16-13-01: Summary Of Essay Thirteen Part One -- Lenin's Disappearing Definition Of Matter

 

Preface

 

If you are using Internet Explorer 10 (or later), you might find some of the links I have used won't work properly unless you switch to 'Compatibility View' (in the Tools Menu); for IE11 select 'Compatibility View Settings' and then add this site (anti-dialectics.co.uk). Microsoft's new browser, Edge, automatically renders these links compatible; Windows 10 also automatically makes IE11 compatible with this site.

 

However, if you are using Windows 10, Microsoft's browsers, IE11 and Edge, unfortunately appear to colour these links somewhat erratically. They are meant to be dark blue, but those two browsers render them intermittently mid-blue, light blue, yellow, purple and red!

 

Firefox and Chrome reproduce them correctly.

 

~~~~~~oOo~~~~~~

 

This is an Introductory Essay, which has been written for those who find the main Essays either too long, or too difficult. It doesn't pretend to be comprehensive since it is simply a summary of the core ideas presented at this site. Most of the supporting evidence and argument found in each of the main Essays has been omitted. Anyone wanting more details, or who would like to examine my arguments in full, should consult the Essay for which this is a summary. [In this particular case, that can be found here.]

 

As is the case with all my work, nothing here should be read as an attack either on Historical Materialism [HM] -- a theory I fully accept --, or, indeed, on revolutionary socialism. I remain as committed to the self-emancipation of the working class and the dictatorship of the proletariat as I was when I first became a revolutionary nearly thirty years ago.

 

The difference between Dialectical Materialism [DM] and HM, as I see it, is explained here.

 

Phrases like "ruling-class theory", "ruling-class view of reality", "ruling-class ideology" (etc.) used at this site (in connection with Traditional Philosophy and DM), aren't meant to suggest that all or even most members of various ruling-classes actually invented these ways of thinking or of seeing the world (although some of them did -- for example, Heraclitus, Plato, Cicero, and Marcus Aurelius). They are intended to highlight theories (or "ruling ideas") that are conducive to, or which rationalise the interests of the various ruling-classes history has inflicted on humanity, whoever invents them. Up until recently this dogmatic approach to knowledge had almost invariably been promoted by thinkers who either relied on ruling-class patronage, or who, in one capacity or another, helped run the system for the elite.**

 

However, that will become the central topic of Parts Two and Three of Essay Twelve (when they are published); until then, the reader is directed here, here, and here for more details.

 

[**Exactly how this applies to DM will, of course, be explained in the other Essays published at this site (especially here, here, and here). In addition to the three links in the previous paragraph, I have summarised the argument (but this time aimed at absolute beginners!) here.]

 

[Latest Update: 26/01/20.]

 

Quick Links

 

Anyone using these links must remember that they will be skipping past supporting argument and evidence set out in earlier sections.

 

If your Firewall/Browser has a pop-up blocker, you will need to press the "Ctrl" key at the same time or these and the other links here won't work!

 

I have adjusted the font size used at this site to ensure that even those with impaired vision can read what I have to say. However, if the text is either too big or too small for you, please adjust your browser settings!

 

(1) Image Conscious

 

(a) Lenin Confuses Repetition And Bluster With Proof

 

(b) Lenin And Santa Claus

 

(i)   Lenin's Theory

 

(ii)  Images Can Exist Even Though What They Supposedly Depict Do Not

 

(iii) Many Things Exist Of Which We Can Form No Image

 

(c) Images Can't Correspond With Anything In Reality

 

(2) Interconnection Strikes Back

 

(a) Idealism In Disguise?

 

(b) The Nature Of Matter

 

(c) Prevarication -- Dialecticians Have Developed This Tactic Into An Art Form

 

 

Summary Of My Main Objections To Dialectical Materialism

 

Abbreviations Used At This Site

 

Return To The Main Index Page

 

Contact Me

 

Image Conscious

 

Lenin Confuses Repetition And Bluster With Proof

 

In this Essay it will be argued that Lenin's philosophical ideas (in MEC, and elsewhere) only succeed in undermining materialism, they in no way support it.

