, exist in us thus confused because we are not wholly perfect. And it is evident that it is not less repugnant that falsity or imperfection, in so far as it is imperfection, should proceed from God, than that truth or perfection should proceed from nothing. But if we did not know that all which we possess of real and true proceeds from a Perfect and Infinite Being, however clear and distinct our ideas might be, we should have no ground on that account for the assurance that they possessed the perfection of being true." [Ibid., Part 4, pp.95-96; quoted from here. Bold emphases added. (Both of these passages link to a translation that is different from the referenced version.)]

 

And yet, even to 'God', such ideas would still only be 'appearances'! Plainly, 'God' couldn't appeal to a superior 'Deity' to ratify 'His' ideas. Even if such 'appearances' coincided with their 'essence' (to use the jargon, once more), they would still be 'appearances', and those 'essences' would still only 'appear to be essences', just as all this 'coinciding' would only appear to be such (given this odd way of talking).

 

Of course, it could be argued that 'God's perfect nature' would guarantee that 'His' ideas shouldn't be classified as 'appearances'. But if the 'evil demon' Descartes invented could make him question all his ideas and beliefs, then why can't there be a 'Super Evil Demon' [SED] that screws with 'God's mind' in the same way? It would be no good anyone trying to argue that that is impossible with 'God' because of the distinct possibility that this SED has messed with their head to make them draw this and other false conclusions about 'God'!

 

Just as soon as we admit the existence of any 'god' we are in no position to deny the existence of SEDs. Once we go down that rabbit hole, where there are no established rules and, like Descartes, we are free to make stuff up as we go along, how can any such SED be ruled out? Each and every attempt to do so will just prompt the invention of a 'Mega SED' [MSED] that has screwed with their head, too...

 

Rinse and repeat...

 

[Compare this with what was argued in Essay Thirteen Part Three about the (ubiquitous) use of science fiction in Philosophy (especially in the Philosophy of Mind, theories about Personal Identity and the Philosophy of Time). There is a way out of this rabbit hole (should anyone be foolish enough to go down it), but it requires the use of the approach developed in Wittgenstein (1974b).]

 

40. As we have seen, and as we will see even more in other Essays published at this site, dialectical thoughts are far from self-certifying. In fact, many of them self-destruct with alarming ease, while the rest are based on one or more of the following seriously flawed factors:

 

(i) A series of egregious logical blunders;

 

(ii) A handful of superficial attempts at 'conceptual analysis';

 

(iii) Badly constructed, ill-considered 'thought experiments'; and,

 

(iv) Lorry loads of Mickey Mouse Science and Minnie Mouse Philosophy.

 

Admittedly, it is controversial to claim that thoughts are to be classified with appearances, but since these terms-of-art (as they feature in Metaphysics) are devoid of any clear meaning to begin with, its denial is devoid of sense, too. Either that or the claim itself is impossible to assess, and for the same reason. After all, the negation of non-sense is also non-sense.

 

[Follow the last link above for an explanation of the technical meaning of "non-sense" employed at this site. On the inappropriateness of depicting sensations and 'appearances' (etc.) in the traditional manner, see Hacker (1987).]

 

40a. As Wittgenstein noted, in that case what we would have here are yet more signs, and yet no sign can interpret itself or inform anyone how it is to be used. Any such instruction, certification or authentication (at some point) has to be performed by a human agent (or a device constructed/programmed by a human) -- and each has to be open to check if it is to count as such.

 

Peter Hacker is worth quoting in this regard:

 

"It is indeed true that a sign can be lifeless for one, as when one hears an alien tongue or sees an unknown script. But it is an illusion to suppose that what animates a sign is some immaterial thing, abstract object, mental image or hypothesised psychic entity that can be attached to it by a process of thinking. [Wittgenstein (1969), p.4: 'But if we had to name anything which is the life of the sign, we should have to say that it was its use.'] One can try to rid oneself of these nonsensical conceptions by simple manoeuvres. In the case of the idealist conception, imagine that we replace the mental accompaniment of a word, which allegedly gives the expression its 'life', by a physical correlate. For example, instead of accompanying the word 'red' with a mental image of red, one might carry around in one's pocket a small red card. So, on the idealist's model, whenever one uses or hears the word 'red', one can look at the card instead of conjuring up a visual image in thought. But will looking at a red slip of paper endow the word 'red' with life? The word plus sample is no more 'alive' than the word without the sample. For an object (a sample of red) does not have the use of the word laid up in it, and neither does the mental image. Neither the word and the sample nor the word and the mental pseudo-sample dictate the use of a word or guarantee understanding.... It seemed to Frege, Wittgenstein claimed, that no adding of inorganic signs, as it were, can make the proposition live, from which he concluded that [for Frege -- RL] 'What must be added is something immaterial, with properties different from all mere signs'. [Wittgenstein (1969), p.4.] He [Frege -- RL] did not see that such an object, a sense mysteriously grasped in thinking, as it were a picture in which all the rules are laid up, 'would itself be another sign, or a calculus to explain the written one to us'. [Wittgenstein (1974a), p.40.].... To understand a sign, i.e., for it to 'live' for one, is not to grasp something other than the sign; nor is it to accompany the sign with an inner parade of objects in thought. It is to grasp the use of the sign itself." [Hacker (1993), pp.167-68. Link and bold emphases alone added. Paragraphs merged. ]

 

There is an excellent account of this in Bloor (1997). A more profound (but ultimately flawed) analysis can be found in Kripke (1982) -- which is a modern classic --, with another intelligent approach developed in Williams (1999a). [This topic is covered in more detail in Essay Thirteen Part Three.]

 

Bloor's book is one of the best contributions to the debate over the nature of rule-following to have appeared in the last twenty-five or so years. Having said that, there are several serious weaknesses in his overall argument. They will be discussed in more detail a later Essay. [On this in general, see also Kusch (2006), which develops ideas not a million miles different from Bloor's and Kripke's. It is also worth pointing out that these authors mistakenly portray Wittgenstein as some sort of 'meaning sceptic', which he certainly wasn't. He would simply have pointed out that the word "meaning" has a use (in fact many). On that, see Essay Thirteen Part Three, and Malcolm (1986b). On Bloor's work, see Note 35 of Essay Twelve Part One. See also Hanna and Harrison (2004), Chapter Eight.]

 

41. Although TAR does add the following remark:

 

"[C]oncepts which arise from direct interaction with the world cannot be false." [Rees (1998), p.92.]

 

However, from the surrounding context it is unclear whether or not Rees fully agrees with those sentiments. If not, he was wise to demur. Clearly, concepts themselves can't be either true or false. It makes no sense at all to ask whether "….cat" (or even "cat") is true or false. Hegel thought otherwise, but that belief was itself based on a confusion between concepts, objects and propositions/indicative sentences, covered in Part One of this Essay (but in more detail in Essay Four Part One, here and here). I will return to this topic again in Part Three of this Essay, and once more, at greater length, in Essay Twelve Part Six.

 

42. In fact, this work is aimed at demonstrating that although DM appears (at least to its supporters) to be an excellent theory, in reality it is the exact opposite.

 

Another rather ironic 'dialectical' inversion, one feels.

 

There would, of course, be no point arguing for or against the truth of DM, or seeking to confirm any of it in practice, if 'dialectical thoughts' were self-certifying.

 

43. This word (i.e., "semblances") isn't being used here in the way Hegel seems to have understood  it. This is what the Glossary over at the Marxist Internet Archive [MIA] has to say about the Hegelian version of this term (and good luck to anyone trying to make sense of it!), quoted earlier:

 

"Illusory Being [or semblance] is a category of Hegel's philosophy denoting the sceptical moment when an object is first perceived. The Dialectic of Reflection is the dialectic of the essential and unessential. Illusory Being is the negative moment in this dialectic -- the unessential. Against the position of scepticism, Hegel says that it must be recognised that the unessential is Being's unessential, that is, the thing is expressed in the unessential as well as in the essential, only the unessential is not yet recognised for what it is." [Quoted from here; accessed 14/02/2017. Italic emphasis and link in the original. Here we see yet more fluent Martian from self-proclaimed Marxists! Is it any wonder workers ignore us in their hundreds of millions?]

 

44. That topic won't be addressed here for reasons outlined in Essay One.

 

References

 

Several of Marx and Engels's works listed below have been linked to the MIA, but since Lawrence & Wishart threatened legal action over copyright infringement many of these links no longer work.