 

[MEC = Materialism and Empirio-Criticism, i.e., Lenin (1972).]

 

One of the main problems with MEC is that Lenin seems to be determined to base human knowledge on "images" -- and, even worse, in his Philosophical Notebooks [PN], on Hegel's theories (upside down or 'the right way up'). This seems about as sensible as trying first of all to build a skyscraper on sand -- and then on quicksand. As if to compound even this error, Lenin's supported his theory with very few -- but nonetheless surprisingly weak -- arguments, accompanied by scant evidence, topped off with a surfeit of repetitive bluster and misrepresentation. I have counted no fewer than 36 places in MEC alone where Lenin keeps saying things like the following, over and over again:

 

"[I]t is the sole categorical...recognition of nature's existence outside the mind...that distinguishes dialectical materialism from relativist agnosticism and idealism." [Lenin (1972), p.314. Cf., Lenin (1972), pp.1-2, 50, 58, 61, 63, 69, 86, 111, 123, 136-37, 165, 177, 191, 197, 200, 202-03, 211, 212, 215, 216-18, 221-22, 259, 270, 287-88, 306, 311-14, 320, 322, 324, 326, 354-55, 364, 366, 373, 377, 394, 407, 418, 420 (twice), 422, 425, and 426. This is an incomplete list!]

 

If repetition were enough to win arguments, parrots would indeed be "mighty" thinkers.

 

Lenin And Santa Claus

 

Lenin's Theory

 

However, in one of the few detectable arguments to be found in MEC, Lenin claimed that an image implies the existence of the thing imaged:

 

"Our sensation, our consciousness is only an image of the external world, and it is obvious that an image cannot exist without the thing imaged, and that the latter exists independently of that which images it. Materialism deliberately makes the 'naïve' belief of mankind the foundation of its theory of knowledge." [Ibid., p.69. Bold emphasis added.]

 

Later on, Lenin was even clearer:

 

"The image inevitably and of necessity implies the objective reality of that which it 'images.'" [Ibid., p.279. Bold emphasis added. In both of these, the quotation marks have been altered to conform to the conventions adopted here.]

 

There are several problems with this way of viewing things.

 

Images can exist even though what they supposedly depict do not

 

Contrary to what Lenin imagined, images not only can, they do exist without there being anything 'objective' corresponding to them in reality. It is easy to conjure an image of Santa Claus, for instance, but apparently only children and foolish parents believe he exists.

 

However, if we take Lenin at his word -- "The image inevitably and of necessity implies the objective reality of that which it 'images'" --, this must mean that we should add Lenin to the list of those who believe in Santa!

 

This particular argument didn't go down too well with the revolutionaries I laid it on at RevLeft a while back. Almost to a dialectical clone they all reacted emotively and irrationally to it. [For example, here and here. Why they all tend to respond this way is explained in Essay Nine Part Two.]

 

Anyway, as I pointed out in those debates, the fact that Lenin didn't actually believe in Santa Claus means that his argument that images ("inevitably") imply the objective existence of whatever they are the image of is manifestly unsound, leaving him in no better position than Mach or Bogdanov (characters he was criticising in MEC), since he, too, has to depend on faith in order to try to prove the existence of the outside world.

 

Nevertheless, in the above debates, one of the more rational attempts to defend Lenin ran along the following lines:

 

We have images of things like colour and shape because of our interaction with the world. So, even if we have an image of Santa Claus, that doesn't imply that Lenin believed he existed. That is because Lenin was merely committed to the view that, for example, the coloured parts we imagine belonging to Santa (etc.) have been derived from experience. Out of such parts, and as a result of various cultural influences, we can construct at will, or otherwise, images (on paper, in the mind, in film, etc.) of various things, some of which do, and some of which do not exist, even though their parts manifestly do exist. In that case, Lenin isn't claiming that just because we have images of, say, Big Foot or the Tooth Fairy that they exist. All that Lenin is arguing is that the images we have of such parts imply that those parts must exist in reality, since we couldn't have derived them from anywhere else.

 

This brave attempt to defend Lenin fails in several places. First of all, as noted above, Lenin argued as follows:

 

"Our sensation, our consciousness is only an image of the external world, and it is obvious that an image cannot exist without the thing imaged, and that the latter exists independently of that which images it. Materialism deliberately makes the 'naïve' belief of mankind the foundation of its theory of knowledge." [Ibid., p.69. Bold emphasis added.]

 

And:

 

"The image inevitably and of necessity implies the objective reality of that which it 'images.'" [Ibid., p.279. Bold emphasis added. In both of these, the quotation marks have been altered to conform to the conventions adopted here.]

 

No mention here of "parts".

 

Secondly, those whom Lenin was criticising in MEC could easily have responded as follows:

 

"And how, comrade Lenin, do you know that the images you have (whether they are of parts or of wholes) represent objects, or even the properties or parts of objects in the real world, and aren't just figments of your own imagination?"

 

Lenin plainly had no answer to this in MEC (and none in PN, either), and, as far as can be ascertained, no DM-supporter who argues along these lines has produced an answer since -- mainly because they are content merely to regurgitate thoughtlessly Lenin's defective non-arguments, or simply copy his bluster and invective, imagining (no pun intended!) that this tactic constitutes proof. Naturally, this leaves Lenin (and his followers) in the same predicament as the Subjective Idealists and Immanentists he was criticising in MEC -- that is, he had no proof that the external world actually exists, or that our "images" are indeed "copies" of objects/properties in extra-mental reality. [On this, see also Essay Five, here.]

 

[It is important to add that this does not imply I think the external world doesn't exist, merely that if all we had to rely on are Lenin's rather weak arguments, materialism would surely sink without trace.]

 

When faced with this, DM-fans tend to retreat to the fall-back position of saying that only madmen, sceptics or Idealists would even think to doubt the existence of the outside world -- often appealing to the reader's 'commonsense' to reject this absurd view of reality.

 

However, that reply merely labels the problem, it doesn't solve. Those whom Lenin was criticising in MEC are unlikely to have been persuaded by such a cop-out, and would no doubt have wanted to know how Lenin could possibly know, or prove, that his 'image' of what he thinks are the beliefs of ordinary folk itself represents anything in reality and isn't just another figment of his own over-active imagination. Or even that there are any "ordinary folk" in reality, as opposed to 'images' supposedly of them.

 

Hence, it is little use trying to take on the sophisticated arguments of Phenomenalists if in the end all that a supporter of Lenin can do is appeal to what one imagines madmen, sceptics and Idealists do or do not believe, when the existence even of these individuals (as opposed to their images) has yet to be demonstrated.

 

One last desperate fall-back position might involve an attempt to argue that we determine in practice that what we have images of actually do exist. The problem with this response is that, if Lenin were right, all we would have are images of practice, and it is difficult to see how such images could help anyone escape the solipsistic world Lenin has created for himself (and for anyone who agrees with him). A similar problem faces those who say we should rely on the deliverances of science to tell us which images are valid and which aren't. That is because, if Lenin is to be believed, we would only have access to 'images' of science and what scientists have to say, leaving us in the same Idealist hole.

 

Hence, any dialectician who adopts a traditional, representational theory of mind/knowledge must inevitably trap her/himself in just such a solipsistic 'world' -- as we will see in more detail in Essay Thirteen Part Three. Indeed, those who appropriate the methods and concepts handed down to them from previous generations of ruling-class hacks should learn to accept this self-inflicted predicament with fortitude. They are the ones who dropped themselves into this subjective idealist hole --, and, in the vast majority of cases, they are also the ones who refuse even to consider effective ways of avoiding these and similar pitfalls -- for instance, the deflationary anti-metaphysical method adopted at this site -- nor do they seem inclined even to consider, let alone accept, Marx's diagnosis of the obvious source of such 'problems':

 

"The philosophers have only to dissolve their language into the ordinary language, from which it is abstracted, in order to recognise it, as the distorted language of the actual world, and to realise that neither thoughts nor language in themselves form a realm of their own, that they are only manifestations of actual life." [Marx and Engels (1970), p.118. Bold emphasis added.]