 

However, all of their published works can now be accessed here.

 

Aaron, R. (1967), The Theory Of Universals (Oxford University Press, 2nd ed.).

 

Aczel, A. (2000), The Mystery Of The Aleph. Mathematics, The Kabbalah, And The Search For Infinity (Simon & Schuster).

 

Alexander, H. (1956) (ed.), The Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence (Manchester University Press).

 

Allaire, E. (1963), 'Bare Particulars', Philosophical Studies 14, pp.1-8; reprinted in Laurence and Macdonald (1998), pp.248-54, and Loux (2001), pp.114-20.

 

--------, (1985), 'Another Look At Bare Particulars', Philosophical Studies 16, pp.16-21; reprinted in Laurence and Macdonald (1998), pp.259-63.

 

Allen, R. (1960), 'Participation And Predication In Plato's Middle Dialogues', Philosophical Review 69, pp.147-64, reprinted in Allen (1965), pp.43-60, and Vlastos (1971), pp.167-83. [This links to a PDF.]

 

--------, (1965) (ed.), Studies In Plato's Metaphysics (Routledge).

 

Althusser, L. (2001), Lenin And Philosophy And Other Essays (Monthly Review Press). [This links to a PDF.]

 

Ambrose, A., and Lazerowitz, M. (1972) (eds.), Ludwig Wittgenstein: Philosophy And Language (George Allen & Unwin).

 

Anderson, P. (1979), Lineages Of The Absolutist State (Verso).

 

Aquila, R. (1973), 'Predication And Hegel's Metaphysics', Kant-Studien 64, pp.231-45; reprinted in Inwood (1985), pp.67-84. 

 

Arib, M., and Hesse, M. (1986), The Construction Of Reality (Cambridge University Press).

 

Aristotle, (1984a), The Complete Works Of Aristotle, Two Volumes, edited by J. Barnes (Princeton University Press).

 

--------, (1984b), Categories, in Aristotle (1984a), Volume One, pp.3-24.

 

Arnhart, L. (2001), 'Review of Plato's Democratic Entanglements. Athenian Politics And The Practice Of Philosophy, by Sara Monoson', American Political Science Review, 95, 2, pp 466-67.

 

Audi, R. (1999), The Cambridge Dictionary Of Philosophy (Cambridge University Press, 2nd ed.).

 

Aune, B. (1986), Metaphysics. The Elements (Blackwell).

 

--------, (2002), 'Universals And Predication', in Gale (2002), pp.131-50.

 

Austin, J. (1962), Sense And Sensibilia, edited by G. Warnock (Oxford University Press).

 

Ayer, A. (1971), 'Could Language Be Invented By A Robinson Crusoe?', reprinted in Jones (1971), pp.50-61.

 

Baake, K. (2003), Metaphor And Knowledge. The Challenges Of Writing Science (State University of New York Press).

 

Baraka, A. (2009), Home -- Social Essays (Akashic Books). [This is now published under Baraka's other name, LeRoi Jones.]

 

Baker, G., and Hacker, P. (1988), Wittgenstein: Rules, Grammar And Necessity, Volume 2 (Blackwell, 2nd ed.).

 

--------, (2005), Wittgenstein: Understanding And Meaning. Volume 1 Of An Analytic Commentary On The Philosophical Investigations. Part One: Essays (Blackwell, 2nd ed.).

 

Barrett, M. (1991), The Politics Of Truth. From Marx To Foucault (Stanford University Press).

 

Baz, A. (2012), When Words Are Called For. A Defense Of Ordinary Language Philosophy (Harvard University Press).

 

Beaney, M. (1996), Frege. Making Sense (Duckworth).

 

Becker, A. (2018), What Is Real? The Unfinished Quest For The Meaning Of Quantum Physics (John Murray).

 

Beiser, F. (1987), The Fate Of Reason. German Philosophy From Kant To Fichte (Harvard University Press).

 

--------, (2002), German Idealism. The Struggle Against Subjectivism, 1781-1801 (Harvard University Press).

 

--------, (2005), Hegel (Routledge).

 

--------, (2008) (ed.), Hegel And Nineteenth-Century Philosophy (Cambridge University Press).

 

Benjamin, A., Cantor, G., and Christie, J. (1987) (eds.), The Figural And The Literal (Manchester University Press).

 

Bennett, J. (2019) (ed.), Selected Correspondence Of Descartes (Early Modern Texts). [This links to a PDF.]

 

Bennett, M., and Hacker, P. (2008), History Of Cognitive Neuroscience (Blackwell).

 

--------,  (2022), Philosophical Foundations Of Neuroscience (Blackwell, 2nd ed.).

 

Ben-Yami, H. (2015), Descartes' Philosophical Revolution: A Re-Assessment (Palgrave Macmillan).

 

Benz, E. (1983), The Mystical Sources Of German Romantic Philosophy; Pittsburgh Theological Monographs (Pickwick Publications).

 

Berkeley, G. (1975a), Philosophical Works In One Volume (Everyman). [Links to Berkeley's on-line texts can be accessed here.]

 

--------, (1975b), A Treatise Concerning The Principles Of Human Knowledge, reprinted in Berkeley (1975a), pp.71-153.

 

--------, (2016), Three Dialogues Between Hylas And Philonous, edited by Michael B. Mathias (Routledge).

 

Bicchieri, C., and Alexander, J. (2006), (eds.), PSA 06 74, 5 (University of Chicago Press).

 

[PSA = Philosophy of Science Association; the PSA volumes comprise papers submitted to its biennial meeting.]

 

Bloor, D. (1997), Wittgenstein, Rules And Institutions (Routledge).

 

Bogen, J., and McGuire, J. (1985) (eds.), How Things Are. Studies In Predication And The History And Philosophy Of Science (Reidel).

 

Bolton, M. (2003), 'Universals, Essences, And Abstract Entities', in Garber and Ayers, (2003), pp.178-211.

 

Borkenau, F. (1987), 'The Sociology Of The Mechanistic World Picture', Science In Context 1, pp.109-27.

 

Born, M. (1965), Einstein's Theory Of Relativity (Dover, 2nd ed.).

 

Brock, W. (1992), The Fontana History Of Chemistry (Fontana).

 

Brown, T. (2003), Making Truth. Metaphor In Science (University of Illinois Press).

 

Burger, A., Cohen, H., and DeGrood, D. (1980) (eds.), Marxism, Science, And The Movement Of History (B. R. Gruner Publishing Co.).

 

Burtt, E. (1954), The Metaphysical Foundations Of Modern Physical Science (Doubleday, 2nd ed.). [This links to a PDF.]

 

Button, G., Coulter, J., Lee, J., and Sharrock, W. (1995), Computers, Minds And Conduct (Polity Press).

 

Callinicos, A. (1978), The Logic Of 'Capital', D.Phil. Thesis (Balliol College, Oxford University, July 1978; deposited at the Bodleian Library, 30-03-79).

 

Campbell, K. (1981), 'The Metaphysic Of Abstract Particulars', in French, Uehling and Wettstein (1981), pp.477-88; reprinted in Laurence and Macdonald (1998), pp.351-63. [This links to a PDF.]

 

--------, (1990), Abstract Particulars (Wiley-Blackwell).

 

Candlish, S, (2019), 'Private Language', Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta (Fall 2019 edition).

 

Cantor, G. (1987), 'Weighing Light: The Role Of Metaphor In 18th Century Optical Discourse', in Benjamin, et al (1987), pp.124-46.

 

Casullo, A. (1988), 'A Fourth Version Of The Bundle Theory', Philosophical Studies 54, pp.125-39; reprinted in Loux (2001), pp.134-48.

 

Caudwell, C. (1938a), Further Studies In A Dying Culture (Bodley Head).

 

--------, (1938b), 'Reality. A Study In Bourgeois Philosophy', in Caudwell (1938a).

 

Caygill, H. (1995), A Kant Dictionary (Blackwell).

 

Chappell, S. (2019), 'Plato On Knowledge In The Theaetetus', Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta (Spring 2024 edition).

 

Chappell, V. (1964). 'Particulars Re-Clothed', Philosophical Studies 15, pp.60-64; reprinted in Laurence and Macdonald (1998), pp.255-58.

 

Code, A. (1985), 'On The Origins Of Some Aristotelian Theses About Predication', in Bogen and McGuire (1985), pp.101-31.

 

Cohen, H. (1980), 'Countering The Revision Of Marxist-Leninist Philosophy', in Burger, Cohen and DeGrood (1980), pp.109-35.

 

Cohen, S. (1971), 'The Logic Of The Third Man', Philosophical Review 80, pp.448-75, reprinted in Fine (1999a), pp.275-97.

 

Cook, J. (1979), 'A Reappraisal Of Leibniz's Views On Space, Time And Motion', Philosophical Investigations 2, 2, pp.22-63.

 

--------, (1980), 'The Fate Of Ordinary Language Philosophy', Philosophical Investigations 3, 2, pp.1-72.

 

Collins, C. (1999), Language, Ideology And Social Consciousness: Developing A Sociohistorical Approach (Ashgate).

 

--------, (2000), 'Vygotsky On Language And Social Consciousness: Underpinning The Use Of Voloshinov In The Study Of Popular Protest', Historical Materialism 7, pp.41-69.

 

--------, (2003), 'Review Of Bodies Of Meaning: Studies On Language, Labor And Liberation, By David McNally', Historical Materialism 11, 2, pp.227-38.

 

--------, (2004), 'Marxism And Language: A Response To McNally', Historical Materialism 12, 2, pp.169-87.

 

Copleston, F. (2003a), A History Of Philosophy, Volume One: Greece And Rome (Continuum Books).

 

--------, (2003b), A History Of Philosophy, Volume Two: Medieval Philosophy (Continuum Books).

 

--------, (2003c), A History Of Philosophy, Volume Three: Late Medieval And Renaissance Philosophy (Continuum Books).

 

--------, (2003d), A History Of Philosophy, Volume Four: The Rationalists, Descartes To Leibniz (Continuum Books).

 

--------, (2003e), A History Of Philosophy, Volume Five: British Philosophy, Hobbes To Hume (Continuum Books).

 

--------, (2003f), A History Of Philosophy, Volume Six: The Enlightenment: Voltaire To Kant (Continuum Books).

 

--------, (2003g), A History Of Philosophy, Volume Seven: 18th and 19th Century German Philosophy (Continuum Books).

 

Cornford, F. (1997), Plato's Cosmology. The Timaeus Of Plato (Hackett Publishing Company).

 

Cornforth, F. (1963), Dialectical Materialism. An Introduction. Volume Three: The Theory Of Knowledge (Lawrence & Wishart, 3rd ed.).

 

--------, (1976), Materialism And The Dialectical Method (Lawrence & Wishart, 5th ed.). [A copy of the 1968 (4th) edition is available here.]

 

Cowie, F. (1997), 'The Logical Problem Of Language Acquisition', Synthèse 111, pp.17-51. [This links to a PDF.]

 

--------, (2002), What's Within. Nativism Reconsidered (Oxford University Press).

 

--------, (2008), 'Innateness And Language', Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta (Summer 2010 Edition).

 

Cowley, F. (1991), Metaphysical Delusion (Prometheus Books).

 

Crombie, A. (1970), Robert Grosseteste And The Origins Of Experimental Science 1100-1700 (Oxford University Press, Corrected Edition).

 

--------, (1979), Augustine To Galileo: Science In The Middle Ages; Science In The Later Middle Ages And Early Modern Times, Two Volumes in One (Heinemann, 3rd ed.).

 

Crombie, I. (1963), An Examination Of Plato's Doctrines. Volume Two: Plato On Knowledge And Reality (Routledge).

 

Crosland, M. (2006), The Language Of Science. From The Vernacular To The Technical (The Lutterworth Press).

 

Dancy, J. (1987), Berkeley. An Introduction (Blackwell).

 

Danziger, K. (1997), Naming The Mind. How Psychology Found Its Language (Sage Publications).

 

Daston, L. (1994), 'Baconian Facts, Academic Civility, And The Prehistory Of Objectivity', in Megill (1994), pp.37-63.

 

Daston, L., and Galison, P. (2007), Objectivity (Zone Books).

 

Dauben, J. (1979), Georg Cantor: His Mathematics And Philosophy Of The Infinite (Princeton University Press).

 

Desmond, W. (1989) (ed.), Hegel And His Critics. Philosophy In The Aftermath Of Hegel (State University of New York Press).

 

Descartes, R. (1991), Philosophical Writings Of Descartes, Volume Three: The Correspondence, translated by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, D. Murdoch, and A. Kenny (Cambridge University Press).

 

--------, (1997a), Descartes Key Philosophical Writings, translated by E. S. Haldane and G. T. R. Ross (Wordsworth Classics).

 

--------, (1997b), Discourse On The Method, in Descartes (1997a), pp.71-122. [This links to a different translation.]

 

--------, (1997c), Meditations On First Philosophy, in Descartes (1997a), pp.123-90. [This links to a different translation.]

 

De Ste. Croix, G. (1981), The Class Struggle In The Ancient Greek World (Duckworth).

 

Dietzgen, J. (1906), The Positive Outcome Of Philosophy (Charles Kerr).

 

Dillenberger, J. (1988), Protestant Thought And Natural Science (University of Notre Dame Press).

 

Dilman, I. (1984) (ed.), Philosophy And Life (Kluwer Academic Press).

 

DiSalle, R. (2020), 'Space And Time: Inertial Frames', Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta (Summer 2020 Edition).

 

Dodds, E. (1951), The Greeks And The Irrational (University of California Press).

 

Doherty, S. (2000), 'The Language Of Liberation', International Socialism 87, pp.151-64.

 

Dorr, C. (2008), 'There Are No Abstract Objects', in Hawthorne and Zimmerman, pp.32-63.

 

Downing, E, (2011), 'George Berkeley', Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta (Fall 2021 Edition).

 

Dulckeit, K. (1989), 'Hegel's Revenge On Russell: The "Is" Of Identity Versus The "Is" Of Predication', in Desmond (1989), pp.111-31.

 

Dummett, M. (1991), Frege. Philosophy Of Mathematics (Duckworth).

 

Dunayevskaya, R. (2002), The Power Of Negativity. Selected Writings On The Dialectic In Hegel And Marx (Lexington Books)

 

Dupré, J. (1993), The Disorder Of Things. Metaphysical Foundations Of The Disunity Of Science (Harvard University Press).

 

--------, (2002), Humans And Other Animals (Oxford University Press).

 

Eastman, M. (1926), Marx, Lenin And The Science Of Revolution (George Allen & Unwin).

 

Ebersole, F. (1967/2001), Things We Know (University of Oregon Press/2nd ed. Xlibris Corporation).

 

--------, (1979a/2002a), Meaning And Saying (Universities Press of America/2nd ed., Xlibris Corporation).

 

--------, (1979b/2002b), Language And Perception (Universities Press of America/2nd ed., Xlibris Corporation).

 

Eklund, M. (2024), 'Fictionalism', Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta (Spring 2024 Edition).

 

Engels, F. (1845), The Condition Of The Working-Class In England, in MECW Volume 4, pp.362-83 (Lawrence & Wishart).

 

--------, (1888), Ludwig Feuerbach And The End Of Classical German Philosophy, reprinted in Marx and Engels (1968), pp.584-622.

 

--------, (1891a), 'Letter To Conrad Schmidt', 01/11/1891, in Marx and Engels (2001), p.286.

 

--------, (1891b), The Origin Of Family, Private Property And State, in Marx and Engels (1968), pp.449-583.

 

--------, (1892), Socialism: Utopian And Scientific, reprinted in Marx and Engels (1968), pp.375-428. [This links to a PDF.]

 

--------, (1954), Dialectics Of Nature (Progress Publishers).

 

--------, (1976), Anti-Dühring (Foreign Languages Press).

 

Epstein, L. (1985), Relativity Visualized (Insight Press).

 

Everson, S. (1990) (ed.), Cambridge Companions To Ancient Thought. Volume One, Epistemology (Cambridge University Press).

 

Fahnestock, J. (2002), Rhetorical Figures In Science (Oxford University Press).

 

Ferrari, G. (2005), City And Soul In Plato's Republic (University of Chicago Press).

 

Feuerbach, L. (1957), The Essence Of Christianity, translated by George Eliot (Harper Torchbooks).

 

Feynman, R. (1992), The Character Of Physical Law (Penguin Books, New Edition).

 

Fine, G. (1978), 'Knowledge And Belief In Republic V', Archiv fur Geschicte der Philosophie 60, pp.121-39, reprinted in Fine (2003), pp.66-84.  