 

As we saw in Essay Twelve Part One, the radical misuse of language found throughout Traditional Thought (and in DM), renders such theses incoherently non-sensical. [Summary here.]

 

Finally, as noted in Essay Thirteen Part One, it is a bit rich of those who spare no effort telling us of the limitations of 'commonsense' to turn round now and inform us that it underpins their theory of knowledge!

 

Nevertheless, the following considerations show that this untoward example (concerning images of mythical characters like Santa Claus) isn't entirely unique:

 

(1) The existence of mirages doesn't commit us to their 'objectivity' -- it is to be hoped!

 

(2) It is possible to form images in the mind's eye of people who no longer exist -- which fact plainly doesn't imply they do exist.

 

(3) It is easy to induce vivid but formless coloured images (phosphenes) 'inside' the eyeball by gently pressing one or other of them with a finger. Clearly, this doesn't mean that these artificial images don't reflect anything 'objective' in the 'outside world'.

 

(4) Again, by re-focussing, or by pressing one eye, it is possible to form two images of the same object (which our system of sight normally merges into one). But, no one believes that there are in fact two identical copies of the same object in reality answering to these two pre-merged images. By a similar trick, it is also possible to see a three-dimensional image in two-dimensional "magic eye" pictures. Similarly, this doesn't mean that these images correspond with anything in the 'external world'.

 

(5) We see stars every night (or are they merely images of stars?); according to scientists, many of these no longer exist. Does this mean that they are mistaken and these stars do exist?

 

(6) A scientist photographs a bent stick in a bucket of water. Does this image of the bent stick prove that there really are bent sticks in buckets of water?

 

(7) Someone claims to see an image of Christ in the clouds. Should we all become Christians? [Maybe not.]

 

(8) Those who have lost limbs claim they can still feel them long after they have been amputated. Does this odd sensation (or is it an image?) prove that the surgeon who performed the operation was incompetent? Others experience sensations in these false limbs. Does that show they aren't artificial after all?

 

Examples like these can be multiplied almost indefinitely. Any book (or website) devoted to optical illusions will provide numerous further examples. Indeed, few of us aren't already familiar with most of these.

 

But, if the above are correct (in fact, they are surely part of common knowledge), why did Lenin claim that DM begins with the "naïve belief" of humankind if this introduces "images" of things that only the severely disturbed actually believe picture things in 'objective' reality? Few ordinary people (not in the grip of superstition, drink, drugs, or mental illness) would be fooled into believing that phantom limbs, mirages, and dragons actually exist -- or that sticks bend when immersed in water.

 

"The 'naïve realism' of any healthy person who has not been an inmate of a lunatic asylum or a pupil of the idealist philosophers consists in the view that things, the environment, the world, exist independently of our sensation, of our consciousness, of our self and of man in general.... Materialism deliberately makes the 'naïve' belief of mankind the foundation of its theory of knowledge." [Lenin (1972), pp.68-69. Bold emphases alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

Lenin can't have been unaware of this. In which case, it isn't easy to understand why he concluded that anyone (not afflicted in the above manner) begins with "images" --, rather than with a healthy distrust of them. Or, even better: Why should anyone mention "images" in this connection to begin with, if only the mentally ill, the terminally naïve, the superstitious and those high (perhaps) on LSD or Mescaline would even think to base their knowledge of the world on such things?

 

Of course, the above examples trade on the patent truth that images do not have to correspond with things in the real world, or, indeed, with anything.

 

Many Things Exist Of Which Can Form No Image

 

There are many things that exist -- to which we can easily refer -- but of which we can form no image. For example, who among us can imagine (or 'image') a light ray, a π-meson, a gene, 10100 elementary particles (or even one elementary particle) --, or the universe itself?

 

Be this as it may, as we are about to see in the next sub-section the problems faced by Lenin's theory are much worse -- since images can't in fact correspond with anything in 'reality'.