 

--------, (1990), 'Knowledge And Belief in Republic V-VII', in Everson (1990), pp.85-115, reprinted in Fine (2003), pp.85-116, and Fine (1999a), pp.215-46.

 

--------, (1999a) (ed.), Plato 1. Metaphysics And Epistemology (Oxford University Press).

 

--------, (1999b) (ed.), Plato 2. Ethics, Politics, Religion And The Soul (Oxford University Press).

 

--------, (2003), Plato On Knowledge And Forms (Oxford University Press).

 

Fodor, J. (2011), 'Fire The Press Secretary. Review Of Why Everyone (Else) Is A Hypocrite: Evolution And The Modular Mind By Robert Kurzban', London Review of Books 33, 9, 28/04/2011, pp.24-25.

 

Foster, L., and Swanson, J. (1970) (eds.), Experience And Theory (University of Massachusetts Press).

 

Foster, M. (1934), 'The Christian Doctrine Of Creation And The Rise Of Modern Natural Science', Mind 43, pp.446-68; reprinted in Russell (1973), pp.294-315.

 

Frank, P. (1950), Modern Science And Its Philosophy (Harvard University Press).

 

Frede, M. (1992), 'Plato's Sophist On False Statements', in Kraut (1992), pp.397-424.

 

Frege, G. (1979), Posthumous Writings, translated by Peter Long and Roger White (Blackwell).

 

--------, (1980), Translations From The Philosophical Writings Of Gottlob Frege, translated by Peter Geach and Max Black (Blackwell, 3rd ed.).

 

French, P., Uehling, T., and Wettstein, H. (1981) (eds.), Midwest Studies In Philosophy, 6 (University of Minnesota Press).

 

Freudenthal, G. (1986), Atom And Individual In The Age Of Newton (Kluwer Academic Press).

 

Gale, R. (2002) (ed.), The Blackwell Guide To Metaphysics (Blackwell).

 

Garber, D., and Ayers, M. (2002) (eds.), The Cambridge History Of Seventeenth Century Philosophy, Volume 1 (Cambridge University Press).

 

Geach, P. (1956), 'The Third Man Again', Philosophical Review 65, pp.72-83; reprinted in Allen (1965), pp.265-77.

 

--------, (1957), Mental Acts (Routledge).

 

--------, (1968), 'What Actually Exists', Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 42, Issue 1, 14 July 1968, pp.1-16, reprinted in Geach (1969), pp.65-74.

 

--------, (1969), God And The Soul (Routledge).

 

--------, (1972a), Logic Matters (Blackwell).

 

--------, (1972b), 'History Of The Corruptions Of Logic', in Geach (1972a), pp.44-61.

 

George, R., and Van Evra, J. (2006), 'The Rise Of Modern Logic', in Jacquette (2006), pp.35-48.

 

Glock, H-J. (1996), A Wittgenstein Dictionary (Blackwell).

 

--------, (2001) (ed.), Wittgenstein: A Critical Reader (Blackwell).

 

Goldstick, D. (1980), 'The Leninist Theory Of Perception', Dialogue 19, 1, pp.1-19. [Abstract here.]

 

Gollobin, I. (1986), Dialectical Materialism. Its Laws, Categories And Practice (Petras Press).

 

Goodman, N. (1970), 'Seven Strictures On Similarity', in Foster and Swanson (1970), pp.19-30, reprinted in Goodman (1972), pp.437-47.

 

--------, (1972), Problems And Projects (Bobbs-Merrill).

 

Gould, S. (1988), Time's Arrow, Time's Cycle. Myth And Metaphor In The Discovery Of Geological Time (Penguin Books).

 

Grant, E. (1996), The Foundations Of Modern Science In The Middle Ages (Cambridge University Press).

 

Griffiths, P. (2001), 'Genetic Information. A Metaphor In Search Of A Theory', Philosophy of Science 68, pp.394-412.

 

Gross, A. (1996), The Rhetoric Of Science (Harvard University Press).

 

Grossmann, H. (1987), 'The Social Foundations Of Mechanistic Philosophy And Manufacture', Science in Context 1, pp.129-80.

 

Guthrie, W. (1986), A History Of Greek Philosophy, Volume IV: Plato: The Man And His Dialogues (Cambridge University Press).

 

Guttenplan, S. (2005), Objects Of Metaphor (Oxford University Press).

 

Guyer, P. (1992a) (ed.), The Cambridge Companion To Kant (Cambridge University Press).

 

--------, (1992b), 'The Transcendental Deduction Of The Categories', in Guyer (1992a), pp.123-60.

 

Hacker, P. (1982a), 'Events And Objects In Space And Time', Mind 91, pp.1-19.

 

--------, (1982b), 'Events, Ontology And Grammar', Philosophy 57, pp.477-86.

 

--------, (1987), Appearance And Reality (Blackwell).

 

--------, (1993), Wittgenstein. Meaning And Mind, Volume 3 Part 1 (Blackwell, 2nd ed.).

 

--------, (1996), Wittgenstein's Place In Twentieth Century Analytic Philosophy (Blackwell).

 

--------, (1997), Insight And Illusion. Themes In The Philosophy Of Wittgenstein (Thoemmes Press, 2nd ed.).

 

--------, (2001), 'Philosophy', in Glock (2001), pp.322-47.

 

--------, (2007), Human Nature, The Categorial Framework (Blackwell).

 

Hacking, I. (1975), Why Does Language Matter To Philosophy? (Cambridge University Press).

 

Hadden, R. (1994), On The Shoulders Of Merchants (State University of New York Press).

 

Hale, B., and Wright, C. (1999) (eds.), A Companion To The Philosophy Of Language (Blackwell).

 

Hallett, G. (1984), Logic For The Labyrinth (Universities Press of America).

 

--------, (1988), Language And Truth (Yale University Press).

 

--------, (1991), Essentialism: A Wittgensteinian Critique (State University of New York Press).

 

--------, (2008), Linguistic Philosophy. The Central Story (State University of New York Press).

 

Hanfling, O. (1984), 'Scientific Realism And Ordinary Language', Philosophical Investigations 7, pp.187-205.

 

--------, (1989), Wittgenstein's Later Philosophy (Macmillan).

 

--------, (2000), Philosophy And Ordinary Language (Routledge).

 

--------, (2001), 'Thinking', in Glock (2001), pp.138-55, reprinted in Hanfling (2002), pp.133-48.

 

--------, (2002), Wittgenstein And The Human Form Of Life (Routledge).

 

Hanna, P., and Harrison, B. (2004), Word And World. Practice And The Foundations Of Language (Cambridge University Press).

 

Hannam, J. (2009), God's Philosophers. How The Medieval World Laid The Foundations Of Modern Science (Icon Books).

 

Hallett, G. (1991), Essentialism. A Wittgensteinian Critique (SUNY Press).

 

Harrington, A. (1996), Reenchanted Science: Holism In German Culture From Wilhelm II To Hitler (Princeton University Press).

 

Hawthorne, J., and Zimmerman, D. (2008) (eds.), Contemporary Debates In Metaphysics (Blackwell).

 

Hegel, G. (1920), The Philosophy Of Fine Art, translated by F. Osmaston (Bell & Sons).

 

--------, (1975), Logic, translated by William Wallace (Oxford University Press, 3rd ed.).

 

--------, (1977), Phenomenology Of Spirit, translated by A. V. Miller (Oxford University Press).

 

--------, (1995a), Lectures On The History Of Philosophy: Volume 1, Greek Philosophy To Plato, translated by E. S. Haldane (University of Nebraska Press).

 

--------, (1995b), Lectures On The History Of Philosophy: Volume 2, Plato And The Platonists, translated by E. S. Haldane and F. H. Simson (University of Nebraska Press).

 

--------, (1999), Science Of Logic, translated by A. V. Miller (Humanity Books).

 

--------, (2004), Philosophy Of Nature, translated by A. V. Miller (Oxford University Press). [The version published at the Marxist Internet Archive appears to be a different edition of this work.]

 

--------, (2005), Philosophy Of Right, translated by S. W. Dyde (Dover Publications).

 

--------, (2018), Phenomenology Of Spirit, translated by T. Pinkard (Cambridge University Press). [This links to a PDF.]

 

Hendrix, J. (2019), 'Philosophy Of Perception In Hegel'. [This links to a PDF.]

 

Hesse, M. (1966), Models And Analogies In Science (University of Notre Dame Press).

 

Hintikka, J. (2005), Knowledge And Belief: An Introduction To The Logic Of The Two Notions, edited by V. Hendriks and J. Symons (London College Publications, 2nd ed.).

 

Hirsch, R. (2004), 'Logic And Dialectics', Cultural Logic 7.

 

Holborow, M. (1999), The Politics Of English (Sage Publications).

 

Hossenfelder, S. (2018), Lost In Math. How Beauty Leads Physics Astray (Basic Books).

 

Hume, D. (1955), Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding (Bobbs-Merrill).

 

Hooykaas, R. (1973), Religion And The Rise Of Modern Science (Scottish Academic Press).

 

Hoyle, F. (1973), Nicolaus Copernicus. An Essay On His Life And Work (Heinemann).

 

--------, (1975), Astronomy And Cosmology. A Modern Course (W H Freeman).

 

Ilyenkov, E. (1979), 'The Problem Of Contradiction In Logic', in Kedrov (1979), pp.122-43. [Partially quoted from here.]

 

Inwood, M. (1985) (ed.), Oxford Readings In Philosophy: Hegel (Oxford University Press).

 

--------, (1992), A Hegel Dictionary (Blackwell).

 

--------, (2002), Hegel (Routledge).

 

Irwin, T. (1999), 'The Theory Of Forms', in Fine (1999a), pp.143-70.

 

Jackson, T. (1936), Dialectics (Lawrence & Wishart). [This links to a PDF.]

 

Jacquette, D. (2006) (ed.), A Companion To Philosophical Logic (Blackwell).

 

James, J. (1995), The Music Of The Spheres. Music, Science And The Natural Order Of The Universe (Abacus Books).

 

James, W. (1978), The Works Of William James (Harvard University Press).

 

Jesseph, D. (1993), Berkeley's Philosophy Of Mathematics (University of Chicago Press).

 

Jones, O. (1971) (ed.), The Private Language Argument (St., Martin's Press).

 

Kabeshkin, A. (2022), 'Hegel's Metaphysics Of Nature', European Journal of Philosophy 30, 2, June 2022, pp.778-92. [This links to a PDF.]

 

Kant, I. (1953), Prolegomena To Any Future Metaphysics That Will Be Able To Present Itself As A Science (Manchester University Press). [This links to a PDF.]

 

--------, (1998), Critique Of Pure Reason (Cambridge University Press).

 

Kaye, J. (1998), Economy And Nature In The Fourteenth Century. Money, Market Exchange, And The Emergence Of Scientific Thought (Cambridge University Press).

 

Keat, R. and Urry, J. (1982), Social Theory As Science (Routledge, 2nd ed.).

 

Kedrov, B. (1979) (ed.), Dialekticheskoe Protovorochie (Dialectical Contradiction) (Politizdat).

 

Keller, E. (1995), Refiguring Life. Metaphors Of Twentieth-Century Biology (Columbia University Press).

 

--------, (2002), Making Sense Of Life. Explaining Biological Development With Models, Metaphors, And Machines (Harvard University Press).

 

Kennick, W. (1972), 'Philosophy As Grammar And The Reality Of Universals', in Ambrose and Lazerowitz (1972), pp.140-85.

 

Kenny, A. (1963), Action, Emotion And Will (Routledge).

 

--------, (1969), 'Mental Health In Plato's Republic', Proceedings of the British Academy 55, pp.229-53; reprinted in Kenny (1973b), pp.1-27.

 

--------, (1975), Will, Freedom And Power (Blackwell).

 

--------, (1973a), Wittgenstein (Penguin Books).

 

--------, (1973b), The Anatomy Of The Soul. Historical Essays In The Philosophy Of Mind (Blackwell).

 

--------, (1984a), The Legacy Of Wittgenstein (Blackwell).

 

--------, (1984b), 'The Homunculus Fallacy', in Kenny (1984a), pp.125-36. [This links to a PDF.]

 

--------, (1992), The Metaphysics Of Mind (Oxford University Press).

 

--------, (2006), A New History Of Western Philosophy, Volume Three: The Rise Of Modern Philosophy (Oxford University Press).

 

Kirk, G., Raven, J., and Schofield, M. (1999), The Presocratic Philosophers (Cambridge University Press, 2nd ed.).

 

Koestler, A. (2017), The Sleepwalkers. A History Of Man's Changing Vision Of The Universe (Penguin Books). [Part of this book is available here (this links to a PDF).]

 

Konstantinov, F., et al (1974), The Fundamentals Of Marxist-Leninist Philosophy (Progress Publishers, 2nd ed.).

 

Krapivin, V. (1985), What Is Dialectical Materialism? (Progress Publishers).

 

Kraut, R. (1992) (ed.), The Cambridge Companion To Plato (Cambridge University Press).

 

Kretzmann, N., Kenny, A., and Pinborg, J. (1988) (eds.), The Cambridge History Of Later Medieval Philosophy (Cambridge University Press).

 

Kripke, S. (1982), Wittgenstein On Rules And Private Language (Blackwell).

 

Kuhn, T. (1993), 'Metaphor In Science', in Ortony (1993), pp.533-42, and Kuhn (2000), pp.196-207.

 

--------, (1995), The Copernican Revolution (Harvard University Press, corrected edition). [This links to a PDF.]

 

--------, (2000), The Road Since Structure. Philosophical Essays, 1970-1993, With An Autobiographical Interview, edited by James Conant and John Haugeland (University of Chicago Press).

 

Kusch, M. (2006), A Sceptical Guide To Meaning And Rules. Defending Kripke's Wittgenstein (Acumen).

 

Laurence, S., and Macdonald, C. (1998) (eds.), Contemporary Readings In The Foundations Of Metaphysics (Blackwell).

 

Laurence, S., and Margolis, E. (2012), 'Abstraction And The Origin Of General Ideas', Philosophers' Imprint 12, 19, pp.1-22.

 

Leatherdale, W. (1974), The Role Of Analogy, Model, And Metaphor In Science (North Holland Publishing).

 

Lecercle, J-J. (2006), A Marxist Philosophy Of Language, translated by Gregory Elliott (Brill).

 

Lecercle, J-J., and Riley, D. (2004), The Force Of Language (Palgrave).

 

Ledwith, S. (2023), 'The Revolutionary Spirit Of The Buddha' (Counterfire).

 

Lee, E., Mourelatos, A., and Rorty, R. (eds.), Exegesis And Argument (Van Gorcum & Co.).

 

Lenin, V. (1921), 'Once Again On The Trade Unions, The Current Situation And The Mistakes Of Comrades Trotsky And Bukharin', reprinted in Lenin (1980), pp.70-106.

 

--------, (1947), What Is To Be Done? (Progress Publishers).

 

--------, (1961), Philosophical Notebooks, Collected Works Volume 38 (Progress Publishers).

 

--------, (1962), Materialism And Empirio-Criticism, Collected Works Volume 14 (Progress Publishers). [This links to a PDF.]

 

--------, (1972), Materialism And Empirio-Criticism (Foreign Languages Press).

 

--------, (1980), On The Question Of Dialectics (Progress Publishers).

 

Lenoir, T. (1982), The Strategy Of Life. Teleology And Mechanics In Nineteenth-Century Biology (University of Chicago Press).

 

Lepore, E., and Smith, B. (2008) (eds.), The Oxford Handbook Of Philosophy Of Language (Oxford University Press).

 

Levins, R., and Lewontin, R. (1985), The Dialectical Biologist (Harvard University Press).

 

Lifton, R. (1989), Thought Reform And The Psychology Of Totalism (University of North Carolina Press).

 

--------, (2019), Losing Reality. On Cults, Cultism, And The Mindset Of Political And Religious Zealotry (The New Press).

 

Lindberg, D. (2007), The Beginnings Of Western Science. The European Scientific Tradition In Philosophical, Religious, And Institutional Context, 600 BC To AD 1450 (University of Chicago Press, 2nd ed.).

 

Locke, J. (1975), An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, edited by P. H. Nidditch (Oxford University Press). [This links to a PDF, but a different edition to the one cited.]

 

Long, P. (1969), 'Are Predicates And Relational Expressions Complete?', Philosophical Review 78, pp.90-98.

 

--------, (1976), 'On Expressing Functions And Properties', Analysis 36, pp.118-25.