 

Images Can't Correspond With Anything In Reality

 

Even worse still, images cannot correspond with the objects they supposedly depict. If anything, this observation is even more true of the sort of objects and processes studied in the sciences -- or even those mentioned by Lenin.

 

To be sure, Lenin did attempt to argue as follows:

 

"It is beyond doubt that an image cannot wholly resemble the model, but an image is one thing, a symbol, a conventional sign, another. The image inevitably and of necessity implies the objective reality of that which it 'images.'" [Lenin (1972), p.279.]

 

"A reflection may be an approximately true copy of the reflected, but to speak of identity is absurd. Consciousness in general reflects being -- that is a general principle of all materialism. It is impossible not to see its direct and inseparable connection with the principle of historical materialism: social consciousness reflects social being." [Ibid., p.391. Bold emphases added.]

 

How Lenin knew this to be the case is somewhat unclear. Indeed, and quite the opposite, Lenin couldn't possibly have known that an image is an "approximate" copy of the "thing reflected" unless he had independent access to the "thing reflected" with which to compare it. Was he able to 'jump out of his own head'?

 

[And we have already seen that an appeal to practice can't bail him out here, either.]

 

Even so, he went on to assert (or imply) the opposite of the above:

 

"There is definitely no difference in principle between the phenomenon and the thing-in-itself, and there can be no such difference. The only difference is between what is known and what is not yet known. And philosophical inventions of specific boundaries between the one and the other, inventions to the effect that the thing-in-itself is 'beyond' phenomena (Kant), or that we can and must fence ourselves off by some philosophical partition from the problem of a world which in one part or another is still unknown but which exists outside us (Hume) -- all this is the sheerest nonsense, Schrulle, crotchet, invention." [Ibid., p.110.]

 

"What two lines of philosophical tendency does Engels contrast here? One line is that the senses give us faithful images of things, that we know the things themselves, that the outer world acts on our sense-organs. This is materialism -- with which the agnostic is not in agreement. What then is the essence of the agnostic's line? It is that he does not go beyond sensations, that he stops on this side of phenomena, refusing to see anything 'certain' beyond the boundary of sensations. About these things themselves (i.e., about the things-in-themselves, the 'objects in themselves,' as the materialists whom Berkeley opposed called them), we can know nothing certain -- so the agnostic categorically insists. Hence, in the controversy of which Engels speaks the materialist affirms the existence and knowability of things-in-themselves. The agnostic does not even admit the thought of things-in-themselves and insists that we can know nothing certain about them." [Ibid., pp.116-17.]

 

"All knowledge comes from experience, from sensation, from perception. That is true. But the question arises, does objective reality 'belong to perception,' i.e., is it the source of perception? If you answer yes, you are a materialist. If you answer no, you are inconsistent and will inevitably arrive at subjectivism, or agnosticism, irrespective of whether you deny the knowability of the thing-in-itself, or the objectivity of time, space and causality (with Kant), or whether you do not even permit the thought of a thing-in-itself (with Hume). The inconsistency of your empiricism, of your philosophy of experience, will in that case lie in the fact that you deny the objective content of experience, the objective truth of experimental knowledge....

 

"The Machians love to declaim that they are philosophers who completely trust the evidence of our sense-organs, who regard the world as actually being what it seems to us to be, full of sounds, colours, etc., whereas to the materialists, they say, the world is dead, devoid of sound and colour, and in its reality different from what it seems to be, and so forth.... They do not recognise objective reality, independent of man, as the source of our sensations. They do not regard sensations as a true copy of this objective reality, thereby directly conflicting with natural science and throwing the door open for fideism...." [Ibid., pp.142-43. In all of the above, bold emphases alone added. Quotation marks altered to conform with the conventions adopted at this site.]