 

--------, (1982), 'Formal Relations', Philosophical Quarterly 32, pp.151-61; reprinted in Long (2001), pp.79-91.

 

--------, (1984), 'Universals: Logic And Metaphor', in Dilman (1984), pp.271-89; reprinted in Long (2001), pp.93-106.

 

--------, (2001), Logic, Form And Grammar (Routledge).

 

Losee, J. (2001), A Historical Introduction To The Philosophy Of Science (Oxford University Press, 4th ed.).

 

Loux, M. (2001) (ed.), Metaphysics: Contemporary Readings (Routledge).

 

Lovejoy, A. (1964), The Great Chain Of Being (Harvard University Press). [This links to a PDF.]

 

Lowe, E. (1989), Kinds Of Being: A Study Of Individuation, Identity And The Logic Of Sortal Terms (Blackwell).

 

--------, (1995), Locke On Human Understanding (Routledge).

 

--------, (1999), 'Objects And Criteria Of Identity', in Hale and Wright (1999), pp.613-33.

 

--------, (2015), More Kinds Of Being. A Further Study Of Individuation, Identity And The Logic Of Sortal Terms (Wiley-Blackwell).

 

Lukács, G. (1971), History And Class Consciousness. Studies In Marxist Dialectics (Merlin Press).

 

Lynch, M. (1993), Scientific Practice And Ordinary Action (Cambridge University Press).

 

MacBride, F. (2008), 'Predicate Reference', in Lepore and Smith (2008), pp.422-75.

 

MacCormac, E. (1976), Metaphor And Myth In Science And Religion (Duke University Press).

 

Macdonald, M. (1938), 'Things And Processes', Analysis 3, reprinted in Macdonald (1954), pp.287-96.

 

--------, (1954) (ed.), Philosophy And Analysis (Oxford University Press).

 

MacPherson, C. (1964), The Political Theory Of Possessive Individualism (Oxford University Press).

 

Magee, G. (2008), Hegel And The Hermetic Tradition (Cornell University Press). [The introduction to this book can be accessed here.]

 

Malcolm, N. (1986a), Wittgenstein: Nothing Is Hidden (Blackwell).

 

--------, (1986b), 'Following A Rule', in Malcolm (1986a), pp.154-81.

 

Mandel, E. (1976), 'Introduction' To Marx (1976), pp.11-86. [This links to a PDF.]

 

Mandelbaum, E. (2020), 'Associationist Theories Of Thought', Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta (Fall 2020 Edition).

 

Mao Tse-Tung, (1937), 'On Contradiction', in Mao (1964a), pp.311-47.

 

--------, (1964a), Selected Works Volume 1 (Foreign Languages Press).

 

--------, (1964b), 'Speeches At The National Conference Of The Communist Party Of China', in Mao (1964c), pp.154-71.

 

--------, (1964c), Selected Works Volume 5 (Foreign Languages Press).

 

Marcuse, H. (1968), One Dimensional Man (Abacus Books).

 

--------, (1973), Reason And Revolution (Routledge).

 

Markie, P. (2021), 'Rationalism Vs Empiricism', Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta (Spring 2023 Edition).

 

Marquit, E. (1990), 'A Materialist Critique Of Hegel's Concept Of Identity Of Opposites', Science & Society 54, 2, pp.147-66.

 

Marx, K. (1968), Preface To A Contribution To The Critique Of Political Economy, in Marx and Engels (1968a), pp.180-84.

 

--------, (1973), Grundrisse (Penguin Books).

 

--------, (1975a), Marx & Engels Collected Work (MECW) Volume 1 (Lawrence & Wishart).

 

--------, (1975b), The Difference Between The Democritean And Epicurean Philosophy Of Nature, in Marx (1975a), pp.25-106.

 

--------, (1975c), Early Writings (Penguin Books).

 

--------, (1975d), A Contribution To The Critique Of Hegel's Philosophy Of Right, in Marx (1975c), pp.243-57.

 

--------, (1975e), Economical And Philosophical Manuscripts, in Marx (1975c), pp.279-400.

 

--------, (1976), Capital, Volume 1 (Penguin Books).

 

--------, (1978), The Poverty Of Philosophy (Foreign Languages Press).

 

--------, (1981), Capital, Volume 3 (Penguin Books).

 

--------, (1986), Economic Manuscripts Of 1857-58, MECW Volume 28 (Lawrence & Wishart). [This is The Grundrisse.]

 

--------, (1996), Capital, Volume 1, MECW Volume 35 (Lawrence & Wishart).

 

--------, (1998), Capital, Volume 3, MECW Volume 37 (Lawrence & Wishart).

 

Marx, K., and Engels, F. (1968a), Selected Works In One Volume (Lawrence & Wishart).

 

--------, (1968b), Manifesto Of The Communist Party, in Marx and Engels (1968a), pp.31-63.

 

--------, (1970), The German Ideology, Students Edition, edited by Chris Arthur (Lawrence & Wishart).

 

--------, (1975a), The Holy Family, MECW Volume 4, pp.3-211 (Lawrence & Wishart).

 

--------, (1975b), Selected Correspondence (Progress Publishers, 3rd ed.).

 

--------, (1976), MECW Volume 5 (Lawrence & Wishart).

 

--------, (2001), MECW Volume 49 (Lawrence & Wishart).

 

--------, (2004), MECW Volume 50 (Lawrence & Wishart).

 

McGarr, P. (1994), 'Engels And Natural Science', International Socialism 65, pp.143-76.

 

McGrath, A. (2005), Dawkins' God. Genes, Memes, And The Meaning Of Life (Blackwell).

 

McLear, M. (2015), 'Kant: Philosophy Of Mind', Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. [This article is undated, so I have assigned it an arbitrary date based on internal evidence.]

 

McNally, D. (2001), Bodies Of Meaning. Studies On Language, Labor, And Liberation (State University of New York Press).

 

--------, (2004), 'Language, Praxis And Dialectics: Reply To Collins', Historical Materialism 12, 2, pp.149-67.

 

Megill, A. (1994) (ed.), Rethinking Objectivity (Duke University Press).

 

Meinwald, C. (1990), Plato's Parmenides (Oxford University Press).

 

--------, (1992), 'Good-Bye To The Third Man', in Kraut (1992), pp.365-96.

 

Mellor, D., and Oliver, A. (1997) (eds.), Properties (Oxford University Press).

 

Miller, F. (2003), 'Review of Plato's Democratic Entanglements. Athenian Politics And The Practice Of Philosophy, by Sara Monoson', The Philosophical Review, 112, 4, pp.561-66.

 

Miles, M. (2003), Inroads: Paths In Ancient And Modern Western Philosophy (University of Toronto Press).

 

Mills, R. (1994), Space, Time And Quanta. An Introduction To Contemporary Physics (W H Freeman).

 

Monoson, S, (2000), Plato's Democratic Entanglements. Athenian Politics And The Practice of Philosophy (Princeton University Press).

 

Moore, G. (1923), 'Are Characteristics Of Particular Things Universal Or Particular?', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume, Volume III, pp.95-113, reprinted in Moore (1970), pp.17-31. [This links to a PDF.]  

 

--------, (1953), Some Main Problems Of Philosophy (George Allen & Unwin).

 

--------, (1959), Principia Ethica (Cambridge University Press).

 

--------, (1970), Philosophical Papers (George Allen & Unwin).

 

Mortensen, C. (2020), 'Change And Inconsistency', Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta (Spring 2020 edition). 

 

Novack, G. (1965), The Origins Of Materialism (Pathfinder Press).

 

--------, (1971), An Introduction To The Logic Of Marxism (Pathfinder Press, 5th ed.).

 

O'Hear, A. (1999) (ed.), German Philosophy Since Kant (Cambridge University Press).

 

Oizerman, T. (1982), Dialectical Materialism And The History Of Philosophy (Progress Publishers).

 

Ollman, B. (1993), Dialectical Investigations (Routledge).

 

--------, (2003), Dance Of The Dialectic. Steps In Marx's Method (University of Illinois Press).

 

--------, (2019), 'Eight Steps In Marx's Dialectical Method', in Vidal, et al (2019), pp.97-110.

 

O'Regan, C. (1994), The Heterodox Hegel (State University of New York Press).

 

Orilia, F., and Paoletti, M. (2020), 'Properties', Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta (Spring 2022 edition). 

 

Ortony, A. (1993) (ed.), Metaphor And Thought (Cambridge University Press, 2nd ed.).

 

Osler, M. (2004), Divine Will And The Mechanical Philosophy. Gassendi And Descartes On Contingency And Necessity In The Created World (Cambridge University Press).

 

Owen, G. (1953), 'The Place Of The Timaeus In Plato's Dialogues', Classical Quarterly 3, pp. 75-95, reprinted in Allen (1965), pp.313-38, and Owen (1986), pp.65-84.

 

--------, (1986), Logic, Science And Dialectic. Collected Papers In Greek Philosophy (Duckworth).

 

Parrington, J. (1997), 'In Perspective: Valentin Voloshinov', International Socialism 75, pp.117-50.

 

Passmore, J. (1970), Philosophical Reasoning (Duckworth).

 

Peat, D. (2008), 'Trapped In A World View', New Scientist 197, 2637, 05/01/08, pp.42-43.

 

Peels, R., and Woudenberg, R. (2020) (eds.), The Cambridge Companion To Common Sense Philosophy (Cambridge University Press).

 

Pickover, C. (2000), The Girl Who Gave Birth To Rabbits. A True Medical Mystery (Prometheus Books).

 

Pinkard, T. (2002), German Philosophy 1760-1860. The Legacy Of Idealism (Cambridge University Press).

 

Plato, (1997a), Complete Works, edited by John Cooper (Hackett Publishing).

 

--------, (1997b), Sophist, translated by N. White, in Plato (1997a), pp.235-93.

 

--------, (1997c), Timaeus, translated by D. Zeyl, in Plato (1997a), pp.1224-91.

 

--------, (1997d), Parmenides, translated by M. Gill and P. Ryan, in Plato (1997a), pp.359-97.

 

--------, (1997e), Theaetetus, translated by M. Levett and J. Burnyeat, in Plato (1997a), pp.157-234.

 

--------, (1997f), Republic, translated by G. M. A. Grube, revised by C. D. C. Reeve, in Plato (1997a), pp.971-1223.

 

--------, (1997g), The Laws, translated by T. J. Saunders, in Plato (1997a), pp.1318-1616.

 

--------, (1997h), Meno, translated by G. M. A. Grube, in Plato (1997a), pp.870-97.

 

Plekhanov, G. (1956), The Development Of The Monist View Of History (Progress Publishers). This is reprinted in Plekhanov (1974), pp.480-737. [Unfortunately, the Index page for this book over at the Marxist Internet Archive has no link to the second half of Chapter Five, but it can be accessed directly here. I have informed the editors of this error. Added June 2015: they have now corrected it!]

 

--------, (1974), Selected Philosophical Works, Volume One (Progress Publishers).

 

Polanyi, M. (1962), Personal Knowledge. Towards A Post-Critical Philosophy (Routledge).

 

Popper, K. (1966), The Open Society And Its Enemies. Volume 1: Plato (Routledge, 5th ed.).

 

Price, H., and Corry, R. (2007) (eds.), Causation, Physics, And The Constitution Of Reality: Russell's Republic Revisited (Oxford University Press).

 

Priest, G. (2014), 'Beyond True And False. Buddhist Philosophy Is Full Of Contradictions. Now Modern Logic Is Learning That Might Be A Good Thing', Aeon, 5 May 2014.

 

Prosch, H. (1966), The Genesis Of Twentieth Century Philosophy. The Evolution Of Thought From Copernicus To The Present (George Allen & Unwin).

 

Putnam, H. (1975a), Mind Language And Reality. Philosophical Papers Volume Two (Cambridge University Press).

 

--------, (1975b), 'Language And Philosophy', in Putnam (1975a), pp.1-32.

 

Pyle, A. (1997), Atomism And Its Critics: From Democritus To Newton (Thoemmes Press).

 

Ravetz, J. (1996), Scientific Knowledge And Its Social Problems (Transaction Publishers, 2nd ed.).

 

Redwood, J. (1976), Reason, Ridicule And Religion. The Age Of Enlightenment In England 1660-1750 (Thames & Hudson).

 

Rees, J. (1998), The Algebra Of Revolution (Routledge). [This links to a PDF.]

 

--------, (2016), The Leveller Revolution (Verso).

 

--------, (2024), Marxism And The English Revolution (Whalebone Press).

 

Rendsvig, R., Symons, J., and Wang, Y. (2023), 'Epistemic Logic', Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta (Summer 2024 edition).

 

Resnick, S., and Wolff, R. (1987), Knowledge And Class. A Marxian Critique Of Political Economy (Chicago University Press).

 

Rhees, R. (1971), 'Could Language Be Invented By A Robinson Crusoe?', reprinted in Jones (1971), pp.61-75.

 

Richards, R. (2002), The Romantic Conception Of Life. Science And Philosophy In The Age Of Goethe (University of Chicago Press).

 

Rickless, S. (2020), 'Plato's Parmenides', Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta (Spring 2020 edition).

 

Roberts, E. (1991), The Cartesian Revolution: A Study Of Descartes' Meditations, PhD Thesis submitted to The Australian National University, July 1991.

 

Robinson, G. (2003), Philosophy And Mystification. A Reflection On Nonsense And Clarity (Fordham University Press). [Many of Guy's essays have been re-posted here with the permission of his son.]

 

Robinson, J. (1953), On Re-Reading Marx (Students Bookshop).

 

Rohlf, M. (2020), 'Immanuel Kant', Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta (Fall 2023 edition).

 

Ross, W. (1961), Plato's Theory Of Ideas (Oxford University Press).

 

Rosser, W. (1967), Introductory Relativity (Plenum Press).

 

Rousseau, J. (1913), The Social Contract (J. M. Dent and Sons).

 

Ruben, D-H. (1979), Marxism And Materialism: A Study In Marxist Theory Of Knowledge (Harvester Press, 2nd ed.). [This links to a PDF.]

 

Rubenstein, R. (2003), Aristotle's Children. How Christians, Muslims And Jews Rediscovered Ancient Wisdom And Illuminated The Dark Ages (Harcourt, Inc.).

 

Russell, B. (1917a), Mysticism And Logic (George Allen & Unwin).

 

--------, (1917b), 'On The Notion Of A Cause', in Russell (1917a), pp.132-51.

 

--------,  (1937), The Principles Of Mathematics (George Allen & Unwin, 2nd ed.). [This links to a PDF of the Routledge 2010 edition.]

 

Russell, C. (1973) (ed.), Science And Religious Belief. A Selection Of Recent Historical Studies (Open University Press).

 

Ryle, G. (1949), 'A Review Of Meaning And Necessity By Rudolf Carnap', Philosophy 24, pp.69-76, reprinted in Ryle (1971) as 'Discussion Of Rudolf Carnap: Meaning And Necessity', pp.225-35.

 

--------, (1960), Dilemmas (Cambridge University Press).

 

--------, (1971), Collected Papers Volume One: Critical Essays (Barnes & Noble Inc.).

 

Sampson, G. (2005), The 'Language Instinct' Debate (Continuum Books, 2nd ed.).

 

Sayer, A. (1992), Method In Social Science. A Realist Approach (Routledge, 2nd ed.).

 

--------, (2010), Method In Social Science. A Realist Approach (Routledge, 2nd Revised ed.).

 

Sayers, S. (1982), 'Contradiction And Dialectic In The Development Of Science', Science and Society 45, pp.409-36.

 

--------, (1985), Reason And Reality. Dialectic And The Theory Of Knowledge (Blackwell). [This links to a PDF.]

 

Schaeffer, D., and Nicholls, M. (2003), 'Review of Plato's Democratic Entanglements. Athenian Politics And The Practice Of Philosophy, by Sara Monoson', Polity, 25, 3, pp.466-69. 

 

Schmidt, A. (1971), The Concept Of Nature In Marx (New Left Books).

 

Scott, D. (1995), Recollection And Experience: Plato's Theory Of Learning And Its Successors (Cambridge University Press).

 

Sellars, W. (1997), Empiricism And The Philosophy Of Mind (Harvard University Press). [This links to a PDF.]

 

Sheptulin, A. (1978), Marxist-Leninist Philosophy (Progress Publishers).

 

Shirokov, M., et al (1937), A Textbook Of Marxist Philosophy (Victor Gollancz). [This book has no publication date but internal evidence suggests that it was published in the mid-, to late-1930s, so I have arbitrarily assigned it the given date. The entire book can now be accessed here (as a PDF), with parts of it here.]