 

These passages seem pretty clear: there can be "no difference in principle" between "the phenomena and the thing-in-itself"; "objective reality" belongs to "perception"; sensations are a "true copy of" objective reality. No hint here of Lenin's usual 'relativism':

 

"In the theory of knowledge, as in every other branch of science, we must think dialectically, that is, we must not regard our knowledge as ready-made and unalterable, but must determine how knowledge emerges from ignorance, how incomplete, inexact knowledge becomes more complete and more exact." [Ibid., p.111. Italic emphases in the original.]

 

"Dialectics -- as Hegel in his time explained -- contains the element of relativism, of negation, of scepticism, but is not reducible to relativism. The materialist dialectics of Marx and Engels certainly does contain relativism, but is not reducible to relativism, that is, it recognises the relativity of all our knowledge, not in the sense of denying objective truth, but in the sense that the limits of approximation of our knowledge to this truth are historically conditional." [Ibid., p.154. Italic emphases in the original.]

 

But, from the above rather dogmatic pronouncements concerning non-dogmatism (for which he offered no proof, and not even a single argument in support), it looks like Lenin had already reached the end of that "infinite journey" (upon which we are all supposed to be involuntary pilgrims) that takes the DM-acolyte ever closer to 'The Truth' (here, quoting Engels):

 

"Here once again we find the same contradiction as we found above, between the character of human thought, necessarily conceived as absolute, and its reality in individual human beings with their extremely limited thought. This is a contradiction which can only be solved in the infinite progression, or what is for us, at least from a practical standpoint, the endless succession, of generations of mankind." [Ibid., p.149. For the exact reference to Engels, see below.]

 

[We have already seen that this approach to 'truth' would condemn anyone foolish enough to accept it to infinite ignorance.]

 

Hence, Lenin doesn't say that perception or sensation is an approximate copy of "objective reality", but that it is a "true copy", and that "objective reality" belongs to "perception" --, nor yet that "the phenomena" roughly correspond to "the thing-in-itself", but that there is "in principle" no "difference" between them. 

 

Again, how he knew all this he annoyingly kept to himself.

 

Nevertheless, as noted above, even if Lenin were correct, no image (in Lenin's sense of that word --, i.e., a sort of 'mental' copy of objects and processes in the external world, albeit later enhanced over time by practice) could possibly correspond with its 'intended' object, nor anything like it. That is because images are confined to partial and perspectivally-limited 'views' of their 'intended' targets. In that case, it isn't possible to form an image of the whole object viewed from every angle all at once. So, at best, even if an image could correspond with its 'intended' target, it would only match a partial view of that object from that angle and that distance. That is, at the every most, it would correspond with how that object would look when seen from that angle and that distance and direction --, but it wouldn't correspond with the object itself.

 

So, the 'images' to which Lenin refers could only correspond with views of objects from some angle or other, which would make his theory a rather naive form of Phenomenalism -- since those 'images' would correspond with perspectivally-limited (possible) views of objects, not those objects themselves.

 

And, even if Lenin's 'image' analogy were re-jigged (so that it now applied to an all-round scientific description of an object or process), not only would the 'copy' metaphor have to be abandoned, the word "objective" would have to go, too.

 

That is because, in an objective world there are no "views" of objects for 'images' to correspond, or fail to correspond with. Clearly, in such a world there are no viewers to have any views at all, no views to be had, and no specially privileged angles from which to 'view' them. The 'objective' world, so we are told, is supposed to be that which exists independently of mind:

 

"To be a materialist is to acknowledge objective truth, which is revealed to us by our sense-organs. To acknowledge objective truth, i.e., truth not dependent upon man and mankind, is, in one way or another, to recognise absolute truth." [Lenin (1972), p.148. Bold emphasis added.]

 

"Knowledge can be useful biologically, useful in human practice, useful for the preservation of life, for the preservation of the species, only when it reflects objective truth, truth which is independent of man." [Ibid., p.157. Bold emphasis added.]

 

Hence, in such a world there are no 'views' for Lenin's "images" to match.

 

Of course, it could be argued that the images Lenin had in mind actually correspond with how an object (or processes) would look to a viewer if he or she looked at it from that angle. No doubt this is so; but in that case, such 'images' would once more correspond to possible views of objects (but views enjoyed by whom?) not those objects themselves. And, if there are only views, what becomes of the objects themselves? Given Lenin's account, it seems that there could only be 'images' of 'views' of objects -- or, as seems plain, just 'images' of 'images', and no objects!