 

Shriver, D., and Atkins, P. (2001), Inorganic Chemistry (Oxford University Press, 3rd ed.).

 

Sider, T. (2006), 'Bare Particulars', Philosophical Perspectives 20, pp.387-97. [This links to a PDF.]

 

Silverman, A. (2014), 'Plato's Middle Period Metaphysics And Epistemology', Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta (Fall 2022 edition).

 

Simons, P. (1994), 'Particulars In Particular Clothing: Three Trope Theories Of Substance', Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54, 3, pp.533-75, reprinted in Laurence and Macdonald (1998), pp.364-84. [This links to a PDF.]

 

Slater, H. (2000), 'Concept And Object In Frege', Minerva 4. [Minerva is an on-line Philosophy Journal. This article has now been reprinted in Slater (2007), pp.99-112.]

 

--------, (2007), The De-Mathematisation Of Logic (Polimetrica).

 

Sluga, H., and Stern, D. (1996) (eds.), The Cambridge Companion To Wittgenstein (Cambridge University Press).

 

Smith, Q. (1993), Language And Time (Oxford University Press). [More details here.]

 

Sober, E. (1975), Simplicity (Oxford University Press).

 

Sohn-Rethel, A. (1978), Intellectual And Manual Labour (Macmillan).

 

Solomon, E. (1976), Indian Dialectics. Methods Of Philosophical Discussion (BJ Institute of Learning and Research).

 

Sorabji, R. (2004) (ed.), The Philosophy Of The Commentators 200-600AD. A Sourcebook, Volume Three: Logic And Metaphysics (Duckworth).

 

Sorel, G. (1950), Reflections On Violence (Free Press).

 

Sorensen, R. (2003), A Brief History Of The Paradox. Philosophy And The Labyrinths Of The Mind (Oxford University Press).

 

Spirkin, A. (1983), Dialectical Materialism (Progress Publishers).

 

Squires, R. (1974), 'Silent Soliloquy', in Vesey (1974), pp.208-25.

 

Staniland, H. (1973), Universals (Macmillan).

 

Stebbing, L. (1958), Philosophy And The Physicists (Dover).

 

Stich, S. (1975) (ed.), Innate Ideas (University of California Press).

 

Stout, G. (1923), 'Are Characteristics Of Particular Things Universal Or Particular?', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume, Volume III, pp.114-22. [This links to a PDF.]

 

Stove, D. (1991), The Plato Cult And Other Philosophical Follies (Blackwell).

 

Strang, C. (1963), 'Plato And The Third Man,' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 37, pp.147-64; reprinted in Vlastos (1971), pp.184-200.

 

Stroud, B. (2000), The Quest For Reality (Oxford University Press).

 

Swartz, N. (1985), The Concept Of A Physical Law (Cambridge University Press).

 

--------, (2009), 'Laws Of Nature', Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

 

Teichmann, R. (1992), Abstract Entities (Macmillan).

 

Thalheimer, A. (1936), Introduction To Dialectical Materialism. The Marxist World-View (Covici Friede Publishers).

 

Tian, C. (2005), Chinese Dialectics. From Yijing To Marxism (Lexington Books).

 

Trotsky, L. (1971), In Defense Of Marxism (New Park Publications).

 

--------, (1986), Notebooks 1933-35 (Columbia University Press).

 

Tugendhat, E. (1982), Traditional And Analytic Philosophy (Cambridge University Press).

 

Vailati, E. (1997), Leibniz And Clarke (Oxford University Press).

 

Van Brakel, J. (2000), Philosophy Of Chemistry. Between The Manifest And The Scientific Image (Leuven University Press).

 

Van Cleve, J. (1985), 'Three Versions Of The Bundle Theory', Philosophical Studies 47, pp.95-107; reprinted in Laurence and Macdonald (1998), pp.264-74, and Loux (2001), pp.121-33. 

 

VandeWall, H. (2006), 'Why Water Is Not H2O, And Other Critiques Of Essentialist Ontology From The Philosophy Of Chemistry', in Bicchieri and Alexander (2006), pp.906-19.

 

Vickery, H. (1950), 'The Origin Of The Word Protein', The Yale Journal of Biology and Medicine 22, 5, pp.387-93. [This links to a PDF.]

 

Vesey, G. (1974) (ed.), Understanding Wittgenstein (Macmillan).

 

Vidal, M., Smith, T., Rotta, T., and Prew, P. (2019) (eds.), The Oxford Handbook Of Karl Marx (Oxford University Press). 

 

Vlastos, G. (1954), 'The Third Man Argument In The Parmenides', Philosophical Review 63, pp. 319-49; reprinted in Allen (1965), pp.251-63, and Vlastos (1995), with an Addendum, pp.166-93.

 

--------, (1956), 'Postscript To The Third Man: A Reply To Mr Geach', Philosophical Review 65, pp. 83-94; reprinted in Allen (1965), pp.279-91, and Vlastos (1995), pp.204-14.

 

--------, (1971) (ed.), Plato. A Collection Of Critical Essays. Volume One: Metaphysics And Epistemology (Doubleday Anchor).

 

--------, (1995), Studies In Greek Philosophy, Volume II: Socrates, Plato And Their Tradition, edited by D. W. Graham (Princeton University Press).

 

Voloshinov, V. (1973), Marxism And The Philosophy Of Language (Harvard University Press). [The first two chapters can be accessed here.]

 

Way, E. (1994), Knowledge, Representation And Metaphor (Intellect Books).

 

Welsh, M. (2000), 'Berkeley, God, And The Existence Of Matter', Ephemeris 1, pp.93-100. [This links to a PDF.]

 

White, J. (1996a), Karl Marx And The Intellectual Origins Of Dialectical Materialism (Macmillan).

 

White, R. (1996b), The Structure Of Metaphor (Blackwell).

 

--------, (2006), Wittgenstein's Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (Continuum).

 

Williams, B. (1973), 'The Analogy Of The City And The Soul In Plato's Republic', in Lee, et al (1973), pp.196-206, reprinted in Fine (1999b), pp.255-64.

 

-------- (1990), Descartes: The Project Of Pure Enquiry (Penguin Books). 

 

Williams, M. (1999a), Wittgenstein, Mind And Meaning (Routledge).

 

--------, (1999b), 'Vygotsky's Social Theory Of Mind', in Williams (1999a), pp.260-81.

 

Wittgenstein, L. (1969), The Blue And Brown Books (Blackwell). [The Blue Book can be accessed here.]

 

--------, (1974a), Philosophical Grammar, edited by Rush Rhees, translated by Anthony Kenny (Blackwell).

 

--------, (1974b), On Certainty, translated by Denis Paul and Elizabeth Anscombe (Blackwell).

 

--------, (1976), Wittgenstein's Lectures On The Foundation Of Mathematics: Cambridge 1939, edited by Cora Diamond (Harvester Press).

 

--------, (1978), Remarks On The Foundations Of Mathematics, translated by G. E. M. Anscombe (Blackwell, 3rd ed.).

 

--------, (1998), Culture And Value, edited by G. H. von Wright, translated by Peter Winch (Blackwell, 2nd ed.).

 

--------, (2009), Philosophical Investigations, translated by G. E. M. Anscombe, revised by Peter Hacker and Joachim Schulte (Blackwell, 4th ed.).

 

--------, (2013), The Big Typescript: TS 213, edited and translated by C. G. Luckhardt and M. A. E. Aue (Blackwell).

 

Wong, C., Ciocca, V., Chan, A., Ha, L., Tan, L., and Peretz, I. (2012), 'Effects Of Culture On Musical Pitch Perception', Plos One 7, 4.

 

Wood, A. (2004), Karl Marx (Routledge, 2nd ed.).

 

Woods, A., and Grant, T. (1995), Reason In Revolt. Marxism And Modern Science (Wellred Publications).

 

Yates, F. (2004), The Rosicrucian Enlightenment (Routledge).

 

Young, R. (1985), Darwin's Metaphor (Cambridge University Press).

 

Zumdahl, S. (1989), Chemistry (D C Heath and Company, 2nd ed.)

 

Word Count: 124,580 (that figure is now out-of-date)

 

Latest Update: 14/08/24

 

Return To The Main Index

 

Back To The Top

 

© Rosa Lichtenstein 2024

 

Hits Since March 2007:

 

Web Page Hit Counter
Online Dating Website