 

Ironically, Lenin's 'theory', which was cobbled-together partly in order to counter various Idealist attempts to spirit matter away, in the end actually manages to accomplish what his theoretical enemies had all along wanted to achieve -- that is, Lenin's theory makes matter vanish even more effectively.

 

In Lenin's 'universe' there are now only partial, and perspectivally-challenged 'images' of views, or 'images' of 'images'!

 

Once again, introducing science here would be of little help; every object and process in nature is -- according to physicists --, a set of scalar, vector, and/or tensor fields, spruced-up with a few probability density distributions, situated in at least four dimensions. No humanly-formed 'image' could possibly correspond with that bowl of 'mathematical spaghetti'!

 

In such a 'scientific' universe, each 'image'-former would, at best, have 'images' of perspectivally-limited views of heaps of knotted 'mathematical noodles'. And even if such 'images' could be formed, no human would be able to do so without first ascending into a higher dimension, and probably a considerably higher plane of 'consciousness' (which one supposes only Gerry Healy and Bob Avakian have ever attained). And, with that the objectivity of DM would collapse, since it clearly requires the existence of an Ideal Observer, who is everywhere and nowhere all at once.

 

Interconnection Strikes Back

 

Idealism In Disguise?

 

Furthermore, if DM-theorists are correct in believing that everything in nature is interconnected with everything else, then yet another idea of theirs  -- i.e., that matter is independent of mind (in the sense that (a) the vast bulk of matter in the universe is unaffected by our knowledge of it, and that (b) matter existed before there were any minds) -- will have to be abandoned. While it might be possible to base the independence of mind and matter successfully on the connectivity of all things in nature, this can't be done on the basis of their interconnectivity. Why this is so will now be explained.

 

If all things are interconnected then the material processes in, say, a scientist's central nervous system from which 'emerges' the thought that the Sun is approximately 93 million miles from earth must itself be connected with the material facts that make this thought true -- or, plainly, it wouldn't be true, but false.

 

So, the fact that the Sun is approximately 93 million miles from earth is connected with and causes the processes from which 'emerges' the thought that the Sun is roughly that distance from the earth (or at least the material and social processes involved cause this). So far so good.

 

However, if everything in nature is interconnected then the reverse must also be true: the thought that the Sun is approximately 93 million miles from earth is interconnected with and causes the material facts that make it true that the Sun is approximately 93 million miles from earth. In other words there is at least one 'mental state' that is interconnected with and thus causes a remote material state of the universe. And if there is one, there are many; indeed, there is at least one for each true thought about nature.

 

There seem to be only two ways to avoid this Idealist conclusion: (i) The doctrine that everything in nature is interconnected must be abandoned, or (ii) The link between interconnectivity and causation must be broken.

 

If the first escape route is chosen, much of classical DM would collapse, but if the second option is preferred, the interconnectivity of nature would have to be recast in a non-causal (perhaps a non-physical?) terms. But, how might that be done without the whole thing turning into full-blown Idealism, with mystical and magical 'influences' permeating nature at every turn? The conveniently opaque DM-word "mediation" and the openly misleading phrase "internal relation" are perhaps a little too obscure to rescue this beleaguered 'theory' from oblivion -- unless, of course, both of these terms are interpreted as synonyms for "causation", again.

 

Anyway, their deployment here would confirm the suspicion that in order to cover the gaping wounds in their theory, the only sticking plasters available to DM-theorists come in the form of yet more self-serving linguistic fixes.

 

[That would, of course, turn at least this part of DM into a variety of Conventionalism.]

 

The Nature Of Matter

 

The precise nature of matter is an issue that all DM-apologists duck, to a greater or lesser extent. Oddly enough for avowed materialists, DM-theorists since Engels's day believe that matter is an abstraction:

 

"N.B. Matter as such is a pure creation of thought and an abstraction. We leave out of account the qualitative differences of things in lumping them together as corporeally existing things under the concept matter. Hence matter as such, as distinct from definite existing pieces of matter, is not anything sensuously existing." [Engels (1954), p.255. Bold emphasis added.]

 

This risks DM being liable to prosecution under the Metaphysical Trade Descriptions Act, for, on this view, it isn't even a materialist theory!

 

Nevertheless, and independently of this, it isn't too clear from the above what Engels imagined the 'process of abstraction' was supposed to work on, or what it was supposed to be applied to. What are the 'common features' of all material objects that distinguish them from the non-material? Lenin seemed to think it was 'objective' existence outside the mind (but, as we have seen in Essay Thirteen Part One, this 'definition' is no use at all). In contrast, Engels appealed to motion and several unspecified "common properties" to explain its nature:

 

"Matter is nothing but the totality of material things from which this concept is abstracted and motion as such nothing but the totality of all sensuously perceptible forms of motion; words like matter and motion are nothing but abbreviations in which we comprehend many different sensuous perceptible things according to their common properties.... Subject-matter -- matter in motion.... The different forms and varieties of matter itself can likewise only be known through motion, only in this are the properties of bodies exhibited; of a body that does not move there is nothing to be said. Hence the nature of bodies in motion results from the forms of motion." [Ibid., pp.236, 248.]

 

However, not everything that moves is material (on that, see Essays Five and Twelve Part One); but, even if what Engels said were 100% correct, it really is little help being given a circular 'definition' of matter and motion:

 

"Matter is nothing but the totality of material things from which this concept is abstracted and motion as such nothing but the totality of all sensuously perceptible forms of motion...." [Ibid.]

 

What we still do not understand (philosophically) are the words "matter", "material", and "motion" (however, on the latter, and Engels rather odd views about it, see Essay Five again). The appearance of these words here as part of their own alleged definition is about as useful as this would be:

 

"Schmatter is nothing but the totality of schmaterial things from which this concept is abstracted and schmotion as such nothing but the totality of all sensuously perceptible forms of schmotion...."

 

And there is little point appealing to the everyday words we have for material things and moving objects, for they are far too varied to be restricted or co-opted in this way. [Once more, that was demonstrated in Essays Five and Twelve Part One.] The language we have for such things is indeed our best guide here, but that language is incredibly rich, and doesn't favour the 'philosophical' spin Engels (or Hegel, or Lenin) wished to impose upon it.

 

Prevarication -- Dialecticians Have Developed This Tactic Into An Art Form

 

DM-theorists are in general aware of their serial prevarication in this area (i.e., their failure to tell us what matter actually is); indeed, far from regarding this as a weakness, they view it as one of their theory's strengths. That is because it allows them to argue that DM is compatible with any future (genuine) development in the physical sciences. A fixed definition of matter, they seem to think, would compromise their obvious desire to tail-end Physics. Unfortunately, such a strategy is a hostage to fortune; in fact, as is reasonably clear, it has already backfired on them, especially now that many Physicists have declared that matter "has vanished" -- i.e., that it is now just a "field", or it is merely a 'subjective' aspect of how 'conscious beings' experience their existence in a four-dimensional manifold, etc., etc.

 

Dialecticians have so far failed to address this gaping hole in their version of 'materialism'. In fact, far too many have been content merely to bury their vanishing heads in these disappearing sands. Others have re-defined materialism in such a loose way that makes it compatible with practically anything at all (including, for example, belief in angels, 'gods' and assorted mythical beasts -- again, as we saw in Essay Thirteen Part One).

 

[Lenin's attempt to response to this objection (i.e., about 'disappearing matter') has been neutralised in Essay Thirteen Part One, too.]

 

Unless a satisfactory resolution of this critical problem can be found, DM itself might just as well stand for Disappeared Matter!

 

Latest Update: 26/01/20

 

Word Count: 6,260

 

Return To The Main Index

 

Back To The Top

 

 

© Rosa Lichtenstein 2020

 

Hits Since 14/03/11:

 

Hit Counter
office software